UrbanAffairsReview 2014 Hendriks 553 76
UrbanAffairsReview 2014 Hendriks 553 76
UrbanAffairsReview 2014 Hendriks 553 76
net/publication/261537374
CITATIONS READS
112 3,322
1 author:
Frank Hendriks
Tilburg University
285 PUBLICATIONS 2,513 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Frank Hendriks on 03 March 2015.
Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
On behalf of:
Additional services and information for Urban Affairs Review can be found at:
Subscriptions: http://uar.sagepub.com/subscriptions
Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav
Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
Citations: http://uar.sagepub.com/content/50/4/553.refs.html
What is This?
New Direction
Urban Affairs Review
2014, Vol. 50(4) 553–576
Understanding Good © The Author(s) 2013
Reprints and permissions:
Urban Governance: sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/1078087413511782
Essentials, Shifts, and uar.sagepub.com
Values
Frank Hendriks1
Abstract
Building on the relevant international literature, as well as empirical research
on urban cases, this article determines and discusses five core values of
good urban governance: responsiveness, effectiveness, procedural justice,
resilience, and counterbalance. The quest for good governance can take
various forms. This article focuses on urban governance, and identifies four
different shifts, with increased emphasis on the real decision makers or the
ordinary citizens, with increased attention to selective choice or integrative
deliberation as modes of urban governance. Urban governance and good
urban governance are not synonymous. This article advocates critical
reflection, moving beyond the performance bias that tends to accompany
governance reform.
Keywords
urban governance, good governance, democracy, rule of law, responsiveness,
effectiveness, procedural justice, resilience, counterbalance, urban regime,
urban market, urban trust, urban platform.
Corresponding Author:
Frank Hendriks, Public Administration, Tilburg School of Politics and Public Administration,
Tilburg University, Warandelaan 2, Tilburg 5037 AB, Netherlands.
Email: F.Hendriks@uvt.nl
urban cases are, thus, connected to the long-standing debate, in which the
Italian town of Siena plays a pivotal role.
In the Siena town hall, we find the world-famous fourteenth-century paint-
ings by Lorenzetti depicting the precepts and effects of good governance in
the city. The painting Effeti del Buon Governo in Città shows citizens living
peacefully together, engaging in transactions and alliances. Lorenzetti sug-
gests that these good effects follow from “good governance,” illustrated by
his Allegoria del Buon Governo in Città. This painting nicely exemplifies
that good governance is more than “doing good things.” Good governance is
about doing things in a sound institutional setup, characterized by effective
checks and balances and countervailing powers—as we have subsequently
come to call them in the wider framework of the democratic rule of law. As a
medieval artist, Lorenzetti did, of course, not use these terms but worked with
images. His allegory of good governance depicts a diversified institutional
setting that knows no absolute power, but power checked by Lady Justice as
well as a train of free citizens, and led by cardinal virtues such as prudence,
temperance, magnanimity, and fortitude.
If we were to make a Buon Governo in Città for today’s urban areas, what
should we highlight as essential? What qualities and characteristics of urban
governance need to be stressed? In addressing this question—in social sci-
ence language rather than painting—this article will link up with the relevant
literature, which has gone through a much-discussed “shift from government
to governance” (Bevir 2010; Kjaer 2004; Pierre 2000; Rhodes 1996, 2000)
and appears to be witnessing a further shift from governance to “good gover-
nance” (Ahrens, Weingarth, and Caspers 2010; Bovaird and Löffler 2003;
Mulgan 2006; Rothstein and Teorell 2008).
The aim of this article is not to present an exhaustive overview of all the
literature on governance and good governance. The aim is, more modestly, to
determine the essential elements and dimensions of urban governance and to
develop a framework for understanding good urban governance. The relevant
international literature constitutes a means to this end, in addition to empiri-
cal research into the quest for good governance (QGG) in a series of Dutch
cities.1
Although the terminology on governance has its shortcomings (more
about this in the next section), it has two major advantages for present pur-
poses. First of all, the governance concept calls our attention to the fact that
governing in the urban realm involves more than “city hall” as a metaphor for
monocentric government in the city. “Local government” is no more (and no
less) than one constituent part of “urban governance.” Second, and perhaps
more importantly, if we widen the concept of governance to “good gover-
nance,” this will encourage us to reflect more systematically on what quality
to mention just one department, can still intervene, even when private secu-
rity does a lot of the day-to-day surveillance.
“Governance without a lot of government” is by no means the only theo-
retical variant. Lowndes and Skelcher (1998), Pierre and Peters (2000),
Kooiman (2003), Bovaird (2005), and others distinguished different “modes
of governance,” which would include “networks,” “markets,” and “hierar-
chies.” These are three basic modalities that occur in various blends in exist-
ing urban governance models. In the Los Angeles blend of urban governance,
the market mechanism and the mode of self-organization are comparatively
more prominent than, for example, in the Dutch mixture of governance
modalities, in which government and top-down planning remain relatively
important (Hendriks and Musso 2004).
In a realistic approach to urban governance, government and hierarchy
may be downplayed, as city hall is indeed not a city’s control center, but they
cannot be defined away altogether (Stoker 2011). The idea that modern gov-
ernance is a web of purely horizontal, nonhierarchical relations is an unreal-
istic one, as is the idea that working arrangements in dealing with public
problems could be purely nonformal, without any official strings attached.
Governance is a compound of both horizontal and vertical, both nonformal
and formal arrangements that have structural significance for public issues,
here in the urban realm (cf. Haus, Heinelt, and Stewart 2005; Peters and
Pierre 1998; Stoker 1998).
To do something in a particular way, for a limited amount of time (ad hoc),
does not yet amount to “governance.” This would require some regularity, a
certain level of institutionalization. The working arrangements of urban gov-
ernance can be understood as institutions in the sense of “rules in use” (E.
Ostrom 2005).
these parties were too obsessed with power over (who was having power over
whom), rather than with power to (how are things actually accomplished?).
Flyvbjerg (1998), in his detailed study of Aalborg, Denmark, indeed observed
that the heart of the matter was not so much “Who governs?” but more “How
is the governing being done?” and how is power being executed in this.
Although just as important, the issue of how checks and balances and
countervailing powers are institutionalized has received less attention in
today’s urban governance literature. These issues are usually associated with
national constitutions. Yet discourse on corrective capacity originated in
highly polycentric urban domains. As highlighted in the introduction, the
allegory Buon Governo in Città was all about the checks and balances pro-
vided by institutions and powers around the government of a city like Siena,
comparable with cities like Florence, Genua, Venice, and other city-states
(Finer 1999). One of the most spectacular examples of “multiactor gover-
nance” in a sprawling “urban field”’ manifested itself still earlier: Republican
Rome (not to be confused with the latter-day Empire).2
It is remarkable and a pity that, in the contemporary debate on urban gov-
ernance, the framing of checks and balances is given less consideration than
in the current discourse on corporate governance, in which the “constitu-
tional” relations between CEOs, boards of directors, supervisory boards,
assemblies of shareholders, and other stakeholders have been hotly debated
(Pietrancosta 2009). In urban governance, there are many fragmented
“offices” that can and should be understood in terms of countervailing forces:
local councils, neighborhood councils, mayor and aldermen, urban district
coordinators, higher level co-governments, civil service departments, ombud-
spersons, audit committees, housing corporations, welfare organizations,
community work agencies, municipal advisory councils, chambers of com-
merce, residents’ organizations, neighborhood management companies, indi-
vidual citizens, and so on. Their added value should be assessed not only in
productive or instrumental terms but also in terms of corrective capacity (cf.
V. Ostrom 1982).
regime only serves the interests of the city’s top dogs; their connected power
is not so much “power over” (controlling) but rather “power to” (productive),
and this may well be in the citizen’s best interest—at least, according to urban
regime theory (cf. DiGaetano and Klemanski 1993; Harding 1994; Lauria
1997; Stoker 1995; Stone 1989).
civil society, but it does not come as close to the citizenry as the urban plat-
form aspires to come (Noveck 2009; H. Wagenaar and Duiveman 2012).
well in the urban domain but need not do so at all. This requires critical
reflection, informed by essential quality standards.
2008; Haus, Heinelt, and Stewart 2005; Heinelt, Sweeting, and Gemitis 2006;
Hendriks 2010; Mulgan 2006; Pierre 2009; Rothstein and Teorell 2008). This
has led to the construction of a good governance values catalogue, covering
five core values: responsiveness, effectiveness, procedural justice, resilience,
and counterbalance. Table 1 helps to clarify how these values interlock.
The good governance values catalogue collapses many of the specific val-
ues mentioned above into fewer and more fundamental categories. This is
done not only because the human mind can deal better with a smaller number
of items but also and primarily because the good governance debate is in dire
need of the second step in the evolutionary process of “variation and
shows an ability to actually do things, solve problems, and deliver value for
money.5
In the urban domain, responsiveness and effectiveness are relevant values
that are often pursued in programs aiming to further urban governance. One
of the cases in the Dutch QGG research, the Eindhoven Brainport project,
explicitly aimed to accomplish added (economic) value for the urban region
(Van Ostaaijen and Schaap 2012). It was mostly focused on output legiti-
macy, and not so much on input legitimacy, just like the urban regime cum
growth coalition was that Stone (1989) had witnessed in Atlanta. In the case
of Breda, it was the other way around. There, Neighborhood Tables were
established to improve openness and rapport with the citizens on the input
side of the urban governance model. For the establishment of Neighborhood
Councils in cities like Los Angeles and Lille, this was also the prime concern
(Cole 2011; Musso et al. 2006; Van Ostaaijen and Drosterij 2012).
Procedural Justice
Good governance amounts to more than gratifying the citizenry, let alone a
momentary majority of citizens. This is central to the idea of the Rechtsstaat
or the “rule of law,” which complements the idea of democracy as the “rule
of the people.”6
Regarding process values, we may think of the officially-prescribed
Algemene Beginselen van Behoorlijke Bestuur (General Principles of
Appropriate Administration) in the Netherlands or similar process values
(accountability, transparency, ethical conduct, human rights, rule of law)
included in the good governance code issued by the Council of Europe
(2008). The values catalogue presented in Table 1 lists the crucial ones under
the umbrella term “procedural justice,” bringing together more legal (lawful-
ness, accountability, equal rights) and more interactionist (correctness, integ-
rity, civility) types of values. Rothstein and Teorell (2008) considered one
element out of this set—impartiality—as the essence of good governance.
However important this element is in and of itself, relying on impartiality
alone would undervalue other essential standards of procedural justice (cf.
Esaiasson 2010; Tyler and Darley 2000; Tyler and Huo 2002).
Procedural justice is no less a core value for good governance in the urban
domain than responsiveness or effectiveness. Those involved in urban gover-
nance have legitimate procedural expectations and rights, and they are fully
entitled to demand respect to them, even if urban governance is said to be
working by and for the demos at large. Especially where formal political
rights and deeply-felt social norms concerning due process converge—as in
principles such as fair play, equality, and proportionality—sensitivity to this
dimension of good governance tends to be well developed among the
citizenry. Against this background, it is remarkable that only one case out of
the eight cases in the Dutch QGG study specifically prioritized process val-
ues in the attempts to improve urban governance. Only for the Neighborhood
Tables, initiative in Breda was due process a top priority (Van Ostaaijen and
Drosterij 2012).
Funding
The author(s) received no financial support for the authorship, and/or publication of
this article. The underlying QGG research project was financed by Nicis Institute for
Urban Research in the Netherlands.
Notes
1. In addition to the international literature, this article builds on the QGG (Quest
for Good Governance) research project, financed by Nicis Institute for Urban
Research in the Netherlands. This QGG research was focused on urban gover-
nance reforms in eight Dutch cities (Amsterdam, The Hague, Eindhoven, Zwolle,
Dordrecht, Tilburg, Almere, and Breda), resulting in an edited volume (Hendriks
and Drosterij 2012) with case studies provided by a host of authors (Bram
Boluijt, Marcel Boogers, Gerard Drosterij, Robert Duiveman, Frank Hendriks,
Koen van der Krieken, Tamara Metze, Julien van Ostaaijen, Linze Schaap,
Hendrik Wagenaar, and Sabine van Zuydam). The research was guided by the
framework presented here, which was in its turn also refined by the research. The
author acknowledges all those mentioned for, thus, sharpening the understanding
of (good) urban governance. Special thanks go to Gerard Drosterij, who helped
to prepare earlier drafts of this argument in Dutch. The editors of Urban Affairs
Review (UAR) and two anonymous reviewers are thanked for valuable com-
ments and suggestions.
2. The governance of Republican Rome was divided over many public positions
and private parties (often families), who more or less balanced each other out.
Day-to-day governing was in the hands of two consuls, elected for just one year
at a time, who were to share power with a powerful Senate, and with assem-
blies and tribunes of the people. Classic authors, such as, Polybios and Cicero
celebrated and defended the extensive system of countervailing forces, which
was codified in Roman law but even more so in cultural norms and social codes
(Finer 1999; Macchiavelli [1513] 1998).
3. Why urban areas in the Western world? In addition to practical limitations in
terms of available research and literature, there is a more fundamental point:
What urban areas in the Western world have in common is that public issues have
to be managed within the confines of the democratic rule of law, which implies a
particular constitutional framework that does not apply to urban governance in,
say, Singapore or Beijing.
4. One could apply the metaphor of a computer here, which also needs some fun-
damental prescriptions, defined in the operating system, to function properly.
Although one should never push a metaphor too far, this one does help to see
merits and limits: A sound operating system may be the basis for good programs,
but these do not automatically result from it.
5. Dahl (1994) referred to “participation” versus “effectiveness,” and Lijphart
(1999) referred to “‘representation” versus “performance,” but to all intents
and purposes, these are all about the same thing: input legitimacy versus output
legitimacy, or, in terms of their more generic synonyms, responsiveness, and
effectiveness (cf. Hoggart and Clark 2000).
6. Forcing the issue, one could distinguish input values (“rule by the law,” or gov-
ernance that abides by, follows, respects, and internalizes the law) and output
values (“rule for the law,” or governance that expresses, operationalizes, admin-
isters, and enforces the law), but the essentials of procedural justice actually
relate to the entire process connecting inputs and outputs. Therefore, the input/
output distinction is not highlighted in Table 1 when it comes to process values.
References
Ahrens, J., R. Caspers, and J. Weingarth, eds. 2010. Good Governance in the 21st
Century. Aldershot: Edward Elgar.
Alexander, L. 2001. Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations. Cambridge:
Cambridge Univ. Press.
Almond, G. A., and S. Verba. 1980. The Civic Culture Revisited. Boston: Little,
Brown.
Andrews, M. 2010. “Good Government Means Different Things in Different Countries.”
Governance 23 (1): 7–35.
Berry, J. M., K. E. Portney, and K. Thompson. 1993. The Rebirth of Urban Democracy.
Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Bevir, M. 2010. Democratic Governance. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press.
Boluijt, B., G. Drosterij, and F. Hendriks. 2012a. “Omgaan met botsende verwacht-
ingen: Burgers aan Zet! in Dordrecht” [Dealing with Conflicting Expectations:
Citizens Turn! In Dordrecht]. In De zucht naar goed bestuur in de stad: Lessen
uit een weerbarstige werkelijkheid, edited by F. Hendriks and G. Drosterij, 31–
46. The Hague: Boom/Lemma.
Boluijt, B., G. Drosterij, and F. Hendriks. 2012b. “Samen maken we de Stad: Naar een
nieuw besturingsmodel in Zwolle” [Let's Build This Town Together: Towards a
New Steering Model in Zwolle]. In De zucht naar goed bestuur in de stad: Lessen
uit een weerbarstige werkelijkheid, edited by F. Hendriks and G. Drosterij, 79–90.
The Hague: Boom/Lemma.
Bovaird, T. 2005. “Public Governance: Balancing Stakeholder Power in a Network
Society.” International Review of Administrative Sciences 71 (2): 217–28.
Bovaird, T., and E. Löffler. 2003. “Evaluating the Quality of Public Governance:
Indicators, Models and Methodologies.” International Review of Administrative
Sciences 69:313–28.
Box, R. 1998. Citizen Governance: Leading American Communities into the 21st
Century. Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Callahan, M. 2005. “Institutionalizing Participation and Governance? New
Participative Structures in Local Government in Ireland.” Public Administration
83 (4): 909–29.
Cole, A. 2011. “France, between Centralisation and Localisation.” In The Oxford
Handbook of Local and Regional Democracy in Europe, edited by J. Loughlin,
F. Hendriks, and A. Lidström, 307–30. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.
Council of Europe. 2008. The Strategy for Innovation and Good Governance at Local
Level. Strasbourg, France: Council of Europe.
Daalder, H. 1987. “Countries in Comparative European Politics.” European Journal
of Political Research 15:3–21.
Dahl, R. A. 1994. “A Democratic Dilemma: System Effectiveness versus Citizen
Participation.” Political Science Quarterly 109:23–34.
Daily, C. M., D. R. Dalton, and A. A. Cannella Jr. 2003. “Corporate Governance:
Decades of Dialogue and Data.” The Academy of Management Review 28 (3):
371–82.
Denis, D. K., and J. J. McConnell. 2003. “International Corporate Governance.” The
Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis 38 (1): 1–36.
De Rynck, F., and J. Voets. 2005. “Re-institutionalisation in the Flemish Region:
Cases of Collaborative Management.” In Urban-Regional Cooperation in the
EU: Practices and Prospects, edited by F. Hendriks, V. van Stipdonk, and P.
Tops, 163–86. The Hague: Elsevier.
DiGaetano, A., and J. S. Klemanski. 1993. “Urban Regime Capacity: A Comparison
of Birmingham, England, and Detroit, Michigan.” Journal of Urban Affairs 15
(4): 367–84.
Pierre, J., ed. 2000. Debating Governance: Authority, Steering and Democracy.
Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.
Pierre, J. 2005. “Comparative Urban Governance: Uncovering Complex Causalities.”
Urban Affairs Review 40 (4): 446–62.
Pierre, J. 2009. “Reinventing Governance, Reinventing Democracy?” Policy &
Politics 37 (4): 591–609.
Pierre, J., and B. G. Peters. 2000. Governance, Politics and the State. London:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Pietrancosta, A. 2009. Enforcement of Corporate Governance Code: A Legal
Perspective. Tilburg: Tilburg Univ. Press.
Putnam, R. D. 1993. Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy.
Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press.
Putnam, R. D. 2007. “E Pluribus Unum: Diversity and Community in the 21st
Century.” Scandinavian Political Studies 30 (2): 137–74.
Rhodes, R. A. W. 1996. “The New Governance: Governing without Government.”
Political Studies 44:652–67.
Rhodes, R. A. W. 1997. Understanding Governance: Policy Networks, Governance,
Reflexivity and Accountability. Buckingham: Open Univ. Press.
Rhodes, R. A. W. 2000. “Governance and Public Administration.” In Debating
Governance, edited by J. Pierre, 54–90. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.
Rhodes, R. A. W. 2007. “Understanding Governance: Ten Years On.” Organization
Studies 28 (8): 1243–64
Rosanvallon, P. 2008. Counter-Democracy: Politics in the Age of Distrust. Cambridge:
Cambridge Univ. Press.
Rothstein, B., and J. Teorell. 2008. “What Is Quality of Government? A Theory of
Impartial Government Institutions.” Governance 21 (2): 165–90.
Scharpf, F. W. 1997. Games Real Actors Play: Actor Centered Institutionalism in
Policy Research. Boulder: Westview.
Scharpf, F. W. 1999. Governing in Europe: Effective and Democratic? Oxford:
Oxford Univ. Press.
Stassen, H. E. 1942. “E Pluribus Unum” [Out of Many, One]. Public Administration
Review 2 (3): 187–94.
Stoker, G. 1995. “Regime Theory and Urban Politics.” In Theories of Urban Politics,
edited by D. Judge, G. Stoker, and H. Wolman, 54-72. London: Sage.
Stoker, G. 1998. “Governance as Theory: Five Propositions.” International Social
Science Journal 155:17–28.
Stoker, G. 2000. “Urban Political Science and the Challenge of Urban Governance.”
In Perspectives on Governance, edited by J. Pierre, 91–109. Oxford: Oxford
Univ. Press.
Stoker, G. 2011. “Was Local Governance Such a Good Idea? A Global Comparative
Perspective.” Public Administration 89 (1): 15–31.
Stone, C. N. 1989. Regime Politics: Governing Atlanta 1946-1988. Lawrence:
University Press of Kansas.
Stone, C. N. 2006. “Power, Reform, and Urban Regime Analysis.” City & Community
5 (1): 23–38.
Sunstein, C. 2008. Infotopia: How Many Minds Produce Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford
Univ. Press.
Surowiecki, J. 2004. The Wisdom of Crowds: Why the Many Are Smarter than the
Few. London: Abacus.
Swyndegouw, E. 2005. “Governance Innovation and the Citizen: The Janus Face of
Governance-beyond-the-State.” Urban Studies 42 (11): 1991–2006.
Toonen, T. A. J. 2010. “Resilience in Public Administration: The Work of Elinor
and Vincent Ostrom from a Public Administration Perspective.” Public
Administration Review 70 (2): 193–202.
Tyler, T., and J. Darley. 2000. “Building a Law-abiding Society, Taking Public Views
about Morality and the Legitimacy of Legal Authorities into Account When
Formulating Substantive Law.” Hofstra Law Review 28:482–97.
Tyler, T., and Y. J. Huo. 2002. Trust in the Law: Encouraging Public Cooperation
with the Police and Courts. New York: Russell Sage.
Uitermark, J., and J. W. Duyvendak. 2008. “Citizen Participation in a Mediated Age:
Neighborhood Governance in the Netherlands.” International Journal of Urban
and Regional Research 32 (1): 114–31.
United Nations Development Programme. 1977. Governance for Sustainable Human
Development. New York: United Nations Development Programme.
Van Ostaaijen, J., and G. Drosterij. 2012. “Tussen woorden en daden: De Bredase
wijktafels en de vraag naar goed bestuur” [Between Words and Deeds:
Neighborhood Tables in Breda and the Demand for Good Governance]. In De
zucht naar goed bestuur in de stad: Lessen uit een weerbarstige werkelijkheid,
edited by F. Hendriks and G. Drosterij, 47–62. The Hague: Boom/Lemma.
Van Ostaaijen, J., and L. Schaap. 2012. “De legitimiteit van regionale samenwerking:
Het regime Brainport” [The Legitimacy of Regional Cooperation: The Brainport
Regime]. In De zucht naar goed bestuur in de stad: Lessen uit een weerbarst-
ige werkelijkheid, edited by F. Hendriks and G. Drosterij, 91–108. The Hague:
Boom/Lemma.
Wagenaar, C. 1992. Welvaartsstad in wording: De wederopbouw van Rotterdam
1940-1952 [Welfare State in the Making: The Reconstruction of Rotterdam
1940-1952]. Rotterdam: NAi Uitgevers.
Wagenaar, H., and R. Duiveman. 2012. “De kwaliteit van een stadswijk: Good gover-
nance door stedelijke daadkracht in Den Haag” [The Quality of an Urban Quarter:
Good Governance through Vigor in The Hague]. In De zucht naar goed bestuur
in de stad: Lessen uit een weerbarstige werkelijkheid, edited by F. Hendriks and
G. Drosterij, 63–78. The Hague: Boom/Lemma.
Author Biography
Frank Hendriks is a professor of comparative governance at Tilburg University. His
research focuses on the analysis, assessment, and comparison of democratic gover-
nance at the national, subnational, and urban-regional level. He is the author of Vital
Democracy: A Theory of Democracy in Action, Oxford University Press, 2010, and
coeditor of the Oxford Handbook of Local and Regional Democracy in Europe,
Oxford University Press, 2011 (with John Loughlin and Anders Lidström) and City in
Sight: Dutch Dealings with Urban Change, Amsterdam University Press, 2009 (with
Jan Willem Duyvendak and Mies van Niekerk).