Divine Right of Kings
Divine Right of Kings
Divine Right of Kings
I. James I, 'A Speech to the Lord. and Commons of the Parliament at White-H2.l1, on W<dn=lay
the XXI. of March. Anno 1609 [1610:r, in The WorM of the Most HIgh lind MIghue Prince; J=
'"
King of Greu Briiane; FWI«and Ireland (London, 16(6), p.
529.
2. Note the broadly favourable assessment of Figgis by G. R. Elton, "The Divine Right of Kings',
in his s-JUs m Tudor end St-rt Poliucs lind Gooemment (1 vols., Cambridge, (974), ii. 193-
14.
J. J. N. Figgis, The Divine RIght of Kmgs (znd edn., Cambridg e, (921), p. 156. The attitude which
Figgis decried may not yet be dead, 'CIurI es was unaware that it was not enough that b. sincerely
believed in the divine right absolutism of monarchy or that h. appointed a second-rate CT<W of divin es
to provide a choral accompaniment to his VI<WS': David S. Berkowitz, 'Reason of Stat. in England and
the Petition of Right, 160J- 1619', in SliUtSr.iwn: StwUm XIIT Gt:schichu = poliruchm Begriffi,
<d. Roman Schnur (Berlin, (971), p.lSe.
+ E.g. Figgis, Dioine Right of Kings, pp. '57, 159-63, lJ7-8, 186ff.
EHR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF ~INGS RECONSIDERED October
kings had an essential place in the development of Western political
theory: it enabled the establishment of a proper theory of sovereignty.
It was 'necessary as a transition stage between medieval and modern
politics' because it served as 'the popular form of expression for the
theory of sovereignty'.' The divine right of kings made the theory
of sovereignty concrete, thus facilitating its growth.
Subsequent work has on the whole expanded upon, perhaps qualified,
1. Ibid., pp.
25&,237·
2. See W. H. Greenleaf, "The Thornasian Tradition and tho Theory of Absolute Monarchy', ante,
lxxix (1964), 7-47-ro; and id., 'J= I and tho Divme Right of Kmgs', Poluicd S~, V (1957), J6-+B.
Cf. also id., Order, Empiricism end Poluics: Two Trsduums of Engluh Poluual n-gh~lfOO-1?OO(W<St
port, Conn., (980), esp. chs, I-,l;Francis Oakley, 'jacobean Political Theology: The Absolute and Ordinary
Pow= of tho King' ,foumtd 0/ the History o/Ideas, xxiI (1968),J2J--46; id , "The "Hidden" and "Revealed"
WilIJ of james I: MOT< Political Tbeology', Stud", Gr.u..na, xli (1972), }65-75; and id., Omrupotence;
CotAma~ and Order. An Excursum in the History of Ideas from Abelerd UJ Lnimzz (Ithaca, NY, (94).
J- A selective list of recent work might include A. Fox and J. Guy, Reassessing the HmTUWI A~
HU11Jamsm, Poliucs snd Rtforrn, I~IffO (Oxford, (986); P<'I<r Lake Ang/iums and P"ritansf PrtsbyterU.
nism end Engluh Omf0771llSt 71x>MfPt from Wbilgift UJ Hooker (London, 19B8); and Quentin Skinner,
The Foundstums 0/ Modn-n Poiiucd Thought (2 vols., Cambridge, (978),ii.
-4. Figgis, Divine RIght 0/ Kings, p. IJ-
5. Ibid., pp. 5-6·
6. Margaret Judson, The Crisu of the Consutuuon: An Essey in Consuuaumd and Poltucal Tbougbz
In &tg/And, 160J-Itlff (New York, (976), pp. 201., 21Jif. (the two were Roger Manwanng and William
Dickinson).
EHR Oct. 92
1992 THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED
of the theory. It was not solely absolutist, but could also imply some
sort of limitation on royal authority.' Two scholars, however, have
gone furtherr' James Daly and - rather earlier - J. W. Allen. Daly
has argued that the world-view underlying divine-right theories, far from
making kings absolute, was actually hostile to the idea that kings had
any substantial latitude for the discretionary exercise of sovereign will.
It embedded them in a divinely created hierarchy, and this position
EHR Oct. 91
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED October
work of J. P. Sommerville has been central to this development,' and
has already had a substantial impact upon early seventeenth-century his
tonography.' Dissenting voices have been few - though they have,
admittedly, been powerful voices.' Sommerville has argued that 'the
contention that the king drew his authority from God alone was the
central plank upon which absolutist theory rested'. Further, 'the effect
of absolutist theory was to make the king sovereign in England.' As
I. J. P. Sommerville, Poluics end Ideology in EngUmd, 16c!J-l~ (London. 1986). esp. ch. I; also id.,
'Ideology, Property and tho Constitution'. in Ccnflia in &.rly Stuert England: Studie: In Rt!ilgWn end
Poliucs; I60,J-I6.p. <d. Richard Cust and Ann Hughes (London. 1989), ch. 2; id., 'From Suarez to Filma:
A Reappraisal'. Hiaoncal jolt17llti, :nv (1982), 525-40; id., 'Richard Hooker, Hadrian Saravia, and tho
Advent of tho Divino Right of KIngs', Hisiory of Poluusl 7bo.tght. iv (1983), ~45; and id., 'History
and Theory: Tho Norman Conquest in Early Stuart Political Thought', Poluicd SII<lhes,miv (1986),
249-61.
1. See for example tho =ptancr of his interpretations in Lake, Angl= end P"nt4nS?, esp. p.s,
also pp. 64-5, 246. but d. pp. 204-5; Richard Cost, Tbe Forced Loom snd EngUsh Pduics, 1626-1~8
(Oxford, 1987). p . .J28; Thomas Cogswell, "The Politic> of Propaganda: Charles I and tho People in
tho 162OS·.jOlmJlll of Bruub Su.d.." nix (1990), 190; Ann Hughes, Tbe c._, of the EnglISh OvJ W.r
(London, 1991). pp. 81-3.
J. Kevin Sharpe, Poluics and lde.u In £rrly Su...rt EngLuuJ (London. 1989). pp. 285-8. Conrad
Russell, The c......" of the EnglISh Cioil W.r (Oxford, 1990), cb. 6. See also my own remarks in
'Revisionism, Politico and Political Ideas in Early Stuart England', Hisioriod [oumsl, miv (1991), f65-fi.
4. Sommerville, Politia and /<kolog;y. pp. 12, 38,35·
5. Russell, GtJ<Se of the English Civil War, p. t50.
6. Ibid., pp. LU-8.
EHR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED
or common law.' It is, then, the fact that the differences between Figgis
and Allen are once more being fought over in the most recent work
on pre-Civil-War England that makes the subject of the divine right of
kings worth investigating again.
The divine right of kings and the theory of royal absolutism were not
the same thing.2 Both had long medieval pedigrees, but they were differ
£HR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED October
had elected them or not. This was indeed the main function of the theory
in post-Reformation political thought.
In performing that function there was no need for divine-right theory
to go to the length of accepting the claims of absolutist theory. The
essential feature of absolutism was its claim that the king alone was super
ior to the positive law and not bound by it. In practical terms, this
guaranteed the right of an absolute sovereign to give people laws without
their consent.' In the words of the civil law maxims frequently used
I. For [ean Bodrn 'the principall point of Soveraigne rnajestie, and absolute power ... [lies] In giving
laws unto the subjects In general], without their consent': Tbe SIX BooIet:s of" Commonueale, trans.
Richard Knolles, eel. Kenneth McRae (Cambridge, Mass., 1962), i. 8, p. 98.
1. For example, Penrungton In Cambridge History of Mtdirr.J Poluicd Thought, pp. 431-4; Brian
Tierney, '''The Prince is not Bound by the Laws": Accursius and the Ongins of the Modern State',
Comparaioe Su.d~ 1.11 So=ty.nd Hutory, v (1963), 37S-400; and Myron P. Gilmore, Argwnmts from
R01tUtn lAtv in Political Tho.tght, uOC>-I600 (Cambridge, Mass., 19~1).
3. For the concept of plenuudo poUStAW, see I. S. Robinson in Gunbndge Hutory of Mtdietwl Poliuce!
'JboMght, pp. iliff. Compare 'the pope IS not bound by laws because he makes the laws' (ibid., p.l8:7)
with Figgis's defininon of soveretgnty quoted above. Also Pennington, ibid., pp. ~JO-I, ~33-+ For
EHR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED October
Catholic and Calvinist. But, on the whole, political thought in this period
used divine-right theory without connecting it with absolutism. The clas
sic examples are men like John Aylmer, Thomas Bilson andJohn Bridges.
There may have been elements of Caesaropapalism in some Tudor -
especially Henrician - understandings of the Royal Supremacy and of
monarchy', but the dominant Elizabethan position seems to have com
bined the view that monarchical authority in both Church and State
Royal S"{JmTlItCY In tk El~ Church (London. 1969).esp. ch. I By the seventeenth century the
idea of imperial kingship was employed for general Erastian pllrJ'OSC'bSy writers whom none
would
consider Caesaropapalists: e.g. Sir Edward Coke. 'Of the Kings Ecclesiastical Law'. Fifth Part 0/ tbe
R~ of Sir Edward Cok» (160s).repro ill Coke. R~ (London. 1776).iii. pp. vii-ix, xl; and Nathaniel
Fiennes in the Long Parliament (8 Feb. 1141).in John Rushworth, Historical Collections (8 vols.•London.
1659-1721)i.v. 176.
2. See parucularly G. R. Elton. 'La Terrae Vumx: The Triumph of Parliamentary Law in the
Sixteenth Century'. in Tbe Par/UI= 0/E/iZAheth.n England, ed. D. M. Dean and N. L. Jones (Oxford.
1990). ch. I.
J. Willi:un Lamont. 'The Rise and Fall of BIShop Bilsori', joumsl oj Bnush StMdin. v (1966). -4.
See also Patrick Collinson, 'If Constantine, then also Theodosius: St Ambrose and the Integrity of
the Elizabethan Ecclesia Ang/ICIt1U·. in his Godly People: Essays on Eng/tsh Protestantism and Purusnism
(London. I98J).ch 4.
4. For Bilson and Bridges, see Lake. Anglicsns end Puruansi' pp. 132"5.For Aylmer. see John
Aylmer. An HsrborouJe for Fauhfull and Treee ~ [Strasburg [London], 1559).sigs. HJ'~ (the
English Constitution], and B2v·BJ,R2 (divine right). I am not persuaded by the attempt to explain away
Aylmer's constirutionahsm in Michael Mendle, Dan~ Posuions:Mixed ~mmt, tbe F.sttzus of
tbe R..Jm,
and tbe A nsuer to tk XIX Propositions (Alabama, 1985)p. p. 48-sJ. For general accounts, see Christopher
Morris, Poliucd 'Tbougbt In En~ Tyndale to Hooim- (Oxford, 1953).pp. 77"9. "7-21; and J. W.
Allen. A History of Poluicd Tbougbt In tbe Sixteend: CentJtry(London.I960). pp.I~J.
5. For recent work on the resistance theory with which so much of the Elizabethan clerical establish
ment was tainted, see Donald R. Kelley. 'Ideas of Resistance before Elizabeth', in Tbe Historical Renais
SIt1I«: N= Essays on Tudor end Stuart i..JuT1IlI= and Culu.... ed, Heather Dubrow and Richard Strier
(Chicago, 1988).pp. 4B-76; and Gerry Bowler. 'Marian Protestants and the Idea of Violent Resistance
to Tyranny'. in Proteuantism and tk Nsuonal CJnm:h In Sixteenth Ccuury Eng/tuui. ed, Peter Lake
and Maria Dowling (London. 1987)c. h. 5.
EHR Oct. 92
1992 THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED
EHR Oct. 91
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED October
polity (culminating in the extensive intellectual energy poured into the
Oath of Allegiance controversy after r606), and the Jacobean Union of
England and Scotland.' The former produced an increase in the vigour
and single-mindedness with which resistance theory was pursued by Eng
lish controversialists, and a greater care in closing off possible paths to
the development of resistance theory. This task was increasingly carried
out before a European audience, and so took on a degree of abstraction
from the specifics of the ancient constitution of England that had not
I. Conrad Russell, 'English Parliaments, [593-[606: One Epoch or Two?', in Perlionents ofEllZAkthttn
Engloui, ch. 8, esp, pp. 1O;ff., is useful on the way the issue of union with Scotland affected the political
'atmosphere' of James's reign.
2. TIlls is panicularly true of the Oath of Allegiance controversy, on which see C. H Mcllwain's
introduction to h15 edition of Tbe Poluuxl Works of [eme: I (Cambridge, Mass., [9[8); Peter Milward,
ReligioItJ Controoersus of the jlUoJ-n Age: A Seroey of Pnnted SoMrces (London, [978), ch. J; and Sommer
ville, Politics end Ideology, pp. ['7-2[, [95-208. There are also useful perspecnves on the subject in
J. H. M. Salmon, 'Gallicanisrn and Anglicanism in the Age of the Counter-Reformation', in
hisRm.ussance and Reodt: £ss,rys In the lntellectuel end Socul History of &.rly Mrxkm Fra.na
(Cambndge, [~), cb.
7·
3 This is particularly evident in the arguments and decisions given by Bacon, Coke and Ellesmere
in Calvin's Case ([608): State Truls, ii, cols. 55~; and Louis A. Knafla, [.,.U! and Politics in jlUobun
Eng14nd: Tbe Tracts of Lord OJ.mce/lor Ellesmere (Cambndge, [977), pp. 202-B. For further material,
see Bruce R. Galloway and Brian P. Levack (ed.], Tbe jttCOb6m Unum: Six Trects of t/5o.f (Edinburgh,
[985), esp. tracts by Doddridge and Spelman.
4. Pocock,Anaenr Constiiutum, ch. iii; Donald R. Kelley, 'History, English Law and the Renaissance',
PIlSl md Present, l.xv ([97-4),2-4-51; also Burgess, Poliucs of the Anntnt Consutution, ch.
3.
5. WIlliam WIlkes, Obedience; or Ecclenestiod Union (London, I~), p. 56. (The work was reissued
in [608 under the title A &rond Mommto for Magim-aus.] Sommerville, Politics end Ideology. p. }6,
cites tbis as an example of the absolutist contention thai kings alone made law.
EHR Oa. 92
1992 THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED
I. Wilk<s, Obedience, p. 49 (bur d. p. s8 where room is made for the dispensing power).
1. Ibid, p. 6J.
J. Ibid, pp. 49 (law), 6Jff. (the king), 3S(both); and passtm.
-4- Ibid, p. 43.
S. Peter Heylyn, A Briefe lind Moderau AIU'!DtT, to the Seduious end Sc.nd.:Jol<J CJ,allmges of Henry
BJITUm (London, (637), p. 37.
6. Ibid, p. 33[stress added].
EHR Oct. 91
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED October
to question in the abstract what kings could and could not do - which
1
is not to say that in actual fact they could do whatever they liked.
These passages are very similar to statements made by King James
himself in 1610.2 He too distinguished between the abstract and concrete
powers of a king. Interestingly, the distinction was advanced as part of
the defence of a political sermon by one of his bishops.' James argued
that general statements of divine right should not be read as making
And therefore that reverend Bishop here amongst you, though I heare that
by divers he was mistaken or not wei understood, yet did he preach both
learnedly and trewly annent this point concerning the power of a King: For
what he spake of a Kings power in Abstracto, is most trew in Divinitie [stress
added]: For to Emperors, or Kings that are Monarches, their Subjects bodies
& goods are due for their defence and maintenance. But if I had bene in
his place, I would only have added two words, which would have cleared
all: For after I had told as a Divine, what was due by the Subjects to their
Kings in general, I would then have concluded as an Englishman, shewing
this people, That as in general! all Subjects were bound to relieve their King;
So to exhort them, that as wee lived in a setled state of a Kingdome which
was governed by his owne fundamentall Lawes and Orders, that according
thereunto, they were now (being assembled for this purpose in Parliament)
to consider how to helpe such a King as now they had; And that according
to the ancient forme, and order established in this Kingdome: putting so,
a difference between the generall power of a King in Divinity, and the setled
and established State of this Crowne, and Kingdorne.'
l. John Rawlinson, Vitoal Rex: A Sermon Prescbed 41 Pauls Cross on tbe Day of hIS Ma}estus Hsppie
ir14"gur41,on, MArch Lf. 1614 (Oxford, .6(9), pp. 6-8. Rawlinson also talked of kings as stewards
accountable for their stewardship (pp "1-(6), and as public servants (p. J.1). Those, like Rawlinson
perhaps, who wished to equate tyranny WIth refusal to obey positive law, seem to have left little
room for absolute monarchy at all: .ny monarch not bound by positive law would become. tyrant
ThIS line of thought was developed extensively by Parliamentarians in the I~OS (It is found, too, m
Locke). For good prop. ganda reasons the Parliamentarians found it useful to be able to label any theory
of irresistible monarchy
as • theory of arbitrary monarchy or tyranny. Henry Feme (in a passage quoted later] responded
to an effort of this SOrt made by Philrp Hunton, who claimed that the divines' arguments for Charles's
irresisribihry amounted to the view th at he was an absolute, or even an arbitrary, monarch- Hunton,
A Treatise of M0114rcbie (London, '~3), p. 33- From Feme's point of vie..., Hunton SImply
conflared two separate issues: resistance and the extent of royal authoriry, Reading early Stuart divine-
right theory as • theory of absolutism is to interpret it in accordance WIth later Parliamentarian
propaganda, which attempted to dissolve distinctions between divine-right irresistibdiry, absolute
monarchy, arbitrary monarchy and tyranny.
1. Rawlinson, Vi",,! Rex, pp. 4-16-
3- Foster (ed.) Proceedings in P~rliAmm4 .6.0, ii. J.1B.
4- Sec Abbot's reasons for hISrefusal to license Sibthorpe's sermon, in Rushworth, Hisumcd Collec
turns, i. 434-57, esp. p. 441; also pnnted in Stae Trials, ii, cols, Lf5J-
80.
5. John Buckeridge, A Sermon Preubed .t Hampton Court btf= tbe Kings M4jestu. on T~ tbe
13- of Septemier, Anno 1606{London, (606), sig.
A3-
6. Robert Wulan, C(}nspmlCl~against Kings, HeatJOTlSScome: A Sermon Preecbed at Westminsur-Abbry
btf= tbeJwdg<!$. "fJ07I tbe Fifth
of N~ 1612 (London, .&2), p_B_
EHR Oct. 92
1992 THE DIVINE RIGHT OF ICINGS RECONSIDERED 851
with cheerefull obedience, and with willing Tribute'.! The claim that
subjects had a duty to pay tribute willingly was a commonplace of divine
right sermons. Few who made it got into the trouble of William Beale,
who was charged in the Short Parliament with having preached in 1635
that 'taxes and subsedyes, tonnage and poundage ... are the Kings Absolu
tely ... as absolutely as his crowne and likewise or [sic] selves our goods
our servants, our children'.'
l. Edward Reynolds, The Shzdtks of the Earth. A Sermon Preached befo", the R~ Judges, SIT R
ubard Huuon, snd SIT Georg< Crooke, it! the ASSlzt5 Holden ~l North-hampton: February '5, 16J.4 (London,
16;6), p.zo.
2. Esther S. Cope and Willson H. Coates (ed.), Proceedings of the Short Perliament of 1~0 (London,
Camden Soc., 4th Ser., vol. XIX, 1977), P 186; d. Judith D. Maltby (ed.), The Short Psriument (l~o}
Diary of SIT 7ho1Tl4S Anon (London, Camden Soc, +th Ser., vol. Xl<XV, 1988),p. Ill. The report of
the sermon was given by John Pyrn. There is, however, much more to the Beale case than this, and
he comes closer than most to fimng Into Sommerville'. categories. Conrad Russell has suggested hLS
unrypicaliry (The F,.// of the British Mon..rcIms, 16J7-1~ [Oxford, 1991), p. 116 and n. 14+). In The
Poluus of the Arnunt Consutuuon, ch. 7, I recount Beale's story at some length, arguIng that he was
used in I~O-I as a weapon in the attempt to lmk the Laudian Cburch with absolutist politics, and
pointing out how little other evidence there was to sustain such a
charge.
J. Patrick Collinson, The Reugion of Protestants: The Chwrch in Engluh Soony, 15~1615(Oxford,
198», p. 18. Collinson's remark refers to Jacobean statements on the relationship between monarchy
and episcopacy. My argument on divine-right politics is analogous to his (ibid. esp. pp. 10, 12-lJ): on
both subjects there has been a tendency to read general statements about the basis of authority as
if they were statements about the modes of operation of that authority, and a tendency to play down
the conventionality of Jacobean thought and Its links wuh the Elizabethan past.
4. Buckeridge, Sermon Pmtched it! Hampton Court. ... 1606, sig. AJV.
EHR Oct. 92
852 THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED October
the principle (which James reiterated later in his 1610 speech") that it
was the law itself which defined what taxes, subsidies and tribute were.'
What needs particular stress is how uncontroversial most statements
of the king's divine right to receive tribute were. Provided that some
basic rules of usage were observed there was nothing objectionable in
such claims. This is apparent from an examination of the most contro
versial of all the sermons addressed to the issue of taxation, those
I. See particularly his comment that it would be absurd for kings to neglect the law since it defined
property rights, including their own right to inherit the crown: 'Speach of XXI. March 1609 [1610]',
p.5Jl.
2. See also the message that lames delivered to Parliament, vi. hi, Lord Treasurer, Salisbury, on
8 March 1610: "That the king m.y take subsidi es without the consent of his people, he condemns
the doctrines as absurd and him rhat maintains the posinon, The marriage between law and prerogative
is inseparable': Foster (ed.), Pro=dmgs in Parliament; 1610,ii. 50; also i. )1 (where subsidi es are also
said to 'proceed out of the love and affection of his people', the only claim that many other divine-right
theorists were actually making); and S.1t Gardiner (ed.), Perliementsry v.bau:s in 1610(London,
Camden
Soc., rst Ser., vol. lxrxi, 1852), p. >+
3- See Cust, Forced Lean, esp. pp. 62ff; also id., 'Charl es I, the Pnvy Council, and the Forced Loan',
[oumel 0/ Bruish SuuiIeS, niv (1985),208-)5.
4- Matthew Wren, A Sermon Preacbed btf= the Kzngs MAjt:slie on Sund.ry the SnJmumth 0/ ~ry
1As~ III wmu.H~ (Cambridge, 1627), passim, esp. 1'1'. 3Off.
5. Isaac Bargrave, A Sennon F'r<ached btf07Y! King Charles, Mn-ch '7' 1627-Eking the Anntvmary of
bis ~ l"""gI<raIUm (London, 1627), pp. 5-6,17,18-19.
6. Id., A Sermon Preabed 1407Y!the Honorable AssmJiy ... of the Louer House of Psriiameru: hbn...ry
the La: 162)b6"Lfl{London, 1624), esp. pp. 5-6,21-5, )4-5·
7. Probably the most accessiblematerial on the reaction to the sermons of Sibthorpe and Manwaring
is that In Stau Truls, ii, cols, '450-80; iii, cols, m-s8. This IS mostly reprinted from Rushworth. For
Charles', proclamation (~ June 1628) calling in Manwaring's work, see James F. Larkin (ed.), StN.rt
Royal ProcJ.malions. Vol. II: Rcryrd Prodsmstions of King Charks I, 1625-1646(Oxford, 198)),pp. 197-8.
There is further material in R. C. Johnson ~ ..I. (ed.), Ccmmoru Debate: 1618(4 vols., New Haven,
1977), ii. 86, 89, 92, 219; iii. 261-2, 404-16, 419, 429, 491, 512, 623-4, 633; iv. )6-7, )9, 45. 68, 90, 92,
101-), 210, 280-.., 307-28, 40J; M. F. Keeler et ..I. (ed), Lords Prrxeadmgs, 1618(New Haven, 198)), Pl'.
58>-5, 596, 6os-7, 612-'4, 621-2, 628, 6)5-7, 6.}2-.., 146-7, 6s4, 660-), 672, 678, ~-6. See also Harry
F. Snapp, 'The Impeachment of Roger Maynwaring', Hsntmgton 1...ibr4ryQlucrterly, XIX (191)6-7), 217-)1;
and Somerville, Poluia end Ideology, pp 127-)1.
EHR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED
into trouble not for espousing the doctrine of the divine right of kings,
but for misapplying it. Both of them addressed too specifically the ques
tion of taxation and deduced from the general principle of divine right
conclusions that were properly matters of law rather than of divinity.
It was the maintenance of this boundary that kept others out of trouble.
Sibthorpe, for example, was rather too explicit about the financial impli
cations of divine-right kingship, specifying the types of taxes to which
EHR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED October
the power to judge is one 'which out of its owne absolutenes serteth
downe a Law', though the exact relation of this remark to the kings
of England was vague.' More interesting, however, is this:
So it is in the Republike, the King is not limited, his power is diffused through
the whole and every particular, and according to the instruments hee works
by, so is his power denominated. Inthe Chauncery hee is called Lord
Cbauncelor, in other counsJudge,Justice, and so of the rest.'
EHR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED
EHR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF lUNGS RECONSIDERED October
terms) as theorists of absolutism by divine right. For this reason, Sommer
ville's account of them may indeed be superior to Allen's;' yet both
accounts seem to miss the untypicality of the pair, commented on above.
There are very few divine-right theorists whose ideas were at all close
to those of Manwaring and Sibthorpe - William Beale may be one, but
others are difficult to find.2 Consequently, the interesting question to
ask about Manwaring and Sibthorpe is whether their sermons marked
a general change in the tone of early Stuart political thinking, the rise
I. Compare Sommerville, Poluus end Ideology, pp. 127-31,with Allen, English Poltucal Thought,
PP·176-80·
2. On Beale, see above p. 851, n. 2. He was reponed to hove argued 'that the King might constitute
Lawes what, whe re, when, and og[amst)t whom hee would .. .', Cope and Coates, Proceedings of
tbe Short Pariument, p. 185.
J. Cf. J. S. MorriU, &umumth Century Britain; 160]-1714 (Folkestone, 1980), pp. 57-8.
-4 Nichol as Tyacke, Arui-Cdomtsts: The Rue of Engluh Anrnn",rnsm, c. 15!J<rI~0 (Oxford, 1987),
P·159·
5. See the neat formulauon of David Owen, Herod lind Pilate Reconciled: Or, The Concord of Pspu:
and Puritan ... for the Coercion, Deposiuon; and Killing of Kings (Cambridge, 1610),sig. "2; also id.,
Arui-Paraus; or, A T~ in tht D.fonce of tht Royr<llRight of Kings \'iork, 1142), sigs. BI-B3v.
6. lames Ussher, 'A Sermon preached before the Commons House of Parliament ... the 18th of
February, 1620 [1621]',in The Wbok Worb ... of Jmu:s Ussber, ed. C. R. Elrington and 1. H. Todd
(17 vols., Dublin, 1!47~), ir, -415-V,Bargrave, Sermon Pretzch«J btfort tbe H01lOJIrahk A;smzbly; The
Worb of the Most R~ Faber In God, WJlittm lAud D. D., ed. W. Scott and J. Bliss (7 vols ,
Oxford, 1147-60),i. 91-117,4?-8l.
7. This would seem to fit weU the picture being drown of the artirudes to puritan conspiracy found
amongst some of Chari",', advisers from the lore 16zos in such works OS L J. Reeve, O>.rrks I and
the Road to Personal RNk (Cambridge, 19B9).and Richard Cust, 'Charles I and a Draft
Declaration for the 1618Parliament', Historical Rt5NrCh,lriii (1990),143-61.
EHR Oct. 91
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF K.INGS RECONSIDERED
I. There is, though, a need for a dew led srudy of the political thought of WilIWn Laud. Arguably,
the best account remains W. H. Hutton, WillIAm LAud (jrd edn., London, 1905), ch. 4- Lick of detailed
guidance on the subject can lead even the best astray. One recent historian, for example, has cited
as Laud's a remark found in his famous table of English Parliaments and their doings ([public Record
Office] SP I6I96IJI - some insight into the point behind this compilation rrught be had from the
document produced at about the same time in which Laud listed the arguments for and ag:unst calling
a Parliament, ibid. 1619+,88), which say, of Magna Carta that it 'had an obscure birth from usurpation:
IlLwas fostered and shewed to the World by Rebellion': Malcolm Smuts, Court eutun-. and tbe Origlns
of a Royalist Tradition in &:rly Stuart England (Philadelphia, 1987), p. 273. The remark, like many
of the annotations from this document, is in fact a quotation from Sir Walter Ralegh, 'The Prerogative
of Parliaments in England' (1628), in his Work>, ed, Willwn Oldy, and Thomas Birch (8 vols., Oxford,
1829), viii. 16I.
2. This concluding section draws upon perspectives developed at grealer length in my Politics of
the A ncient Consutuuon, esp, part
II.
3 John Buckeridge, A Sermon Preabed btf= His ~ at Whiuh.ll, M..rrh 21. 1617 (London,
1618), p. <4. Examples of the use of divine-right theory to express a general obligation of obedience
can ~ multiplied endlessly: e.g. Humphry Sydenham, Mose and Aaron: or, The A/ftnme of QvJ1 and
EcdesWstidee PO'!«r (London, 1626), p. 5; Buckeridge, A Sermon Preabed at Hampton Cm..-t, sigs. AJ,
Clv: Henry Valentine, God s.w tbe King. A Sermon Preecbed in 51 Pa.Js Cbwrch tk 17th of MArch.
16)9 (London, 1639),pp. 3-8, 28; Willan, Conspirecie AgtUnst Kings, Ht!I.'!JmJScome, p.
z+
4. M. E. Rickey and T. B. Stroup (ed.), Certane Sermons or Homilies ... A Faavnik Reproducuon
of the Eduion of 162) (Gainesville, Fl., 1968), i. 6ty-n; ii. 275-)ll. For further material, see Richard
L. Greaves, 'Concepts of Political Obedience in LIte Tudor England', joll77lll1 of Briusb Studies, xxii
(1982), 2J-J4; and Gordon J. Schocher, 'Patriarchalisrn, Politics and Mass Attitudes in Stuart England',
Historical joumal, xii (191'9), 412-41.
EHR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED October
teenth century as it had been under the Tudors. Throughout the early
Stuart period preachers attacked doctrines of resistance, but the works
in which they did so seldom strayed across the boundary that divided
expression of the duty to obey from expression of absolute sovereignty.
There were, of course, particular times when the issue of resistance
became a pressing one, most noticeably after the Scottish rebellion.
Thomas Mor ton, a veteran of Jacobean anti-Catholicism, preached on the
text Romans IJ:I at Durham on 5 May 1639.' But just as in 1605, in
1. Buckendge, &mum Preached i!t Hampton Court, sigs. CI, CIV-C2, C3V If.; Heylyn, Brief« and
ModerdU Ans!«T, pp. 61f., ch. 5; Carleton, [unsdutum, chs. 3, +- Carleton, of course, was very
careful to delineate the boundary between the authonry of the king and that of the bishop, and to
preserve a spiritual authority in the bishops that could be used agamst the king (ibid., pp 4-4--6); but
this should not be seen out of perspective. The book's central object is to rule out any clericisr
resistance theory, and its final chapter is a lengthy refutation of the claim that the Church possesses
coercive jurisdiction over pnnces. For discussion of Carleton, see WtllIarn Lamont, Godly Rule Poliua
and RelIgion, 16o}-60
(London, 1969), pp . .J6-4[; Colhruon, RdlguJTJ of Protestants, pp. 3-4. CZ-lC; and [d. 'If Constantine,
then also Theodosius', pp. [}l-3; but d. J. P. Sommerville, 'The Royal Supremacy and Episcopacy
"Jure DIVIno"', [ournsl of Ecdesusuod HIStory, uxiv ([983), j4S-j8; also, more broadly, id., Poluics
end Ideology, ch. 6.
2. Richard Bancroft, lJdng=>us Posuions snd Proceeding; Publzskd end Prectised smthin tins Ilend
of Brytaine (London, [59). The essential object of Bancroft's criticism was the Genevan view that 'if
Kinges and Princes refused to refourrne Religion, the inferior magistrates or P"DP'e, by direction of
the ministene, might lawfullie, & ought (u need required) even by force & arrnes, to reform it
themselves' (p. 9). He then spent great effort demonstrating that this doctrine infected the British
Isles, thanks largely to the Scots and their English followers.
3 The Canons are reprinted In Works of .. Wzl/!4m Uud, v. 607-)3; see esp, Canon I, pp. 6[3-[5·
For criticism of the Canons as derogatory to the royal prerogative, see Rushworth, Historical Co/lemons,
iii. [209. t207, 1205,[354;IV.35%CSPD, 1/£fo, p. 616;and note that Joseph Hall's defence of the Canons
shows no inclination to defend their divine-righr polnical doctrine: 'A Speech in Parliament in Defence
of the Canons made in Convocation', in Philip Wynter (ed.), Tbe Worb of the RightR~ Joseph
Hsll; D.D. (new edn .•Oxford, 186). viii. 2;r8-8I.More generally, I remain persuaded of the perspectives
advanced in William Lamont, Ricberd Baxter end the Mtllmmum: Protestent Impenalism end the English
Reoolsuon (London, (979), ch. 1, ....hich reveals some of the ways in which the Civil War was not
an anti-authoritarian srruggle, but a battle in defence of true authority.
£HR Oct. 92
860 THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED October
that the king could legitimately make (and which some, no doubt, hoped
he would make).
Most important in the end, though, is understanding not what divine
right theory could be used to do without controversy, but what it could
not do. It was not a language appropriate for addressing specific legal
questions involving prerogatives and liberties; and when it was used as
such (or even, as with Harsnett, when there was an appearance of its
I. lames F. Larkin and Paul L. Hughes (ed.), Suart. Royal Prodemsuons. Vol. 1: Royal Prodsmaions
o{KingJ= I, rooJ-r62f(Oxford, 197J), pp. 355-6·
2. The nearest we get to an exception is the ~ rummarizing Romans IJ:6 that talks of rendering
*
obedience to the prince 'by paytng tribute unto him for his Regall support': Richard Mocker, God
ami King(London, (615), p. J4 - but like so many similar remarks, it IS the bland statement of
a moral duty, not a legal argument.
EHR Oct. 92
THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS RECONSIDERED 861
condemnation of resistance theory), and to suggest more loosely the
dependence of the Church on the secular power, whether this was a
technique (as with Heylyn) for accusing critics of the Church of sedition,
or (in the early 1640S) for arguing that the form of church government
could lawfully be altered. By that time there were attempts to appropriate
the divine-right authority of kings over their churches for use (even con
trary to the king's personal wishes) against the divine right of bishops.'
We should always remember, however, that the performance of none
l. There nuy be a sense, then, in which some of Charles I' enemies were as indebted !O tho divino
right of king> as Ius friends, for that theory had been crucial In establishing tho subjection of tho
Church and its clergy to temporal authoriry. See also tho suggestive remarks in Edmund S. Morgan,
Inventing the People The Rise of Populsr Sowreignty In Eng/4nd end A17U7UlI (Now York, ,988),
ch. I,on tho ways in which divine-right theory could be US«! to limit royal activiey.
2. Since this mid. was written there has appeared a discussion of tho divine-right theori es of larnos
U', reign which in places parallels the argument here: sec Mark Goldie, 'The Political Thought of
the Anglican Revolution', in The R~tl.01U of 168lt The Andre» Browning i1ctsrm, I!J$8, ed, Raben
Beddard (Oxford, 1991), ch. 2., e.g. remarks on pp. til-fl. I would like to thank Cohn Davis for
bringing these similarities to my attention,
J. See funhcr Burgess,Poluia of the A ncient Consiuuuon,part ii.
EHR Oct. 92