Barnes Holmes - RFT Description Evidence and Clinical Applications
Barnes Holmes - RFT Description Evidence and Clinical Applications
Barnes Holmes - RFT Description Evidence and Clinical Applications
Acknowledgements
The current chapter was prepared with the support of the FWO Type I Odysseus Programme at
1
From the perspective of contextual behavioral science (CBS), psychological therapists face the
language, by using assessments and interventions based on language (Zettle, 2015). Whilst
offering a useful description of the core related challenges of psychological assessment and
intervention, this dilemma requires further clarification if we are to try to solve it. We list below
some basic CBS assumptions in this regard that are entirely consistent with Relational Frame
Theory (RFT; Hayes, Barnes-Holmes, & Roche, 2001), and which point to some of the key
links between RFT and Acceptance and Commitment Therapy (ACT; Hayes, Strosahl, &
Wilson, 1999).
• First, we are not arguing that language causes a separate set of events which we
• Rather, we believe that these problems occur as part of the natural processes of
• Given the first two points above, we must be clear that we adhere to the pragmatic
assumption (it is not a scientific fact and is not readily testable) that when you
some point(s) in your life and that you will react or struggle in an “unhealthy”
manner (i.e., narrow and inflexible responding that limits access to reinforcers)
requires both elements listed in the point above (i.e., distress and psychological
struggle) because animals experience distress although they do not have language.
2
struggling in an unhealthy way with distress is problematic and it is this latter
historical and current environments play a strong role in enhancing or reducing our
overstated.
So, what are the implications of these assumptions for our original clinical conundrum?
Broadly speaking, our assumptions dictate that psychological assessment and intervention
should be targeting natural language processes (which RFT refers to as “verbal behavior”, see
below) and that other aspects of a client’s behavior will only change when these processes have
been manipulated appropriately. In simple terms, what RFT does for the contextual behavioral
scientist and clinician is to provide a detailed, and empirically supported, account of these
processes. In recent years, some individuals have used the theory to highlight specific ways in
which therapy can be crafted so as to alter these processes in a manner that helps to return an
individual toward psychological health (Tornëke, 2010; Villatte, Villatte, & Hayes, 2015). This,
in essence, is why we believe that it is important for the future of ACT, and indeed all therapies
embedded within a CBS framework, that clinicians understand RFT and its implications for
psychological assessment and intervention. Put another way, if we use the concepts of RFT,
our clinical hands are not tied as much by the language conundrum as you might first assume.
In the next section, we introduce you briefly, and in simple yet technically precise ways,
to the core concepts of RFT (Barnes-Holmes, Hayes, Barnes-Holmes, & Roche, 2001). In doing
so, we will describe how arbitrarily applicable relational responding (AARRing) is the
foundational unit of language in its ability to relate non-physical properties of stimuli. We will
then work upwards in complexity to the various patterns of AARRing, referred to as relational
frames (e.g., coordination, distinction etc.), and groups of relations referred to as relational
3
networks, with the aim of providing an account of how RFT can offer a rich understanding of
human language and how AARRing can be used to explain increasingly complex examples of
the ways in which humans may suffer psychologically. Lastly, we will highlight the importance
of focusing on the role of AARRing during the process of therapy in order to explore the
Writings on RFT are numerous and widespread, with several hundred published empirical
studies. The theory is over 30 years old, and it is fair to say that its concepts have stood the test
of time, debate, and experimental scrutiny extremely well (Hughes & Barnes-Holmes, 2016a,
2016b; but see Kissi, Hughes, Mertens, Barnes-Holmes, De Houwer, & Crombez, 2017). In
summary, we are now confident in saying that the theory offers a precise, succinct, functional-
analytic account of verbal behavior, although of course it remains very much a work in progress
The current section contains a summary of the basic concepts on which RFT is built
proposes that language comprises the ability to relate stimuli and events (e.g., words and
objects) in ways that do not depend upon the physical properties of the stimuli/events being
4
related. In Europe, for example, a one euro coin is physically smaller than a 50 cent coin, yet
the social culture has established that the euro coin is worth twice the value of the 50 cent coin.
If you were visiting Europe for the first time, you might assume that the opposite applied (i.e.,
the 50 cent coin was more valuable than the one euro coin). That is, when you compare one
coin with the other, you might conclude that the larger one should be the more valuable. RFT
refers to this as a response based on the nonarbitrary or formal properties of the stimuli being
related. In contrast, the socially determined value of the two coins is independent of the
difference in physical size between the coins. RFT refers to this as an arbitrarily applicable
relational response (AARR) because the relating of the two coins in this way (i.e., not based
on physical properties) has been arbitrarily established by the verbal community. Of course,
your relating behavior in the latter case is not arbitrary because it does not change randomly;
The key thing to note is that nonhumans are excellent at nonarbitrary relating (e.g., birds
can differentiate fragments of different green grasses at great distances), but only humans
appear to be highly proficient at AARRing, and only once language has developed (see Barnes-
Holmes, Barnes-Holmes, & McEnteggart, in press). Consider naming, relating words to their
referent objects (e.g., “dog” to an actual dog), as the most basic illustration of AARRing.
Indeed, words rarely resemble the objects to which they refer (e.g., the word “dog” is not in any
way like an actual dog). The verbal community coordinates, or relates together as equal, specific
words and specific objects or events. In time, in that language community, those words always
“mean” (refer to or are equal to) those objects. In simple terms, for RFT, language is about
relating things together that do not actually go together in any physical way. While there is
much more to RFT, it is important to emphasize that AARRing is its most basic process, around
which all additional concepts revolve. In what follows, we walk briefly through these other
5
Mutual entailment. We start with the simplest concept of all, mutual entailment, which
appears to signal the very beginning of language development and is the most basic analytic
unit of AARRing (Lipkens, Hayes, & Hayes, 1993). Mutual entailment simply means that when
two stimuli are related in some way, this relationship links one stimulus to the other in a very
specific way. For example, if I tell you that ‘A is less than B’, this relation mutually entails the
relation that ‘B is more than A’. That is, a less-than relation between two stimuli allows you to
derive a more-than relation between the same two stimuli, but going in the other direction.
things together, not just pairs of stimuli, and RFT employs the concept of combinatorial
entailment to describe how relating three or more stimuli together affects all of the relations
among the stimuli (Leonhard & Hayes, 1991). Imagine if I told you that ‘A is the opposite of B
entailed)’, then you could derive the combinatorially entailed relation of coordination between
A and C. That is, two opposite relations among three related stimuli facilitate the derivation of
a same (coordination) relation among two of the stimuli. In general, two sets of mutually
entailed relations facilitate a combinatorially entailed relation. For RFT, mutual and
Relational frames. As you can already see from the examples above, AARRing allows
us to describe very precisely, the different ways in which stimuli and events can be related, and
how doing so facilitates additional relations among those stimuli. RFT organizes these different
patterns of relational behavior into what are known as relational frames, where a frame simply
describes a type of pattern (Hayes et al., 2001). The frames that have been given at least some
6
Coordination relations. Coordination relations involve relating stimuli as similar or
same, and appears to be the first type of AARRing we learn well (Hayes et al., 2001). For
example, I could show you a picture of a dog, and then point to the picture saying “this is a
dog”. In this case, I have established a picture-word relation, and if you have had this type of
training before, you will be able to generate the mutually entailed word-picture coordination
relation, such that if I said “dog”, you could select the correct picture. As you can see from this
example, coordinate relational responses are typically controlled by the cue "is", such that when
you hear the word “is”, it comes to mean that the two things specified by the “is” cue can be
related together in a coordinate way. In natural language, there are numerous words and phrases
that would likely have the same function in specifying a coordination relation (“same as”,
“equals to”, etc.). Indeed, empirical evidence has demonstrated that mutual entailment has been
(Luciano, Gomez-Becerra, & Rodriguez-Valverde, 2007), and that coordination relations can
children, and in children with autism (Carr, Wilkinson, Blackman, & McIlvane, 2000; Dunne,
Indeed, it is worth noting that the concept of the contextual cue is pivotal in RFT. At
one level, a contextual cue is similar to a discriminative stimulus because the AARRing
controlled by the cue will have been reinforced previously. Imagine I showed you a five-euro
note, a bundle of five one-euro coins, and a ten-euro note, and said “match”. You would likely
point to the five-euro note and the five coins because “match” functions here as a contextual
cue that specifies a coordination relation, which in this case can only be derived between the
five-euro note and the five coins. In simple terms, you have learned across time that “match”
means (is a contextual cue for) pairing things together that are equal (i.e., coordinated) along
7
some dimension (in this case monetary value). Indeed, evidence has suggested that relating in
the absence of contextual cues involves less relational complexity until other cues are
introduced that specify the relation (Dougher, Hamilton, Fink, & Harrington, 2007; Hughes,
relation, but they place the related stimuli at either end of a continuum, in terms of extreme
difference from one another (Barnes-Holmes, Barnes-Holmes, Smeets, Strand, & Friman,
2004). Once again, the nature of the difference is not always specified, although the degree of
difference now is (e.g., black is opposite to white). Because of this somewhat greater degree of
relations can often be specified. Imagine for example, if I tell you that ‘A is opposite to B and
B is opposite to C’, you can derive that A and C are probably the same. That is, combining
opposite relations often entails a coordination relation. This example illustrates that the phrase
"is opposite to" in natural language may function as a cue for the frame of opposition. Empirical
evidence has demonstrated that opposition relations can readily be established in children using
multiple exemplars (Barnes-Holmes et al., 2004), even those with autism who show deficits in
important in language as learning to coordinate stimuli (Dixon & Zlomke, 2005). Indeed, if
some stimuli are similar, they are by definition different from all other stimuli (or else
everything would be the same). In many cases, distinction relations simply specify that two
stimuli are not coordinated, but additional information is often necessary for you to know
exactly where the difference lies. Imagine, for example, I told you that ‘I am very different from
one of my sisters’. Given only this level of information, there are potentially many ways in
which my sister and I differ, but if I add that we have very different personalities, then that
8
narrows down the possible array of differences being referred to. Because of the largely
unspecified nature of distinction relations, two mutually entailed relations do not specify what
the combinatorially entailed relation will be. For example, if I tell you that ‘A and B are
different’ and that ‘B and C are different’, you cannot know whether A and C are the same,
because you do not know the basis of the distinctions between A and B and between B and C.
Note, however, that responding that you ‘cannot know what the relation is’ between A and C is
itself an accurate relational response for the frame of distinction. As you can see from this
example, distinction relational responses may be controlled by the cue "is different from".
Empirical evidence has demonstrated that distinction relations can readily be established in
children with autism using multiple exemplars (Dunne et al., 2014), and Roche and Barnes
(1996), as well as Steele and Hayes (1991), established responding in accordance with
coordination and distinction relations because they specify the relativity between stimuli along
a specific dimension (Barnes-Holmes et al., 2004; Berens & Hayes, 2007). For example, if I
tell you that ‘A is bigger than B’, this specifies the relative difference between the stimuli in
terms of hypothetical size. But, there are many such dimensions for comparison, including
height, weight, color, depth, and so on. Remember, that although physical or formal properties
are being specified here, we are talking about AARRing and language, hence this is not
nonarbitrary responding. For example, if you are told that ‘A is bigger than B and B is bigger
than C’, you can derive that C is smaller than A, even though the stimuli A, B, and C remain
completely unknown. Natural language phrases such as “bigger than”, “smaller than”, “more
than”, and “less than” often serve as contextual cues for the frame of comparison. Empirical
evidence has demonstrated that comparison relations can readily be established in typically-
9
developing children and children with autism using multiple exemplars (Barnes-Holmes,
Barnes-Holmes, Smeets, Strand, & Friman, 2004; Berens & Hayes, 2007; Dunne et al., 2014).
relations, but are restricted to stimuli or events that occur in specific sequences in the natural
environment. Thus, if I tell you that ‘A occurred before B and B occurred before C’, you could
derive that C occurred after A. In natural language, words and phrases such as “before”, “after”,
“followed by”, and “was preceded by” function as cues for temporal relations. Empirical
evidence has thus far focused on establishing this class of relations in adult populations, and
their implications for intelligence and rule‐following (e.g., O’Hora, Barnes-Holmes, Roche, &
Smeets, 2004; O’Hora, Peláez, & Barnes‐Holmes, 2005; O’Hora et al., 2008; O’Toole &
Barnes‐Holmes, 2009).
and is undoubtedly better described in terms of relational networks rather than basic relational
frames (see below). For example, hierarchical relations comprise coordination and distinction
frames. Family trees provide a classic example of hierarchical relational networks. Imagine if I
told you that ‘Ciara is my niece’ (mutually entails that I am Ciara’s aunt) and ‘Margaret is her
mother’ (mutually entails that Ciara is her daughter). This establishes the combinatorially
entailed relation of Margaret and I being sisters. In simple terms, the family tree starts in this
case with two sisters and the generation below contains a daughter of one of the sisters.
Hierarchical relations are like classes that contain members on different levels. Basic
contextual cues, such as “is part of”, “is similar to”, and “is distinct from.” For example, a
steering wheel, a gear stick, a wing mirror, and a bumper could all be defined as parts of a car.
But, the steering wheel and the gear stick could be defined as similar because they are typically
inside the car, but different from the wing mirror and the bumper because they are typically
10
found outside the car. Empirical evidence for hierarchical relations has emerged largely from
studies analoging their potential role in therapeutic interventions, especially ACT (Foody,
Rai, & Luciano, 2015; Gil, Luciano, & Ruíz, 2008; Gil, Luciano, Ruiz, & Valdivia-Salas, 2012;
Gil-Luciano, Ruiz, Valdivia, & Suárez, 2016; Griffee & Dougher, 2002; Luciano et al., 2011;
Ruiz, Hernández, Falcón, & Luciano, 2016; Slattery, & Stewart, 2014; Slattery, Stewart, &
O'Hora, 2011).
Deictic relations. The deictic relations have attracted a great deal of attention in the field
of CBS, most likely because of the pivotal role they play in so-called perspective-taking
Barnes-Holmes, & Barnes-Holmes, 2004). The primary function of deictic relations in natural
language is to allow you to locate yourself verbally in space and time, and in relation to others.
RFT describes the three core deictic relations that go to make up the frame: I versus
YOU/OTHER, HERE versus THERE, and NOW-THEN. RFT suggests that deictic relations
develop through a history of learning to talk about what you are doing where and when, relative
to others. For example, a young child would have to learn to say “I am eating pasta, but my
brother is eating bread”. That is, the deictic relations involve learning to respond verbally from
the perspective of self or I in relation to others about events that occur in specific times and
places.
more basic framing abilities, so that the cues involved in those more basic frames can then be
applied to the deictic relata. For example, the cue “not” (a cue for distinction) would play an
important role in establishing a child’s ability to report “I am eating pasta at the table, but my
brother is not”. There have been many studies of deictic relations that have focused on
developmental assessments (Rehfeldt, Dillen, Ziomek, & Kowalchuk, 2010), and even some
11
examining the impact of training these relations for educational (Heagle & Rehfeldt, 2006;
Weil, Hayes, & Capurro, 2011) and clinical purposes (Villatte, Monestes, McHugh, Baque, &
Loas, 2008; Villatte, Monestes, McHugh, Freixa i Baque, & Loas, 2010).
whereas, others are better considered to involve networks, such as hierarchy and deictics.
Indeed, in one sense, all frames are networks because they involve more than two stimuli. But
in RFT, the term network is typically reserved for instances in which multiple relational frames
become interrelated in the production of relatively complex patterns of behavior, such as rule-
AARRing which we have not yet described and that is referred to as the transformation of
stimulus functions (see Dymond & Barnes, 1995 for the first empirical demonstration). Thus
far, what we have said about AARRing is largely descriptive in the sense that it has focused on
the many relational features of AARRing, such as how stimuli are related to others by mutual
opposition). However, RFT is not a theory of abstract logic or reasoning, but a theory of how
language operates ‘in the real world’. According to RFT, verbally-able humans engage in
AARRing almost constantly about their feelings, thoughts, and reactions to events and stimuli
in the environment, and this involves what is referred to as the transformation of stimulus
functions. Imagine, for example, that a friend tells you that there is a new soft drink that tastes
even better than your favorite. As a result, the evaluative functions of the new drink have been
transformed based on your friend’s advice (i.e., the new drink is better than your favorite drink).
Consequently, the next time you’re asked “What do you want to drink?”, you may order the
12
new soft drink, even though you have never actually tasted this drink before. In this case, your
behavior in the real world has been changed based purely on the process of AARRing.
• RFT concepts have stood the test of time, debate, and experimental scrutiny
extremely well.
• For RFT, language is about relating things together that do not actually go together
in any physical way.
• RFT distinguishes between nonarbitrary relational responding and arbitrarily
applicable relational responding (AARRing).
• AARRing is RFT’s its most basic process.
• Mutual entailment is the most basic analytic unit of AARRing with two stimuli.
• RFT uses combinatorial entailment to describe how relating three or more stimuli
together affects all of the relations among them.
• RFT organizes these patterns of AARRing into relational frames, that include
coordination (sameness), distinction (difference), comparison, opposition,
hierarchy, temporal, and deictic relation.
• The concept of the contextual cue is pivotal in RFT in specifying which relations are
to be derived in a given context.
• Whilst all relational frames are networks because they involve more than two
stimuli, the term network is typically reserved for instances in which multiple
relational frames become interrelated.
• Feelings, thoughts, reactions etc. become part of these relational repertoires through
the transformation of stimulus functions.
The foregoing example of the way in which you can positively evaluate a novel drink
without any direct experience of that drink may be seen as relevant to how AARRing provides
a behavioral explanation for a wide range of clinical phenomena. As a very simple example,
consider how someone might develop an irrational fear or phobia, based on the transformation
13
of stimulus functions. Imagine a young child who is told the story of the three pigs and the big
bad wolf, and is then told at the end of the story that a wolf is a type of dog. Although the child
may have previously had no fear of domestic dogs, they may begin to show some fear or anxiety
around dogs, based purely on the coordinating of dogs with wolves. In this case, the negative
evaluative functions established by the fairytale for wolves transform the evaluative functions
The ability to AARR can be used to explain increasingly complex examples of the ways
in which humans may suffer psychologically. For instance, the ability to relate entire relational
functions. Imagine, for example, a woman who has recently begun to feel trapped in two or
three areas of her life (e.g., work, relationships, and family responsibilities). The extent to which
the word “trapped” is used to describe her struggle in these domains may give rise to bouts of
claustrophobia and panic, when she is required to enter enclosed spaces, including elevators,
subways, and crowded shopping areas. The emergence of so-called claustrophobia and panic
disorder may have little to do with aversive experiences in any of these contexts, but is based
on the transformation of functions of those contexts, because they are related via the term
‘trapped’ to the relational networks that describe work, relationships, and family
responsibilities.
Another example of how AARRing may explain the unique emergence of human
psychological suffering might focus on the development of the verbal self in the context of early
family relationships. Imagine a young boy who is subject to physical and emotional abuse by a
parent over a period of years. The parent may literally abuse the child one moment and then
say, for example, “You know that I love you” the next moment. The fact that the parent employs
language in a manner that is entirely incoherent with the way in which the wider verbal
community employs that language may undermine the child’s ability in later life to connect in
14
a healthy way with other adults who did not experience this verbal fracturing between normative
and unhealthy languaging by his parent (i.e., being told he is loved by an abusive parent). In
simple terms, a frame of coordination has been established for the child between feeling abused
and feeling loved. Not surprisingly, the child may find it challenging in later life to form a close
and intimate relationship with someone who is not abusive towards him in some way.
of AARRing, it highlights the importance of focusing on the role of language during the process
of therapy. In the case of the woman who developed claustrophobia and panic disorder above,
in the context of feeling trapped in several domains in her life, it may be useful in therapy to
focus on the word ‘trapped’ itself. For example, in exploring the functional properties of
‘trapped’, the therapist might literally hold the client’s wrists gently and ask her to describe
how it feels to be trapped by someone else. During the process of therapy, engaging in this
physical metaphor may help the client to see the connections between the claustrophobia/panic
and the wider unhappy features of her life, and to then explore her reactions to these in ways
that are values-driven, rather than values-disabling (e.g., consider changing jobs, sharing her
15
• AARRing provides a behavioral explanation for a wide range of clinical phenomena.
• For example, an individual might develop an irrational fear or phobia, based on the
• Highly abstract transformations of functions may involve the ability to relate entire
• This ability may explain patterns of suffering such as claustrophobia and panic, even
• Another example of how AARRing may explain psychological suffering might focus
on the development of the verbal self in the context of early family relationships.
Conclusions
In the Introduction, we noted that RFT was linked closely to ACT and indeed it is true
that the theory and the application certainly co-evolved closely in the early years. More recently,
however, ACT has developed the hexaflex as its own scientific model, which specifies six
etc.). While those individuals who are highly familiar with the early history of ACT and RFT
may readily see how such terms connect to the functional analysis of verbal behavior that RFT
provides, others who are less familiar may not. Thus, it seems important to continue to explore
exactly how the technical terms and concepts of RFT might be used to understand human
psychological suffering and to treat it in the context of psychotherapy. The current chapter
16
References
Barnes-Holmes, Y. (2001). Analysing relational frames: Studying language and cognition in
Barnes-Holmes, D., Barnes-Holmes, Y., Hussey, I., & Luciano, C. (2016). Relational frame
theory: finding its historical and intellectual roots and reflecting upon its future
The Wiley handbook of contextual behavioral science (pp. 115-128), West Sussex, UK:
Wiley-Blackwell.
Barnes-Holmes, D., Barnes-Holmes, Y., & McEnteggart, C. (in press). Evolution and
Hayes, S. C., & Wilson, D. S. (Eds.). Evolution and contextual behavioral science: A
Barnes-Holmes, Y., Barnes-Holmes, D., Smeets, P. M., Strand, P., & Friman, P. (2004). Testing
and training relational responding in accordance with the relational frame of opposite in
559-586.
Barnes-Holmes, Y., Foody, M., & Barnes-Holmes, D. (2013). Deictic relations and
Barnes-Holmes, Y., Hayes, S. C., Barnes-Holmes, D. & Roche, B. (2001). Relational frame
40(1), 45-71.
17
Carr, D., Wilkinson, K. M., Blackman, D., & McIlvane, W. J. (2000). Equivalence classes in
Dixon, M. R., & Zlomke, K. M. (2005). Using the precursor to the relational evaluation
305-316.
Dougher, M. J., Hamilton, D. A., Fink, B. C., & Harrington, J. (2007). Transformation of the
Dunne, S., Foody, M., Barnes-Holmes, Y., Barnes-Holmes, D., & Murphy, C. (2014).
in accordance with the arbitrarily applicable relations of sameness, more‐than, and less‐
Foody, M., Barnes-Holmes, Y., Barnes-Holmes, D., Rai, L., & Luciano, C. (2015). An
empirical investigation of the role of self, hierarchy, and distinction in a common act
Foody, M., Barnes-Holmes, Y., Barnes-Holmes, D., & Luciano, C. (2013). An empirical
Gil, E., Luciano, C., Ruiz, F. J. & Valdivia-Salas, S. (2012). A preliminary demonstration of
18
Gil, E., Luciano, C., & Ruíz, F. (2008). Transformacion de functiones via el contexto
Gil-Luciano, B., Ruiz, F. J., Valdivia, S., & Suárez, J. C. (2016). Promoting psychological
Griffee, K., & Dougher, M. J. (2002). Contextual control of stimulus generalization and
Hayes, S. C., Barnes‐Holmes, D., & Roche, B. (2001). Relational frame theory: A post-
Skinnerian account of human language and cognition. New York, NY: Plenum.
Hayes, S. C., Strosahl, K., & Wilson, K. G. (1999). Acceptance and Commitment Therapy: An
Hughes, S., & Barnes-Holmes, D. (2016a). Relational frame theory: The basic account. In R.
Hughes, S., & Barnes-Holmes, D. (2016b). Relational frame theory: Implications for the study
A. Biglan (Eds), The Wiley handbook of contextual behavioral science (pp. 179-226),
Hughes, S., Barnes‐Holmes, D., & Vahey, N. (2012). Holding on to our functional roots when
19
Hughes. S., De Houwer, J., & Barnes‐Holmes, D. (2014). On how contextual behavioral science
Kissi, A., Hughes, S., Mertens, G., Barnes-Holmes, D., De Houwer, J., & Crombez, G. (2017).
https://doi.org/10.1177/0145445517693811
Leonhard, C., & Hayes, S. C. (1991, May). Prior inconsistent testing affects equivalence
responding. Paper presented at the meeting of the Association for Behavior Analysis,
Atlanta.
Lipkens, G., Hayes, S. C., & Hayes, L. J. (1993). Longitudinal study of derived stimulus
Luciano, C., Gomez-Becerra, I. G., & Rodriguez-Valverde, M. R. (2007). The role of multiple‐
Luciano, C., Rodríguez, M., Mañas, I., Ruiz, F., & Valdivia-Salas, S. (2009). Acquiring the
progressive guide to change (pp. 149-172). US: New Harbinger, Context Press.
Luciano, C., Ruiz, F. J., Vizcaíno Torres, V., Sánchez Martin, V., Gutiérrez Martinez, O., &
20
Rehfeldt, R. A., Dillen, J. E., Ziomek, M. M., & Kowalchuk, R. K. (2010). Assessing relational
Roche, B., & Barnes, D. (1996). Arbitrarily applicable relational responding and sexual
Ruiz, F. J., Hernández, D. R., Falcón, J. C. S., & Luciano, C. (2016). Effect of a one-session
233.
O'Connor, J., Rafferty, A., Barnes-Holmes, D., & Barnes-Holmes, Y. (2009). The role of verbal
autistic and normally developing children. The Psychological Record, 59(10), 53-74.
O’Hora, D., Barnes‐Holmes, D., Roche, B., & Smeets, P. M. (2004). Derived relational
O’Hora, D., Pelaez, M., & Barnes‐Holmes, D. (2005). Derived relational responding and
performance on verbal subtests of the WAIS‐III. The Psychological Record, 55(1), 155.
O’Hora, D., Pelaez, M., Barnes‐Holmes, D., Rae, G., Robinson, K., & Chaudhary, T. (2008).
O’Toole, C., & Barnes‐Holmes, D. (2009). Three chronometric indices of relational responding
21
Slattery, B., & Stewart, I. (2014). Hierarchical classification as relational framing. Journal of
Slattery, B., Stewart, I., & O'Hora, D. (2011). Testing for transitive class containment as a
Steele, D., & Hayes, S. C. (1991). Stimulus equivalence and arbitrarily applicable relational
Tornëke, N. (2010). Learning RFT: An introduction to relational frame theory and its clinical
Villatte, M., Monestes, J. L., McHugh, L., Baque, E. F. i, & Loas, G. (2008). Assessing deictic
Villatte, M., Monestes, J. L., McHugh, L., Freixa i Baque, E., & Loas, G. (2010). Assessing
Villatte, M., Villatte, J. L., & Hayes, S. C. (2015). Mastering the clinical conversation:
Weil, T. M., Hayes, S. C., & Capurro, P. (2011). Establishing a deictic relational repertoire in
tntroduction to Part III. In R.D. Zettle, S.C. Hayes, D. Barnes-Holmes, & A. Biglan
(Eds), The Wiley handbook of contextual behavioral science (pp. 275-286), West
22