2019.responsibility and Limited Liability in Decision Making For Others An Experimental Consideration
2019.responsibility and Limited Liability in Decision Making For Others An Experimental Consideration
2019.responsibility and Limited Liability in Decision Making For Others An Experimental Consideration
PII: S0167-4870(18)30647-0
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.joep.2019.06.009
Reference: JOEP 2186
Please cite this article as: Füllbrunn, S., Luhan, W.J., Responsibility and Limited Liability in Decision Making for
Others - An experimental consideration, Journal of Economic Psychology (2019), doi: https://doi.org/10.1016/
j.joep.2019.06.009
This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication. As a service to our customers
we are providing this early version of the manuscript. The manuscript will undergo copyediting, typesetting, and
review of the resulting proof before it is published in its final form. Please note that during the production process
errors may be discovered which could affect the content, and all legal disclaimers that apply to the journal pertain.
Responsibility and Limited Liability in Decision Making
∗ †‡
Sascha Füllbrunn, and Wolfgang J. Luhan
Abstract
Agency in nancial markets has been claimed to foster excessive risk taking, ultimately
leading to bubble formation. The main driving factor appears to be the skewed bonus
system for agents who invest other people's money. The resulting excessive risk taking
on behalf of others would imply that such bonus systems crowds out responsible decision
making for others in order to serve egoistic self-interest. To test this implication, we
conduct laboratory experiments comparing decision making for others with and without
such a bonus system. First, we show that, in the absence of bonus systems, decision makers
invested signicantly less for others than for themselves. Second, we show that limited
liable decision makersparticipating only in gains but not in lossesinvested substantially
more for others than for themselves. Hence, our results suggest that indeed limited liability
outweighs responsibility.
JEL: C91, D03, D81, G11
Keywords: nancial decision making, responsibility, limited liability, decision making for others, risk preferences,
experiment
∗ Radboud University, Institute for Management Research, Department of Economics, Heyendaalseweg 141,
of Portsmouth, Radboud University, as well as conference participants of ESA meetings in Zurich, Dallas,
Berlin, and Florida and of the SEF meeting at Radboud Univerity for valuable comments; in particular, we
thank participants of the Decision Making for Others Meeting at Radboud University in 2018. We gratefully
acknowledge funding by the Ruhr-University Bochum's Young Researchers Funds.
Responsibility and Limited Liability in Decision Making
∗
double-blind no author
Abstract
Agency in nancial markets has been claimed to foster excessive risk taking, ultimately
leading to bubble formation. The main driving factor appears to be the skewed bonus
system for agents who invest other people's money. The resulting excessive risk taking
on behalf of others would imply that such bonus systems crowds out responsible decision
making for others in order to serve egoistic self-interest. To test this implication, we
conduct laboratory experiments comparing decision making for others with and without
such a bonus system. First, we show that, in the absence of bonus systems, decision makers
invested signicantly less for others than for themselves. Second, we show that limited
liable decision makersparticipating only in gains but not in lossesinvested substantially
more for others than for themselves. Hence, our results suggest that indeed limited liability
outweighs responsibility.
JEL: C91, D03, D81, G11
Keywords: nancial decision making, responsibility, limited liability, decision making for others, risk preferences,
experiment
1
1 Introduction
Economic research on risk attitudes has traditionally focused on individual decision making
without much consideration for potential social inuences (see e.g., Dohmen et al., 2011; Eckel
and Grossman, 2008b; Harbaugh et al., 2010; Holt and Laury, 2002). As real world decisions are
embedded in a social context however, a decision maker is hardly ever the only person aected
by the consequences of his actions. In fact, many risky decisions are specically taken on behalf
of a third party, e.g. the decision maker's family or business partners. On a larger scale,
a CEO's decision might aect the company or even industry, and political decisions aect a
country's future. On nancial markets, investors usually put an investment adviser or a money
manager in charge of their risky investments. It has been a long standing claimespecially
since the last nancial crisisthat this practice of delegated portfolio investment, with its
skewed bonus systems, leads to excessive risk-taking and ultimately to bubble formation (e.g.,
Allen and Gorton, 1993). Taking excessive risks with the clients' money is largely attributed
to the limited liability payment schemes prevalent in these markets (Allen and Gorton, 1993;
Allen and Gale, 2000; Cheung and Coleman, 2014; Kleinlercher et al., 2014). However, the
question remains whether such payment schemes alter the money managers' behaviour towards
To answer this question, we study investment decisions for others in a laboratory experiment
in conditions with and without limited liability. First, we try to establish whether agency
without or with perfectly aligned monetary incentive schemes increases risk taking for others.
Second, we introduce limited liability with the propensity to privatize prots and socialize
losses to see whether this aects risk taking for others. We are the rst to consider such a
The terms risky shift and cautious shift introduced by Stoner (1961) describe situations
in which the initial individual level of risk preference is altered due to exogenous impacts.
Without any prior assumptions, taking responsibility for others could result in a shift in either
direction.
self-other distance (e.g., Beisswanger et al., 2003; Cvetkovich, 1972; Stone and Allgaier, 2008;
Trope and Liberman, 2010; Wray and Stone, 2005), in which the assessment of a potential loss
in a risky situation is decreasing in the distance of the aected party to the decision maker.
This nding translates directly to the results from economic experiments which report a risky
2
shift in hypothetical risk taking without monetary consequences (e.g., Harrison, 2006; Holt and
Laury, 2002, 2005). Albrecht et al. (2011) nd that making inter-temporal decisions for others
results in lesser activation of areas of the brain that are thought to be engaged in emotion and
reward-related processes, than when taking decisions for oneself. The resulting argument would
be that decisions made on behalf of a third party are equivalent to situations without any real
outcome.
nation for a cautious shift. Taking responsibility for a third party's welfare induces pro-social
behavior which results in conservative risk taking (Charness, 2000; Charness and Jackson, 2009).
Several studies report a cautious shift. Physicians, for example, have been found to prefer treat-
ments with higher mortality rates for themselves than what they recommend to their patients
(Garcia-Retamero and Galesic, 2012; Ubel et al., 2011). Managers also try to avoid responsibil-
ity for decisions with even a minimal probability of hazardous outcomes (Swalm, 1966; Viscusi
et al., 1987). Using controlled laboratory experiments, we aim to ultimately determine whether
agency in risky nancial decisions leads to increased risk taking and what role limited liability
In our experiment, a decision maker (henceforth money manager) took investment decisions
for himself and for six other subjects (henceforth clients) using the investment environment
from Gneezy and Potters (1997). First, we tested whether the money manager invests more
or lesstook more or less riskfor himself than for his clients. In the individual decision
making treatment `IND', the money manager invested for himself only. Further, we needed a
treatment in which the money manager invests for his clients onlywithout any own payo
payosdenoted as treatment `ALL'in which the money manager invests the same amount
for himself AND for his clients; here, IND and OTH were combined in one decision. With
this treatment, we can see whether the money manager invests in line with his egoistic pref-
erencesinvests the same amount in IND and in ALLor whether he steps back to invest in
line with his social preferencesinvests the same in OTH and ALL. Therefore, we adminis-
tered a within-subjects design to enable the analysis of individual heterogeneity controlling for
order eects. Our study is the rst to systematically compare these theoretically very dierent
situations. Second, we implemented limited liability by replacing OTH with a new treatment
`LIM'. Here, the money manager earns a xed percentage from each client's prot, while an
investment failure has no monetary consequence for the money manager. In general, such an
option-like payment scheme increases risk taking already in individual decision making. The
3
question is, however, whether the money manager takes excessive risks with the clients' money
to increase his own payo, suggesting rather anti-social behaviour. Here, we compare LIM to
Our aggregate results indicate investment behavior to be in line with responsibility alle-
viation, as we observed a clear cautious shift. The money managers invested signicantly
less when clients bore the consequences (OTH), even when the money manager's payo was
perfectly aligned (ALL). Limited liability, however, changes the picture drastically; money man-
agers show a signicant risky shift and invest signicantly more in LIM than in OTH. Limited
2 Related Literature
In recent years a growing body of literature has studied risky decisions for others using economic
experimentsnding mixed results. Some studies nd evidence for a risky shift using rst price
sealed bid auctions and multiple price lists (Chakravarty et al., 2011) or investment decisions
(Polman, 2012; Pollmann et al., 2014; Sutter, 2009). In contrast, plenty of studies nd evidence
for a cautious shift using lottery choices (Reynolds et al., 2009; Bolton and Ockenfels, 2010),
investment decisions (Eriksen and Kvaløy, 2010), or strategic risk taking in stag-hunt games
(Charness and Jackson, 2009). Pahlke et al. (2015) nd both, a risky shift in the loss domain and
a cautious shift in the gain domain using a battery of lotteries. Finally, using a multiple price list
Andersson et al. (2016) nd little evidence for a signicant shift in either direction. All studies
listed above consider ` risk taking for others '. They focus on the dierence between making a
decision for oneself and making the same decision for an anonymous stranger. However, there
are important dierences in the decision maker's payo when making decisions for others. Either
the decision maker decides for the others only and earns a lump sum payment independent of
the client's earnings (OTH), or the decision maker makes the same decision for himself and
the others with equal payo consequences (ALL). The previous studies on decision making
rational behavior predict similar investments in IND and ALL, based on the decision maker's
in OTH (Eriksen and Kvaløy, 2010). We conduct a systematic study of the impact of these two
types of decision making for others, by implementing both treatments using a within-subjects
design.
1 The only exception is the study by Andersson et al. (2016). However, they do not discuss theoretical
dierences nor do they compare OTH and ALL in their analysis.
4
Convex incentive structures in nancial institutions seem to foster excessive risk taking in
nancial markets, which is supposed to be one of the causes for market bubbles (e.g., Bebchuk
and Spamann, 2009; Dewatripont et al., 2010; French et al., 2010; Gennaioli et al., 2012). Ra-
jan (2006) even argues that one of the main origins of instability in highly developed nancial
markets are widely used convex incentives structures. In many cases, the managers' incentives
are barely aligned with the investors' interests. The agency problem of misaligned incentives
of money managers and their clients and its eects on markets is theoretically considered by
Allen and Gorton (1993); money managers do not share the losses but earn a proportion of the
prots. Such a convex incentive structure induces the money managers to trade at prices above
fundamental value, causing a price bubble. Holmen et al. (2014) tested this conjecture exper-
imentally and found convex incentives to inate prices. However, the experimental literature
only s convex incentive structures and the eects on markets. What appears to be missing are
the eects on investment decisions when clients are immediately aected, i.e. when a money
manager is investing the clients' money facing convex incentive structures. We aim to ll this
gap.
which is an established tool to elicit investment decisions under dierent conditions. The amount
invested provides a good metric for capturing treatment eects and dierences in attitudes to-
ward risk taking between individuals; see Charness et al. (2013) for a detailed discussion. We
consider four dierent decision environments: individual decision making ('IND'), decision mak-
ing for others ('OTH'), decision making for others and for oneself ('ALL'), and decision making
under limited liability ('LIM') using a mixture of within- and between-subject comparisons.
euro and was asked to decide on the amount to invest in a risky asset.
2 With a probability of
2/3 the amount invested was lost and with a probability of 1/3 the investment was returned in
addition to a gain of 2.5 times the amount invested. For X ∈ {0, 9} being the amount invested,
In our others treatment (' OTH ', O ), subjects were randomly organized in groups of seven,
2 Instructions can be found in the appendix section B.4
5
consisting of six passive members, the clients (c), and one active member, the money manager
(m). Each client was endowed with nine euro and the money manager decided on the amount
to invest in the risky asset for each of the six clients. The amount invested was identical for all
clients. Hence, each client earned either πcO = 9 − X , in case of a loss, or πcO = 9 + 2.5 X , in
O
case of a win. The money manager was unaected by the outcome of the investment, πm = 0.
O
Additionally, we ran some extra sessions ('OTH315') with πm = 31.5 to test whether a high
xed paymentthe highest possible payment for the clientaected the money manager's
others as each money managers invested on behalf of six clients instead of only one.
In our aligned treatment ('ALL', A), we implemented the same group protocol as in OTH,
but also endowed the money manager with nine euro. Now, the money manager decided on the
amount to invest which was binding for each of the six clients and for himself. Each subject,
πcA = πm
A
=9−X in case of a loss.
In our limited liability treatment (' LIM ', L), we also implemented the same group protocol
as in OTH. In contrast, the money manager earned a fee which equaled ve percent from each
clients' prot in case of a win. In case of a loss, however, the money manager faced no monetary
L
consequences. Hence, in case of a win the payo was Xm = 0.05 × 6 × 2.5X for the money
manager and XcL = 9 + (1 − 0.05) × 2.5X for each client. In case of a loss, the payo was
L
Xm =0 for the money manager and XcL = 9 − X for each client. Hence, the money manager
participated only in gains but not in losses. However, th fee is quite small; note that risking
the entire endowment for all clients (in total 54 euro) earns an expected payo of just about
2.25 euro for the money manager. To control whether the magnitude of the fee inuenced the
decision, we ran some extra sessions (treatment `LIM50' ) in which the fee equaled 50 percent
L
instead of ve percent. Now, the payo in case of a win was changed to Xm = 0.5 × 6 × 2.5X for
the money manager and XcL = 9 + (1 − 0.5) × 2.5X for each client. Hence, the clients' expected
earnings for X euro invested was negative: (1 − 0.5) × 2.5X × 1/3 − X × 2/3 = −1/4X . Any
amount invested yields an expected loss for the clients but high expected gains for the money
manager.
3.2 Implementation
The experiment was programmed and conducted using z-Tree (Fischbacher, 2007). Upon arrival
subjects were randomly placed at computer terminals separated by blinds. For each treatment,
6
instructions were read aloud separately and questions were answered privately. The experiment
only started once the instructor was sure that all subjects had comprehended the instructions.
Once the experiment started, each money manager was endowed with an on-screen calculator
which calculates potential payos for the money manager himself and/or the clients for arbi-
trarily entered investment levels (screenshots can be found in appendix B.5). Eventually, the
money manager selected one investment from the generated list and conrmed his choice.
In each session, the subjects made investment decisions in three separate treatments. To
exclude hedging eects from repetitions or cross-game eects, only one of the three treatments
was payo relevant (Charness et al., 2016). The subjects were informed that the experiment
would consist of three independent parts, without specifying the exact nature of each part
upfront. The instructions for each part were distributed only after the previous part was
concluded.
In OTH, ALL, and LIM, each subject made the investment decision in the role of the money
manager. At the end of the session, one of the seven subjects was randomly determined to be
the active money manager while the remaining six subjects became the passive clients. To avoid
accountability eects, we guaranteed anonymity (Pollmann et al., 2014). Neither the money
managers knew the identity of the clients nor did the clients know the identity of the money
manager.
To avoid psychological anchoring eects, such as gamblers fallacy or hot hand fallacy, sub-
jects did not receive any information on the outcome of their investments. To determine the
payos, one subject rst threw a dice to determine the payo relevant treatment and then
threw a dice for each group to determine the outcome of the investment. The computer nally
assigned the roles as money manager and clients in a group. Subjects were payed privately in
cash.
We additionally elicited sex, age, eld of study, self-reported risk preferences (Dohmen
et al., 2011), and a social responsibility indicator (Berkowitz and Lutterman, 1968). The latter
two provide information on the general willingness to take risks (likert scale, 1-10) and social
responsibility, the tendency to help others without expecting any immediate personal reward
All sessions were conducted at the [ double-blind, location hidden ]. Our participants were
mainly bachelor students from all departments of [ double-blind, location hidden ]. Subjects
participated only once in this experiment. Figure 1 provides an overview of the implementation
and the comparisons together with the investment means for all treatments.
To answer our rst research question, whether money managers take more or less risk for
7
Figure 1: Overview of experiments with strategy for comparison
Notes. The gure shows the treatments as conduced in the sessions with ALL as the last treatment; however, we also
tested for order eects. Additionally, we provide the investment means. The links with diamonds indicate within-
subject considerations and links with bullets between-subject considerations.
others than for themselves, we ran 15 sessions with a total of 140 participants. We implemented
two dierent setups. In setup one (70 observations), the treatment order was OTH-IND-ALL.
In setup two (70 observations), the treatment order was ALL-IND-OTH. Average payments
were 15.82 euro (max. 34.5, min. 3, SD 10.10) including a show-up fee of 3 euro. As indicated
we ran three high payo sessions in the order OTH315-IND-ALL (35 observations). Average
payments were 10.95 euro (max. 34.5, min. 3, SD 8.64) including a show-up fee of 3 euro. Here,
we aimed to compare OTH315 to OTH. All sessions lasted roughly half an hour.
To answer the question whether limited liability has an impact on decision making for
others, we ran ve sessions with a total of 105 participants. We implemented two dierent
setups. In setup one (49 observations), the treatment order was LIM-IND-ALL. In setup two
(56 observations), the treatment order was ALL-IND-LIM. Average payments were 16.43 euro
(max. 34.5, min. 3, SD 10.74) including a show-up fee of 3 euro. To see whether the size of
the fee plays an important role, we ran three additional sessions with high fees, 50 percent, in
the order LIM50-IND-ALL (21) and ALL-IND-LIM50 (28). Average payments were 16.27 euro
(max. 70.5, min. 8, SD 12.75) including a show-up fee of 3 euro. The experiments lasted about
8
with bullets).
3.3 Predictions
Our experimental setup focuses on two considerations. The rst consideration is about the
dierences in decision making for others and for oneself using the sessions with the treatments
IND, ALL, and OTH (140 observations). Our second focus lies on the implementation of limited
liability, comparing mainly the 140 observations in OTH to the 105 observations in LIM.
For the rst consideration, we are less interested in individual investment levels; our focus lies
on the shift of investments comparing IND and OTH, and IND and ALL respectively. As stated
above, the decision in IND will be determined by the subjects' risk preferences (Charness et al.,
2013). For the decisions in ALL, economic standard models of perfectly rational and egoistic
agents make clear predictions. Without other-regarding preferences the money manager is just
investing the same amount as in IND, i.e. XI = XA . However, the standard models provide no
predictions for OTH as the payment for the money manager is not aligned to the investment
decision. Eriksen and Kvaløy (2010) as well as Andersson et al. (2016) pick up the social
distance hypothesis arguing that loss aversion is less pronounced when deciding for others than
when deciding for oneself, as these decisions are perceived as less important. Indeed Füllbrunn
and Luhan (2017) report experimental evidence for lower levels of loss aversion when decisions
are taken for others compared to decisions for oneself. However, our setup by design does not
emphasize losses as the payo on screen is framed only in the gain domain (the total payo is
displayed). Coming back to responsibility alleviation (Charness, 2000; Charness and Jackson,
2009), we should nd that money managers' behavior will be more conservative when investing
for others, i.e., XI > XO .3 When the money manager believes his clients to have similar
risk preferences as he has, he wouldin line with the false consensus eect (Ross et al., 1977)
invest the same amount for himself as for the clients, i.e., XI = XO .
Another prominent model to explain dierences between risky decisions for oneself and for
other, the self-others discrepancy eect, describes a bias when predicting others' risk aversion,
as this is perceived to be dierent from the individual's own risk preference. In the context of
our design this would state that money managers evaluate their own risk preferences dierently
than the risk preferences of their clients (Hsee and Weber, 1997; Eckel and Grossman, 2008a)
leading to an observed shift. The direction and magnitude of the predicted shift depends on the
3 As the investment in our experiment has a positive expected payo, it is not immediately clear that low
investments are a "responsible" choice. As one reviewer pointed out, it could be seen as responsible to maximize
the clients expected payos with a maximal investment. Our denition of a shift driven by responsibility,
however, follows Charness and Jackson (2009) who clearly predict a decrease in the risks taken on behalf of
others.
9
risk attitudes of the money managers relative to their clients. If money managers believe their
clients to be relatively risk averse, they would invest less for their clients than for themselves
(XI > XO ), while money managers who believe their clients to be relatively risk seeking, would
invest more for their clients than for themselves (XI < XO ).
The investment decision in ALL might induce a conict of preferences when the egoistic
preferences of the money manager and the social preferences for clients clash. On one side of
the spectrum, social preferences play no role (XA = XI ) inline with the economic prediction
of an egoistic decision maker who strictly follows his own preferences. On the other end of the
spectrum, social preferences for the clients would completely crowd out egoistic preferences,
i.e., XA = XO . When we assume that both preferences play a role in the consideration of the
money manager, the investment in ALL is expected to be in-between investments in IND and
OTH, i.e., either XI > XA ≥ XO (for a cautious shift) or XI < XA ≤ XO (for a risky shift).
Note that the interaction of social and/or egoistic preferences in risky decision making can only
In LIM, standard economic theory would predict the money manager to invest the full
amount. Such behaviour would also be optimal for risk averse clients. Expected returns from
investment are positive and higher investments lead to higher expected payos, at least when
the fee is merely ve percent. Hence, neglecting responsibility as in standard economic theory,
we predict subjects to invest the entire amount in the LIM treatments. However, there might
be a conict between the monetary incentives that trigger the egoistic preferences and other-
regarding preferencesthe former predicting high investment while the latter a rather cautious
investment. Nonetheless, high investment in LIM can still be judged as acting in line with risk
neutral clients. This argument does not hold any longer for a fee of 50 percent though. Here,
the clients clearly suer from excessive risk taking due to their negative expected payo (e.g.,
Allen and Gorton, 1993). In contrast to OTH, the decision maker now has an incentive to take
risks in order to earn a positive payo for himself. If responsibility plays the main role, however,
we expect similar investment levels in OTH and LIM. When egoistic preferences play the main
role, the money managers will not hesitate to risk the entire endowment of the clients.
4 Results
We rst consider the eect of risk taking for others by testing within-subjects whether dierences
exist between XI , XA , and XO . Then, we consider the eect of limited liability by testing
10
payment eect in OTH (vs. OTH315) and an eect of a 50% fee in LIM (vs LIM50) between-
subjects. The p-values for the all tests conducted were derived from two sided permutation
tests.
While negative values indicate a cautious shift, positive values indicate a risky shift. Table 1
provides averages (and standard deviations) for investment levels and shifts for 140 independent
observations. .
4
Table 1: Average Investments in Euro
General Risk
below median risk above median risk
n = 140 (n = 53) (n = 64)
4.53 (2.42) 3.19 (1.75) 5.42 (2.49)
3.92 (1.91) 3.04 (1.50) 4.41 (1.96)
XI
-0.60 (1.57)
∗∗∗
-0.15 (0.85) -1.01 (1.86)∗∗∗
Notes. The second column contains averages for all observations. The next two columns categorize subjects in two
groups according to elicitation of risk attitudes in line with Dohmen et al. (2011). Subjects in the group below median
(above median ) stated below (above) median risk attitudes on a scale from 1 - 10. Rows report average investments
and average shifts together with the standard deviation in parentheses. The asterisks refer to the p-value from a
permutation test testing the Null that S equals zero (** = p <0.05, *** = p <0.01).
The table shows that investment levels in ALL and in OTH are on average about 13 and
14 percent lower than in IND, respectively. Using a two-sided permutation test, we conrm a
signicant cautious shift for ALL and for OTH which is on average at SA = −0.60 (p < 0.001)
Observation 1. Money managers invest signicantly less for their clients than for themselves
in ALL and in OTH.
This result is a clear indication of acting in line with the responsibility alleviation hypothesis.
We nd a signicant cautious shift, not only in OTH but also in ALL, which is in contrast to
4 As we nd no signicant order eect in non-parametric tests and regressions, we pool all 140 observations
(see appendix B.1 and A)
5 We nd no signicant relationship between demographics and decision making for others nor was the social
responsibility score signicant (see appendix table A.5 and A.6).
11
The self-other discrepancy might be seen as a renement of trying to act responsibly, as
the money manager tries to act according to the investors risk preferences while deviating from
his personal preferences. According to this view, the direction of the observed shift depends
on the perceived risk preferences of the clients in comparison to the money managers own
risk preferences. Therefore, we conjecture that relatively risk averse subjects invest more for
others while relatively risk seeking subjects invest less for others. To test this conjecture, we
consider the self-reported willingness to take general risks based on Dohmen et al. (2011) which
provides a number from 1 (not willing to take risks) to 10 (willing to take high risk). We
make use of a median split to compare two groups; the relatively risk averse subjects (reported
general risk below 5) and the relatively risk seeking subjects (reported general risk above 5;
we neglect 23 observations at the median). Table 1 indicates that in the below-median group
the shift not signicantly dierent from zero. In the above-median group, however, the general
pattern observed above is quite strong, i.e., we nd a signicant cautious shift in ALL and in
OTH (for both p < 0.001).6 As the averages in table 1 already suggest, we nd a signicant
eect comparing above-median group and below-median group for each of the ve variables
Observation 2. Investment levels in OTH and ALL do barely dier for rather risk averse
money managers, while rather risk seeking money managers show a signicant cautious shift.
the above median risk group tend to assume that they are relatively risk seeking in comparison
to the population while at least the averages suggest the opposite for the risk averse money
managers. The decisions for their clients reect a propensity towards the perceived average
preference of their clients; nally, the above median risk level money managers are clearly
driving the aggregate results. The regression in the appendix (Table A.5) shows a clear picture:
the higher the willingness to take general risks, the higher the cautious shift.
These conclusions are only derived from observed behavior under the assumption that money
managers did indeed presume the average risk aversion to be higher or lower than their personal
risk preferences. To test whether this assumption was correct or a mere artifact, we let the
subjects estimate the investment level XI of the other subjects' (unincentivized) which we
6 Implementing the same analysis by categorizing subjects according to their observed risk preference in the
IND treatment (XI ), we get similar results (see appendix B.3).
7 To elicit beliefs, we included the question What would you say, how much do others in your group on
average invest for themselves? in the questionnaire. We abstained from using incentivized believe elicitation
methods as this would increase the complexity and duration of the experiment with vague additional benets
(see Trautmann and Kuilen, 2015, for a discussion). Unfortunately, we have elicited the beliefs for 91 subjects
12
Table 2: Average Beliefs about Investments of Clients
General Risk
below-median risk above-median risk
n = 91 (n = 36) (n = 40)
4.41 (1.62) 3.85 (1.14) 4.65 (1.95)
0.00 (2.22) 0.77 (1.32) -0.90 (2.36)
XIb
∗∗∗ ∗∗∗
XIb − XI
XIb − XO 0.58 (2.56)
∗∗∗
0.92 (1.88)
∗∗∗
0.05 (3.11)
Notes. The second column contains observations from 91 subjects from which we elicited beliefs. X , X , and X
denote the beliefs about the investments of others in IND, own investment in IND, and investment in OTH, respectively.
Ib I O
The next two columns categorize subjects in two groups according to elicitation of risk attitudes in line with Dohmen
et al. (2011). Subjects in the group below median (above median ) stated below (above) median risk attitudes on a
scale from 1 - 10. The asterisks refer to the p-value from a permutation test testing the Null that S equals zero (** =
p <0.05, *** = p <0.01).
Taking all observations into account, the average dierence between beliefs and own invest-
ment is not signicantly dierent from zero (p = 0.979). This indicates that money managers
on average do not believe others to take less or more risk then they take for themselves. Such
thinking might lead money managers to take similar risks for others as they would take for
themselves in line with behaviour of nancial advisers in Canada (Foerster et al., 2017).
On the individual level, however, the investment level in OTH can still deviate signicantly
from the expectation of the average risk preference. Thus, we again separate between subjects
with general risk below and above the median, and nd that the above median money managers
believe others to invest signicantly less than they do (XIb − XI = −0.90, p < 0.001), while the
below median money managers believe others to invest signicantly more (XIb − XI = 0.77,
p < 0.001). However, above-median risk takers generally believe others to take more risk than
The question remains, whether money managers in OTH invest in line with their beliefs,
i.e., does XIb − XO = 0 hold? Overall, we nd money managers to invest signicantly less for
their clients than what they believe their clients would invest for themselves (XIb − XO = 0.58,
p = 0.033). In particular, the below-median money managers invest signicantly less for their
clients than what they believe their clients would invest for themselves (XIb − XO = 0.92,
p < 0.001). In contrast, the above median money managers tend to invest in line with their
beliefs about others (XIb − XO = 0.05, p = 0.701).8 Overall, the results suggest that money
managers are relatively conservative in that they invest at most what they believe the clients
would invest for themselves. This supports Bolton et al. (2015), who nd that decision makers
Finally, we compare investment levels between OTH and ALL, i.e., a situation in which the
only.
8 However, comparing XIb − XO between the two categories we nd no signicant dierence (p = 0.150).
13
payment of the money manager is perfectly aligned (ALL) and when the payment is not aligned
(OTH). Results in table 1 indicate that dierences between XA and XO are negligible when
considering all subjects (XA − XO = 0.05, p = 0.766), but also when considering subjects below
median risk attitudes (XA − XO = −0.14, p = 0.501) and above (XA − XO = 0.32, p = 0.246).
Hence, overall it seems that money managers in ALL put their egoistic preferences on hold to
and the passive client in OTH. While the clients' expected earnings are positive, the money
managers' earnings are zero. When fairness preferences come into play, the money manager
might change his behavior to match his preferences for a fair allocation of payments (Fehr and
Schmidt, 1999; Bolton and Ockenfels, 2000; Charness and Rabin, 2002, 2005; Fudenberg and
Levine, 2012). However, models that incorporate risk preferences and fairness preferences are
missing. Nonetheless, we wanted to control whether the money manager's xed payment in
OTH has an inuence on decision making for others. Therefore, we compared the investment
levels in treatment OTH315 and OTH. We nd no signicant dierence in investments compar-
ing the two treatments (see appendix section B.2 and the regression in appendix table A.5 and
A.6) suggesting that the money manager's own unrelated payo when deciding for his clients
in OTH plays a minor role. However, the power is not sucient to claim that investment levels
In this section, we compare investment levels and shifts in OTH and in LIM between-subjects.
Figure 2 shows average investments (A) for IND (as the benchmark), OTH, and LIM and the
Table 4 reports the descriptives of the investments and shifts together with test statistics
for dierent categories of subjects. Considering the full data set, we nd a clear and signicant
dierence between investing in OTH and in LIM. On average, the money managers invested
2.79 euro more in LIM than in OTH, a 77 percent increase. Even though order played a role
9 However, even with n = 140 we would not be able to detect a small eect size of 0.2 as the power would
be only 0.63. Merging the data with observations from OTH315, i.e. having 175 observations, we still nd no
signicant dierence but for the same parameters we get a decent power of 0.73.
10 For a small eects size of 0.2, the power for a given number of observations of 70 and 35 respectively (same
order sessions) would be 0.28.
11 We neglect ALL as the relevant comparison is between OTH and LIM.
14
Figure 2: Comparing Investments: OTH vs LIM
played last than when LIM was played rst (p = 0.014), investment levels and shifts remain
Additionally, we conducted a full analysis of session and treatment eects in a panel regres-
sion for which the results are reported in table 3. The dependent variable is the investment
level in euro. To compare the treatments in the sessions with OTH, `OTH-sessions', to the ses-
sions with LIM, `LIM-sessions' (row one vs. row two in the grey area in gure 1), we introduce
LIM session as a dummy for the latter sessions. Further, the dummy ALL equals 1 if ALL is
played (and zero otherwise) and the dummy OTH* equals 1 if the decision is made for others
(and zero otherwise), which is OTH in the OTH-sessions and LIM in the LIM-sessions. The
references was therefore the investment in IND in the OTH-sessions. Model 2 adds subjects
characteristics.
15
Table 3: Session and treatment eects on investment
Notes. Random-eects panel regression with robust standard errors, variables explained above. Column 1 contains
the estimation results without controlling for individual characteristics, column 2 contains the results from the same
estimation controlling for gender, age, self-reported risk preferences (Dohmen et al., 2011), and a social responsibility
indicator (Berkowitz and Lutterman, 1968). Standard errors in parentheses.(* = p <0.1, ** = p <0.05, *** = p
<0.01).
Firstly, the LIM session dummy is is not signicant and close to zero. Hence, investments
in IND are not dierent comparing LIM- and OTH-sessions. Secondly, the OTH* coecient
is signicantly negative, which conrms the cautious shift in OTH, while the interaction co-
ecient OTH* × LIM-sessions is signicantly positive which conrms the risky shift in LIM.
Third, the ALL coecient is signicantly negative, which conrms the cautious shift in ALL.
However, this eect is diminished in the LIM-sessions, suggested by the signicantly positive
interaction coecient ALL × LIM-sessions. Maybe money managers more generally invest
more for others in the LIM-sessions than in the OTH-sessions and the risky shift in LIM is just
a consequence. However, the interaction with ALL is signicantly lower than the interaction
with OTH* conrmed by a Wald test (p < 0.001). This result conrms that even if money
managers invest generally more for others in the LIM-sessions than in the OTH sessions, the
eect is much stronger in OTH* than in ALL. These results remain unchanged if we control
The signicant increase of investments between OTH and LIM still holds if we compare
LIM to OTH separately for below- and above-median general risk group (see table 4), i.e.
independent of risk attitudes, investments in LIM exceed investments in OTH. To keep this
section concise, we provide respective regressions with shifts and investment levels as dependent
16
Table 4: Investment in OTH and LIM
∗∗∗ ∗∗∗
All 3.87 -0.65 6.85 2.30 <0.001
(n=140/105) (2.22) (2.3) (2.15) (2.68)
∗∗∗
Below Median risk 3.24 0.05 6.80 3.13 <0.001
(n=53/40) (1.96) (3.13) (2.25) (2.84)
∗∗∗ ∗∗∗
Above Median risk 4.27 -1.15 6.85 1.46 <0.001
(n=64/49) (2.4) (2.75) (2.11) (2.43)
∗∗∗ ∗∗∗
OTH/LIM rst 3.95 -0.77 6.30 1.52 <0.001
(n=70/49) (1.85) (2.11) (2.13) (2.49)
∗ ∗∗∗
OTH/LIM last 3.84 -0.53 7.33 2.06 <0.001
(n=70/56) (2.54) (2.67) (2.98) (2.67)
Notes. The table reports averages (SD) of investment levels and shifts in the treatments OTH and LIM for all
observations, subjects in the category below and above median risk, and in the orders OTH-IND-ALL/LIM-IND-ALL
(`rst') and in the orders ALL-IND-OTH/ALL-IND-LIM (`last'). The number of observations are in brackets for
OTH/LIM. The last column shows the p-values from a permutation test testing the Null X = X in the dierent
categories. The asterisks refer to the p-value from a permutation test testing the Null that the shift equals zero (* =
O L
17
variables and a LIM dummy plus controls as independent variables in the appendix (tables A.5
and A.6); these conrm our results as the LIM dummy is signicantly positive. Hence, we state
observations 3 and 4.
Observation 3. Money managers invest signicantly more for their clients than for themselves
in LIM.
Observation 4. Money Managers show a signicant risky shift independent of personal risk
attitudes.
This appears to be an indication of egoistic-, monetary incentives crowding out the previ-
ously observed eects of responsibility. However, these higher investment levels for others in
LIM could in principle stem from the fact that the money managers believe their clients to prefer
higher investments. We have shown in section 4.1 that money managers in OTH acted rather
cautiously, investing less than, or at most what they believe their clients would invest them-
selves. While there is no obvious reason for a change in believes, such a shift would in principle
explain increased investments even if money managers still try to act responsibly. We therefore
again compare the investments with the elicited beliefs. The average dierence between XL and
XIb equals 1.57 euro (SD 2.52) which is signicantly positive (p < 0.001).12 Recall, in OTH
the average dierence between XO and XIb was -0.58 (SD 2.36) which is signicantly negative
(p = 0.035). Hence, without limited liability the money manager invests rather cautiously for
others, as he invests less than he believes others would invest for themselves. With limited lia-
bility, however, such cautious investment behavior has disappeared and investment levels were
higher than what the money managers believed their clients would prefer.
We implemented additional sessions to test whether a higher fee with negative expected
earnings changes the decisions for others for the money manager. The increase to a fee of 50
percent yields an average investment of 6.03 euro (SD 2.90) which is slightly lower than in
LIM with a ve percent fee (6.85, p = 0.053).13 However, the shift is still signicantly positive
(SLIM 50 =1.64 euro, SD 2.72, p < 001) and not signicantly dierent to LIM (p = 0.158). Again,
investments are signicantly higher than in OTH (p < 0.01). Hence, the money managers in
our setting seem to care less about the expected negative consequences for their clients.
As a side eect, the new LIM50 treatment also allows us to consider ex-ante and ex-post
fairness. If the money manager strives for equal expected earnings (ex-ante fairness), he should
have invested 3.27 euro to have an expected earning of 8.17 euro for each client and himself.
If instead the money manager strives for equal earnings (ex-post earnings), he should have
18
invested 1.44 euro to earn 10.80 euro for clients and himself in case of success; there was no way
for equal earnings in case of a loss. Nevertheless, as shown above, the investment in LIM50 is
signicantly higher than 3.27 euro and of course than 1.44 euro (p < 0.001).
Looking at the clients' expected earnings given the investments, we see that they were
highest in LIM (average 9.86 euro, SD 0.27), slightly but signicantly lower in OTH (9.65 euro,
SD 0.37, p < 0.001), and signicantly lower in LIM50 (7.49 euro, SD 0.73, p < 0.001). In
this particular setting, limited liability with a ve percent fee increased the clients' expected
earnings. On the one hand, the fee is suciently low to keep expected earnings positive, and
on the other hand, the convex incentives increased the investment levels. However, limited
liability with a 50 percent fee makes the investment opportunity unprotable for the clients due
5 Discussion
5.1 Risk Taking for Others
Our rst question was, whether making decisions for others, in the absence of limited liability,
would lead to a risky or cautious shift as compared to decisions for oneself. In particular,
in contrast to the literature, our decision makers make decisions for a substantial number of
clients. This is a necessary rst step in establishing whether it is limited liability that leads to
increased risk taking on nancial markets. Overall, we nd clear evidence of a cautious shift in
both OTH and ALL, which in our experiment is mainly driven by relatively risk seeking money
managers. They believe others to be more risk averse than themselves and act accordingly. Our
aggregate results are line with the results from Eriksen and Kvaløy (2010) who use a similar
design in a between-subject setting with only one client. However, our results dier from those
experiments in the literature who nd rather a risky shift. How can we explain those mixed
The conclusions from the literature are based on aggregate results only and the heterogeneity
of subjects with respect to risk attitudes has barely been considered. Due to our within-subject
design we are able to take the relative risk attitudes of the money manager into account. We
nd that our results are driven by the relatively risk seeking subjects. Therefore, any study
with a rather risk averse subject pool would nd an aggregate risky shift, of course. Dierences
to Andersson et al. (2016), for instance, might be due to the fact that their subject pool is
taken from the general Danish population which has been found to be more risk averse than
19
the common student population (von Gaudecker et al., 2012).
Among others, Eriksen and Kvaløy (2010) report that hypothetical decision making for
others the most extreme social distanceleads to higher risk taking in comparison to a
situation with monetary consequences. Thus, experiments with higher social distance, which is
the case for internet experiments as opposed to laboratory experiments, might lead to higher risk
taking for others. Furthermore, our experimental design allows the potential money managers
to put themselves into the shoes of their clients, as the money manager becomes a client with
a probability of 6/7. This might lead to a higher empathy for the others leading to a cautious
shift (as in the equal opportunity mode treatment in Bolton and Ockenfels, 2006).
Experiments in which the subjects pick lotteries rather than making investments, the results
seem to support a risky shift in the loss domain or in the mixed domain, while lotteries in the
gain domain support a cautious shift (Pahlke et al., 2015). One reason might be that loss
aversion is weaker when making decisions for others (see e.g. Füllbrunn and Luhan (2017)).
In our Gneezy and Potters (1997) investment game, however, we cannot control the subjects'
reference point, as we have no record of the editing phase (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979).
When the endowment is integrated, the decision takes place in the gain domain only (9 + 2.5X
vs. 9 − X ). When the endowment is segregated, the decision takes place in the mixed domain
(2.5X vs. −X ). As we provide integrated outcomes on the decision screen, the subjects might
have perceived the task in the gain domain (see screenshot appendix B.5).
While money managers are assumed to know their own preferences, they are uncertain
about their clients' preferences; in particular when estimating the preferences of six clients.
This creates an ambiguous situation when deciding for others in contrast to when deciding for
oneself. From this point of view, our results are in line with ambiguity aversion, as subjects take
less risk in a situation with higher ambiguity (e.g., Trautmann and Van De Kuilen, 2015). This
eect might be amplied due to comparative ignorance (Fox and Tversky, 1995) as in a within-
subject design subjects are able to compare decisions for others and for themselves. When
money managers observe the decision of their clients in OWN beforehand, we would reduce
ambiguity and thus can see whether they behave indeed in line with the client's preferences as
our results on following their believes suggest, Bolton et al. (2015) also nd that the decision
maker follows their client's own choice (for one single client). However, how money managers
select the level of investment when they know the preferences of several clients in a group
remains a question for future research. So far, subjects in a group had to discuss and agree on
one common amount to invest; the results support a risky shift (Sutter, 2009).
Further design elements might be interesting to reconsider. For example, we only consider a
20
situation under anonymity; the money manager's identity is not revealed nor is s/he accountable
for his/her decision. When accountability comes into play, subjects might behave dierently.
Pahlke et al. (2012) nd that accountability leads to reduced risk aversion in mixed lotteries
with one 'client'. We consider a situation in which one subject is randomly chosen to be
the money manager, i.e. the decision is implemented with probability 1/7. When the money
manager knows for sure that his/her decision is implemented, s/he might be even more cautious.
Finally, we use a student subject pool for our experiments. It might be interesting to analyze the
same situation using the 'relevant decision maker'; Kirchler et al. (2019), for example, consider
nancial professionals who make investment decisions for others (in a dierent setting though).
agers who participate in gains only do not risk their own money but the money of each of the
six clients. A risky shift in comparison to OTH would provide evidence that social preferences
of money managers are crowded out by egoistic monetary incentives. To be able to answer
this question, we invented a new experimental setting which has not been considered in the
literature before; in particular, only a substantial number of clients allows for a 'privatizing
We do indeed nd a clear indication for a risky shift once we introduce limited liability.
This result is not driven by the beliefs about the clients preferences; as money managers invest
signicantly more for their clients than what they believed their clients would prefer. The
investment levels taken for clients are signicantly higher than for oneself. This result is quite
robust testing for the size of the bonus (5 percent or 50 percent), risk preferences (below- or
limited liability treatments with a ve percent and a 50 percent bonus and nd no dierence in
investments. Given that the expected payos for their clients were negative with a 50 percent
bonus, the money managers' decisions are clearly motivated by their own payo expectations
with social preferences playing only an inferior role. In this treatment, investments could be
chosen such that expected earnings for the money manager and the clients were equal, both,
in line with ex-ante and ex-post fairness. However, we found that the investment levels under
limited liability were signicantly higher than any fairness benchmark. We only consider two
14 The result is also robust when separating the subjects by sex. For the interested reader, we have added
appendix D.11 considering gender eects.
21
dierent bonus conditions. Future research might consider dierent bonus conditions to carve
out whether indeed the size of the bonus has an inuence on the money manager, in particular
One argument against our interpretation of the eects of limited liability on investment levels
might be that the observations are driven by a few participants who, for whatever reason, take
the maximum risk, i.e. invest the entire endowment. Without limited liability only six percent
invest the entire endowment; with limited liability 37 percent invest the entire endowment (41
percent in the 50 percent condition). The remaining money managers might behave in a similar
with and without limited liability. However, we still nd a signicant risky shift (p < 0.001).
6 Conclusion
Coming back to our real-world motivation, we asked the question whether limited liability
payment schemes on nancial markets lead to money managers taking excessive risks when
investing their clients' money (e.g., Allen and Gorton, 1993; Allen and Gale, 2000; Cheung and
Coleman, 2014; Kleinlercher et al., 2014). Such a situation involves two possible motivational
factors that could increase the willingness to take risks, the mere fact that the decision is taken
for somebody else, and limited liability. We decided to study both separately in an incremental
design. In the rst condition, we aimed to establish whether money managers take higher risks
for their six clients in absence of limited liability. In a second condition, we introduced limited
liability to test whether behaviour changes in comparison to the rst condition. We found that
agency in itself leads to a cautious shift, i.e. decision makers took less risk with other people's
money. However, if gains are shared, while losses remain with the clients, we observe a risky
shift, i.e. decision makers took more risk with other people's money. Our results clearly suggest
that decision makers on one hand have social preferences and invest more cautiously for others
than for themselves. On the other hand these social preferences are crowded out by egoistic
Our ndings of initially decreased risk taking are in line with responsibility alleviation, and
we found that investors seek to act according to the perceived preferences of their clients. Our
participants were aware of their relative risk preferences in that money managers with low
risk aversion sought lower risks for others than for themselves and money managers with high
risk aversion increased the risks taken for their clients. When the decision maker bears the
same consequences as their clients (ALL), the clients' preferences seem to outweigh the money
manager's own preferences. This situation changed drastically once we introduced limited
22
liability in the form of convex incentives. Promising a ve percent share of the possible returns
on investment, with losses being incurred only by the clients, was sucient to increase the
investment levels by more than 77 percent. While the perception of what the clients would
prefer did not change, money managers nonetheless follow their own egoistic preferences and
invest much more. The emerging picture is that while decision makers initially try to accomplish
what their clients want and overall take lower risks for others, the convex incentives reverse the
decision. Apparently, social preferences are largely crowded out by egoistic monetary incentives.
The fact that in one treatment the expected prot was even negative for the clients did not
signicantly change the money managers' behaviour. A clear sign that egoistic preferences are
If one would want to draw conclusions for the nancial markets, the recommendation is
straightforward. A fee based on the success of the investment, without consequence in case of
losses increases risk taking and potentially fosters bubble formation. Both a at fee, as well as
a bonus including negative consequences in case of losses for the client leads to investments that
aim to follow the client's preferences. However, the results stem from a laboratory experiment
Our limited liability design is the rst that applies convex incentives with consequences for
other people's earnings in an experiment. This experimental design can be applied to answer
more questions regarding `privatizing prots and socializing losses' scenarios. Such a design
could for example consider 'trust' in the fund industry when money managers compete which
each other under convex incentives (Gennaioli et al., 2015; Agranov et al., 2014) but can also be
applied to asset market experiments to test whether such an environment indeed fosters asset
References
Agranov, M., Bisin, A., Schotter, A., 2014. An experimental study of the impact of competition
for other people's money: the portfolio manager market. Experimental Economics, 564585.
Albrecht, K., Volz, K. G., Sutter, M., Laibson, D. I., Von Cramon, D. Y., 2011. What is for me
is not for you: brain correlates of intertemporal choice for self and other. Social Cognitive
Allen, F., Gale, D., 2000. Bubbles and crises. The Economic Journal 110 (460), 236255.
23
Allen, F., Gorton, G., 1993. Churning bubbles. The Review of Economic Studies 60 (4), 813
836.
Andersson, O., Holm, H. J., Tyran, J.-R., Wengström, E., 2016. Deciding for others reduces
Bebchuk, L. A., Spamann, H., 2009. Regulating bankers' pay. Georgetown Law Journal 98,
247287.
Beisswanger, A. H., Stone, E. R., Hupp, J. M., Allgaier, L., 2003. Risk taking in relationships:
Dierences in deciding for oneself versus for a friend. Basic and Applied Social Psychology
25 (2), 121135.
Berkowitz, L., Lutterman, K. G., 1968. The traditional socially responsible personality. Public
Bolton, G. E., Ockenfels, A., 2000. Erc: A theory of equity, reciprocity, and competition.
Bolton, G. E., Ockenfels, A., 2006. Inequality aversion, eciency, and maximin preferences in
simple distribution experiments: comment. The American economic review 96 (5), 19061911.
Bolton, G. E., Ockenfels, A., 2010. Betrayal aversion: Evidence from brazil, china, oman,
switzerland, turkey, and the united states: Comment. The American Economic Review
Bolton, G. E., Ockenfels, A., Stauf, J., 2015. Social responsibility promotes conservative risk
Chakravarty, S., Harrison, G. W., Haruvy, E. E., Rutström, E. E., 2011. Are you risk averse
Charness, G., 2000. Responsibility and eort in an experimental labor market. Journal of Eco-
Charness, G., Gneezy, U., 2012. Strong evidence for gender dierences in risk taking. Journal
Charness, G., Gneezy, U., Halladay, B., 2016. Experimental methods: Pay one or pay all.
24
Charness, G., Gneezy, U., Imas, A., 2013. Experimental methods: Eliciting risk preferences.
Charness, G., Jackson, M. O., 2009. The role of responsibility in strategic risk-taking. Journal
Charness, G., Rabin, M., 2002. Understanding social preferences with simple tests. The Quar-
Charness, G., Rabin, M., 2005. Expressed preferences and behavior in experimental games.
Cheung, S. L., Coleman, A., 2014. Relative performance incentives and price bubbles in exper-
Cvetkovich, G., 1972. Eects of sex on decision policies used for self and decision policies used
Dewatripont, M., Rochet, J.-C., Tirole, J., 2010. Balancing the banks: Global lessons from the
Dohmen, T., Falk, A., Human, D., Sunde, U., Schupp, J., Wagner, G. G., 2011. Individual
Eckel, C. C., Grossman, P. J., 2008a. Forecasting risk attitudes: An experimental study using
actual and forecast gamble choices. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 68 (1),
117.
Eckel, C. C., Grossman, P. J., 2008b. Men, women and risk aversion: Experimental evidence.
Eriksen, K. W., Kvaløy, O., 2010. Myopic investment management. Review of Finance 14 (3),
521542.
Fehr, E., Schmidt, K. M., 1999. A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. The Quar-
Fischbacher, U., 2007. z-tree: Zurich toolbox for ready-made economic experiments. Experi-
25
Foerster, S., Linnainmaa, J. T., Melzer, B. T., Previtero, A., 2017. Retail nancial advice: does
Fox, C. R., Tversky, A., 1995. Ambiguity aversion and comparative ignorance. The Quarterly
French, K., Baily, M., Campbell, J., Cochrane, J., Diamond, D., Due, D., Kashyap, A.,
Mishkin, F., Rajan, R., Scharfstein, D., et al., 2010. The squam lake report: xing the
Fudenberg, D., Levine, D. K., 2012. Fairness, risk preferences and independence: Impossibility
Füllbrunn, S. C., Luhan, W. J., 2017. Decision making for others: The case of loss aversion.
Garcia-Retamero, R., Galesic, M., 2012. Doc, what would you do if you were me? on self
18 (1), 38.
Gennaioli, N., Shleifer, A., Vishny, R., 2012. Neglected risks, nancial innovation, and nancial
Gennaioli, N., Shleifer, A., Vishny, R., 2015. Money doctors. The Journal of Finance 70 (1),
91114.
Gneezy, U., Potters, J., 1997. An experiment on risk taking and evaluation periods. The Quar-
Harbaugh, W. T., Krause, K., Vesterlund, L., 2010. The fourfold pattern of risk attitudes in
choice and pricing tasks. The Economic Journal 120 (545), 595611.
Harrison, G. W., 2006. Hypothetical bias over uncertain outcomes. In: List, J. A. (Ed.), Using
pp. 4169.
Holmen, M., Kirchler, M., Kleinlercher, D., 2014. Do option-like incentives induce overvalua-
tion? evidence from experimental asset markets. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control
40, 179194.
Holt, C. A., Laury, S. K., 2002. Risk aversion and incentive eects. American Economic Review
92 (5), 16441655.
26
Holt, C. A., Laury, S. K., 2005. Risk aversion and incentive eects: New data without order
Hsee, C. K., Weber, E. U., 1997. A fundamental prediction error: Selfothers discrepancies in
Kahneman, D., Tversky, A., 1979. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econo-
Kirchler, M., Lindner, F., Weitzel, U., 2019. Delegated decision making and social competition
Kleinlercher, D., Huber, J., Kirchler, M., 2014. The impact of dierent incentive schemes on
Pahlke, J., Strasser, S., Vieider, F. M., 2012. Risk-taking for others under accountability. Eco-
Pahlke, J., Strasser, S., Vieider, F. M., 2015. Responsibility eects in decision making under
Pollmann, M. M., Potters, J., Trautmann, S. T., 2014. Risk taking by agents: The role of
Polman, E., 2012. Selfother decision making and loss aversion. Organizational Behavior and
Rajan, R. G., 2006. Has nance made the world riskier? European Financial Management
12 (4), 499533.
Reynolds, D. B., Joseph, J., Sherwood, R., 2009. Risky shift versus cautious shift: determining
dierences in risk taking between private and public management decision-making. Journal
Ross, L., Greene, D., House, P., 1977. The "false consensus eect": An egocentric bias in social
perception and attribution processes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 13 (3), 279
301.
Stone, E. R., Allgaier, L., 2008. A social values analysis of selfother dierences in decision
making involving risk. Basic and Applied Social Psychology 30 (2), 114129.
27
Stoner, J. A. F., 1961. A comparison of individual and group decisions involving risk. Ph.D.
Sutter, M., 2009. Individual behavior and group membership: Comment. The American Eco-
Swalm, R. O., 1966. Utility theory-insights into risk taking. Harvard Business Review 44 (6),
123136.
Trautmann, S. T., Kuilen, G., 2015. Belief elicitation: A horse race among truth serums. The
Trautmann, S. T., Van De Kuilen, G., 2015. Ambiguity attitudes. The Wiley Blackwell hand-
Trope, Y., Liberman, N., 2010. Construal-level theory of psychological distance. Psychological
Ubel, P. A., Angott, A. M., Zikmund-Fisher, B. J., 2011. Physicians recommend dierent
treatments for patients than they would choose for themselves. Archives of Internal Medicine
Viscusi, W. K., Magat, W. A., Huber, J., 1987. An investigation of the rationality of consumer
von Gaudecker, H.-M., van Soest, A., Wengström, E., 2012. Experts in experiments. Journal of
Wray, L. D., Stone, E. R., 2005. The role of self-esteem and anxiety in decision making for self
28
Appendix
A Regressions
In the tables A.5 and A.6, we regress the investment levels for the clients (XO and XL ) and
the shifts (SO and SL ) in OTH and LIM respectively on dierent treatments (dummy for LIM
( LIM ), dummy for high payment in OTH (High Payment ), dummy for high fee in LIM (High
Fee )), on order (whether decision making for others (OTH or LIM) was rst or last (Order = 1
if last), and on subjects' background (general risk ( Risk ), female dummy (Female ), age (Age ),
dummy for the eld of study being economics ( Econ ), and social responsibility (SRS )).
General risk equals the self-reported risk preference in form of a likert scale question from
one to ten with a higher number indicating a higher willingness to take risks(Dohmen et al.,
2011). The social responsibility score was taken from Berkowitz and Lutterman (1968)).
Table A.5 considers three OLS regressions considering the 140 observations without limited
liability (model 2) and the 105 observations with limited liability (model 3), and a model
including both (model 1) clustered at session level. The rst model neglects the additional
treatments with higher payments in OTH (xed payment was 31.50 euro instead of zero) or
higher fees in LIM (fee was 50 percent instead of 5 percent). The results reect our observations.
Limited liability increases the shift signicantly (observation 3. General risk decreases the shift
signicantly 1 in model 2. However, general risk plays no signicant role in model 3. The
additional treatments High Payment and High Fee show no or a weak correlation with the
shift, i.e. high payments for the money managers in OTH do not change risk taking for others
but a higher fee in LIM tends to reduces risk taking for other. The social responsibility score
29
Table A.5: Investment shifts in OTH (SO ) and LIM (SL )
∗∗∗ ∗∗∗
Order 0.80 0.41 1.18
(0.24) (0.24) (0.32)
∗∗∗
LIM 2.92
(0.25)
∗∗∗ ∗∗∗
General Risk -0.36 -0.34 -0.11
(0.100) (0.11) (0.22)
Social Responsibility Score 0.16 0.025 -0.27
(0.26) (0.33) (0.39)
Female 0.099 -0.10 0.044
(0.29) (0.36) (0.32)
Econ -0.31 -0.35 0.15
(0.27) (0.34) (0.46)
∗
Age 0.023 0.091 -0.073
(0.043) (0.046) (0.053)
High Payment 0.044
(0.26)
∗
High Fee -0.66
(0.35)
∗∗
Constant -0.073 -1.08 4.70
(1.61) (1.93) (1.83)
Observations 245 175 154
Adjusted R2 0.320 0.076 0.045
Notes. Variables explained above. Standard errors in parentheses. The asterisks refer to the p-value from a permutation
test testing the H that the shift equals zero (* = p <0.1, ** = p <0.05, *** = p <0.01).
0
Table A.6 considers similar regressions as table A.6. However, we now consider investment
levels instead of investment shifts and make use of truncated regressions censored at X = 0 and
X = 9. Money managers invest signicantly more for their clients when limited liable. Further
on, order plays a role in the experiments with limited liability, i.e. subjects invest more when
LIM is played last. The money makers willingness to take risk is also reected in the decision
for others, i.e. the higher the willingness to take risks, the higher the risk money managers take
for others. Finally, females seem to take less risk for their clients when limited liable.
30
Table A.6: Investment levels in OTH (XO ) and LIM (XL )
∗∗ ∗∗∗
Order 0.74 0.094 1.46
(0.30) (0.25) (0.39)
∗∗∗
LIM 3.52
(0.31)
∗∗
General Risk 0.16 0.28 0.25
(0.12) (0.12) (0.29)
Social Responsibility Score 0.24 0.32 0.17
(0.36) (0.43) (0.26)
∗∗
Female -0.72 -0.28 -1.74
(0.45) (0.45) (0.67)
∗∗ ∗
Econ -0.90 -0.81 0.095
(0.39) (0.43) (0.92)
∗ ∗
Age 0.0094 0.057 -0.14
(0.046) (0.033) (0.082)
High Payment 0.22
(0.41)
High Fee -0.68
(0.74)
∗∗∗
Constant 2.47 0.49 9.01
(1.94) (1.80) (3.05)
Notes. Variables explained above. Standard errors in parentheses. The asterisks refer to the p-value from a permutation
test testing the H that the shift equals zero (* = p <0.1, ** = p <0.05, *** = p <0.01).
0
in which subjects made investment decisions in the order OTH-IND-ALL and 70 observations
We make use of a permutation tests to evaluate the Null that investment levels and shifts do
not dier comparing the two dierent orders. As table B.7 indicates, the order of the treatments
has no eect on the main variables of interest. Further on, observation 1 also holds each of the
two subsets.
31
Table B.7: Order Dierences
∗∗∗ ∗∗
SA -0.83 (1.61) -0.38 (1.51) -0.45 (0.088)
∗∗∗ ∗
SO -0.77 (2.11) -0.53 (2.67) -0.24 (0.558)
Notes. The table reports averages in investments and shifts in the three treatments separated by order. The last
column shows the p-values from a permutation test comparing the two previous columns. The asterisks refer to the
p-value from a permutation test testing the H that dierences equal zero (* = p <0.1, ** = p <0.05, *** = p <0.01).
0
investment levels we compare 70 observations with a zero payment for the decision maker and
35 observations with a payment of 31.50 euro for the decision maker (both in the order OTH-
IND-ALL). We nd no signicant dierence comparing the two dierent payment conditions;
the investment level in OTH and the shift are almost equal in both conditions. Table B.8 shows
Notes. The table reports averages in investments and shifts in the three treatments separated by order. The last
column shows the p-values from a permutation test comparing the two previous columns. The asterisks refer to the
p-value from a permutation test testing the H that dierences equal zero (* = p <0.1, ** = p <0.05, *** = p <0.01).
0
we can also use XI as a measure for risk attitudes (Charness et al., 2013). If we replicate table
1 by using the categories below median XI and above median XI we nd similar results
32
Table B.9: Average Investments in euro
Investment in IND
∗∗∗
SA -0.60 (1.57) 0.20 (0.83) -1.43 (1.83)
∗∗∗
SO -0.65 (2.39) 0.34 (1.62) -1.75 (2.61)
Notes. The second column contains all observations. The next two columns categorize subjects in two groups according
to XI which can be seen as a measure of risk attitudes. Subjects in the group below median (above median ) invested
below (above) median investment levels in IND. Rows report average investments and average shifts together with the
standard deviation in parentheses. The asterisks refer to the p-value from a permutation test testing the Null that S
equals zero (** = p <0.05, *** = p <0.01).
B.4 Instructions
Find below the translated instructions for the order OTH-IND-ALL. They start with general in-
structions, followed by the three separate instructions for each treatment which were distributed
only when the preceding treatment was concluded. The German instructions are available upon
request.
INSTRUCTIONS
Welcome to the experiment. Please do not talk to any other participant from now on. We
kindly ask you to use only those functions of the PC that are necessary for the conduct of
the experiment. The purpose of this experiment is to study decision behavior. You can earn
real money in this experiment. Your payment will be determined solely by your own decisions
according to the rules on the following pages. The data from the experiment will be anonymized
and cannot be related to the identities of the participants. Neither the other participants nor
the experimenter will nd out which choices you have made and how much you have earned
during the experiment.
SUB EXPERIMENTS
You will participate in three independent sub experiments followed by a short questionnaire.
For each sub experiment you receive a new set of instructions. Of the three sub experiments
only one will be paid out at the end of the experiment. The payo relevant experiment will be
randomly determined by the roll of a die.
Role - In this part participants are either active or passive members. In each group there
is only one active member. This member decides for the other six members and, thereby,
determines their payo. The active group member will randomly be determined at the end of
the experiment. First, all participants decide as the active member for all other group members.
At the end of the experiment the real active member will be determined and his decision will
be implemented.
Task - In the following your decision as an active member will be explained. The passive
members receive 9 euro each. You now decide for each of the other members how much of
The investment is the same for each passive group
their 9 euro to invest in a risky project.
member, i.e., when you invest a certain amount then you invest this amount for each passive
group member. The remaining amount (9 euro - Investment) will be paid out to each passive
member independent of the project's success.
33
The project is either a success or a failure. In case of a success each passive member gets her
invested amount back and in addition receives 2.5 times of the investment as a gain:
Payment in case of success = 9 + 2.5×Investment.
In case of a failure the investment is lost:
Payment in case of failure = 9−Investment.
Whether the project is successful will be determined by the throw of a six-sided die at the end
of the experiment. In case of a ve or six, the project is a success, in case of a one, two, three
or four the project is a failure. The probability of success is therefore 33.33%.
Procedure - Details on how to enter the investments - calculation of potential payments, elds
of entry, etc - will be displayed on the upper part of your screen once the experiment has started.
In this experiment you decide only for yourself, independent of the other participants. You
receive 9 euro and decide how much of their 9 euro to invest in a risky project. The remaining
amount (9 euro - Investment) will be paid out independent of the project's success.
The project is either a success or a failure. In case of a success You will get your invested
amount back and in addition receive 2.5 times of the investment as a gain:
Payment in case of success = 9 + 2.5×Investment.
In case of a failure the investment is lost:
Payment in case of failure = 9−Investment.
Whether the project is successful will be determined by the throw of a six-sided die at the end
of the experiment. In case of a ve or six, the project is a success, in case of a one, two, three
or four the project is a failure. The probability of success is therefore 33.33%.
Procedure - Details on how to enter the investments - calculation of potential payments, elds
of entry, etc - will be displayed on the upper part of your screen once the experiment has started.
Role - In this part participants are either active or passive members. In each group there is
only one active member. This member decides for himself and the other six members and, there
by, determines the payos for the whole group. The active group member will randomly be
determined at the end of the experiment. First, all participants decide as the active member for
all group members. At the end of the experiment the real active member will be determined
and his decision will be implemented.
Task - In the following your decision as an active member will be explained. Each group member
(active and passive) members receives 9 euro each. You now decide for each member of the
The investment
group, including yourself, how much of the 9 euro to invest in a risky project.
is the same for each passive group member, i.e., when you invest a certain amount then you
invest this amount for yourself and for each passive group member. The remaining amount (9
euro - Investment) will be paid out to each group member independent of the project's success.
The project is either a success or a failure. In case of a success each group member gets her
invested amount back and in addition receives 2.5 times of the investment as a gain:
Payment in case of success = 9 + 2.5×Investment.
In case of a failure the investment is lost:
Payment in case of failure = 9−Investment.
Whether the project is successful will be determined by the throw of a six-sided die at the end
of the experiment. In case of a ve or six, the project is a success, in case of a one, two, three
or four the project is a failure. The probability of success is therefore 33.33%.
34
Procedure - Details on how to enter the investments calculation of potential payments,
elds of entry, etc will be displayed on the upper part of your screen once the experiment has
started.
END OF EXPERIMENT
At rst we will determine, by the roll of a die, which experiment will determine your payo.
Thereafter, a separate dice roll for each group will determine whether the project was successful
or not. After you answered a short questionnaire your payment will be shown at your screen.
Please enter the amount on your receipt. You will be called individually to the payo desk.
Please bring the small number plate and the signed receipt with you. The payment will be in
cash, private and anonymous.
were able to enter arbitrary investment levels in the eld EINSATZ in euro (Investment in
euro). A click on the gray button (Generate Payos) added a new line to a table. The table
listed the chosen investment and the potential payos for the passive and the active members
together depending on the treatments together with the respective probabilities. The ultimate
investment was chosen by marking one line in the list and by clicking the red button (CONFIRM
YOUR DEFINITIVE INVESTMENT). Then a pop-up asked whether the decision is ultimate or
whether the subject wants to revise it. In this example, the subject rst entered an investment
amount of 2.86 euro, then 1.75 euro, and then 8.62 euro. The amount 5.67 euro was not
generated yet. However, the investment 1.75 euro was chosen and the red button opened the
dialog for a nal conrmation of the choice. The z-Tree code is available upon request.
35
Figure B.9: Screenshot of Investment Decision: IND
36
Figure B.9: Screenshot of Investment Decision: ALL
37
Figure B.9: Screenshot of Investment Decision: OTH
observations in which subjects made investment decisions in the order LIM-IND-ALL and 56
We make use of a permutation tests to evaluate the Null that investment levels and shifts do
not dier comparing the two dierent orders. As table B.7 indicates, the order of the treatments
has an eect on the main variables of interest. However, observation 1 also holds for the two
subsets.
38
Table C.10: Order Dierences
Notes. The table reports averages in investments and shifts in LIM separated by order. The last column shows the
p-values from a permutation test comparing the two previous columns. The asterisks refer to the p-value from a
permutation test testing the H that dierences equal zero (* = p <0.1, ** = p <0.05, *** = p <0.01).
0
C.2 Instructions
The instructions for LIM simply replace the instructions for OTH (Section B.4). Instructions
Role - In this part participants are either active or passive members. In each group there
is only one active member. This member decides for the other six members and, thereby,
determines their payo. The active group member will randomly be determined at the end of
the experiment. First, all participants decide as the active member for all other group members.
At the end of the experiment the real active member will be determined and his decision will
be implemented.
Task - In the following your decision as an active member will be explained. The passive
members receive 9 euro each. You now decide for each of the other members how much of
The investment is the same for each passive group
their 9 euro to invest in a risky project.
member, i.e., when you invest a certain amount then you invest this amount for each passive
group member. The remaining amount (9 euro - Investment) will be paid out to each passive
member independent of the project's success.
The project is either a success or a failure. In case of a success each passive member gets her
invested amount back and in addition receives 2.5 times of the investment as a gain. The active
member receives 5 % from the gain of each passive member:
Payment in case of success
Prot = 2.5 × Investment
passive member = 9 + 95% × Prot
active member = 6 × 5% × Prot
In case of a failure the investment is lost and the active member receives no payment
Payment in case of failure
passive member = 9 − Investment
active member =0
Whether the project is successful will be determined by the throw of a six-sided die at the end
of the experiment. In case of a ve or six, the project is a success, in case of a one, two, three
or four the project is a failure. The probability of success is therefore 33.33%.
Procedure - Details on how to enter the investments - calculation of potential payments, elds
of entry, etc - will be displayed on the upper part of your screen once the experiment has started.
39
C.3 Decision Screen
Figures C.10 provides a screenshots of the investment decisions for treatment LIM similar to
section B.5.
40
D Gender Eects
We added this section for those researchers who are interested in gender eects in risk taking.
Charness and Gneezy (2012) provide evidence for a gender eect in the Gneezy and Potters
(1997) environment with varying payments and probabilities. To test whether a gender eect,
or rather a sex eect, has an impact on investment levels, we compare the observations in
which females made investment decisions to the observations in which males made investment
decisions. As table D.11 indicates, males invest signicantly more than females in IND, ALL,
and LIM, i.e. in all treatments in which the money managers faces true outcome consequences.
Investments in OTH, however, are not dierent. The general patterns from observation 1 and
∗∗∗
SA (162/132) -0.40 (1.39) -0.19 (1.38) -0.21 (0.193)
∗∗ ∗∗
SO (59/46) -0.69 (2.62) -0.61 (2.13) -0.08 (0.842)
∗∗∗ ∗∗∗
SL (75/65) 1.84 (2.56) 2.89 (2.69) -1.05 (0.45)
Notes. The table reports averages in investments and shifts separated by sex. The numbers in column one report the
number of observations for males and females (males/females). The last column shows the p-values from a permutation
test comparing the two previous columns. The asterisks refer to the p-value from a permutation test testing the H
that dierences equal zero (* = p <0.1, ** = p <0.05, *** = p <0.01).
0
In a debrieng questionnaire, we ask several questions on risk aversion in line with Dohmen
et al. (2011). Using a Mann-Whitney U test, we nd signicant gender dierences in questions
about risk taking in general (p = 0.004), driving a car (p = 0.019), and making nancial
decisions (p = 0.002). We nd no eect in questions on risk taking in sports and leisure
41
Highlights
• We consider financial decision making for others with and without limited liability
• Without, decision makers take less risks for others than for themselves
• With limited liability decision makers take excessive risks for others
• Conclusion: Convex incentives crowd out social preferences
• New experimental design allows for private gains and social losses
Page | 1