Developments in Intellectual Property Strategy: The Impact of Artificial Intelligence, Robotics and New Technologies
Developments in Intellectual Property Strategy: The Impact of Artificial Intelligence, Robotics and New Technologies
Developments in Intellectual Property Strategy: The Impact of Artificial Intelligence, Robotics and New Technologies
Nadia Naim
Developments
in Intellectual
Property Strategy
The Impact of Artificial
Intelligence, Robotics
and New Technologies
Developments in Intellectual Property
Strategy
“This is a fascinating book that provides its readers with a comprehensive inter-
disciplinary journey to addressing unpacking intellectual property, ethical and
governance challenges while frontier technologies are engaged, as well as explor-
ing responding strategies to the business world. It is an impressive reading book
for academic scholars, business professionals, industry practitioners and
policymakers.”
—Dr Luo Li, Assistant Professor of Law, Coventry Law School, Coventry
University, UK
“Dr. Nadia has put out an awesome literature, which is relevant not just for
academics, but it is for all cadre of society. Her interdisciplinary and cross-
cultural approaches to the treatment of the evolving issues surrounding artificial
intelligence (AI) is uniquely presented in this work: ‘Developments in Intellectual
Property Strategy: The Impact of Artificial Intelligence, Robotics and New
Technologies.’ I highly recommend this book to anyone engaged in the econom-
ics, politics, legal, and technology spaces.”
—Professor Samuel Samiái Andrews, USA Ambassador’s Distinguished Scholar,
Professor of Intellectual Property Law & faculty, member, Prince Mohammad Bin
Fahd University, College of Law, Al Khobar, Kingdom of Saudi Arabia
Nadia Naim
Editor
Developments in
Intellectual Property
Strategy
The Impact of Artificial Intelligence,
Robotics and New Technologies
Editor
Nadia Naim
Law and Social Sciences
Aston University
Birmingham, UK
© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Nature
Switzerland AG 2024
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether
the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and
transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar
or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or
the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any
errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional
claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG.
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
v
vi Foreword
This latest book offers chapters by Nadia and a number of expert con-
tributors whose analyses encompass both fundamentals and crucial areas
that are often overlooked or do not receive the deserved attention they
warrant in the raging exchanges over future projections on society and
business. The impact of emerging and future technologies upon society
and its relationship between established current intellectual property
rights protection regimes and the new technologies like artificial intelli-
gence require a sound and balanced contribution to tempering discourses
coloured by speculation and emotion. This book sets out to achieve that
high aspiration. It covers core topics such as artificial intelligence cre-
ations and ownership—who can, and should, own the intellectual prop-
erty that artificial intelligence, as distinct from natural person or legal
entity, might create?—which in itself require examination of the regula-
tion and/or protection of intellectual property creativity or invention
conceived by artificial intelligence or protection and whether such issues
are just a matter of time or a step too far. Irrespective of that response,
society and business are already confronted with the challenge of the big
data and the risk of data legislation such as the EU Data Act and compa-
rable UK statutes enshrining quasi-exclusivity data lockups. The legal
nature of non-fungible tokens, utilising the exemplar of trade in artworks
in the digital environment, also receives attention, as does the potential
for robots to adopt a role as care contributors in the ever-increasing and
concerning industry of proper and appropriate attention to our ageing
population in care. Finally, the book offers perspectives on the value of
intellectual property financing for companies and businesses, and an
examination of transformative (bio)technologies in knowledge societies.
Nadia and her co-contributors bring a fresh and essential critical analy-
sis to the debate on these legal and regulatory considerations of intellec-
tual rights and artificial intelligence within society and the business
world. This book covers a broad yet manageable array of topics, some of
which are otherwise overlooked, on the future of business intellectual
property strategy and planning, with a comprehensive interdisciplinary
Foreword vii
Artificial Intelligence Creations and Ownership – Who Should
the Intellectual Property Belong To? 1
Nadia Naim
1 What Is Artificial Intelligence (AI)? 3
2 Defining Artificial Intelligence Within Intellectual
Property Law 4
3 EU Commission and Artificial Intelligence 6
4 So Where Does That Leave Us? 7
5 To DABUS or Not to DABUS 8
6 The Copyright and AI Battle 9
7 Can the Four-Step Test Be Applied to AI-Generated Outputs
and Pave the Way for AI Ownership of Copyright? 12
8 Non-human Actors in the Originality Test 14
9 Artificial Intelligence: A Black Swan for Intellectual Property
Systems? 15
10 Legal and Ethical Considerations 17
11 Trustworthy AI 17
12 Patent Offices and AI 18
13 AI in Copyright Law 19
14 AI in Patent Law 21
15 Alas, Who Should the Intellectual Property Belong To? 21
References 23
xiii
xiv Contents
Fostering Innovation by Utilising Big Data: The Data Act and
the Risk of Quasi-Exclusivity Reinforcing Data Lockups 25
Marc A. Stuhldreier
1 Introduction 25
2 Utilising the Value of Big Data: Innovation in the Fourth
Industrial Revolution (4IR) 27
2.1 Big Data 27
2.2 The Importance of Big Data for Future Innovation in
the 4IR 30
2.3 Unlocking the Value/Potential of Big Data 31
3 The EU Data Strategy and the Data Act 38
3.1 The European Data Strategy 38
3.2 The Data Act 40
4 A de-Facto Exclusive Right to Data 53
4.1 The Problem with Exclusivity: Lessons from the
Global Harmonisation of Intellectual Property Rights 55
4.2 An Exclusive Right to Data and the Problem of IP
Overlaps 57
5 Conclusion 58
References 60
Legal Nature of NFTed Artwork: A Comparative Study 65
Jia Wang and Arianna Alpini
1 Introduction 65
2 Blockchain and the Tokenisation of Artwork 68
2.1 The Blockchains: Private, Public and Consortium Chain 68
2.2 The Tokens: Fungible and Non-fungible 69
3 The Trading of Artworks 70
4 Legal Status of NFT: The Common Law Approaches 73
4.1 The United Kingdom 73
4.2 Singapore 75
5 Legal Status of NFT: The Civil Law Approaches 76
5.1 The Theoretical and Legislative Discussion 76
5.2 European Cases 78
5.3 Chinese Cases 81
6 Conclusions 82
References 85
Contents xv
Intellectual Property Regulation of Artificial Intelligence: A
Matter of Time or a Step Too Far? 91
Lucius Klobucnik
1 Introduction 91
2 AI and Copyright 93
2.1 Originality of Works Created by AI 93
2.2 Potential Legislative Lead Given by Computer-
Generated Works 95
3 An Appropriate Mechanism to Use Copyright-Protected
Works by AI 96
3.1 AI Creator Learning from Existing Copyright-
Protected Works 96
3.2 Text and Data Mining (TDM) Exception 97
4 DABUS Case – A Milestone in Patent Case Law or an
Unsuccessful AI Challenge to Patent Law 101
4.1 AI and Patent Law 101
4.2 United Kingdom 101
4.3 USA 104
4.4 Germany 104
4.5 South Africa 106
4.6 Australia 106
5 Conclusion 107
References108
Care Robots for the Elderly: Legal, Ethical Considerations
and Regulatory Strategies129
Hui Yun Chan and Anantharaman Muralidharan
1 Introduction 129
1.1 An Ageing Population 129
1.2 Ethical Complexities 133
1.3 Deception and Manipulation 134
1.4 The ‘Zombie Relationship’ Problem 137
2 Governance Framework for Care Robots 141
2.1 Legal Complexities and Considerations 141
2.2 User Health, Safety and Wellbeing 143
2.3 Data Security and Privacy Protection 143
2.4 Balancing Innovations, Market and Protecting User
Safety145
2.5 Regulatory Strategies and Options 148
3 Conclusion 151
References152
Transformative (Bio)technologies in Knowledge Societies:
Of Patents and Intellectual Commons181
Mariela de Amstalden and Nivita Sukhadia
1 Transformative Biotechnologies: Cell-Cultivation for
Human Food Consumption 181
2 Saving the Intellectual Commons in Future Knowledge
Societies183
3 Patent Effectiveness and the WTO TRIPS 184
4 Conclusion 188
References188
A
nnexure: Table of Cases191
I ndex193
Notes on Contributors
xix
xx Notes on Contributors
Research in this area enters the rapidly growing artificial intelligence and
robotics industries in the legal, business, manufacturing, and healthcare
sectors and the impact of intellectual property protection on emerging
technologies. This chapter aims to develop an understanding of the legal
and ethical challenges posed by artificial intelligence and robotics tech-
nologies, along with consideration of appropriate legal and regulatory
responses. It provides a philosophical and legal framework for consider-
ing concepts and principles that relate to the development and use of
such technologies. It considers different legal and regulatory governance
regimes at the international, regional, and national levels. Currently, all
intellectual property rights created with human and artificial intelligence
“effort”, belong to the human however as artificial intelligence becomes
more sophisticated, the law on intellectual property protection will need
to adapt accordingly. The chapter will focus on the interplay between
N. Naim (*)
Law and Social Sciences, Aston University, Birmingham, UK
e-mail: n.naim@aston.ac.uk
owner has given permission for the use of copyrighted content. The reso-
lution added that AI or related technologies used for the registration pro-
cedure to grant IPRs and for the determination of liability for
infringements of IPRs cannot be a substitute for human review carried
out on a case-by-case basis, in order to ensure the quality and fairness of
decisions.
All WIPO signatories by in large follow the same four step test, indi-
vidual countries will differ on what they deem as an exclusion or excep-
tion dependent on the Constitution and commonly these fall under
morality or public policy. A patent is an official document that confers
proprietorship of an invention on the recipient, grant of a patent is pre-
ceded by examination of applications by the patenting authority. The
fundamental principle behind patents is that the government awards
exclusive control over an invention for a fixed number of years to the
individual who first discloses the invention within its territory.
In most systems, a patent is granted to an applicant who is first to
submit a detailed description of the invention, for example in the UK,
the system operates on a first to file model. The TRIPS agreement sought
to set international minimum standards in patent protection and at
8 N. Naim
After several consultations on Copyright and IP, the UK IPO has con-
firmed that a copyright work can be created by a human who has assis-
tance from AI. If the work expresses original human creativity it will
benefit from copyright protection like a work created using any other
tool. By default then, if the work is AI assisted or generated and lacks
original human creativity, it cannot be classed as a copyright work.
Exclusion apply to computer generated works as a sui generis right.
CDPA section 178 a computer generated work with no human author,
the “author” of a “computer- generated work” (CGW) is defined as “the
person by whom the arrangements necessary for the creation of the work
are undertaken”. The protection lasts for 50 years from the date the work
is made.
Distinction between when there is human involvement to when there
isn’t needs to be made more clear which can be achieved with a tiered
distinction between AI assisted and AI generated in all categories of copy-
right, not only computer generated works.
The extent and nature of human involvement needs to be specified.
Does it suffice if a human instructs an AI application to produce music
of a specific genre? Is that sufficient to make the resulting work fall out-
side the qualification of AI generated work? This is relevant to authorship
and ownership of the work. Thinking about the creative process in
AI-assisted outputs, who does the creative process in AI-assisted started
with, what is the equivalent production for the idea expression dichot-
omy (Fig. 1).
The Institute for Information Law (IViR) and Centre for International
Intellectual Property Studies (CEIPI) carried out a survey looking at
music and AI outputs and found many of the AI music outputs examined
will likely pass steps (1), (2) and (4). The crux of the test is therefore in
step (3), the core of the originality standard under copyright law. From
this perspective then, where an output does not qualify as original in the
sense that it reflects the author’s free and creative choices, that output is,
from the perspective of copyright, in the public domain. Although it
could still benefit from protection under related rights, where is the
incentive for artificial system creators to further enhance and improve the
offering of systems if the current copyright laws exclude the AI generated
work from protection (Bulayenko 2017).
In the context of step (3), it is possible in the first place to identify a
series of external constraints on the assessment of originality: rule- based,
technical, functional, and informational. The existence of such con-
straints reduces the author’s margin for creative freedom, sometimes
below the originality threshold. In the second place, the step allows for
the identification of three iterative stages of the creative process when
using an AI system: “conception”, “execution”, and “redaction” as dis-
cussed above. The iterative stages could support the qualification of AI
outputs for copyright protected work. (Grauwe and Gryspeerdt 2022).
The Office will not register works produced by a machine or mere mechan-
ical process that operates randomly or automatically without any creative
Artificial Intelligence Creations and Ownership – Who Should… 15
This links back to the initial argument of this chapter as to whether the
current divide between AI assisted and AI generated requires further clar-
ification or better yet, whether a third wave of AI will address step 3 of
the copyright test and be able to fulfil all three iterative stages of the origi-
nality test.
11 Trustworthy AI
Although the advantages of AI in our daily lives are undeniable, there are
concerns about its dangers. Inadequate physical security, economic losses,
and ethical issues are just a few examples of the damage AI could cause.
As discussed earlier, the European Commission has identified examples
of unacceptable risk as uses of AI that manipulate human behavior and
systems that allow social-credit scoring (European Commission, 2021).
For example, the European legal framework would prohibit an AI system
similar to China’s social credit scoring (Marcia 2021). A legal framework
would require minimum level of uniformity at an international level, for
example, through the TRIPS agreement or a supplementary provision
with staggered grace periods dependent upon individual states’
18 N. Naim
standards for AI. The reasoning for this is that the AI systems, albeit far
more sophisticated in the current wave of AI, still lack sentient ability and
despite the ability for AI to create a product, the role of a human is still
required. However, there will be a further wave of AI, and the exception
of computer-generated works will not suffice to meet the intellectual
effort of AI. The next stage for intellectual property law policy and ethics
is to create the framework where AI and humans can both have an equi-
table slice of the IP pie.
References
Barazza, S. The Year Of Data?, Journal of Intellectual Property Law & Practice,
Volume 16, Issue 2, February 2021, Pages 89–90, https://doi.org/10.1093/
jiplp/jpab024
Bulayenko, O, Frosio, G and Geiger, C. Opinion of the CEIPI on the European
Commission’s Proposal to Reform Copyright Limitations and Exceptions in
the European Union, Centre for International Intellectual Property Studies
(CEIPI) Research Paper No. 2017–09.
Cochrane, D and Mhangwane, C. Dabus: rise of inventive machines, (2022).
Spoor and Fisher. Available at https://spoor.com/dabus-the-rise-of-
the-inventive-machines/.
Cooke, C. Will Page says “music copyright has never had it so good” as global
revenues reach almost $40 billion (2022), Complete Music Update.
Copyright, Design and Patent Act 1988
EU Commission on Civil Law Rules on Robotics (2015/2103(INL)
European Commission, Coordinated Plan On Artificial Intelligence 2021 Review.
Available at https://digital-strategy.ec.europa.eu/en/library/coordinated-plan-
artificial-intelligence-2021-review
Fogel, D. Evolutionary Computation: Toward a New Philosophy of Machine
Intelligence, Third Edition, (2005), Wiley.
Grauwe, D P and Gryspeerdt, S. Artificial intelligence (AI): The qualification of
AI creations as “works” under EU copyright law, (2022), Grewer.
Guadamuz, A. Artificial intelligence and copyright (2017) World Intellectual
Property Office Magazine.
Hoppe, M. Theories and Applications of Artificial Intelligence. (2022). United
Kingdom: States Academic Press.
24 N. Naim
1 Introduction
In Thaler v Commissioner of Patents [2021] FCA 879, a judge of the
Federal Court of Australia for the first time found that an artificial intel-
ligence (AI) can satisfy the requirements to be regarded as an inventor
according to Australian patent laws. While the judgement was revoked in
2022, and other courts around the world do not seem to follow the initial
court’s approach anytime soon, this case provides an indication of how AI
and the Big Data which feeds its learning processes slowly but steadily
tend to pick up a ‘life’ of their own. Smart devices, as part of the Internet
of Things (IoT), that utilise AI have become prevalent in almost any
aspect of our day to day lives, including smart homes, the agricultural
sector, and medicinal products. The development, appropriate use and
advancement of such smart technologies requires vast amounts of data,
M. A. Stuhldreier (*)
Linköping University, Linköping, Sweden
e-mail: marc.stuhldreier@liu.se
recognises the need of facilitating access to data for the purpose of foster-
ing innovation with societal objectives, and for responding to current
challenges including in the fields of public health, agriculture and for
achieving the Sustainable Development Goals (SDGs). With its 50
Articles, the Data Act thus sets ambitious goals as to creating a level play-
ing field for the various stakeholders in what may be called user-generated
data. The task of striking an adequate balance is complicated by the num-
ber of contrasting interests at stake. Concerns can be raised over ques-
tions of access to data, its ownership, the protection of personality rights
of the users that provide the data, and particularly their right to self-
determination. On the other hand, increasing access to user-generated
data calls into question the protection of the legitimate rights of the
inventors of smart technologies. Ultimately, while recent EU legislation
aims for opening data lockups to make data accessible and re-usable, the
scope of these regulations seems to in fact strengthen the position of data
holders, providing them with further legal measures to maintain their
data enclosures (Noto La Diega 2022b).
In this respect, this contribution scrutinises the provisions of the Data
Act to analyse whether the Data Act is successful in striking an adequate
balance between the rights and obligations of the various stakeholders in user-
generated big data. Further, this chapter seeks to ascertain whether the
Data Act provides for sufficient accessibility to facilitate that data can be re-
used for innovation activity toward societal objectives.
In the digital age, data can be loosely described as a unit containing digi-
tal information. While information was always a valuable asset to human-
ity and thus sensitive for businesses, states and citizens, data can now be
defined as a building block in the modern digital economy (Burri 2021;
28 M. A. Stuhldreier
The importance of big data for the digital economy lies in its potential
value not just for the original data collector, but for a variety of stakehold-
ers (Jülicher 2018). Additional stakeholders include the users of smart
technology as well as, for example, manufacturers, aftermarket service
providers, insurances, health service providers, and public and private
sector researchers (Jülicher and Delisle 2018). Fully unlocking the poten-
tial of big data can provide enterprises with previously unknown infor-
mation. New insights derived through data analytics, such as identified
patterns and conclusions that indicate future trends, are big data’s pre-
dominant economic value, helping businesses to improve their decisions
and strategies (Storr and Storr 2017; Seuba 2021). Unsurprisingly, big
data is now of enormous economic interest, both for its value as a busi-
ness asset as well as for its future value that can be derived by unlocking
its innovative potential. In this regard, big data, and particularly personal
data, is often referred to as the new oil (Storr and Storr 2017). By not
only facilitating more efficient business operations but by also fostering
better innovation big data has vast potential to positively serve the public
interest (Burri 2021).
It is recognised today that data is key to achieving sustainability and
that adequately unlocking its potential is of enormous value for the com-
mon good. Access to and utilisation of data, for example, are considered
to be a key factor in achieving climate justice and sustainable innovation
Fostering Innovation by Utilising Big Data: The Data Act… 31
(Noto La Diega and Derclaye 2023). Similarly, health data collected from
wearables can be utilised to improve personal health by amending per-
sonal habits before health conditions occur, thereby helping to mitigate
modern public health issues (Storr and Storr, 2017). To make adequate
use of the information contained in big datasets, and to achieve these
societal objectives, it is crucial to unlock the potential of the collected
data. To be effective, it is important to recognise that data mining can be
conducted to gain new insights from currently unused big data, not only
by the data collector but by other stakeholders with access to the data as
well. For this to be effective at large, however, open access to the locked-
up data would be required. While competitors on the markets and the
general public thus have both economic and public interests in gaining
access to and utilising available data, the collectors of big data and those
who analyse it tend to also seek (legal) protection for their respective
interests in the data and its value (Gervais 2021). Overly strong protec-
tion, either via legal instruments such as intellectual property (IP) laws,
or through the factual control exercised by the data holder, can in turn
lockup data, hamper its utilisation, and prevent the realisation of big
data’s full potential for the societal benefit.
2.3.1 Data Ownership
interests take precedent (Storr and Storr 2017). In reality, while there is
no general legal property right to data, data holders can rely on other
measures such as trade secret protection and database rights as well as
technical and contractual measures to effectively establish a property-like
protection, providing them with a technical-factual position of data own-
ership (Noto la Diega 2023; Podszun and Pfeifer 2022; Storr and Storr
2017). Additionally, in the EU, the creator of a databank can own the
data contained in this databank via a sui generis right established by the
EU Database Directive (96/9/EC).
The main concern with property and property-like rights is that his-
torically, property rights derived from the need to regulate scarce
resources. Data, however, is not scarce and its use by one party does not
exclude another party from extracting value from the same data (Storr
and Storr 2017; Hornung and Schomberg 2022). This general non-
scarcity of data is also where its main potential lies if data is made suffi-
ciently accessible (Hornung and Schomberg 2022). With various
technical difficulties already hampering the adequate sharing of data, a
property-like right in data, adding a further layer of complications, can
severely exacerbate problems concerning the accessibility and utilisation
of data by the various stakeholders. Ultimately, property rights tend to be
of an exclusive nature, meaning that non-right holders, including the
general society the very users who generate the data, can be excluded
from enjoying the benefits arising from big data (Storr and Storr 2017).
While this recognition provides a strong argument against a property
right to data, a balanced approach to the question of ownership also
needs to take account of concomitant questions and debates concerning
the protection of investments and the maintaining of incentives for the
future generation of data. In essence, similar to the debates on industrial
IP rights, the incentive argument suggests that investors in data generat-
ing products and services need to be incentivised to make such invest-
ments by receiving protection which prevents competitors who did not
make similar investments from using the generated data (Kerber 2022).
Conversely, it may be argued that such incentives are less relevant in the
context of big data, particularly when collected via IoT devices, as the
data collection occurs automatically as a by-product of the regular use of
such devices. Thus, the required investment into the data collection itself
34 M. A. Stuhldreier
made between the individual and other (economic) actors. It thus seems
that, compared to an ownership right in user generated non-personal
data, privacy rights are stronger in that they cannot generally be traded
away (Storr and Storr 2017). In theory, data ownership could thus poten-
tially help mitigating some of the prevailing problems of the digital econ-
omy by providing individuals with a better negotiation position vis-à-vis
other economic actors (Thouvenin and Tamò-Larrieux 2021). Then
again, due to prevalent information asymmetries, it would be easy for
corporations to gain ownership of the data, for example, through hidden
contractual terms, a problem that already can be observed in the field of
data privacy where the use of intransparent consent tick boxes is
commonplace.
Ultimately, as long as clear regulations on data ownership and access
rights are missing, data collectors and developers of connected devices
can implement technical designs for products that provide them with the
de-facto control over the data collected by their devices, which
then enables them to effectively exclude competition and to prevent other
enterprises and organisations from using the available data for innovative
activities (Kerber 2022).
In addition to questions of data ownership, the second big issue for data
governance in the digital economy concerns the accessibility and re-use
of data. As of yet, there are no general data access rights, neither for busi-
nesses vis-à-vis other businesses, nor for government vis-à-vis businesses
(Thouvenin and Tamò-Larrieux 2021). The situation, however, is about
to change, with the implementation of the European Data Strategy, inter
alia, via the EU Data Governance Act, already providing for the accessi-
bility of publicly held data for further utilisation and re-use, and other
regulations, including the Data Act, following in the near future. From a
business perspective, data is generally viewed as a valuable asset that
should not be freely shared, particularly with competitors (Thouvenin
and Tamò-Larrieux 2021). Access to data, however, is a precondition for
market entry, participation in a supply chain and innovation (SWD(2022)
36 M. A. Stuhldreier
Recognising the high value of big data, and the challenges surrounding
its utilisation, the EU adopted the Digital Single Market (DSM) Strategy,
intending to unlock the economic and social potential of the digital
economy. One of the DSM’s key aims lies in facilitating the free flow of
data to improve its accessibility and utilisation, and to facilitate innova-
tion in the EU (Thouvenin and Tamò-Larrieux 2021; Hennemann and
Steinrötter 2022). According to the German Ethics Council it is crucial
to recognise the value of data as a social resource (Hornung und
Schomberg 2022). One of the key challenges of the digital transforma-
tion is to facilitate adequate data access for both individuals and busi-
nesses in accordance with fair competition standards, while simultaneously
safeguarding the protection of privacy and consumer rights as well as of
IP rights. To round-up the potential for value generation from big data,
the EU aims to likewise facilitate the transfer of knowledge and data
between public and private data holders. Free flow of data is further
regarded as a key component of European competitiveness in the global
digital economy (Thouvenin and Tamò-Larrieux 2021).
In February 2020, the EU supplemented the DSM by adopting the
European Data Strategy which aims at creating the necessary precondi-
tions for a genuine European data economy to establish Europe as a
global leader in the digital economy. The Data Act is one of the key pillars
Fostering Innovation by Utilising Big Data: The Data Act… 39
In recognition of the importance of data for the digital economy and for
achieving the green and digital transition as well as the fact that data
remains under-utilised where its value is held locked-up by a small num-
ber of large corporations which hampers the realisation of the full poten-
tial of the digital age, on 23 February 2022, the EU introduced a Proposal
for a Regulation on harmonised and fair access to and use of data (Data
Act, or DA) which aims to establish fairer access to and a fairer value
allocation from non-personal data. The proposed Regulation was adopted
by the Council on 15 November 2023. Unlocking enclosed data provides
immense potential for strengthening a sustainable data economy in
Fostering Innovation by Utilising Big Data: The Data Act… 41
Europe that can reduce the “digital divide” and shall create beneficial
opportunities that are available to everyone. To achieve this, data access
and its use need to be regulated accordingly. Notably, the European
Council explicitly concluded in October 2021 that the regulatory frame-
work for facilitating this accessibility of data shall be conducive to inno-
vation (COM(2022) 68 final at 1). As will be elaborated below, however,
the Data Act is unlikely to achieve its goal of creating an environment
that enables the full potential of innovativeness as exclusive rights and
quasi-exclusive rights that protect data holders remain in place and con-
tinue to restrict the accessibility of data for research purposes. The prob-
lem of insufficient data access and use for societal purposes is thus not
sufficiently mitigated by this regulation.
In March 2021, the European parliament further recognised and high-
lighted the need for the creation of European data spaces that should
enable the free flow of data between different sectors and between public
and private stakeholders, including academia (COM(2022) 68 final at
2). While this statement found its way into the Explanatory Memorandum
of the Data Act, the Act itself provides no direct data access rights for
academia, limiting any public sector access to situations of exceptional
need, such as public emergencies (Arts. 14 and 21 DA) or to situations
where data access is granted to academia as a third party by request of the
user of a device (Art. 5 DA). The European Parliament further high-
lighted the importance of tackling restrictions of competition, barriers to
market entry and broader issues concerning the access and use of data
that arise from data enclosures. In this regard, the Data Act aims at facili-
tating that EU businesses of all sectors receive opportunities through
which they can be innovative and competitive (COM(2022) 68 final at 2).
Importantly, the Explanatory Memorandum clarifies that the provi-
sions on data access do not change the scope of previous regulation and
protection of data through IP rights, which remain unaltered with the
notable exception of the sui generis right established by the Database
Directive. Similarly, the Data Act will not amend previous European data
legislation on sectoral level, but any (future) sectoral legislation should
“be aligned with the horizontal principles of the Data Act” (COM(2022)
68 final at 5). In this regard, the Data Act was proposed as a horizontal
full-harmonisation regulation that shall provide basic rules applicable to
42 M. A. Stuhldreier
services. Central to the regulations of the Data Act is thus the creation of
mandatory data access rights for both private and business users of con-
nected devices (Specht-Riemenschneider, 2022a). Importantly, the Data
Act shall facilitate innovation by opening data enclosures, while main-
taining sufficient incentives for the generation of new data (Hennemann
and Steinrötter 2022; Podszun and Pfeifer 2022). To achieve the aim of
opening data enclosures, the Data Act regulates data accessibility by
addressing three main socio-economic dimensions: business to consumer
(B2C) relationships, business to business (B2B) relationships, and
Business to Government (B2G) relationships (Podszun and Pfeifer 2022).
According to Article 1, the Data Act applies to:
Notably, similar to the applicability of the GDPR, the Data Act fol-
lows the lex loci solutionis principle, meaning that its applicability is sub-
ject to the relevant marketplace. In other words, the regulations of the
Data Act apply to all data holders when data is generated within the
European market (Hennemann and Steinrötter 2022). Additionally,
44 M. A. Stuhldreier
Article 1(5) DA provides that the Data Act is without prejudice to the
applicability of EU data privacy and data protection laws, and that the
access rights of Chap. II of the Data Act shall supplement the access and
portability rights of the GDPR. Considering, however, that user gener-
ated data in many instances is likely to be of personal nature, the Data
Act leaves various tensions between data access and data protection largely
unresolved (Kerber 2022).
Article 2 DA provides definitions that apply for the purposes of the
regulation. Here, data is defined as “any digital representation of acts,
facts or information and any compilation of such acts, facts or informa-
tion, including in the form of sound, visual or audio-visual recording”
(Art. 2(1) DA). The term data is thus not simply regarded as synonymous
to the term information but is rather regarded as a means for transporting
information (Hennemann and Steinrötter 2022). Notably, storage
devices and mere online services are a priori excluded from the scope of
the Data Act (Specht-Riemenschneider 2022b). Furthermore, recital 15
specifically excludes derivative data – i.e. data that results from the pro-
cessing or analysis of raw data – from the regulations of the Data Act
(Recital 15 DA). This exclusion is particularly regrettable as raw data can
often be too limited to be re-usable, while the re-use of derivative data
could provide valuable insights, benefitting research for societal purposes
(Podszun and Pfeifer 2022). In contrast to raw data, however, the cre-
ation of derivative data requires an effort by the data holder and may thus
be protected by IP rights. Where such data is not protected by IP rights,
the Data Act may then strengthen the exclusive position of data holders
in the future. For achieving the aim of promoting innovation towards
sustainability and the common good, however, it is key that adequate
data accessibility is designed in a way that facilitates the unlocking of the
full value of big data (Noto La Diega and Derclaye 2023).
actual costs incurred by making the data available (Art. 9(4) DA). In
general, the Data Act seems to emphasize the specific needs of small
enterprises, as Article 7 DA completely exempts data holders who qualify
as small and micro enterprises according to Union law from the B2C and
B2B data sharing requirements, provided that they are not linked to
other enterprises or partner organisations (Art. 7 DA).
In addition to the B2C and B2B data access rights, chapter V of the Data
Act provides a direct data access entitlement for the public sector, i.e.
public sector bodies or Union Institutions, agencies and bodies. The
main regulation facilitating public sector access, Article 14 DA, however,
strictly limits the access right to situations of exceptional need (Art. 14
DA). Article 15 DA then defines that an exceptional need to use data
shall be limited in time and scope, and only exists in circumstances:
As the arguments for a de facto control of data holders are quite similar
to the debates concerning patent rights, the following analysis shall exem-
plify the conflict between exclusive rights and innovation by reference to
a notable experience that emerged from the international harmonisation
of minimum patent protection standards through the WTO TRIPS
Agreement. One of the main arguments for introducing patent rights for
all fields of technology, including the pharmaceutical sector, in countries,
and particularly developing countries that formerly did not provide for
the patentability of pharmaceuticals was that patents provide inventors
with an incentive for being innovative. The premise of stronger global
patent protection was then to increase encouragement for the develop-
ment of new medicines, including products that serve the interests of the
developing world. Particularly in the field of pharmaceuticals, the devel-
opment of new products involves substantially high costs and are regarded
as a high-risk investment (Abbott 2015; ECOSOC 2001; Hestermeyer
2007; Reichman 2009). Granting exclusive rights via the provision of
patents should then incentivise high risk investments by facilitating the
successful commercialisation of new medicines through the provision of
time-limited monopoly positions on the markets (Abbott 2011; Flynn
56 M. A. Stuhldreier
et al. 2009). As tackling global disease burdens not only requires the
affordability of existing medications, but also the future availability of
new medicines, it can be argued that limited exclusive rights provide a
balance between the interests of industry and the wider societal interests
(Abbott 2015; Henry and Searles 2012; Phillips 2006).
While it may be true that an adequate level of patent protection can be
beneficial for stimulating innovation, overly strong or excessive protec-
tion may in fact have detrimental impacts on innovation by creating new
obstacles for future research activity. As innovation is frequently the result
of research activity that builds upon prior discoveries, a stringent patent
protection of older inventions is liable to prevent researchers from utilis-
ing existing knowledge, thereby delaying future innovation (Abbott
2015; Richards 2008; Smith et al. 2009). A continuous proliferation of
patent protection therefore directly contradicts its very purpose of stimu-
lating innovation by restricting the innovative activity of competitors.
The exclusive rights granted under patent protection thus can be used to
effectively hinder innovation (Richards 2008; ECOSOC 2001). This
concern is particularly prevalent in the pharmaceutical sector, where the
development of an administrable medicine is the result of several stages
of innovation. As each of these stages can potentially suffice for fulfilling
patentability requirements, the granting of patents can create further
obstacles for researchers who cannot utilise the results of previous devel-
opment steps if a competitor receives exclusive protection (ECOSOC
2001). By restricting opportunities for utilising existing knowledge, the
exclusive rights granted to patentees are therefore liable to ultimately
delay technological progress (Richards 2008). By and large, it can be
summarised that the global introduction of pharmaceutical patent rights
created new obstacles that hamper appropriate research efforts, thereby
defeating the very purposes for which they were introduced. Adding a
new layer to this protection by consolidating quasi-exclusive rights for
data holders of user generated raw data, particularly from smart health
devices, would in all probability create further obstacles, aggravating the
already problematic situation.
Fostering Innovation by Utilising Big Data: The Data Act… 57
5 Conclusion
This chapter has highlighted the importance of big data for the modern
digital economy and particularly the crucial importance of facilitating
access to data to enhance meaningful innovation toward societal objec-
tives. Section 3 has introduced the European strategy on how data can be
used more efficiently, including consideration of how access for the vari-
ous stakeholders shall be facilitated. In this respect, this contribution
took a deeper look at the initial proposal of the Data Act that shall estab-
lish fairer access to and a fairer value allocation from non-personal data.
The unlocking of data enclosures shall thereby strengthen a sustainable
data economy in Europe, creating beneficial opportunities for everyone.
Fostering Innovation by Utilising Big Data: The Data Act… 59
References
Aaronson, S. A. (2021). Data is Different, so Policymakers should pay Close
Attention to its Governance. In M. Burri (Ed.), Big Data and Global Trade
Law (pp. 340–359) Cambridge University Press
Abbott, F.M. (2011). Intellectual Property and Public Health: Meeting the
Challenge of Sustainability. Global Health Programme Working Paper
No7/2011. Retrieved December 12, 2023, from https://papers.ssrn.com/
sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1965458
Abbott, F.M. (2015). Trade in Medicines. In R. Smith et al. (eds), Trade and
Health: Towards Building a National Strategy (pp. 117–136) World Health
Organization
Fostering Innovation by Utilising Big Data: The Data Act… 61
Bartke, L. et al. (2022). Der Schutz von Trainingsdaten de lege ferenda: What
would Machlup do? RDi Recht Digital, 431–439
Burri, M. (2021). Data Flows and Global Trade Law. In M. Burri (Ed.), Big
Data and Global Trade Law (pp. 11–41) Cambridge University Press
Culik, N. (2018). Brussels Calling: Big Data and Privacy. In T. Hoeren, &
B. Kolany-Raiser (Eds.), Big Data in Context: Legal, Social and Technological
Insights (pp. 29–35) Springer Nature
Drexl, J. et al. (2016). Data Ownership and Access to Data – Position Statement
of the Max Planck Institute for Innovation and Competition of 16 August
2016 on the Current European Debate. Max Planck Institute for Innovation
& Competition Research Paper No. 16–10. Retrieved December 12, 2023,
from http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2833165
Ferracane, M. F. (2021). The Cost of Data Protectionism. In M. Burri (Ed.), Big
Data and Global Trade Law (pp. 63–82) Cambridge University Press
Flynn, S., Hollis A. and Palmedo M. (2009). An Economic Justification for
Open Access to Essential Medicine Patents in Developing Countries. 37
Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 184–208
G20, (2019, June 29). G20 Osaka Leaders’ Declaration. Retrieved December 12,
2023, from https://www.consilium.europa.eu/media/40124/final_g20_
osaka_leaders_declaration.pdf
Gervais, D. J. (2021). TRIPS Meets Big Data. In M. Burri (Ed.), Big Data and
Global Trade Law (pp. 160–176) Cambridge University Press
Hennemann, M. & Steinrötter, B. (2022). Data Act – Fundament des neuen
EU-Datenwirtschaftsrechts? NJW Neue Jusristische Wochenschrift, 1481–1486
Henry, D. and Searles, A. (2012). Chapter 9: Pharmaceutical Pricing Policy. In
Management Sciences for Health (ed.) MDS-3: Managing Access to Medicines
and Health Technologies (at 9.2–9.22) 3rd edn, Management Sciences
for Health
Hestermeyer, H. (2007) Human Rights and the WTO: The Case of Patents and
Access to Medicines. Oxford University Press
Hornung, G. and Schomberg, S. (2022). Datensouveränität im Spannungsfeld
zwischen Datenschutz und Datenzugang: das Beispiel des Data Governance
Acts. Computer und Recht, 508–516
Irion, K. (2021). Panta Rhei: A European Perspective on Ensuring a High Level
of Protection of Human Rights in a World in Which Everything Flows. In
M. Burri (Ed.), Big Data and Global Trade Law (pp. 231–242) Cambridge
University Press
62 M. A. Stuhldreier
Podszun, R. and Pfeifer, C. (2022). Datenzugang nach dem EU Data Act: Der
Entwurf der Europäischen Kommission. Gewerblicher Rechtsschutz und
Urheberrecht, 953–961
Regulation (EU) 2016/679 of the European Parliament and of the Council of
27 April 2016 on the protection of natural persons with regard to the pro-
cessing of personal data and on the free movement of such data, and repeal-
ing Directive 95/46/EC (General Data Protection Regulation). Retrieved
December 12, 2023, from https://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/TXT/
PDF/?uri=CELEX:32016R0679
Reichman, J.H. (2009). Comment: Compulsory Licensing of Patented
Pharmaceutical Inventions: Evaluating the Options. 37 Journal of Law,
Medicine & Ethics, 247–263
Richards, D.G. (2008). A Skeptik’s View of Intellectual Property Rights. In
R.C. Bird & S.C. Jain (eds), The Global Challenge of Intellectual Property
Rights (pp. 267–282) Edward Elgar Publishing
Röttgen, C. (2018). Like or Dislike – Web Tracking. In T. Hoeren, & B. Kolany-
Raiser (Eds.), Big Data in Context: Legal, Social and Technological Insights
(pp. 73–79) Springer Nature
Seuba, X. (2021). Big Data, AI and Border Enforcement of Intellectual Property
Rights. In M. Burri (Ed.), Big Data and Global Trade Law (pp. 177–192)
Cambridge University Press.
Smith, R.D., Correa, C. and Oh, C. (2009). Trade, TRIPS, and Pharmaceuticals.
373 The Lancet, 684-691
Specht-Riemenschneider, L. (2022a). Der Entwurf des Data Act: Ein großer
Wurf in die falsche Richtung? GRUR Gewerblicher Rechtsschutz und
Urheberrecht, 937–938
Specht-Riemenschneider, L. (2022b). Data Act – Auf dem (Holz-)Weg zu mehr
Dateninnovation? Zeitschrift für Rechtspolitik, 137–140
Specht-Riemenschneider, L. (2022c). Der Entwurf des Data Act: Eine Analyse
der vorgesehenen Datenzugangsansprüche im Verhältnis B2B, B2C und
B2G. MMR Zeitschrift für IT-Recht und Recht der Digitalisierung, 809–826
Storr, C. & Storr, P. (2017). Internet of Things: Rights to Data from a European
Perspective. In M. Corrales et al. (Eds.), New Technology, Big Data and the
Law (pp. 65–96) Springer Nature
Thaler v Commissioner of Patents [2021] FCA 879
The European Commission. (2022, February 23). Proposal for a Regulation of the
European Parliament and of the Council on harmonised rules on fair access to
and use of data (Data Act). COM(2022) 68 final. Retrieved December 12,
64 M. A. Stuhldreier
1 Introduction
The platform economy is the tendency for commerce to move increas-
ingly towards digital platform business models. Platforms are underlying
computer systems that can host services allowing consumers, entrepre-
neurs, businesses and the general public to connect, share resources or sell
products. Blockchain technology can support immutable and trustless
transactions in a distributed and disintermediated way among various
users. The trustless environments that blockchains have created enable
peer-to-peer (P2P) sending and receiving transactions, smart contract
agreements, and more. On the blockchain platform, tokenisation is used
to transform ownerships and rights of particular assets into a digital form.
J. Wang (*)
Durham Law School, Durham University, Durham, UK
e-mail: jia.wang2@durham.ac.uk
A. Alpini
Department of Law, University of Macerata, Macerata, Italy
e-mail: arianna.alpini@unimc.it
NFTs fully. When buying an art piece, one does not purchase its copy-
right, which would have to be transferred separately. According to inter-
national copyright law, to own a piece of artwork does not necessarily
entail the subsequent right to display the work in a public place and col-
lect copyright royalties paid for the use of the work. The right to display
and receive royalties remains with the copyright holder.
In this chapter, we explore the legal nature of NFTed artwork. When
purchasing an NFTed artwork, what rights and interests does the pur-
chaser acquire? Is holding an NFTed work equivalent to holding a physi-
cal copy? The objectives of this chapter are, first, to contextualise the
discussion against the background of the trade of artworks in a block-
chain environment; second, to examine the most recent legislation and
court decisions concerning NFTs and cryptocurrency; finally, to conduct
a comparative study between the selected common law and civil law sys-
tems of their concept of assets and property in relation to NFTs.
We undertake a comparative approach to facilitate the understanding
of how different jurisdictions view the legal nature of NFTs. We look at
the Anglo-American countries, then turn to Europe and China as civil
law jurisdictions. Traditionally, the two legal systems view property rights
differently. A comparative study offers insight into whether the conver-
gence of law applies to legal issues of global relevance in a digital environ-
ment. Furthermore, this chapter conducts a case study of the most recent
court decisions concerning property and intellectual property issues. As
the legislation could lag behind the speedy advancement of technologies,
court decisions offer a more timely reflection of the judiciary’s attitude
to NFTs.
This chapter proceeds as follows. The first section introduces block-
chain and NFTs as an application of blockchain technologies, particu-
larly the tokenisation of artwork. The second section examines how
artworks are traded in the mortar-and-brick era and the digital era. The
third and fourth sections scrutinise the common law and civil law
approaches towards NFTs and the NFTed artwork. The last section offers
a comparative analysis of the different approaches and provides conclud-
ing remarks.
68 J. Wang and A. Alpini
Blockchains have been developed into three types: private chain, public
chain and consortium chain. Private chains operate under the control of
certain individuals or organisations. This is done by setting up a permis-
sioned network, restricting the individuals allowed to participate in the
network and transactions (Jayachandran 2017). As participants must
obtain an invitation to join the network, private chains can filter out
illegal activities within a chain (Iredale 2021). Yet as there are fewer nodes
within the chain, the entire chain may become more easily compromised,
posing a potential security risk (Brown 2022). Having a unique hash is
vital for maintaining security throughout the different blocks because
there are concerns about hackers tampering with the blocks and changing
the hashes.
In contrast to a private chain, public chains, such as Bitcoin and
Ethereum, are openly accessible to all who can access the internet
(Jayachandran 2017), who can also see the ledger and participate in the
consensus process (Iredale 2021). This design enables participants in a
public chain to have equal rights and boosts transparency (Iredale 2021).
Yet it also comes with drawbacks. For instance, a high amount of compu-
tational power is necessary for a public chain to function, to maintain the
distributed ledger at a large scale (Jayachandran 2017). It takes a rela-
tively long time to verify each transaction compared to other chains.
A consortium chain is a permissioned ledger where information can
only be shared among a small group of organisations (Crypto News 2021).
It is formed by combining various private blockchains belonging to differ-
ent groups, where each group forms a node on the chain as a stakeholder.
While each group manages its own blockchain, the data within it can be
accessed, shared and distributed among the other organisations in the
consortium (Bybit Learn 2022). A consortium chain is created among
organisations to facilitate cooperation among these groups (Banerjee
Legal Nature of NFTed Artwork: A Comparative Study 69
collection and uploading work (OpenSea Learn 2022). The third method
to create tokens is through tokenisation by linking or embedding the
economic value and the rights derived from the asset to digital tokens
created on the blockchain (OECD 2020). The tokenised asset can then
be listed and sold on NFT marketplaces. In this chapter, we mainly focus
on the third tokenisation method for discussing NFTed artworks.
with the act of minting. The purchase of the NFTed AI-created artwork
takes place by creating and minting the artwork.
However, NFTs are not the artwork, nor does it become the artwork.
The NFT records the existence and ownership of the artwork onto the
blockchain, and because no two NFTs are the same, and no two block-
chain registrations can be the same, the tokenised asset linked to the NFT
also can be considered unique and non-fungible. Each NFT contains
metadata that describes the corresponding assets in order to prove the
physical object’s authenticity or rarity. The NFT represents the physical
object in code written into the blockchain containing various informa-
tion. This information frequently contains the name of the creator of the
NFT, a URL linking to a representation of the underlying work of the
NFT, the date it was minted, and any contractual terms that follow the
NFT after it is sold. While the separate URL embedded in the NFT con-
tains a link to a copy of the underlying work, it is not itself a copy of that
work. Thus, an NFT is not a reproduction of content; it is merely a token
that authenticates the source of the content. For this reason, NFTs them-
selves are not “copies” and thus not subject to copyright infringement.
The metadata does not contain any recognisable content of the underly-
ing work, nor does it describe its contents. Similarly, the metadata does
not add, transform, or recast any underlying work.
Nevertheless, NFT establishes an exclusive ownership relationship
with the underlying artwork. The hash is stored on a blockchain with an
associated time stamp. Consequently, NFT keeps track of hash sales, so it
is possible to trace the hand steps of the hash to the creator. This mecha-
nism provides proof of authenticity and, simultaneously, ownership of
the work. The transfer of an NFT connected to a work of art transfers the
digital ownership of the authentic copy of the work; however, the pur-
poses that can be pursued with this tool are different, so it is necessary to
identify the crypto activity, the specific utility that the NFT is intended
to create from time to time.
Authors can create and sell NFTs representing their works. In practice,
the NFT digital art market recognises the owner of a “legitimate” NFTed
work as the “owner” of the work, even though NFTs do not convey copy-
right ownership of the work (Frye 2022). NFT owners encourage others
to use their work because popularity increases the value of the work.
Legal Nature of NFTed Artwork: A Comparative Study 73
Increasing the author’s impact creates more value than controlling the use
of the work. If the profit from selling NFTs alone is large enough to moti-
vate authors, copyright is no longer necessary as a legal monopoly to
reward authors. The value of art has always come from the reputation of
the author and the scarcity of the work through “authenticity”.
views property as being of only two kinds, choses in possession and cho-
ses in action” (AA at [55], citing Colonial Bank v Whinney [1885]
(“Colonial Bank”)). Bitcoins, and other cryptocurrencies, did not fall
neatly into either category and thus could not be classified as a form of
property (AA at [56] and [58]). Bryan J, however, considered that it was
“fallacious to proceed on the basis that the English law of property recog-
nises no forms of property other than choses in possession and choses in
action” (AA at [58]). In doing so, he cited extensively from the legal state-
ment on crypto assets and smart contracts published by the UK
Jurisdiction Task Force (the “Legal Statement”). Thus, the Task Force
believed that Colonial Bank was not to be treated as limiting the scope of
what kinds of things could be property in law. Rather, it showed the abil-
ity of the common law to stretch “traditional definitions and concepts to
adapt to new business practices” (Legal Statement at [77]). The Legal
Statement, therefore, formed the basis for Bryan J’s conclusion that while
a crypto asset might not be a thing in action based on a narrow definition
of that term, it could still be considered property (AA at [59]). He made
a finding that crypto assets such as Bitcoin were property, given that they
met the four criteria set out in National Provincial Bank Ltd. v Ainsworth
[1965] (“Ainsworth”) at 1248 – namely that it must be “definable, iden-
tifiable by third parties, capable in its nature of assumption by third par-
ties, and have some degree of permanence or stability”.
The UK’s High Court recently ruled that NFTs are property, and thus
victims of NFT theft can now have their stolen assets frozen through
court injunctions. The decision comes after months of repeated NFT
thefts, as savvy hackers have exploited loopholes and poor security liter-
acy to seize high-profile NFTs. In an earlier case involving NFTs
(Osbourne v Persons Unknown [2022]), the court also found a claimant
has a good arguable case that misappropriated crypto assets are held on a
constructive trust is therefore clear that the courts are open to construc-
tive trust claims as regards crypto assets. However, Ms. Osbourne did not
go so far as to seek, as Mr. D’Aloia has, to ask the courts to consider a
claim in which – in addition to the alleged fraudsters - the exchanges are
also said to hold the crypto assets on constructive trust. In D’Aloia case,
therefore, appears to be the first in which the Court has found that there
is a good arguable case for this claim against the exchanges themselves.
Legal Nature of NFTed Artwork: A Comparative Study 75
4.2 Singapore
Lee Seiu Kin J adopted the Ainsworth test and upheld the following
findings. First, an NFT with its unique metadata is definable (Janesh s/o
Rajkumar, [44]). NFTs are not just mere information, but rather, data
encoded in a certain manner and securely stored on the blockchain ledger
(Janesh s/o Rajkumar, [58]) ‘It provides instructions to the computer
under a system whereby the “owner” of the NFT has exclusive control
over its transfer from his wallet to any other wallet.’ (Janesh s/o Rajkumar,
[58]) Second, per the second requirement that the “asset must have an
owner being capable of being recognised as such by third parties” (CLM,
[45(b)], citing Ruscoe at [109]) the presumptive NFT owner would be
whoever controls the wallet which is linked to the NFT an NFT with its
private keys would be an asset, with an owner being capable of being
recognised as such by third parties. The third requirement is that “that the
right must be capable of assumption by third parties, which in turn
involves two aspects: that third parties must respect the rights of the
owner in that asset, and that the asset must be potentially desirable” The
‘nature of the blockchain technology gives the owner the exclusive ability
to transfer the NFT to another party, which underscores the “right” of
the owner.’ Lastly, an NFT has a relevant degree of permanence and sta-
bility as money in bank accounts which, nowadays, exist mainly in the
form of ledger entries and not cold hard cash.
In summary, Singapore’s first court decision on NFTs rejects the anal-
ogy between a title deed and a certificate of property. The court applies
the Ainsworth criteria and upholds NFTs as property.
thing as the objects of real rights but also incorporeal assets, such as pat-
rimonial rights” (Von Bar and Drobnig 2004). However, some legal sys-
tems take a narrower approach concerning the scope of the property,
which is limited to “corporeal things”, as is the case under both German
and Swiss law (e.g. §§90 Bürgerliches Gesetzbuch30 -BGB- or §641
Swiss Civil Code 31). This means that tokens could not be regarded as
the object of property in these legal systems, e.g. in Germany, tokens have
been defined as “eine faktische Vermögensposition”, meaning ‘a factual
situation’ (Lehman and Krysa 2019). Other EU legal systems have either
incorporated a broader definition of the concept of a “thing” to include
“patrimonial or valuable rights” (e.g. arts. 334.10 CC; §§292, 298 and
299 Allgemeines bürgerliches Gesetzbuch, ABGB35) or a broader defini-
tion of the concept of an “asset” (art. 3.1 Burgerlijk Wetboek -BW-),
which makes regulating tokens as an object of ownership more accessible.
For example, in Spain, the judgment of the Supreme Court 20/06/201937
denied the recognition of bitcoin as a legal tender (money) but consid-
ered it an “incorporeal asset”. In Italy, tokens have been regarded as “digi-
tal assets” under the provisions of art. 810 Italian Civil Code (“Sono beni
le cose che possono formare oggetto di diritti”); and art. 65 French Loi n.
486 categorises tokens as “incorporeal assets” (bien incorporel).
From an EU perspective, the Proposal for a Regulation of the European
Parliament and of the Council on Markets in Crypto-assets (MiCA) 24
September 2020 aims to enhance legal certainty to crypto-assets while
encouraging innovation and protecting consumers. However, this pro-
posal does not cover the legal nature, the legal effects and the admissibil-
ity of using asset-backed tokens to transfer property rights. Tokens issued
in blocks of fewer than 150 tokens are excluded from the Regulation. So,
the Regulation does not cover small issuances, which are typically the
case in the tokenisation of real-world assets. The European Union Court
of Justice has ruled that cryptocurrencies fall into legal goods exempt
from VAT (EUCG, sez. V, 22 October 2015, case − 214/2016).
China’s first Civil Code became effective in 2021 and includes provi-
sions peripherally relevant to virtual assets. In Book I General Provisions,
Article 114 provides that civil subjects enjoy property rights (rights in
rem), which are the exclusive rights to directly dominate a particular
thing, including ownership, usufructuary rights, and security interests.
78 J. Wang and A. Alpini
Article 116 is a Numerus Clausus that limits the types and contents of
property rights exclusively by law. Article 127 provides that the Civil
Code shall recognise the existing legal provisions for virtual property.
names are reproduced. The decision indicated that the court viewed the
infringement of IP by NFTs as equivalent to an infringement made
through physical reproduction. Therefore, we can deduce that the court
considers NFT as equivalent to (intellectual) property.
At the European level, the Court of Rome is the first to order an
injunction to the creation and marketing of NFTs infringing registered
trademarks. It also ordered the NFTs to be removed from the trading
website. The decision represents a reference point at a global level at a
time when strong attention is paid, by all operators in the sector, to the
legal aspects of this new digital tool. It goes from who defines NFT as “a
digital not interchangeable good, such as a photograph, a song or a video,
whose property has been authenticated and stored in a database called
blockchain and which can be collected, sold and exchanged on various
online platforms” (Trevisi et al. 2022) to those who consider them as
“unique digital certificates, registered in a blockchain, used as a means to
register the ownership of an object, as a digital artwork or a collectible
object” (EUIPO 2022). The decision represents an implicit accreditation
of the interpretation - already adopted by the main national and interna-
tional offices, including EUIPO, for which Class 9 is the one for regis-
tered trademarks used to distinguish certain types of “digital goods”.
The Italian Court reiterates the provision of art. 97 of the Copyright
Law, relating to the permitted uses of the right to the image of a person,
does not extend to the use of trademarks possibly represented in the same
image. The same consideration, however, also introduces the probably
most important concept of the decision, which confirms the fact that the
creation of NFTs - which are “goods intended for commercial sale” -
requires specific authorisation from the proprietor of the trade mark, of
which it, therefore, constitutes a separate infringement and distinct from
the infringement constituted by the use of the trademark in the digital
images associated with the NFT.
This confirms the preference for a legal definition of NFT that under-
takes a dichotomy between the certificate and the content (Janesh s/o
Rajkumar v Unknown Person 2022 SGHC 264). Above all, it explains
the ratio of the same precautionary order, which is not by chance kept
well distinguished between NFTs and the corresponding digital content,
inhibits the “production, marketing, promotion and offer for sale, direct
80 J. Wang and A. Alpini
and/or indirect, in any way and form” of, on the one hand “of the NFT
(non-fungible token)” and, on the other hand, of any other “digital con-
tent or product generally bearing the photograph, even modified, and/or
the Juventus trademarks, as well as the use of said trademarks in any form
and manner”. This judgement echoes the US court decision involving
Maison Hermes against the artist Mason Rothschild and Nike in relevant
goods traded in StockX, a second-hand market.
This dichotomy of NFT/digital content cannot be ignored in the latter
case. The judge needs to decide whether the creation of an NFT generates
an intrinsic value rather than a mere digital certificate of ownership of the
associated property, which, hypothetically, the person who mints and
uploads the NFTed work is the legitimate owner of the work. We can
deduce that even if someone possesses a good legitimately, it can be
unlawful for the legitimate owner to produce NFTs of the good protected
by IP rights. Since the judgments are still at a first summary level, we can
only speculate on this issue.
The Commercial Law Court of Barcelona (Visual Entidad De Gestion
De Artistas Plasticos/ Punto Fa, S.L. [2022] AJM B 1900/2022 –
ECLI:ES: JMB: 2022:1900, Juzgado de lo Mercantil n° 09 de Barcelona)
delivered one of the first judgments dealing with the relationship between
intellectual property and NFT. The decision involves the fast fashion
brand Mango and the Spanish collective society for artists VEGAP
(Visual Entidad de Gestión de Artistas Plásticos). In March 2022, Mango
exhibited a series of artworks created by Farkas, an artist, in a virtual
museum on the Decentraland, a Web 3.0 site. Mango legitimately owns
the original copy of the works. The collection was designed to reinterpret
rather than directly reproduce the artworks, which are under copyright
protection. VEGAP sued Mango for copyright infringement, arguing
that the minting and displaying of the artworks infringed copyright;
Mango argued that the NFTs were just a list on OpenSea and did not
represent any proprietary rights per se. The Court ordered tokens to be
de-listed, and further pointed out that the withdrawal of a work does not
amount to destroying tokens since tokens can be used during the process.
For this reason, the Court orders the claimant to provide a cryptocur-
rency wallet, with a deposit of EUR 1000 that will be used to maintain
Legal Nature of NFTed Artwork: A Comparative Study 81
no license to use such digital assets nor a license or a transfer of the intel-
lectual property rights of the underlying artwork (unless the sales agree-
ment provides otherwise). In the further analysis of copyright
infringement, the court distinguishes NFTed work from a physical object.
It holds that the distribution right does not apply in this case because it
only concerns the distribution of physical objects. The legitimate creator
of an NFT should not be the person who possesses a copy of the underly-
ing work but the person who owns the copyright or obtains a due license
for the underlying work. Hence, it holds that the uploading of the NFTed
work infringed on the right to disseminate work by information networks.
However, as the court is only a district-level court, it remains to be seen
whether its ruling will be widely followed or is likely to be challenged in
subsequent cases by other courts in China. In any case, as the authorities
have not yet enacted any formal NFT laws or regulations, the court’s
insights in the judgment are meaningful, and NFT players in China
should carefully consider the implications of the ruling.
6 Conclusions
The value of art has always come from the reputation of the author and
the scarcity of the work through ‘authenticity’. NFTs offer artists the
opportunity to secure incomes with tracing and tracking functions and
embedded smart contracts while encouraging the dissemination of art-
work that cannot be reproduced without authorisation. If the profit from
selling NFTs is large enough to motivate authors, copyright as a legal
monopoly is no longer necessary to generate rewards. Recognising NFTs
as property encourages artists to be open to the market, which helps cre-
ate cultural prosperity and increase social welfare.
The NFT is more than a recording of digital work. Minting an NFTed
work is to record the work on the blockchain through an identification
code. The creation of the digital tokenised work (i.e. registered block-
chain with hash code) involves the acquisition of ownership by the regis-
tration holder. NFTed artwork might evoke the question of exclusive
possession and control of the work, including property and IP rights. The
right to tokenise a work protected by copyright belongs to the owner of
Legal Nature of NFTed Artwork: A Comparative Study 83
the copyright or those who have the authorisation of the owner; beyond
this hypothesis, this right belongs to the owner of NFTed work.
Consequently, it is necessary to distinguish NFTs from NFTed artwork.
The NFT is a mechanism for forming the ownership of a right of use and
disposition of digital work in the hands of the person who registers
the NFTs.
Although the judiciary from different jurisdictions has been willing to
extend the protection for brick-and-mortar property to NFTed artworks,
NFTs are at the risk of misrepresenting or even infringing IP rights in a
work minted into NFTs. Possessing an NFT does not necessarily confer
any legal right over the digital or physical object the NFT refers to. Several
proposals have been advanced to overcome this limitation to the concept
of NFT. Some try to strike a balance between the legal and the technical
dimension, incorporating aspects of copyright law into the metadata of
the NFT or in accompanying documentation; others propose to incorpo-
rate the actual work into the underlying smart contract. While many
commentators are critical at this point (Ryan 2021), others, like Fairfield,
see the potential of NFTs as forms of ‘unique digital property’, re-
establishing personal property rights that have been lost to user agree-
ments and other instruments of uneven bargaining power (Fairfield 2021).
In the UK, the Task Force took the view that Colonial Bank was not
to be treated as limiting the scope of what kinds of things could be prop-
erty in law. Instead, it showed the ability of the common law to stretch
“traditional definitions and concepts to adapt to new business practices”.
National Provincial Bank Ltd. v Ainsworth [1965] has established a four-
factored test for the property as something “definable, identifiable by
third parties, capable in its nature of assumption by third parties, and
have some degree of permanence or stability”. In Singapore, the court
rejected the analogy between a title deed for real property and NFTs as a
certificate for digital assets. Rather, it adopted the Ainsworth criteria and
upheld NFTs as property.
In Europe, although some jurisdictions traditionally take a narrow
approach concerning the scope of the property, which is limited to “cor-
poreal things”, many others are more open to including incorporeal assets,
such as patrimonial rights, into real rights. The court decisions discussed
in Sect. 5 demonstrate that cryptocurrency and NFTs are considered
84 J. Wang and A. Alpini
digital assets (Calzolaio 2020). The Italian and Spanish Courts noted that
NFTs, on the one hand, bear a certifying function and, on the other hand,
link to specific content. China’s first Civil Code explicitly recognises vir-
tual property as an object protectable by law. In the first NFT-concerned
case, the court distinguishes the NFTed work from a physical object and
holds that an NFTed work is a ‘digital commodity’, and NFTed copies of
the work are digital assets. It adopts a test similar to the Ainsworth test
that evaluates whether the data is unique and securely linked to a work
and is identifiable by third parties. It is consensus that while the right of
the owner to mint and tokenise a work is to be fully protected, it cannot
be overlooked that this right must be exercised in compliance with the
principle of economic solidarity and fair competition.
The comparison between the legal systems implies an increasing level
of convergence of law towards a harmonised concept of digital assets in a
world built on blockchain and tokens. In comparing the common law
and civil law systems, convergence of law is emerging in the digital world.
The legal systems have advanced closer towards a concept of property
with many shared features. First, the data must be stored securely on the
blockchain ledger. The nature of blockchain technology gives the owner
the exclusive ability to transfer the NFT to another party, which under-
scores the “right” of the owner. Second, the data should be capable of
being recognised by third parties. Third, the data has intrinsic value that
is respected and potentially desirable by third parties. Lastly, an NFT has
a relevant degree of permanence and stability as money in bank accounts
which, nowadays, exist mainly in the form of ledger entries and not cold
hard cash. Property is moving from a static concept to a concept of act
and activity. At the same time, ownership is the link between the owner
and the worthy interest to be realised and guaranteed.
NFTed artworks are considered incorporeal assets that confer quasi-
property rights and interests. The legal principle of numerus clausus is an
instrument for legal certainty. However, reality goes beyond the dogmas
of the legal tradition. The jurist must take an evolutionary leap forward
to adapt the mechanisms and techniques of law to emerging digital tech-
nologies that change the societal ecosystem. The concept of property per
se and the rights deriving from the property need a recalibration that
shifts from focusing on exclusive control to the use of the thing.
Legal Nature of NFTed Artwork: A Comparative Study 85
References
Articles
Moringiello, J. M. & Odinet, C.K. (2022) The Property Law of Tokens. Florida
Law Review, 74, 607–671. https://ssrn.com/abstract=3928901 or https://
doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3928901
Murray, M.D. (2022a). Generative and AI Authored Artworks and Copyright
Law. Hastings Communications and Entertainment Law Journal, 45(1),
28–43. https://ssrn.com/abstract=4152484 or https://doi.org/10.2139/
ssrn.4152484
Murray, M.D. (2022b). NFT Ownership and Copyrights. https://ssrn.com/
abstract=4152468 or https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.4152468
Nakamoto, S. (2019). Bitcoin: A Peer-to-Peer Electronic Cash System, ‘Bitcoin:
A Peer-to-Peer Electronic Cash System’, https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.
cfm?abstract_id=3440802, accessed on 20 September 2023.
Perlingieri, P. (1990). L’informazione come bene giuridico. Rass. dir. Civ.,
326–338.
Rodeck & Hooson. (2022). ‘Top NFT Marketplaces of 2023’, available at
https://www.forbes.com/uk/advisor/investing/cryptocurrency/best-nft-mar-
ketplaces/, accessed on 20 September 2023.
Ryan, T. R. (2021, December 2). Will the Artworld’s NFT Wars End in Utopia
or Dystopia? Art Review. https://artreview.com/will-the-artworld-nft-wars-
end-in-utopia-or-dystopia/.
Teruel, G.M.R., Simon-Moreno, H. (2021). The digital tokenization of prop-
erty rights: a comparative perspective. Computer Law and Security Review,
41, 4–5.
Von Bar C., & Drobnig, U. (2004). ‘The Interaction of Contract Law and Tort
and Property Law in Europe: A Comparative Study’, Sellier de Gruyter
(2004). Study on property law and non-contractual law as they relate to
contract law, European Commission–Health and Consumer Protection
Directorate-General, Brussels, Belgium, available at: https://www.academia.
edu/1131084/Study_on_property_law_and_noncontractual_law_as_they_
relate_to_contract_law (last access: 7 November 2016).
Book Chapters
Low, K. F. K. & Hara, M. (2022). Cryptoassets and Property. In Sjef van Erp &
Katja Zimmermann (eds), Edward Elgar Research Handbook on EU Property
Law (forthcoming), available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=4103870
or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.4103870
Legal Nature of NFTed Artwork: A Comparative Study 87
Cases
Singaporean Cases
B2C2 Ltd v Quione Pte Ltd [2019] SGHC(I) 03 [2019] 4 SLR 17 at [142], but
the issue was left open on appeal: [2020] SGCA(I) 02, [2020] 2 SLR 20 at
[144]. See now, however, CLM v CLN [2022] SGHC 46 at [46].
88 J. Wang and A. Alpini
European Cases
Others
1 Introduction
Artificial intelligence (AI) has been disrupting the world of technology
and computing for many years, bringing significant benefits to our daily
lives. Ever more sophisticated AI systems do not only supplement the
work of humans, but can perform tasks which have been traditionally
reserved exclusively for humans. AI can be subdivided into a weak (or
narrow) AI and strong AI, according to whether it is designed to tackle
single task or can accomplish tasks across multiple domains. AI has been
increasingly involved in creative and inventive processes which result in
assets qualifying for intellectual property protection, whether by copy-
right or patent law. However, intellectual property law was designed to
protect inventions and creations of a human mind, thus seemingly leav-
ing AI outside of the scope of protection. Currently, the prominence of
AI has been set to shake up the foundations of intellectual property law
L. Klobucnik (*)
Aston Law School, Aston University, Birmingham, West Midlands, UK
e-mail: l.klobucnik@aston.ac.uk
(IP) law. IP law was established in order to recognise the fruits of human
ingenuity, creativity, and inventiveness. Indeed, for a long time, mankind
assumed that only humans are capable of producing creative works or
inventions. But what happens if the human element is taken away from
the creative or inventive process? Can IP law accommodate the ingenuity
of machines or will legislative changes be required? One of the widely
discussed questions has been whether AI can generate inventions or
copyright- protected works without human contribution. Suggestions
have been provided by academics, governments, policy makers, interna-
tional institutions (most notably the World Intellectual Property
Organisation – WIPO), but legislators have been hesitant to reflect any
of them into the existing legal framework. Policy discussions have been
revolving around the question whether intellectual property law, espe-
cially copyright and patent law, ought to be revised to account for tech-
nological developments in AI. For instance, the European Parliament, in
its resolution from February 2017 noted that ever more sophisticated AI
requires the legislation in virtually every area to consider its legal and
ethical implications without stifling innovation. In the UK, both copy-
right and patent law systems lack specific regulation regarding eligibility
of robot generated works or robot inventions. The UK Government set
out a goal to change this, by asking the public in Autumn 2021 whether
the current rules on copyright and patent are sufficient to accommodate
creations and inventions by AI, or whether a new set of rules is needed. A
large variety of stakeholders exchanged their views with the UK
Government. This may lead to new policy options and potential changes
in law, which will be discussed here. This chapter does not aim to provide
responses as to whether copyright and patent law is ripe for amendment.
Rather, it aims to discuss involvement of AI in the IP value chain – not
only with respect to AI as a creator/inventor (i. e. before IP protection
arises), but also the role of AI as a user of IP protected assets. Challenges
brought by AI are discussed here with respect to two areas of intellectual
property – copyright and patents.
Intellectual Property Regulation of Artificial Intelligence… 93
work requires the author to make free and creative choices, which ulti-
mately reflect the author’s personal touch. Following these criteria, it
seems difficult to detach a copyright protected work from a human ele-
ment. Although the CJEU does not expressly refer to a human touch as
an authorship requirement, it indicates quite clearly that some kind of a
human quality has to be present in the creation process. According to
Ramalho, where there is no human author, a work cannot be original,
and without originality, a work cannot be protected by copyright.
The concept of originality underlines the need for a human author,
insofar as personality can be described as a purely human attribute. With
respect to the requirement concerning free and creative choices, Van
Gompel argues that even though the autonomy of authors to make free
choices is naturally restricted, as individual creators operate within social,
technical and institutional environments, at least some of these choices
are internal and self-imposed. The underlying rationale for free and cre-
ative choices seems to be that these choices are made consciously, i. e. by
a conscious being. Moreover, if copyright protects expression of ideas, it
would be questionable to think of an idea as being expressed by an AI
machine.
The international legal framework for copyright, namely the Berne
Convention, does not explicitly define authorship, nor does it explicitly
require a human author. However, one of the prominent international
copyright commentators, Sam Ricketson, argues that the Berne
Convention is very ‘anthropocentric’, e. g. by granting moral rights to the
author, by linking the duration of protection to the life of the author or
by referring to ‘intellectual creations’. The logical conclusion seems to be
that attributing moral rights to an AI machine or to link copyright pro-
tection to the ‘life’ of a subject matter would not make sense. The view
that copyright-protected works can only have a human author is corrobo-
rated by the International Association for the Protection of Intellectual
Property (AIPPI), which argues that without human intervention, there
should be no copyright protection of AI-generated works. Indeed, with
its robust exclusive rights and a long term of protection, copyright may
not be the most suitable vehicle for the protection of AI-generated works.
However, the copyright law framework may offer a potential vehicle for
protection of AI-generated works in the form of neighbouring
Intellectual Property Regulation of Artificial Intelligence… 95
rights (related rights) – with a shorter duration and without the element
of moral rights, as opposed to copyright. A legislative construct that may
serve as an example is already present in the UK copyright law – computer-
generated works. Let us have a closer look at the relevance of the debate
on computer-generated works for AI-generated works.
The proposed TDM regime should promote a balance between all stake-
holders involved in the copyright value chain – rights holders, users, and
consumers. TDM is not only important for non-commercial research,
but also for other purposes, such as freedom of speech and journalism.
Therefore, allowing access of a large variety of entities to TDM is essen-
tial. Most importantly, TDM is a tool for AI-enabled innovation. Much
of the current and future development of AI depends on TDM. Therefore,
it is important to ensure that no entities are excluded from a possibility
to perform TDM activities. For instance, start-ups, which are not affili-
ated with any research institution and operate on a for-profit basis,
100 L. Klobucnik
cannot currently avail themselves of the TDM exception and can get
caught up in robust licensing mechanisms which can prevent start-ups
from emerging.
Researchers are faced with legal uncertainty as to whether and under
which conditions can they carry out TDM on content they have lawful
access to. TDM exceptions can and should go further in adapting to the
digital environment. It has to be noted that the TDM exception is also
dealt with in the EU Copyright in the Digital Single Market Directive
2019/ 790 (EU CDSM Directive). Unlike the current UK TDM excep-
tion, the TDM exception pursuant to the EU CDSM Directive applies
to both commercial and non-commercial mining purposes. The differ-
ence between the two being that if mining is performed for non-
commercial purposes (i. e. by research organisations or cultural
institutions), right holders do not have a right to opt out of the TDM
exception. If TDM is done for commercial purposes, right holders are
allowed to opt out, i. e. to contractually override the exception to the
reproduction right infringement. The currently applicable UK regime of
TDM exceptions does not distinguish between mining for commercial or
non-commercial purposes. The newly proposed TDM exception blurs
the distinction between TDM done for commercial or non-commercial
purposes and does not allow rights holders to opt out.
Copyright law has to respond to the realities of the twenty-first cen-
tury where the growing use of big data and AI tools in research and inno-
vation are necessary to achieve breakthroughs and result from collaboration
of different stakeholders – start-ups, SMEs, academia, research groups,
governments and business. It should be noted that the main beneficiary
of innovative projects is the public. In order for the public to benefit,
TDM exceptions should exist for all entities and for all purposes. If the
opt out regime is in place, rights holders have control over TDM – they
can decide who to grant a licence to or to entirely prohibit the use of their
content for TDM. For instance, publishers, who already offer paid-for
TDM as value-added services, will be reluctant to grant TDM licences to
third parties. Thus, commercial AI developers, journalists, research hubs,
and other innovative entities will be at a competitive disadvantage. The
opt out regime might cripple innovation for wide range of market play-
ers, from large companies to start-ups and individual researchers with a
Intellectual Property Regulation of Artificial Intelligence… 101
Copyright law is not the only area of IP that seems to be relevant with
respect of involvement of AI in the creative or inventive process. Patent
offices and courts in several countries, including the United Kingdom,
have been dealing with the question as to whether artificial intelligence
(and thus a non-human) can be an owner of a patent or considered an
inventor. Patent offices and courts in several countries have provided – at
least tentatively – answers to these questions.
4.3 USA
In the United States, the DABUS application was had been initially
rejected by the United States Patent and Trademark Office (USPTO),
which took the view that the definition of the ‘inventor’ in the Patent Act
requires an inventor to be a natural person. Consequently, the USPTO
rejected the patent application because no natural person was listed as an
inventor. Dr. Thaler appealed the USPTO’s decision. On appeal, in
September 2021, Judge Leonie Brinkema in the United States District
Court for the Eastern District of Virginia upheld the decision of the
USPTO that an AI machine cannot be an inventor under the US patent
law. In reaching this decision, Brinkema J pointed out that the language
used in the Patent Act (35 U.S. Code) and the recent America Invents
Act 2011 refers to a human quality, especially in terms such as ‘individ-
ual’, ‘himself or herself ’. According to Brinkema J, this implies that an
inventor must be a human being. The decision was appealed by Dr.
Stephen Thaler, but the Supreme Court of the United States declined to
hear the appeal in April 2023.
4.4 Germany
In line with the reasoning adopted in the UK and the USA, in Germany,
the Examining Section of the German Patent and Trade Mark Office
(Deutsches Patent- und Markenamt, hereinafter DPMA), rejected the
patent application filed by Dr. Thaler on the grounds that according to
Section 6 and Section 37 of the Patent Act an inventor can only be a
natural person – a human being with legal capacity under Section 1 of
the Civil Code – which does not apply to AI. The crux of the legal prob-
lem was whether only a natural person can be named as in inventor
within the meaning of Section 37 of the Patent Act. The Federal Patent
Court noted in line with courts in other jurisdictions, that only a natural
person can be designated as an inventor in a patent application. This
conclusion was reached based on a doctrinal understanding of the con-
cept of the ‘inventor’ and a teleological interpretation of the respective
provisions under the German Patent Law. The German Federal Patent
Intellectual Property Regulation of Artificial Intelligence… 105
4.6 Australia
5 Conclusion
The analysis above shows that despite AI being at the forefront of IP dis-
cussions in the past years, legislators, courts, and policy makers are not
quite ready yet to accept AI as creators or inventors. The understanding
that there is inevitably a ‘human behind AI’, without whom a subsequent
creation or invention by AI would not be possible, seems to prevail.
Granting IP rights to AI would raise a host of further legal questions
beyond mere IP rights, for instance questions of legal personhood. The
question of machines obtaining IP protection should ultimately be
decided by policy-makers. Some changes in law and policy can be antici-
pated, since it is becoming increasingly difficult for humans to discern
whether a song or a painting was created or a device was invented by a
machine. Ultimately, a policy decision will have to be made as to what
type of IP protection should be given to creations and inventions devised
by an algorithm with little or no human intervention. In the area of pat-
ent, developments may be slow, as it seems that statutory amendments
will be needed in order to grant patent rights to AI or recognise AI as an
inventor. The latter may be plausible. According to the AIPPI resolution,
AI inventions should not be excluded from patent protection per se. At
the same time, AI inventions should only be granted patent protection if
a natural person is listed as an inventor or co-inventor. However, the
input of a natural person can be quite minimal – even limited to the
108 L. Klobucnik
References
AIPPI – Association for the Protection of Intellectual Property, ‘Copyright and
Artificially Generated Works, Resolution of the 2019 AIPPI World
Congress – London, 18 September 2019’ <http://114.247.84.87/AIPPI/
ztyj/jy/201911/P020191219538152201660.pdf>
——, ‘Inventorship of Inventions Made Using Artificial Intelligence, Resolution
of the 2020 AIPPI World Congress’ <https://aippi.nl/wp-content/
uploads/2020/10/Adopted-Resolution-Q 272-Patents-Inventorship-o f-
inventions-made-using-Artificial-Intelligence.pdf>
Aplin T and Davies J, Intellectual Property Law: Text, Cases, and Materials
(Fourth Edition, Oxford University Press)
Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works 29
Čerka P, Grigienė J and Sirbikytė G, ‘Liability for Damages Caused by Artificial
Intelligence’ (2015) 31 Computer Law & Security Review 376
Drexl J and others, ‘Artificial Intelligence and Intellectual Property Law –
Position Statement of the Max Planck Institute for Innovation and
Competition of 9 April 2021 on the Current Debate’ (9 April 2021) <https://
papers.ssrn.com/abstract=3822924> accessed 15 December 2022
Intellectual Property Regulation of Artificial Intelligence… 109
Koempel F, ‘UK Music’s Legal Expert Outlines Issues With Proposed AI Data
Mining’ (UK Music, 29 November 2022) <https://www.ukmusic.org/news/
uk-m usics-l egal-e xpert-o utlines-i ssues-w ith-p roposed-a i-d ata-m ining/>
accessed 8 December 2022
Matulionyte R, ‘AI as an Inventor: Has the Federal Court of Australia Erred in
DABUS?’ (2022) 13 JIPITEC <http://www.jipitec.eu/issues/jipitec-13-
2-2022/5538>
McCutcheon C, ‘Curing the Authorless Void: Protecting Computer-Generated
Works Following ICE TV and Phone Directories’ (2013) 37 Melbourne
University Law Review
McDermott E, ‘DABUS Scores Again with Win on AI Inventorship Question
in Australia Court’ (IPWatchdog.com | Patents & Intellectual Property Law,
2 August 2021) <https://ipwatchdog.com/2021/08/02/dabus-scores-win-ai-
inventorship-question-australia-court/id=136304/> accessed 25 November
2022
Metz R, ‘These Artists Found out Their Work Was Used to Train AI. Now
They’re Furious | CNN Business’ (CNN, 21 October 2022) <https://www.
cnn.com/2022/10/21/tech/artists-ai-images/index.html> accessed 8
December 2022
‘Patents and Applications – The Artificial Inventor Project’ <https://artificialin-
ventor.com/patent-applications/> accessed 15 December 2022
Ramalho A, ‘Will Robots Rule the (Artistic) World? A Proposed Model for the
Legal Status of Creations by Artificial Intelligence Systems’ (2017) 21 The
Journal of Intenet Law 12
———, Intellectual Property Protection for AI-Generated Creations: Europe,
United States, Australia, and Japan (Routledge 2021)
Ricketson S, ‘The 1992 Horace S. Manges Lecture – People or Machines: The
Berne Convention and the Changing Concept of Authorship’ 16 Colum-
VLA JL & Arts
Senftleben M and Buijtelaar L, ‘Robot Creativity: An Incentive-Based
Neighboring Rights Approach’ [2020] SSRN Electronic Journal <https://
www.ssrn.com/abstract=3707741> accessed 17 November 2022
Stassen M, ‘Over 1,000 Songs with Human-Mimicking AI Vocals Have Been
Released by Tencent Music in China. One of Them Has 100m Streams.’
(Music Business Worldwide, 15 November 2022) <https://www.musicbusi-
nessworldwide.com/over-1000-songs-human-mimicking-ai-vocals-have-
been-released-by-t encent-m usic-i n-c hina-o ne-o f-t hem-h as-over-1 00m-
streams/> accessed 12 December 2022
Intellectual Property Regulation of Artificial Intelligence… 111
about-ip/en/artificial_intelligence/conversation.html> accessed 11
December 2022
Commissioner of Patents v Thaler (Australia) [2022] Federal Court of
Australia FCAFC 62
Decision on patent application GB18169094 and GB18181610, BL O/741/19
[2019] Intellectual Property Office of the United Kingdom BL O/741/19
Dr Stephen L Thaler v Presidentin des Deutschen Patent- und Markenamts,
1 W (pat) 5/21 (Bundespatentgericht (Germany))
Eva Maria Painer v Standard Verlags GmbH [2011] Court of Justice of the
European Union ECLI:EU:C:2011:798
Infopaq International A/S v Danske Dagbladens Forening, Case C-5/08,
ECLI:EU:C:2009:465 [2009] Court of Justice of the European Union
ECLI:EU:C:2009:465
Stephen L Thaler v The Comptroller-General of Patents, Designs and Trade
Marks [2020] EWHC 2412 (Pat) [2020]
Thaler v Commissioner of Patents [2021] Federal Court of Australia FCA 879
Thaler v Comptroller General of Patents Trade Marks And Designs [2021]
EWCA Civ 1374 (EWCA (Civ))
Thaler v Iancu, et al, No 1:2020cv00903 – Document 33 (ED Va 2021) [2021]
United States District Court for the Eastern District of Virginia
1:2020cv00903
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (United Kingdom) 1988
Directive 2001/29/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 22
May 2001 on the harmonisation of certain aspects of copyright and related
rights in the information society, OJ L 167
Directive 2019/790/EU of the European Parliament and of the Council of 17
April 2019 on copyright and related rights in the Digital Single Market and
amending Directives 96/9/EC and 2001/29/EC, OJ L 130/92 2019
H.R.1249 – Leahy-Smith America Invents Act
Patent Act 1990 (Act No. 83) (Australia)
Patentgesetz (Germany) – Patent Act as published on 16 December 1980
(Federal Law Gazette 1981 I p. 1), as last amended by Article 4 of the Act of
8 October 2017 (Federal Law Gazette I p. 3546)
Patents Act 1977 (United Kingdom) 1977
Judgment of the Supreme Court, Thaler (Appellant) v Comptroller-General of
Patents, Designs and Trade Marks (Respondent) [2023] UKSC 49
An Artificial Intelligence Invention
Protection Model
Budi Agus Riswandi
1 Introduction
The industrial revolution period reflects the advancement of technology
in human civilization. All the industrial revolutions that have occurred
have had an impact on economic growth, increased productivity, and
high-quality goods and services (Rabeh Morrar, 2017). The industrial
revolution is currently in the 4.0 phase which is marked by the prolifera-
tion of technology based on computer programs that perform their func-
tions more like a human’s ability to think and act, resulting in the
technology known as artificial intelligence technology.
The terminology of AI was formally coined by John McCarthy, a com-
puter scientist at a conference in 1956, according to him, it was the
notion of a program, processing and acting on information, such that the
result is parallel to how an intelligent person would respond in response
to similar input (Tripathi & Ghatak, 2018). In short, the term ‘Artificial
B. A. Riswandi (*)
Faculty of Law, Universitas Islam Indonesia, Yogyakarta, Indonesia
e-mail: budiagusr@uii.ac.id
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2024 113
N. Naim (ed.), Developments in Intellectual Property Strategy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-42576-9_5
114 B. A. Riswandi
2 Discussion
2.1 Legal Protection of AI Invention Based
on Indonesia Patent Law
Indeed, AI can help society become modern and even bring about very
basic changes, however, its impact on the human condition is clearly
uncertain. Therefore, efforts are needed to respond to the various
122 B. A. Riswandi
actions, both directly and indirectly (ex-post & ex-ante). Law, which
serves as a sanction and/or provides protection, societal norms, the mar-
ket, which determines activity based on supply and demand, and archi-
tecture, which is a configuration of human behavior/action. Despite their
different functions and effects, the four forces work together to regulate
or limit the space for individual action/behavior. Norms are constrained
by the stigma imposed by the community, markets are constrained by the
prices they set, architecture is constrained by the physical burden it
imposes, and laws are constrained by the threats posed by the rules.
The four forces of the Pathetic Dot theory can be used to protect an
invention, especially the invention of AI as a protection model. The four
forces are as follows:
Social norms are general habits or rules that guide behavior in a commu-
nity group and have regional boundaries. The limit of social norms is
behavior that is considered appropriate for a community group, which is
also known as social rules or social regulations. The values of norms that
society owns and believes in can provide an assessment of the usefulness
of a technological invention to society.
Technological advancements, particularly inventions, can also influ-
ence how society perceives a technological advancement by leveraging
124 B. A. Riswandi
social norms that apply in that environment, such as ways, habits, rules
of conduct, customs, laws, or fashion. Furthermore, the development of
AI with engineering characteristics similar to humans may lead to com-
munity disagreements about these inventions.
Thus, social norms control the regulation of AI inventions because the
effects and risks of technological developments, particularly AI inven-
tions, can affect social interaction in society because people will use,
enjoy, and rely on technology in the future.
2.3.3 Stakeholder as ‘Market’
national patent law whose provisions are guided by TRIPs. The AI inven-
tions are explicitly not included in the patent laws of Indonesia, the
United States, and Japan, but the three patent laws of these countries
include provisions regarding computer programs. The patent laws of the
three countries in practice have protected AI inventions under the patent
laws of their respective countries, although only the United States and
Japan have issued patent guidelines for AI inventions.
Lawrence Lessig’s Pathetic Dot/New Chicago School theory can be
used in creating a protection model for AI invention. The protection
model uses 4 powers as protectors, namely the Patent Law “Law” as the
protection provided by the State; Social Norms “Norm” as a protection
from the cultural aspects of the surrounding community; Market
“Market” protection from stakeholders in the business world, and Code
Program / Source Code “Architecture” as protection from programmers
who develop a computer program technology. these four powers are
applied to be a protection against AI and can also be used to be aware of
and avoid the negative effects of AI tech
3.2 Suggestion
(a) The renewal of the Indonesian National Patent Law in dealing with
the development of AI technology does not need to be carried out in
approximately 10 years. Because AI inventions themselves can grant
patents based on Law Number 13 of 2016 concerning Patents and
based on data on the PDKI-Indonesia website there are 2 inventions
based on AI that have been granted patents in 2019 and 2020.
(b) Directorate General Intellectual Property of Indonesia should imme-
diately issue a manual regarding AI artificial intelligence inventions
to provide education to patent examiners, academics, and the general
public about AI artificial intelligence inventions from the point of
view of Indonesian patent law.
An Artificial Intelligence Invention Protection Model 127
References
Blok P. The Inventor’s New Tool: Artificial Intelligence-How Does it Fit the
European Patent System, European Intellectual Property Review, (2017).
Bronwyn H Hall. Patent and Patent Policy, Oxford Review of Economic
Policy, (2007).
DJKI. Modul Kekayaan Intelektual Bidang Paten, Direktorat Jenderal Kekayaan
Intelektual Kementerian Hukum & HAM R.I, 2019.
Ilya M. Rassolov and Svetlana G. Chubukova, “Artificial Intelligence and
Effective Governance: Legal Framework”, Kutafin Law Review Vol. 9 Issues.
2, (2022), p. 314.
Intellectual Property Office, Artificial Intelligence: a worldwide overview of AI
Patents and Patenting by the UK AI sector, A Report by the Economics,
Research and Evidence team at the Intellectual Property Office United
Kingdom, June (2019).
Japan Patent Office. Recent Trends in AI-Related Inventions. Report: Patent
Examination Departement, (July 2020).
Jeffrey A. Burt, “The Revolutionary Impact of Artificial Intelligence on the
Future of the Legal Profession”, Kutafin Law Review, Vol. 8 Issues. 3,
(2021), p. 400.
Rabeh Morrar. The Fourth Industrial Revolution (Industry 4.0): A Social
Innovation Perspective. Technology Innovation Management Review Vol 7
Issue 11, (November, 2017).
Reinaldo Franqui Machin, “It’s Time for the AI Patent: The Case for an Artificial
Intelligence Patent Category”, Research Gate, October 2021.
Simon B.M. Implications of Technological Advancement for Obviousness,
Michigan Telecommunications, and Technology Law Review, (2013).
Swapnil Tripathi & Chandni Ghatak, “Artificial Intelligence and Intellectual
Property Law”, Christ University Law Journal Vol.7, No.1, (2018).
Tatiana Zaplatina, “the Legal Issues of the Artificial Intelligence, Intellectual
Property Rights and Data Protection”, Kutafi n University Law Review Vol 6
Issue 1 (2019), p. 45
Tomoko Miyamoto. Patentability of Computer Software and Business Methods.
PowerPoint Presentation: delivered at WIPO-MOST Intermediate Training
Courses on Practical Intellectual Property Issues in Business, November
10–14, (2003).
128 B. A. Riswandi
Regulation
1 Introduction
1.1 An Ageing Population
It is projected that by 2030 there will be around 1.4 billion people aged
60 years and older and doubling to 2.1 billion by 2050 (WHO 2022).
High income countries such as Japan and the US have a substantial pro-
portion of people who are 60 years and older. As people continue to live
longer, people who are 80 years and older will continue to grow to
426 million by 2050 (WHO 2022). Older people live in various types of
household settings, ranging from living alone or in communities to those
who live in nursing or care homes requiring some form of support in
their daily lives. Some of them could be recovering from illness or in
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2024 129
N. Naim (ed.), Developments in Intellectual Property Strategy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-42576-9_6
130 H. Y. Chan and A. Muralidharan
the purpose of engaging and interacting with former soldiers who suf-
fered from brain trauma with cognitive injuries (Wilks et al. 2015). These
care robots are programmed to remind the users about appointments,
and other activities in their daily lives such as brushing their teeth.
CALONIS was modelled after a European Union- funded Senior
Companion project which was devised to interact with older people,
where these care robots learned about the lives of the elderly via photos,
and conversations (Wilks et al. 2015, 258). Other examples include vir-
tual carers for the elderly that aids their daily living and interacts with
them (Garner et al. 2016) and LOIS, an elderly companion intended to
assist the elderly in managing their needs and monitor their wellbeing on
a long-term basis (Fulbright 2021, 403).
Some scholars observed that despite continuous efforts and scientific
advancements, the production and use of care robots remain minimal
(Hoppe et al. 2022; Fulbright 2021, 404). These could be attributed to
manufacturing obstacles that are largely focused on producing robots
that carry out simple tasks and research and development of care robots
on a smaller scale for specific research purposes that are limited to labora-
tory settings (Van Aerschot and Parviainen 2020). Gaps in regulation,
financing, and data security are among some of the factors influencing
low level of trust in using care robots (Hoppe et al. 2022). A change in
how care robots is used in the world could potentially aid a wider use of
care robots. Van Aerschot and Parviainen (2020, 253) proposed that their
use should be framed within the entire care structure encompassing an
interdependent system of emotional, social and practical contexts of care-
giving. In enabling a widespread use of care robots, they recommended a
realistic approach to research that considers market drivers and needs
(ibid, 254). This approach could be valuable to inform how regulators
shape governance directions for care robots.
What about user experience in interacting with care robots? Some
studies reported positive perceptions towards care robots among caregiv-
ers in elderly homes (Rantanen et al. 2020; Niemela and Melkas 2019).
Adequate training to build competency in interacting with care robots,
incentives and usability are said to encourage the adoption of care robots
by end users (Frennert et al. 2021). A study exploring users’ experience
with care robots however revealed the need to be cautious of potential
132 H. Y. Chan and A. Muralidharan
differences between robots that are tested and operated in lab environ-
ments and robots that are integrated in home settings (von der Putten
et al. 2011, 333, 334). Such findings may affect how users perceive care
robots in their home settings, how these interactions change the users
and the inclination to build relationships with them in spite of their arti-
ficial nature. This seems to support a greater level of comprehensive
awareness of underlying beliefs that humans and robots have in creating
care robots through an observation of how they interact in the real world,
rather than in labs (Heylen et al. 2011). More recent research from
Sweden reported stakeholders’ doubts about the extent of readiness on
the part of their national governance framework within the social and
systemic contexts in introducing care robots as part of elder care
(Johansson-Pajala and Gustafsson 2022). Further studies exploring per-
ceptions of politicians, insurance organisations and the media in Finland,
Sweden and Germany similarly referenced the significance of regulations
in supporting the use of care robots in areas such as employment, avail-
ability of care robots and financing to developers (Hoppe et al. 2022).
There are, however, some resistance to the use of care robots. Sharkey
and Sharkey (2012) raised ethical concerns regarding care robots ranging
from reduction in human contact, vulnerabilities arising from loss of
control and objectification, loss of privacy, personal liberty, and decep-
tion. The inability of care robots to meet the emotional needs of the
elderly due to a lack of authentic social interaction and the capability to
establish affective relations (Sparrow and Sparrow 2006) are further
objections to care robots. It is claimed that robots are incapable of respect-
ing or recognising users and such right to be respected would be under-
mined should they be allowed (Sparrow 2016, 446). It can be said that a
common objection to affective technologies such as social robots and
those with close human interactions such as care robots is the existence of
associated risks with their use such as vulnerability, interdependency,
responsiveness and responsibility, which gives rise to wider implications
on caregiving relationships among human beings.
In response to criticisms against care robots, some scholars emphasised
the importance of empathy to enable the creation of relationships between
care robots and their human users (Leiten et al. 2013; Coeckelbergh
2010). Chan (2021, 638) similarly advocated for care ethics in the design
Care Robots for the Elderly: Legal, Ethical Considerations… 133
of care robots for its value in fostering trust and its suitability both in the
caregiving settings as well as alignment with regulatory guidelines aimed
at promoting the safety and security of users, respect for human rights,
dignity and privacy and accountability of developers. These recommen-
dations could be seen as attempts at defending against claims that robots
are incapable of caring.
These concerns remain as long as robotics continue to develop. Care
robots have the potential to affect people’s health and safety, as they are
placed within the private home environments of the elderly who are
likely to be vulnerable. Their daily lives, relationships, object of depen-
dency and experiences could be transformed, thus raising concerns about
undesirable effects these robots might have upon the users (McTear et al.
2016, 296, 297). Some research suggested that the aims of robotics
should be aligned with human rights principles and relevant ethical val-
ues of privacy and autonomy (Vargas et al. 2011, 330). Practical and legal
questions such as potential changes to liability regimes where harms
occur from the use of care robots are set to become more important as
innovations continue (Wilks et al. 2005) as well as questions regarding
the legal personality of robots and attribution of responsibilities in the
event of harm (Begishev et al. 2021). Whilst their use may be regarded as
beneficial from a scientific perspective, important ethical and legal issues
need to be considered.
all, if they were evidential or alethic, we would think that there is nothing
wrong with Betty not trusting Alf. As such, the reasons must be of a
moral kind. For instance we might think that Betty owes it to Alf in vir-
tue of him being her husband. Or we might think it is good for Betty to
trust Alf so that Alf can learn to develop responsibility or trustworthiness
with regards to his drinking problem. These moral reasons make trust apt
in these circumstances despite Alf ’s lack of trustworthiness. This means
that moral reasons cannot be the wrong kind of reasons to trust. It fol-
lows then that there are at least some cases where we may permissibly
trust a person more than an equally reliable AI.
Given that such a trust-gap can be justified, it is not altogether clear
that increasing trust by shaping AI assistants in humanoid or cute forms
is merely a matter of removing illicit sources of distrust. Instead, it can
plausibly, be described as an illicit attempt to engender trust. After all,
being humanoid or cute is not any sort of reason at all to trust some-
thing however being a person is.
One type of use these AI assistants or care robots may be put to is engag-
ing or at least attempting to engage the elderly in conversations. Let us
call these types of assistants, conversation bots. In using conversation
bots, attention needs to be paid to the value of such assistance. Certainly,
one aspect of this value is instrumental: There are a number of health
problems and risks associated with social isolation (National Academy of
Sciences, Engineering and Medicine 2020). Conversation bots are sup-
posed to be useful in mitigating some of these risks. While the health
risks associated with social isolation are serious, mitigating health risks is
incidental to the practice of having conversations and social relationships.
Instead, the key point of having conversations and social relationships is
to connect with a real person on the other side. This aspect matters for
two reasons. Firstly, it matters because a large part of the value of having
social relationships is grounded in having a relationship with an actual
person. Secondly, it matters because people are not likely to engage in
conversations purely for health benefits. Instead they engage in
138 H. Y. Chan and A. Muralidharan
with the option of getting the elderly to engage with these AI assistants
by deceiving them into thinking that they are conversing with humans.
However, as noted, this would be explicitly deceptive and hence imper-
missible for that reason. If, on the other hand, we remained within ethi-
cal boundaries, it is not clear what benefit such conversation bots would
have since they are unlikely to be used. Moreover, we can see how replac-
ing nurses with conversation bots may even lead to harm. Whereas a
human nurse could genuinely engage the conversational skills of their
charges, it is not clear that conversation bots could do the same to the
requisite degree outside of a laboratory setting.
The ethical considerations discussed so far examined the relationship
complexities between how care robots interact with the elderly that affect
how they ought to be designed and developed. An elderly person is not
automatically vulnerable and lacking in discerning abilities, however, to
prevent deception and manipulation for the elderly who are more likely
to be vulnerable (e.g.: those suffering from dementia), care robots could
be designed to be less human-like as much as possible to ameliorate the
deception and avoid undue attachment to these robots. Further, from a
safety perspective, the more human-like the care robot is, the more agile
it has to be, which will create hazards when placed in the elderly’s home
environment. The priority then should be to ensure that these robots are
functional, stable, and safe to use rather than aesthetically pleasing.
but to ensure that care robots that are marketed and integrated into the
lives of elderly are safe for their use and that the elderly users are secure
when interacting with care robots. Regulatory bodies continue to face
questions such as: how should the legal framework accommodate this
new technology? Are existing laws or guidance sufficient to address this
new application? These and many related questions will continue to
remain important while newer care robots are developed, tested, and
marketed to the relevant sectors.
One of the complexities with designing regulatory options is address-
ing the variety of care robots’ functionalities, purposes, software, and
hardware compositions. The sophistication and development of care
robots meant that it could cross several regulatory scopes, which may give
rise to duplicity or in some instances fall outside of the regulatory scope.
For example, what types of law should apply to a care robot that assist
with the daily routine and can interact with an elderly who is rehabilitat-
ing from stroke or managing a progressive illness such as Alzheimer’s or
dementia? Is the care robot treated as a medical device, or assistive tech-
nology capable of providing information useful for medical diagnoses
and planning future treatment? When care robots learn more informa-
tion about the elderly that they cared for and store or transfer such data,
it becomes clear that such care robots cannot be precisely classified under
laws that govern consumer use of medical devices solely. Further, con-
cerns about security of collected data, privacy of the elderly and families
and how these data are managed, maintained and used by healthcare
providers require additional consideration of applicable laws regarding
data protection and security.
Another relevant consideration is the potential modification to con-
ventional doctor- patient relationships as care robots have seemingly
become the intermediary between the elderly patient and healthcare pro-
viders, and sometimes an integral part of the treatment or rehabilitation
process. Rules relating to doctor-patient confidentiality may have to be
extended to these care robots or revised to accommodate the change in
this relationship. Other important concerns such as trust, and disclosure
of information are similarly affected where care robots enter these health-
care settings (Fosch-Villaronga 2020, 176). It will be seen that Article 9
of GDPR relating to processing of health-related data can become
Care Robots for the Elderly: Legal, Ethical Considerations… 143
The extent of interactions between care robots and the elderly users affect
the latter’s physical safety and emotional wellbeing. User health, safety
and wellbeing implicate legal considerations (Nambu 2016, 484). The
physical appearance of care robots may not mimic an actual human
being, however long periods of interactivities may create ethical issues
that are hidden at first instance. The issue of deceptiveness of care robots,
as discussed above and the inherent vulnerability of elderly who are
dependent on these robots as part of their ‘normal’ functioning in daily
routines augment their susceptibility to risks. There is a need to ensure
that care robots are safe to use within elderly populations where there is a
higher risk and degree of dependency on these robots compared to other
sectors. Doubts about the most appropriate classification for care robots –
whether they are medical devices or general lifestyle gadgets remain prob-
lematic for regulatory purposes as different intended functions attract
different liability considerations (Fosch-Villaronga and Mahler 2021).
Developers and creators need certainty in comprehending their obliga-
tions and protections under applicable standards for safety requirements
to enable legal compliance to ensure that users are truly protected (Fosch-
Villaronga 2016, 35, 42). Strengthening legislative protections and pro-
moting transparency in how these care robots are used and the effect on
the elderly are potential safeguards to ensure the safety and wellbeing of
elderly users.
The struggle for policy makers is not new as some studies from Australia
and New Zealand have shown that there is limited governmental capacity
in steering policy developments to provide oversight for robot technolo-
gies arising from limited capabilities in comprehending important reper-
cussions from adopting robotics technologies within a complex system of
markets, regulation and technological skills. (Dickinson et al. 2022).
Japan grappled with the best way to regulate care robots given that there
is an absence of clear definition for care robots within its legal framework
(Nambu 2016, 484) as well as technology outpacing regulatory scopes
(Iizuka and Ikeda 2021). It is recognised that the difficulty in defining
care robots may well stem from concerns that any definitions could
potentially create unintended obstacles for innovations and commerciali-
sation strategies (Nambu 2016). The lack of established standards creates
difficulties in properly identifying appropriate liability regimes when
harms occur from using care robots. In attempts to balance these two
interests, Japan introduced its New Growth Strategy in 2010 aimed at
ensuring user safety in their interactions with care robots through manag-
ing user feedback and contributing to safety standards (ibid, 494, 495).
Prior to this Strategy, Japan followed the ISO standards concerning safety
guidelines for next generation robots in 2007 (ibid, 488). The publica-
tion of Japan’s Robot Strategy in 2015 provided further regulatory
146 H. Y. Chan and A. Muralidharan
impetus to support the safe and extensive use robots in everyday life while
advancing technological innovations in robotics (ibid, 496). Other sug-
gestions include a greater involvement of various regulatory institutions
and creation of new roles for governments in regulating care robots
(Iizuka and Ikeda 2021) and more cross departmental collaborations in
developing policy response for care robots (Chou et al. 2019). ISO stan-
dards appeared to be a favourable option in regulating safety standards
for care robots as it has the advantage of enabling various stakeholders to
traverse governance processes from an international source point where
manufacturers and developers ought to comply with (Iizuka and Ikeda
2021). The situation regarding regulatory difficulties in Japan is not too
dissimilar from Taiwan where there is a lack of specific care robot policies
and an absence of policy coordination and involvements of various gov-
ernmental departments (Chou et al. 2019).
The balancing approach is influenced by the purpose envisioned by the
regulators when devising regulatory guidance. Reference can be made to
the distinctions between the EU certification approach and the US Food
and Drug Administration (FDA) policy in regulating medical devices.
The EU system (such as a-minimum standards approach in ISO
13482:2014) favours promoting scientific advancements while the FDA
is inclined towards protecting consumers from harm, resulting in the dif-
ferentiated assessment processes (Fosch-Villaronga 2020). One such
aspect is in the classifications of care robots, which has remained unset-
tled. For example, the FDA categorised medical robots as class 2 medical
devices (considered as medium risk), such as surgical robotic systems or
robots that function to improve the quality of life of patients such as
Paro, a robot to help patients with dementia and Alzheimer’s. However,
the increasing sophistication of intelligence in care robots may add fur-
ther complexities in the assessment of risks concerning its autonomous
nature. This approach is due to augmented developments in robotics,
which affect pre-market approval stage costs in testing, resulting in regu-
lators shifting responsibilities to manufacturers in demonstrating safety
equivalence with devices already on the market and self-certification
(Fosch-Villaronga 2020, 3). Those that fall within a higher risk category
will be certified by an external body. This approach however does not
resolve the uncertainties in terms of compliance with medical device laws.
Care Robots for the Elderly: Legal, Ethical Considerations… 147
in the design process as they affect user safety, especially for vulnerable
populations (Chan 2021, 638).
Besides regulatory standards, a more specific-oriented approach in the
form of a robot impact assessment for care robots could potentially ame-
liorate emerging safety risks that arise such as user privacy, data security
and liability issues (Fosch-Villaronga 2020, 5). The assessment is under-
pinned by six principles: impact explanation, comprehensive safety:
physical, cognitive safety requirements, consumer robotics: health, con-
sumer protection and environmental protection, liability: current and
prospective responsibility, accountability and liability, privacy: privacy
and data protection and dignity and broader implications: independence
and autonomy, dignity, ethics, and justice (ibid, 97). These principles are
consistent with existing international guidance and serve to support their
operationalisation. As highlighted earlier, care robots that are used in dif-
ferent settings and contexts create distinct risks and concerns, as such a
robot impact assessment is valuable to identify these distinct risks to
enable a timelier response. In addition to such functional impact assess-
ment, a regulatory sandbox approach trialled in Singapore is useful to
advance innovations but also identify risks that may be hidden when
robotics applications are tested in laboratory settings (Tan and Taeihagh
2020). This sandbox approach enables the creation of robotics testbeds
and pilots in health clusters across the country, with feedback from users
and providers to improve the applications and address concerns that arise.
A broader, overarching type of regulatory approach that strives to
embed adaptive elements is an iterative regulatory process proposed by
Fosch-Villaronga and Heldeweg (2018). They identified a coordination
gap between regulators and robot developers that resulted in disjointed
regulatory outcomes that neither effectively support innovations nor pro-
tect users of care robots. Pursuant to their iterative regulatory approach,
they proposed using forecasts from robot impact assessment for ethico-
legal evaluation and actual results of legislative assessment to revise, mod-
ify and update the laws. These are intended to create an active
evidence-based policy for emerging robotics applications. This means
that regulators should understand the attributes that are sought to be
regulated i.e., the entire spectrum of stakeholders and subject matter to
guide them in developing the laws (ibid, 1269). This could potentially
150 H. Y. Chan and A. Muralidharan
work with other applicable areas of law where care robots are concerned,
as they intersect with other aspects of the law such as liability issues, tort,
insurance, compensation and medical negligence, hospitals liability and
malpractice (Holder et al. 2016, 390). Protecting user safety need not
necessarily conflict with scientific innovations. The European Commission
Robolaw project initiated in 2012 is primarily innovation-driven but
takes a serious view of manufacturers’ responsibilities under existing laws
covering product liability to ensure that consumers are protected from
harm arising from using these products (Holder et al. 2016, 385).
Regulators are expected to regard fundamental principles that apply, such
as the need for robotics not to compromise human dignity, health, safety
and privacy, responsible application of technologies and accountability
for liability where robots caused harm (ibid, 386).
The discussion thus far reveals some feasible options for regulating care
robots. Ad-hoc type regulations may not sufficiently address the purpose
for which care robots are created, (Palmerini et al. 2016) which then
affects the adequacy of these laws in addressing the risks from using care
robots and their liability to harm caused. In arguing for a product-liability
type of regulatory approach for care robots, Palmerini et al. (2016, 80)
drew a parallel to the functions of products similar to existing product
liability laws, thereby precluding special regulatory regimes. It is correctly
observed that liability arising from robotics applications should be regu-
lated in a balanced way that caters to competing interests that are based
on real market considerations rather than assumptions (ibid, 83). This
approach however does not preclude the creation of new customised
rules for certain types of robotics applications, while for other types of
applications, existing laws could be applied with appropriate modifica-
tions. For example, existing consumer protection legislations may still be
relevant where care robots carry risks arising from their design and sale,
however further considerations are needed where they test the limits of
existing consumer protection laws (Holder et al. 2016, 399). It remains
to be seen how this aspect of the law will be applied.
A care robot impact assessment appears to be a feasible option to
address emerging or hidden risks presented by care robots, supported by
active engagements with all relevant stakeholders to feedback and review
the efficacy of laws. The combination of these approaches may mediate
Care Robots for the Elderly: Legal, Ethical Considerations… 151
3 Conclusion
Care robots are continuing to develop according to the needs, contexts,
and use, as well as the level of permissiveness in regulatory landscape
where these applications are developed and deployed. As such it is not
unusual that their developments are fragmented and highly tailored to
the functions they are created to serve. The ethical considerations will
continue to remain relevant, as they raised important implications to the
stakeholders in its lifecycle, from design, production, testing, implemen-
tation and user or market feedback. Research has highlighted the impor-
tance of involving end-users in the design and development processes, a
valid claim as they are the ones who will be interacting with these care
robots on a more frequent basis, and as a result, the effect upon these
users could not be underestimated. The elderly population has vulnera-
bilities which must be addressed in the context in which they use these
care robots. Issues such as control of its use, integration in their daily
lives, their privacy and security are paramount to ensure their safety in
interacting with these care robots. Care robots should meet the purpose
for which they are created, thus regulatory frameworks should be designed
to offer a measure of assurance to these users that their safety and quality
of life are not compromised in favour of scientific advancements.
Balancing these two interests is neither straightforward nor simple, as
they involve careful deliberation of the technology, the end- users, financ-
ing, intellectual property strategies, market needs and developers to guide
152 H. Y. Chan and A. Muralidharan
References
Begishev, I., Khisamova Z., & Vasyukov, V. Technological, (2021). Ethical,
Environmental and Legal Aspects of Robotics. E3S Web of Conferences,
244, 12028 https://doi.org/10.1051/e3sconf/202124412028EMMFT-2020
Caleb-Solly, P., Harper, C., & Dogramadzi, S. (2021). Standards and Regulations
for Physically Assistive Robots. Proceedings of the 2021 IEEE International
Conference on Intelligence and Safety for Robotics. Nagoya, Japan,
March 4–6, 2021
Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental
Theory. Oxford University Press.
Chan, K. Y. G. (2021). Trust in and Ethical Design of Carebots: The Case for
Ethics of Care. International Journal of Social Robotics, 13, 629–645,
https://doi.org/10.1007/s12369-020-00653-w
Chou, Y-h., Wang, S-y. B., & Lin, Y-t. (2019). Long-term care and technologi-
cal innovation: the application and policy development of care robots in
Taiwan. Journal of Asian Public Policy, 12(1), 104–123, https://doi.org/10.
1080/17516234.2018.1492315
Care Robots for the Elderly: Legal, Ethical Considerations… 153
Garner, T. A., Powell, W. A., & Carr, V. (2016). Virtual carers for the elderly: A
case study review of ethical responsibilities. Digital Health, 2, 1–14, https://
doi.org/10.1177/2055207616681173
Heylen, D., op den Akker, R., ter Maat, M., Petta, P., Rank, S., Reidsma, D., &
Zwiers, J. (2011) On The Nature Of Engineering Social Artificial
Companions. Applied Artificial Intelligence, 25(6), 549–574, https://doi.
org/10.1080/08839514.2011.587156
Holton, R. (1994). Deciding to trust, coming to believe. Australasian Journal of
Philosophy, 72(1), 63–76. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048409412345881.
Holder, C., Khurana, V., Harrison, F., & Jacobs, L. (2016). Robotics and law:
Key legal and regulatory implications of the robotics age (Part I of II).
Computer law & Security Review, 32.
Hoppe, J. A., Melkas, H., Pekkarinen, S., Tuisku, O., Hennala, L., Johansson-
Pajala, R-M., Gustafsson, C., & Thommes, K. (2022). Perception of Society’s
Trust in Care Robots by Public Opinion Leaders. International Journal of
Human-Computer Interaction, 1–17, https://doi.org/10.1080/10447318.
2022.2081283
IEEE. (2019). Ethically Aligned Design: A Vision for Prioritizing Human Well-
being with Autonomous and Intelligent Systems. Retrieved Nov 7, 2022,
from https://standards.ieee.org/wp-content/uploads/import/documents/
other/ead1e.pdf
Iizuka, M., & Ikeda, Y. (2021). Regulation and innovation under the 4th indus-
trial revolution: The case of a healthcare robot, HAL by Cyberdyne.
Technovation, 108, 102335.
Johansson-Pajala, R-M., & Gustafsson, C. (2022). Significant challenges when
introducing care robots in Swedish elder care. Disability and Rehabilitation:
Assistive Technology, 17(2), 166–176, https://doi.org/10.1080/17483107.
2020.1773549
Jones, J. (2004, February 20). Public Gives Bush Benefit of Doubt on National
Guard Service. Princeton, New Jersey. Retrieved from https://news.gallup.
com/poll/10690/public-g ives-b ush-b enefit-d oubt-n ational-g uard-
service.aspx
Juravle, G., Boudouraki, A., Terziyska, M., & Rezlescu, C. (2020). Trust in
Artificial Intelligence for Medical Diagnosis. Progress in Brain Research, 253,
263–282. https://doi.org/10.1016/bs.pbr.2020.06.006
Lancaster, K. (2019). The robotic touch: Why there is no good reason to prefer
human nurses to carebots. Philosophy in the Contemporary World,
25(2), 88–109.
Care Robots for the Elderly: Legal, Ethical Considerations… 155
Leiten, I., Pereira, A., Mascarenhas, S., Martinho, C., Prada, R., & Paiva, A. (2013).
The influence of empathy in human–robot relations. Int. J. Human-
Computer Studies, 71, 250–260.
Lim, M.Y. (2012). Memory models for intelligent social companions. In
Zacarias, M., de Oliveira, J.V. (eds.) Human-Computer Interaction. SCI,
396, (pp. 241–262). Springer, Heidelberg.
McTear, M. et al., (2016). Conversational Interfaces: Devices, Wearables,
Virtual Agents, and Robots, (pp. 283–308). Springer International Publishing
Switzerland https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-32967-3_13
Nambu, T. (2016). Legal regulations and public policies for next-generation
robots in Japan. AI & Soc, 31, 483–500.
National Academy of Sciences, Engineering and Medicine. (2020). Social
Isolation and Loneliness in Older Adults: Opportunities for the Healthcare
System. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. https://doi.
org/10.17226/25663
National Health Innovation Centre. (2022). Singapore Health Assistive and
Robotics Programme Grant. Retrieved Nov 2, 2022, from https://nhic.sg/
web/index.php/collaborations/sharp-projects
Niemelä, M., & Melkas, H. (2019). Robots as Social and Physical Assistants in
Elderly Care. In M. Toivonen, & E. Saari (eds.), Human-Centered
Digitalization and Services, Translational Systems Sciences (1st ed.,
pp. 177–197). Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd. https://doi.
org/10.1007/978-981-13-7725-9_10
Palmerini, E., Bertolini, A., Battaglia, F., Koops, B.-J., Carnevale, A., & Salvini,
P. (2016). RoboLaw: Towards a European framework for robotics regulation.
Robotics and Autonomous Systems, 86, 78–85, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.
robot.2016.08.0260921-8890
Pierce, R. (2020). Robots, the Alzheimer patient, and the GDPR: Policy and
privacy considerations for the use of robots in care, treatment, and diagnosis.
Alzheimer’s Dement, 16(Suppl. 10), e043261.
Rantanen, T., Leppälahti, T., Porokuokka, J., & Heikkinen, S. (2020). Impacts
of a Care Robotics Project on Finnish Home Care Workers’ Attitudes towards
Robots. Int. J. Environ. Res. Public Health, 17, 7176; https://doi.
org/10.3390/ijerph17197176
Responsible Robotics. (2022). Assessment principles. Retrieved Nov 2, 2022,
from https://responsiblerobotics.org/quality-mark/assessment-principles/
Sharkey, A., & Sharkey, N. (2012). Granny and the robots: ethical issues in
robot care for the elderly. Ethics Inf Technol, 14, 27–40.
156 H. Y. Chan and A. Muralidharan
Siau, K., & Wang, W. (2018). Building Trust in Artificial Intelligence and
Robotics. Cutter Business Technology Journal, 31(2), 47–53.
Sparrow, R. (2016). Robots in aged care: a dystopian future? AI & Soc,
31, 445–454.
Sparrow, R., & Sparrow, L. (2006). In the hands of machines? The future of
aged care. Mind Mach, 16, 141–161, https://doi.org/10.1007/
s11023-006-9030-6
Sunstein, C. R. (2015). The Ethics of Nudging. Yale Journal on Regulation,
32, 413–450.
Tan, S. Y., & Taeihagh, A. (2020). Governing the adoption of robotics and
autonomous systems in long-term care in Singapore. Policy And Society,
1–20 https://doi.org/10.1080/14494035.2020.1782627
Van Zaalen, Y., McDonnell, M., Mikołajczyk, B., Buttigieg, S., del Carmen
Requena, M., & Holtkamp, F. (2018). Technology implementation in deliv-
ery of healthcare to older people: how can the least voiced in society be heard?
Journal of Enabling Technologies, 12(2), 76–90.
Van Aerschot, L., & Parviainen, J. (2020). Robots responding to care needs? A
multitasking care robot pursued for 25 years, available products offer simple
entertainment and instrumental assistance. Ethics and Information
Technology, 22, 247–256 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-020-09536-0
Vandemeulebrouckea, T., de Casterléb, B. D., & Gastmans, C. (2018). The use
of care robots in aged care: A systematic review of argument-based ethics lit-
erature. Archives of Gerontology and Geriatrics, 74, 15–25.
Vargas, P. A., Fernaeus, Y., Lim, M. Y., Enz, S., Ho, W. C., Jacobsson, M., &
Ayllet, R. (2011). Advocating an ethical memory model for artificial com-
panions from a human-centred perspective. AI & Soc, 26, 329–337.
Von der Pütten, A. M., Krämer, N. C., & Eimler, S. C. (2011). Living with a
Robot Companion – Empirical Study on the Interaction with an Artificial
Health Advisor. ICMI’11, November 14–18, ACM, 327–334,
978-1-4503-0641-6/11/11
WHO. (2022, October 1). Ageing and health. Retrieved Nov 7, 2022, from
https://www.who.int/news-room/fact-sheets/detail/ageing-and-health
Wilks, Y., Bengio, S., & Bourlard, H. (Eds.) (2005). Artificial Companions
MLMI 2004, LNCS 3361, pp. 36–45, Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg.
Wilks, Y., Jasiewicz, J. M., Catizone, R., Galescu, L., Martinez, K. M., & Rugs,
D. (2015). CALONIS: An Artificial Companion Within a Smart Home for
the Care of Cognitively Impaired Patients. In C. Bodine et al. (Eds.): ICOST
2014, LNCS 8456, (pp. 255–260). Springer International Publishing
Switzerland. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-14424-5_30
An Examination of the Tangible Value
of IP Financing for Companies
and Businesses
Nadia Naim
N. Naim (*)
Law and Social Sciences, Aston University, Birmingham, UK
e-mail: n.naim@aston.ac.uk
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2024 157
N. Naim (ed.), Developments in Intellectual Property Strategy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-42576-9_7
158 N. Naim
economic free riders, but also as a litigation tool to recover losses and
other civil law remedies.
An audit allows a company to know what its core assets are, control
mechanisms, actions to strengthen and monetise the company’s IP and
review non-disclosure agreements, confidentiality contracts and IP licens-
ing arrangements. External investment and financing can be challenging
for businesses wishing to expand or avoid an insolvency issue given the
hesitancy in the financial sector to approve financial loans against intan-
gible assets. Land & property are tangible commodities that can be more
easily quantified by lenders and valued against established banking lend-
ing practices. Since the financial crash of 2007, banks and financial insti-
tutions are under stringent monitoring and are generally averse to
non-conventional risk in asset-based financial lending. However, where a
company can demonstrate it has protected its intangible assets and the
competitive advantage gained through patents, copyright, and confiden-
tiality agreements, are adequately protected and accounted for in an IP
audit and it can be demonstrated that they underpin revenues and fore-
casts, then banks or investors will consider taking security over them. The
diligence-backed IP audit can demonstrate how a company’s IP portfolio
clearly underpins its products & services and drives the financial growth
of the business. Further, where the IP audit incorporates risk assessments
for the level of protection for current and upcoming products and ser-
vices, the higher the likelihood of success with investors and financial
institutions. When possible recovery value can be identified from licens-
ing and sale of assets, and subsequently implemented, lenders are more
reassured that risks have been mitigated as part of the exit strategy.
Investment in IP development for growing a business can be costly
especially where there are different divisions or business streams. As
attractive as successful innovation and entrepreneurship is to all busi-
nesses, there is a significant investment needed in the form of research
and development which more often than not, can have a costly number
of failures before successful IP rights are created. Businesses rely on
An Examination of the Tangible Value of IP Financing… 161
The first step is to identify what patents the business has by listing all
registered and pending assets. This includes countries in which they are
registered or will be registered. Patent registration is the most expensive
of all the IP assets and as such requires a patent attorney. For the IP audit,
patents that are filed and/or approved need a record of all fees and details
of the inventors or designers. Filing dates and numbers with status and
expiry date can be aligned to identifiable product lines to which each
invention or design is relevant to. Patents are international in nature, and
are covered by TRIPS (Articles 27 and 28). In the UK, A full patent
application under Patent Act 1977 must contain a request for the grant
of a patent and an abstract which gives technical information, in the form
of a specification about the invention and the field to which it contrib-
utes. The function of the invention needs to be clear and precise to grant
a monopoly right (Strix Ltd v Otter Controls Ltd [1995]). A priority date
is then given as the date on which an application is filed and the duration
of the patent is calculated from that date. The UK patent will only apply
in the UK and an analysis of the territorial reach of the patent is needed
as part of the audit determine whether international protection is neces-
sary and of value.
The patent process involves a series of steps; starting with the applica-
tion form and the request for a search from the UK IPO, the Preliminary
examination is regulated by section 15A, PA 1977 with an 18 month
turnaround window, publication is 18 months from the priority date,
followed by Substantive examination, a period for amendments and if
successful, the IPO grants the patent. The purpose of the audit is to con-
sult relevant patent databases and create a list of any competing patents
that are used by third parties.
The registrar will also examine existing marks, and trade marks may
also be refused registration on the basis of relative grounds. This is con-
cerned with the effect of registration that the proposed mark may have on
other pre-existing marks. It used to be the case that the UK Trade Mark
registry raised these grounds at the application stage. However, it is now
left to owners of trade mark registrations to oppose applications through
publication in the trademark journal. The trade mark application is then
open to public inspection and possible objection for a period of three
months from the date of publication.
If, as occasionally happens, an objection is raised by a third party
against the application, then the matter has to be considered and appro-
priate action taken. It may be possible to deal with such an objection in
a relatively simple exchange of correspondence. On other occasions, the
ensuing opposition proceedings can be long and complicated.
If there is no objection, or any objection has been resolved, then the
application can proceed to registration on completion of certain formali-
ties at the Trade Mark Registry. A registration certificate is then issued
and the trade mark is placed on the Register for a period of ten years from
the date of application. After that, it can be renewed indefinitely.
For classifications of the trade mark, the Nice classification system can
be utilised to ascertain the classes of goods for which this mark should be
applied and nationally, IP offices have a trade mark search to allow for
comparison with existing classified marks. (Trade Mark Search, UK IPO).
2 Passing Off
As well as trade mark protection, the audit benefits from an understand-
ing of brand power and how to protect unregistered marks. Brand power
accumulates significant goodwill which can enable businesses to success-
fully extend the brand to new products, gain trade leverage in the com-
petition for retailers’ distribution points and take advantage of potential
cost savings in the promotion of new products in comparison to potential
new entrants or competitors with less brand power. In addition to the
brand’s reputation amongst consumers,
166 N. Naim
held the style of Coca-Cola’s bottle was part of their get-up and subse-
quently demonstrated their goodwill. Together with goodwill, the tests
for passing off require a misrepresentation and consequential damage
to occur.
Intellectual property rights grant the owner a monopoly right for a set
period; this allows the owner to make commercial gain from their inno-
vation in return for sharing it. In practice, for example, the existence of a
patented breakthrough product can give a business a head start over their
competition. The improvement of existing products or brand recognition
can give a business the edge and allow them to charge a premium cost on
their IP protected products. Intellectual property, as it states, is a prop-
erty. It is an asset of the owners, to do with as they wish. Unless using IP
to create brand value or using the monopoly to develop a market share a
business may decide to sell or license their assets.
Franchising is a version of licensing where the owner provides support
and the rights to use certain assets to anyone who can pay the fee and
agrees to the terms. Subway®, McDonalds® and Europcar® are all examples
of franchising business models. Businesses can also use IP to cross license,
allowing competitors to use their assets in return for the right to use the
competitors assets, and gain access to other technology that may other-
wise cost money, or even be inaccessible.
Looking at the international route, when and if a business decides to
expand beyond the national level of protection, IP rights can be vital to
ensure the business can have access to the wider market and assert its IP
rights. Having the appropriate rights can help to gain key partners in the
countries that a business is looking to trade in or establish a foothold in
the market (UK IPO).
The cost method is a value estimate and is cost adjusted for depreciation
and obsolescence. It is based on the aim of establishing the value of an IP
asset by calculating the cost of developing an identical or similar asset
either internally or externally. The cost method poses two fundamental
questions. First, how much would it cost to reproduce a given set of
assets, taking into account the full cycle of asset production from research
and development to acquisition. Second, how much would it cost to
replace a given set of assets and it is within these constraints that the cost
method values IP assets. The method attempts to determine the value of
an IP asset at a particular point of time by aggregating the direct expen-
ditures and opportunity costs involved in its development and mitigating
for redundant IP assets. Costs can include labour, materials and equip-
ment, research and development, overheads for utilities, accommodation
and support staff, creating a prototype, testing and trials, regulatory
approval, certification, and registering the IP asset.
To reiterate, the more detail the IP audit, the more significant the bear-
ing it has on the cost method and what a potential buyer can expect to
pay for avoiding the same costs, instead opting to buy the IP assets.
Valuable benefits that can make the cost method more attractive is the
saving of time for the purchaser, quantifiable expenditure which reflects
the cost of attempting to recreate the same IP, and there is already a track
record of success with the IP assets. Most importantly, the IP assets are
already protected which not only limits other options but also prevents
IP protection for the similar assets given the remedies available against
infringement. This method of valuing intellectual property assets lends
itself to an overall assessment when buying a business. However, as the
emphasis is on costs, rather than profit, it can skew the figures so that
market potential is not fully appreciated. The cost method does not take
account of future value and therefore loses out on a standard by which
value is traditionally calculated.
The approach of calculating replacement costs for IP asset with an
equivalent asset of similar use and function, can be used more reliably
when considering a going concern and solvent valuation. The
172 N. Naim
of the competition, changes in the economic climate and the cost of reg-
istering, enforcing and defending the IP assets. The way in which the IP
assets are exploited, the costs involved, the time it will take to get to mar-
ket and the risks involved all influence this method. A sub method of the
income or economic benefit method is the relief from royalties method
and is based on an assessment of what royalty costs a company is avoiding
by virtue of owning the IP.
Alternatively, the relief from royalties can act as a security for borrow-
ing money from lenders. In 1997, David Bowie issued a 10-year asset-
backed bond on the value of his future royalties from publishing rights
and master recordings from 25 pre-recorded albums and raised
US$55 million. The purchaser received the right to future royalties from
the albums until the principal plus 8% annual interest had been repaid
(WIPO 2016). Securitisation allows a business to bundle IP assets and
lend against predictable future cash flows directly attributable to the
IP. The loan size can be determined by the net present value of the
expected future profits and gives a manageable discounted cash flow
approach, that is adjusted to reflect the risk. There are also opportunities
to utilize IP assets as collateral, this is usually relevant to underwrite a
recovery value, with a discount rate for going concern expectations
(Inngot 2022).
assets have been sold in the market, followed by analysing data on how
many businesses, owning comparable assets, have been sold and whether
the investment data reveals how much businesses owning comparable
assets are worth and what is the licensing agreements value on these assets
(Calboli and Montagnani 2021).
Therefore, calculating the value of IP assets by reviewing the sale or
licensing of similar products in the market can act as a benchmark for
estimating the value of a product based on its existing track record in the
market. However, in practice, finding publicly published data on IP
transactions, is very difficult as there is no legal requirement to make such
data publicly available and therefore, finding relevant data that can be a
source for a market approach, is very difficult. Even where there is pub-
licly shared data or a bilateral sharing agreement, the market approach
can still be fairly broad as very few IP transactions will provide a valid
comparison. The IP assets may differ on exclusivity rights, territorial dif-
ferences, market conditions, payment structures and the value from spe-
cialist support.
Of the three, it is the most difficult approach to apply to all of a com-
pany’s IP assets as it isn’t suitable for all types of IP. For example, a patent
is granted for a new or novel invention. Finding comparable information
for a novel invention, by its own description, will be a challenge and an
objective standard is applied to create financial projections that can still
reflect the market value through consumer analysis data. For other IP
assets, such as copyright, the market approach method is very effective as
royalty rates in each market sector, can be benchmarked as high, medium
or low (UK IPO).
Exploiting the IP a business owns can create new economic revenue and
achieve other strategic goals through commercialization. IP assets can be
listed on the company accounts and can be a commodity that is bought,
licensed, franchised, or sold. IP assets can be used to secure funding from
banks and lenders, as a fixed or floating charge, depending upon the rel-
evant IP due diligence and audit checks as to who controls the asset. The
An Examination of the Tangible Value of IP Financing… 175
market value method relies more on investment data on the IP value and
ancillary licensing agreements. Despite this method having the most
resemblance to tangible asset valuation, it is flawed as the market com-
parison of intangibles are not as readily available as physical property. The
final method of income-based valuations is the most popular of the three
methods as it assesses the value of the IP assets based on current and
future profits. On the other hand, it is uncertain and can be difficult to
mitigate the risk, if the market traction is limited. To further complicate
matters, valuation priorities are different for each approach and depends
on the purpose of the IP audit such as securitisation, collateral, licensing,
franchising, or equity financing. AI can play a very important role in the
development of AI-assisted and AI-generated audit and valuation meth-
ods to expand the current market limitations on ascertaining the most
accurate value of IP assets and creating more opportunities for IP financ-
ing and lending.
References
Bainbridge, D and Howell, C. Intellectual Property Asset Management : How
to Identify, Protect, Manage and Exploit Intellectual Property Within the
Business Environment, (2014), Routledge.
Brassell, M. Challenges in harnessing IP for finance, (2022), Inngot Limited.
Calboli, I. and Montagnani, M. Handbook of Intellectual Property Research:
Lenses, Methods, and Perspectives (2021), Oxford University Press.
Contreras, J. Introduction to Intellectual Property Licensing. In Intellectual
Property Licensing and Transactions: Theory and Practice, (2022), Cambridge
University Press.
Copyright, Design and Patents Act, 1988
Durant, I. Unlocking potential of intellectual property rights to support the
creative economy, (2021), United Nations Conference on Trade and
Development.
Millien, R. The use of competitive intelligence in IP monetisation, (2014),
Intellectual Asset Management.
Patent Act 1977
Popple, L. Security over IP. Considerations when taking security over IP, (2020),
Taylor Wessing.
An Examination of the Tangible Value of IP Financing… 179
Singh, J. How startups and SMEs should think about IP: an investor’s perspec-
tive, (2021), WIPO Magazine.
Tang, D. Inaugural High-level Conversation on Unlocking Intangible Asset
Finance, (2022), World Intellectual Property Office.
Trade Mark Act 1994
UK Intellectual Property Office
UK Intellectual Property Office (UK IPO), IP Finance Toolkit, (2014). Available
at IP Finance Toolkit (publishing.service.gov.uk).
Williams, L. Anonos Secures $50 Million in IP-Backed Financing to Deliver
Data Privacy Technology with 100% Accuracy and Utility to Data-Driven
Enterprises, (2022), Business Wire.
World Intellectual Property Office, (WIPO), Methodology for the Development
of National Intellectual Property Strategies, (2016). Available at https://www.
wipo.int/edocs/pubdocs/en/wipo_pub_958_3.pdf
World Intellectual Property Office, (2021), Unlocking IP-backed Financing:
Country Perspectives. Singapore’s Jouney. Geneva: WIPO.
Transformative (Bio)technologies
in Knowledge Societies: Of Patents
and Intellectual Commons
Mariela de Amstalden and Nivita Sukhadia
1 Transformative Biotechnologies:
Cell-Cultivation for Human
Food Consumption
The year was 1931. In a line perhaps more suitable to science fiction writ-
ing at the time, Winston Churchill envisioned cell-based meats by declar-
ing that: “[w]e shall escape the absurdity of growing a whole chicken in
order to eat the breast or wing, by growing these parts separately under a
suitable medium” (Churchill 1931). Arguably, a technology, and the
products it produces, is only disruptive when it reaches the masses.
Promoted as a more sustainable alternative to conventional proteins,
research into cell-cultivation technology for human food consumption
(cellular agriculture) has gained new urgency in response to pressing
M. de Amstalden (*)
Law School, University of Exeter, Exeter, UK
e-mail: M.De-Amstalden@exeter.ac.uk
N. Sukhadia
University of Cambridge, Faculty of Law Cambridge, Exeter, UK
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2024 181
N. Naim (ed.), Developments in Intellectual Property Strategy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-42576-9_8
182 M. de Amstalden and N. Sukhadia
In setting the term of patent protection under TRIPS, Art. 33 does not
provide for any distinction on the basis of the field of technology, or
extent of exploitation, of patented inventions. Such distinctions would
arguably encourage discrimination among technological fields, leading to
an ad absurdum scenario whereby patent protection would be assigned
on a case-by-case basis, leading to extreme legal uncertainty (Pires de
Carvalho 2010).
Art. 33 stipulates that “[t]he term of protection available shall not end
before the expiration of a period of twenty years counted from the filing
date.” The term of a patent may not be shorter than 20 years, even if the
actual effects of the patent do not occur until after its grant. Accordingly,
Art. 33 identifies the earliest possible date for the end of patent protec-
tion. Although the provision ties the patent term to the date of filing and
does not contain specific regulations relating to the calculation of time
limits, this aspect was clarified by the Appellate Body in Canada— Patent
Term. In its view, the calculation of a term of patent protection is deter-
mined by taking the date of filing of the patent application and adding
twenty years (AB Canada – Patent Term, para. 85). Conversely, Members
are not bound to compensate for delays, for instance, in the examination
process of the application or in the marketing approval of products
(Correa 2022). As a result, the national patent regulations of Members
remain decisive. However, patent protection may not be significantly
curtailed by unreasonable delays in the procedures for granting patents,
as such delays are inconsistent with the obligations under Art. 62.1 and
2 TRIPS.
More specifically, the Panel in Canada—Patent Term found that Art.
33 establishes a minimum term of protection for patents, which also
raised questions about the possibility of extending rights and obligations
even after the expiry of said patent terms, which would generate spillover
effects (Canada – Patent Term, paras 6.57-6.121). The Panel Report was
subsequently appealed and, relying on the availability requirement in
Art. 33, the Appellate Body considered the provision “straightforward” in
stipulating that the filing date plus 20 years is the earliest date on which
the term of protection of a patent may end and that this 20-year term
must be “a readily discernible and specific right, and it must be clearly
seen as such by the patent applicant when a patent application is filed”
186 M. de Amstalden and N. Sukhadia
4 Conclusion
This chapter explored the impact of transformative biotechnologies like
cell-cultivation on ever-expanding knowledge societies. In doing so, it
examined the role of patents, and their terms of protection under inter-
national IP law to elucidate whether and to what extent IPR as conceived
today are compatible with the calls for open science and the solidification
of an intellectual commons.
Just as cell-cultivation technology has the potential to be considered a
‘technology of abundance’, IP rights can, and indeed, should be con-
strued as an abundant resource. In doing so, it demonstrated, with pat-
ents as an example, that IP rights have the ability to invigorate multiple
tonalities in new global economic governance mechanisms, while being
mindful of, and in fact amplify, a variety of seemingly unrelated elements
uniting to address complex social challenges. Whether IP rights as public
interest mechanisms succeed in advancing policy considerations to rei-
magine food systems through cellular agriculture merits further empirical
research.
References
(Maidana-Eletti) de Amstalden, Mariela (2016), Global Food Governance:
Implications of Food Safety and Quality Standards in International Trade
Law, Peter Lang Publishers.
Transformative (Bio)technologies in Knowledge Societies… 189
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2024 191
N. Naim (ed.), Developments in Intellectual Property Strategy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-42576-9
Index
A B
Ageing population, xi, 129–133 Berne Convention, 94, 158
Algorithms, 2, 5, 13, 30, 71, 107, Big data, vi, x, 5, 25–60, 100, 114,
108, 115–119, 124, 125 143, 184
Artificial Intelligence (AI), v–vii, Biotechnologies, vi, xii, 57, 181–188
ix–xii, 1–23, 26, 30, 40, 71, Blockchain, xi, 65–70, 72, 75, 76,
91–108, 113–115, 117–125, 79, 82, 84
130, 134–137, 139, 141, Blockchain technology, 65–67, 70,
176, 178 71, 75, 76, 84
assisted, 2, 4–6, 9–11, 15, 16, 21,
22, 176, 178
generated, 2, 4, 6, 9–13, 15, 16, C
19, 21, 22, 93–96, 135, Canada—Patent Term, 185, 186
176, 178 Care robots, xi, 129–152
ownership, vi, 1–23 Cell-cultivation technology, xii,
supported, 4, 5, 21, 22 181–184, 188
technology, v, ix, x, 5–7, 26, 40, 99, Cellular agriculture, xii, 181–184,
114, 115, 117–121, 124–126 187, 188
Artwork, vi, xi, 13, 65–85, 97, 108 Centre for International Intellectual
Assignment, 168, 175 Property Studies (CEIPI), 12
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2024 193
N. Naim (ed.), Developments in Intellectual Property Strategy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-42576-9
194 Index
Climate change, xii, 115, 182 Data mining, 30, 31, 97–99
Compendium of US Copyright Data ownership, 31–35, 45
Practices, 14 Data security, 131, 143–145, 149
Computer generated works (CGW), Data transfers, 37, 42, 45, 47,
10, 16, 19, 20, 22, 23, 95, 108 48, 51
Confidentiality, 39, 47, 142, 160, Deception, xi, 132, 134–137, 141
161, 167, 187, 188 Derivative data, 44
Consumer protection, 45–47, 149, Design Rights Audit, 162–163
150, 183 Digital economy, 27, 28, 30, 31,
Contextual adaptation, 16 35–40, 51, 52, 57, 58, 60
Contractual clauses, 6, 21, 167 Digital Markets Act, 39, 48
Copyright, xi, xii, 2, 6, 9–12, 14–16, Due diligence, 168–169, 174, 177
19–20, 22, 67, 70–73, 80–83,
91–101, 105–108, 115, 116,
122, 157, 160, 163, 167, 168, E
174, 177 Emerging technologies, ix, 1, 176
Copyright Audit, 167–168 Ethereum, 66, 68, 69, 75
Copyright Design Patent Act Ethical business strategy, 17
(CDPA) 1988, 9, 10, 19, Ethical discourse, 17
95, 98, 101 Ethics, ix, 6, 17, 20, 23, 124, 125,
Cost method, 170–172 132, 149, 176
Crypto assets, 73–75, 77 European Court of Justice (CJEU),
Cryptocurrency, xi, 66, 67, 69, 12, 77, 93, 94
73–75, 77, 78, 80, 83 European Patent Convention
Culpability, 20 (EPC), 8
Cyber law, 122 European Patent Office (EPO),
Cyberspace, 114–116, 122 8, 18, 103
European Union Commission, 5–7,
11, 22, 26
D European Union Commission IP
DABUS, xi, 8–9, 22, 101–107 Action Plan, 11
DARPA, 3 European Union Trade Marks
Databases, 5, 18, 20, 33, 42, 79, 97, Directive, 163
99, 162, 167
Database Directive, 33, 41, 42, 51
Data enclosures, 26, 27, 41, 43, F
50, 51, 58 Fair, reasonable and non-
Data Governance Act, 35, 39, discriminatory (FRAND)
40, 52, 60 terms, 48, 55
Index 195
S
Small and medium-sized enterprises U
(SMEs), 34, 48, 100 UK Intellectual Property Office
Smart contracts, 47, 65, 66, 70, 74, (UKIPO), 101–103, 164
75, 82, 83 User generated data, 26, 27, 29, 32,
Smart technologies, x, 25–27, 29, 30 44, 45, 50
Source code, 119, 124–125 User safety, xi, 144–150
Sui generis right, 10, 33, 41, 42, 51 US Patent and Trademark Office
Supplementary protection certificates (USPTO), 18, 103, 104,
(SPC), 186 120, 121
T V
Text and data mining (TDM), Visual Entidad de Gestión de
20, 97–101 Artistas Plásticos
Trademark, xii, 19, 57, 78–80, 157, (VEGAP), 80, 81
159, 161, 163–165, 177, 183
Trade Mark International
Classification Services W
(TMICS), 18 World Health Organisation
Trademarks audit, 163–165 (WHO), 129
Trade Related Intellectual Property World Intellectual Property Office
Rights (TRIPS), 7–9, 17, 116, (WIPO), 2–4, 7, 18, 21, 92,
118, 125, 126, 162, 184–188 117, 158, 173
Trade secrets, 33, 36, 46, 47, 57, 58, World Trade Organisation
167, 177, 183, 187, 188 (WTO), 184