Moore 1998
Moore 1998
Moore 1998
1, 1998
We argue that greater precision is needed in the use of the term distributed
cognition if this perspective is to significantly impact educational research. We
describe a continuum of interpretations of distributed cognition ranging from
a conceptualization of cognition as an individual phenomenon that is
influenced by factors external to the individual, to a conceptualization of
cognition as a social phenomenon that cannot be reduced to individual
psychological constructs. We discuss the issues raised by the papers in the
current volume, and locate the perspectives taken in these papers along the
distributed cognition continuum. The relationship between distributed cognition
and situated cognition is then examined, as these terms are often used
interchangeably. Finally, we discuss key issues for further research in distributed
cognition.
KEY WORDS: distributed cognition; situated cognition; context; commentary; educational
psychology.
INTRODUCTION
97
1040-726X/98/0300-0097$15.00/0 © 1998 Plenum Publishing Corporation
98 Moore and Rocklin
meaning is lost (Nash, 1993). This is not a unique phenomenon in the edu-
cational literature. Terms such as "schema," "mental model," "situated cog-
nition" (Lave, 1991), and "structure" (Phillips, 1993) have suffered similar
fates. These terms are used by educational researchers to refer to diverse
constructs and processes, weakening their original power to describe im-
portant phenomena. In order to be informative, a term such as distributed
cognition must distinguish research in some way from research done under
other rubrics. The danger that follows from vague application of a term is
that the term will be used to sanction a piece of work, but have no impact
on either the implementation or interpretation of the work.
We believe that the emerging perspective of distributed cognition has
the potential to significantly influence educational research. Our goal in
this paper is to describe the landscape of distributed cognition, with the
hope that this will help avert a slide into "fuzzy generality of reference"
(Nash, 1993, p. 58). We summarize the issues addressed by the papers in
the current volume, describe several interpretations of distributed cogni-
tion, and then locate these papers along a continuum of distributed cog-
nition perspectives. We then briefly consider the relationship between
distributed cognition and situated cognition, as these terms are sometimes
used interchangeably. Finally, we present the key issues we see for further
research in distributed cognition.
Although the papers in this issue are quite diverse, the authors assume
that the more cognition is distributed the better a system (i.e., a pair of
Interpretations of Distributed Cognition 101
"distributed among people and their environment, including the objects, ar-
tifacts, tools, books, and the communities of which they are a part" (p. 17).
Although labeled as "situative," this position shares much with the interpre-
tations of distributed cognition. There are strong similarities between the
various interpretations of distributed and situated cognition, critiques of the
positions (e.g., Vera and Simon, 1993; Anderson, Reder, and Simon, 1996),
and applications of the positions to the development of learning environ-
ments and empirical work (e.g., Salomon, Perkins, and Globerson, 1991;
Young, 1993; Choi and Hannafin, 1995). Lave (1991) has differentiated three
genres of situated approaches that help illustrate the similarities of these ap-
proaches to the interpretations of distributed cognition.
In an approach Lave labeled "cognition plus," research on individual
cognition remains unchallenged, but social factors are now considered as
one of many influences on individual cognition. The view of situated cog-
nition that Lave has described as cognition plus and the individual-plus
view of distributed cognition are similar both in name and concept. In ad-
dition, they are both similar to Perkins' (1993) notion of "person-plus" to
describe a person and the surround as the proper unit of analysis. These
positions do not challenge the tenets of current information-processing psy-
chology but encourage the exploration of additional factors that might in-
fluence individual cognition.
In a second approach that Lave labeled "interpretative," situatedness
is found in language and/or social interaction. There is no world inde-
pendent of individuals' construction of it, and meanings are located in ne-
gotiated social interaction. Here the term "situated" is not physical but
social. The position that Lave has labeled interpretive does not seem to
have a direct counterpart in the distributed cognition literature, and it
seems most closely aligned with a radical constructivist position (e.g., von
Glasersfeld, 1984, 1990).
Lave labeled the third approach "situated social practice," which is
similar to the social-only position. In this approach, learning is a relation
among people "engaged in activity in, with, and arising from the socially and
culturally structured world" (Lave, 1991, p. 67, emphasis in original). Cog-
nition is situated in the historical development of ongoing activity. The situ-
ated cognition genre that Lave has labeled situated social practice and the
distributed cognition genre that Salomon (1993a,b) has described as cog-
nition as an irreducibly social phenomena are also similar. It is significant
that Lave is often cited as a source for both these positions (e.g., in Salo-
mon, 1993a,b for distributed cognition; in Greeno, Collins, and Resnick,
1996 for situated cognition).
Despite the similarities between distributed and situated cognition out-
lined above, and the fact that many researchers do not distinguish between
106 Moore and Rocklin
these terms in practice, Pea (1993) reserves the term "situated" to mean
tied to the physical world. Pea's interpretation of the situated approach
emphasizes that a reasoner can exploit features of the physical world, avoid-
ing the need to perform mental symbol manipulations unless necessary
(e.g., Scribner, 1988). He also criticizes the work on situated cognition for
failing to acknowledge the fundamental role of artifact design in the activity
of the reasoners, which he sees as an important contribution of distributed
cognition. However, it should be noted that the proponents of situated cog-
nition explicitly include the social, as well as the physical world, as impor-
tant aspects of their position (e.g., Lave and Wenger, 1991; Suchman, 1987;
Greeno, Smith, and Moore, 1993; Greeno et al., 1996).
In our view, much of the work labeled as situated or distributed cogni-
tion falls under the cognition/individual-plus rubric, and seems equally well
described by either nomenclature. Thus, at this point, it is not clear that the
distinction is useful. A more useful distinction might be how the individual
is conceived, as in the distinction between individual-plus and social-only. We
believe that this distinction will continue to be pivotal for work in distributed
cognition; research questions, methodologies, and empirical findings will be
organized around this theme, implicitly or explicitly. In the next section, we
discuss several issues that we believe are important, but understudied, with
respect to distributed cognition. These issues may be viewed differently from
the individual-plus or social-only perspectives but need to be addressed re-
gardless of perspective. One important issue is the development or adoption
of research methodologies to address new concerns raised by distributed cog-
nition. A central question is whether methodologists should focus on indi-
viduals interacting with other people and artifacts, the functioning of a
cognitive system, or some combination of the two. Another key issue contin-
ues to be the role of information-processing constructs in the development
of a theory of cognition as distributed. Will information-processing constructs
continue to have a role in the study of distributed cognition, or will they be
replaced by other theoretical constructs? Finally, those who study distributed
cognition have highlighted the functioning of individuals in groups, raising
questions about the role of individual differences in group activity, as well as
the political dimensions of individual interaction.
nition raise the possibility that psychologists may need to study issues that
have traditionally been the venue of other social sciences.
According to Salomon (1993b), the individual-plus approach implies
that studies should neither be restricted to individuals, nor controlled, ar-
tificial settings. These properties are illustrated by each of the papers in
this issue. Peer tutoring in a classroom setting, group meetings, patients'
histories collected by medical personnel, and a classroom database are
naturalistic settings that involve the interaction of multiple individuals.
Salomon (1993b) also distinguishes the division of cognitive labor from
shared cognitive labor. The division of cognitive labor involves an individual
shifting cognitive responsibility onto a tool(s) or a person(s). When con-
sidering the division of labor, the focus is on the individual. In contrast,
shared cognitive labor occurs when individuals jointly engage in some ac-
tivity. This is collaborative activity, where each action has the potential to
change the joint activity. When considering shared cognitive labor, the fo-
cus is on the cognition of multiple individuals. King's study (1998) of peer
tutoring illustrates this distinction. King characterizes peer tutoring as in-
volving a student off-loading cognitive responsibilities onto another student
as well as onto the tutoring instructions. In addition, she discusses the proc-
ess by which both students jointly engage in understanding written material.
Although the individual-plus approach may shift the research focus, it does
not seem to require a departure from current research techniques.
A tenet of the social-only interpretation of distributed cognition is that
the "mind" cannot be studied independently of the culturally organized set-
tings within which people function. However, it is not obvious what it means
operationally to study the person/environment as an "indivisible unit of
study" (Hewitt and Scardamalia, 1998). The individual-plus approach con-
ceptualizes cognition as divided among an individual, objects, and other peo-
ple; whereas the social-only approach conceptualizes cognition as "stretched
over" people and objects (Lave, 1991). Hewitt and Scardamalia are not pri-
marily concerned with the individual work of the children in CSILE class-
rooms, choosing instead to look at the behavior of the classroom as a whole.
APPLICABILITY OF INFORMATION-PROCESSING
CONSTRUCTS
Can the techniques and constructs that have developed in the study
of individual cognition be applied to the study of distributed cognition?
Clearly, there are varying positions on this issue within the distributed cog-
nition approaches. Salomon (1993b) and Derry et al. (1998) explicitly state
that they are attempting to apply the constructs of individual cognition to
108 Moore and Rocklin
the study of groups. Intriguing questions are raised about whether the proc-
esses of cognition that are distributed are the same as the processes of
individual cognition. If one imposes the psychology of individuals on
groups, then groups must have memory and memory processes. Where do
short-term memory and long-term memory get stored in distributed sys-
tems? Do groups have metacognition? Even from a stance in which indi-
vidual cognition plays an important role, the processes and structures of
information-processing psychology may not map onto group cognition.
Nickerson (1993) suggests that individual cognition and distributed cogni-
tion are so different that different terms should be used.
Hutchins (1995a) takes the more intermediate stance that the same infor-
mation-processing constructs applicable to individuals are applicable to groups,
buy they are manifested differently at the individual and group level. He be-
lieves that systems larger than individuals have cognitive properties in their own
right that are not reducible to the cognitive properties of individuals. Hutchins
applies the classical cognitive science approach to a unit of analysis that is larger
than a person, and has developed a model to demonstrate that a cognitive prop-
erty such as confirmation bias or memory retrieval efficiency is manifested dif-
ferently at the individual and group level (Hutchins, 1991, 1995b).
Finally, the proponents of the social-only approach to distributed cog-
nition claim that information-processing constructs have fundamentally dis-
torted the study of cognition. There is no room for information-processing
constructs in this perspective unless one can characterize the social inter-
action that produces shared understanding.
GROUP ACTIVITY
mental level, the study of cognition is about the ways in which information
is transformed by various units or processes. In traditional information-
processing models these units might be sensory memory, working memory,
and long term memory. In a model of distributed cognition, the units must
include, at some level, the people (as well as the inanimate tools) involved
in the interaction. The differences among these people have important im-
plications for how the information flows and is transformed in the system.
Consider, for example, one way in which people involved in a distrib-
uted cognition process might differ. Some of the people might be women,
and others men. As Tannen (1994) has pointed out, men and women in
many situations—including work—communicate in qualitatively and quan-
titatively different ways. Men are more likely to see asking questions as
putting the questioner in a weak position. They are therefore more reluc-
tant to ask questions and are more careful about when and where they ask
questions. Another example involves what Tannen calls "ritual opposition."
Men more frequently engage in heated arguments and more vigorously at-
tack each other and each other's ideas. Frequently, women respond to these
attacks without accepting their ritual nature. They may give up on a idea
that is challenged, assuming that the vigor of the challenge is an indication
of the low quality of their idea.
Both of these examples suggest that a model of distributed cognition
that does not consider the gender of the group members is seriously in-
complete. If men and women differ in the situations and ways in which
they ask questions, is it possible to understand the processes involved in
the ASK to THINK–TEL WHY interactions (King, 1998) without includ-
ing gender in the analysis? Similarly, if one wants to understand—as do
Derry et al. (1998)—why certain ideas are included in a "to-do" list and
others are not, it might be relevant to examine the gender of the originator
of each of the ideas.
Gender is not the only characteristic that affects the ways in which
people communicate. Another example involves the role of status and
power in the use of indirectness. Messages can vary from quite direct
("Please type, proof, and print this by 3:00.") to quite indirect ("Do you
think you have time to type this this afternoon?"). The use of indirectness
is quite complex, but there are clearly some situations in which low power
and status are associated with indirectness. Imagine, for example, the dis-
tributed cognition of a faculty surgeon and a surgical resident (i.e., a sur-
geon in training). As they work to mobilize the patient's colon, the resident
might remark, as though asking for information, "Is that linear structure
you're considering cutting the ureter?" rather than saying "Stop, you're
about to cut the ureter!" This example speaks directly to the question of
which properties of cognition are distributed and how those properties are
110 Moore and Rocklin
distributed. In this case, the skills, knowledge, and other attributes (perhaps
including simply location at the operating table) needed to recognize an
anatomical structure are at least slightly unevenly distributed. Whether the
problem (i.e., cutting the right structures and leaving other structures in-
tact) is solved effectively depends on how knowledge, skills, and informa-
tion are distributed with respect to status and power. More specifically, the
problem is more likely to be solved effectively if the knowledge, skills, and
information are associated with high status and power.
To close, we emphasize two points. First, the examples we cite involve
mean differences between groups of people (e.g., between men and
women). Although it is of interest to know that particular ways of commu-
nicating are associated with particular characteristics of the communicators,
it is likely more important to study the variety of ways in which people
communicate (e.g., use of questions) and to include those in models of
distributed cognition than it is to study the group differences. We expect
that although such subject variables as gender might provide an appropriate
starting point, ultimately effective models of distributed cognition will in-
clude styles of communication, for example, rather than these subject vari-
ables. In other words, ritual opposition is more common among men than
women, but it is the ritual opposition, whether it comes from a man or a
woman, that is of interest. Secondly, we emphasize that the examples we
have chosen are intended only to be illustrative. We make no claims that
these are the most important issues in the domain of communication styles
for distributed cognition researchers to consider.
POLITICAL CONTEXT
CONCLUSIONS
REFERENCES
Anderson, J. R., Reder, L. M., and Simon, H. A. (1996). Situated learning and education.
Educ. Res. 25(4): 5-11.
Brown, A. L., Ash, D., Rutherford, M., Nakagawa, K., Gordon, A., and Campione, J. (1993).
Distributed expertise in the classroom. In Salomon, G. (ed.), Distributed Cognitions: Psy-
chological and Educational Considerations, Cambridge University Press, New York, pp.
188-228.
Choi, J., and Hannafin, M. (1995). Situated cognition and learning environments: Roles, struc-
tures, and implications for design. Educ. Technol. Res. Devel. 43(2): 53-69.
Cobb, P., and Yackel, E. (1996). Constructivist, emergent, and sociocultural perspectives in
the context of developmental research. Educ. Psychol. 31(3/4): 175-190.
112 Moore and Rocklin
Deny, S. J., DuRussel, L. A., and O'Donnell, A. M. (1998). Individual and distributed cog-
nitions in interdisciplinary teamwork: A developing case study and emerging theory. Educ.
Psychol. Rev. 10: 25-56.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, Houghton Mifflin, Boston.
Greeno, J. G. (1994). Gibson's affordances. Psychol. Rev. 101(2): 336-342.
Greeno, J. G., Smith, D. R., and Moore, J. L. (1993). Transfer of situated learning. In Det-
terman, D. K., and Sternberg, R. J. (eds.), Transfer on Trial: Intelligence, Cognition, and
Instruction, Ablex, Norwood, NJ, pp. 99-167.
Greeno, J. G., Collins, A., and Resnick, L. (1996). Cognition and learning. In Berliner, D.,
and Calfee, R. (eds.), Handbook of Educational Psychology, Simon and Schuster Macmil-
lan, New York, pp. 15-46.
Hewitt, J., and Scardamalia, M. (1998). Design principles for distributed knowledge building
processes. Educ. Psychol. Rev. 10: 75-96.
Hutchins, E. (1991). The social organization of distributed cognition. In Resnick, L. B., Levine,
J. B., and Teasley, S. D. (eds.), Perspectives on Socially Shared Cognition, American Psy-
chological Association, Washington, DC, pp. 283-307.
Hutchins, E. (1995a). How a cockpit remembers its speeds. Cogn. Sci. 19: 265-288.
Hutchins, E. (1995b). Cognition in the Wild, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA,
King, A. (1998). Transactive peer tutoring: Distributing cognition and metacognition. Educ.
Psychol. Rev. 10: 57-74.
Lave, J. (1988). Cognition in Practice: Mind, Mathematics, and Culture in Everyday Life, Cam-
bridge University Press, Cambridge.
Lave, J. (1991). Situating learning in communities of practice. In Resnick, L. B., Levine, J.
M., and Teasley, S. D. (eds.), Perspectives on Socially Shared Cognition, American Psycho-
logical Association, Washington, DC, pp. 63-82.
Lave, J., and Wenger, E. (1991). Situated Learning: Legitimate Peripheral Participation, Cam-
bridge University Press, Cambridge.
Lebeau, R. (1998). Cognitive tools in a clinical encounter in medicine: Supporting empathy
and expertise in distributed systems. Educ. Psychol. Rev. 10: 3-24.
Linde, C. (1988). The quantitative study of communicative success: Politeness and accidents
in aviation discourse. Lang. Soc. 17: 375-399.
Moschkovich, J. N. (1996). Moving up and getting shorter: Negotiating shared descriptions
of linear graphs. J. Learn. Sci. 5: 241-279.
Nardi, B. (1996). Studying context: A comparison of activity theory, situated action models,
and distributed cognition. In Nardi, B. (ed.), Context and Consciousness: Activity Theory
and Human-Computer Interaction, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 69-102.
Nash, W. (1993). Jargon: Its Uses and Abuses, Blackwell, Cambridge, MA.
Newman, D., Griffin, P., and Cole, M. (1989). The Construction Zone: Working for Cognitive
Change in School, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Nickerson, R. S. (1993). On the distribution of cognition: Some reflections. In Salomon, G.
(ed.), Distributed Cognitions: Psychological and Educational Considerations, Cambridge
University Press, New York, pp. 229-261.
Pea, R. (1993). Practices of distributed intelligence and designs for education. In Salomon,
G. (ed.), Distributed Cognitions: Psychological and Educational Considerations, Cambridge
University Press, New York, pp. 47-87.
Perkins, D. N. (1993). Person-plus: A distributed view of thinking and learning. In Salomon,
G. (ed.), Distributed Cognitions: Psychological and Educational Considerations, Cambridge
University Press, New York, pp. 88-110.
Phillips, D. C. (1993). Paul Hirst's structure, or, the uses and abuses of an overworked concept.
In Barrow, R., and White, P. (eds.), Beyond Liberal Education: Essays in Honor of Paul
H. Hirst, Routledge, New York, pp. 79-93.
Reed, E. S. (1988). James Gibson's ecological approach to cognition. In Costall, A., and Still,
A. (eds.), Cognitive Psychology in Question, St. Martin's Press, New York, pp. 142-173.
Resnick, L. B. (1991). Shared cognition: Thinking as social practice. In Resnick, L B., Levine,
J. M., and Teasley, S. D. (eds.), Perspectives on Socially Shared Cognition, American Psy-
chological Association, Washington, DC, pp. 1-20.
Interpretations of Distributed Cognition 113