Teachphil Usandotv
Teachphil Usandotv
Teachphil Usandotv
KEVIN S. DECKER
Eastern Washington University
Abstract: Teaching Kantian ethics is difficult, for “getting Kant right” extends
to a wide field of concerns. This paper is aimed at instructors who wish to
give interdisciplinary criticism of Kantian deontology by discussing excep-
tions naturalist critics take to Kant’s concept of “autonomy.” This concept
can and should be supplanted by the notion of “emergent intelligence.”
Surprising support for this project comes from the fictional exploits of Star
Trek’s Captain Jean-Luc Picard. I conclude by indicating how the residual
lessons from this criticism of Kant should lead us back to an understanding
of emergence within Kant’s own third Critique.
3. A Deweyan Alternative
Dewey’s corrective to Kant comes without the benefit of contempo-
rary computational theory, cognitive science, and neuroscience that
Lakoff, Johnson, and Dennett use to put flesh on the bones of the
idea of emergent intelligence. The best framework for understanding
Dewey’s alternative to Kantian autonomy was developed rather late
in his long career, in his 1938 Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, a book
that diametrically opposed a priori efforts to ground logic by analytic
thinkers like Russell and Frege. Dewey’s positions in this book are
naturalistic in part because he understands philosophical inquiry—as
with all intelligent inquiry—as an operationalization of certain habits
that have proved to be extraordinarily fruitful in the physical sciences,
but are by no means invidiously scientistic. Instead, intelligent action
and intention guide his casting of the basic categories and methods of
philosophy and logic:
338 KEVIN S. DECKER
acting. What he disagrees with is the notion that habits are in some
way opposed to free and intelligent decision-making and action:
The more numerous our habits the wider the field of possible observation and
foretelling. The more flexible they are, the more refined is perception in its
discrimination and the more delicate the presentation evoked by imagination.
. . . [H]abits formed in process of exercising biological aptitudes are the sole
agents of observation, recollection, foresight and judgment.27
Here we are presented with a more suitable philosophical framework
for understanding the significance of the discovery made in “Emer-
gence.”28 Not only do cross-cutting and mutually reinforcing habits
critical of other habits—Dewey’s definition of “intelligence”—provide
a naturalistic framework which may be applied indiscriminately be-
tween “natural” and “artificial” agents, but it also untethers the notion
of intelligence—understood as supplanting and transcending Kantian
autonomy—from a too-narrow moral application. Dewey can agree
with Kant regarding the passage in the Groundwork that “rational na-
ture is distinguished from the rest of nature by this, that it sets before
itself an end.”29 In the context of “Emergence,” that end is a sense
of self-preservation not originally programmed into the Enterprise’s
systems. However, when Kant goes on to say that there may be only
one such end for rational nature, that it must be an end in itself and
thus identified with a will acting from autonomy, Dewey disagrees. For
this would be to say that the only significant use of autonomy regards
moral decision-making. In Human Nature and Conduct, he explodes
this conception of the autonomous will, “The essence of habit is an
acquired predisposition to ways or modes of response, not to particular
acts. . . . Habit means special sensitiveness or accessibility to certain
classes of stimuli, standing predilections and aversions, rather than
bare recurrence of specific acts. It means will.”30 It clearly seems that
there is little role for autonomy to play once emergent intelligence is
understood along these lines.
From this Deweyan standpoint, it might be of only minor interest
to argue by analogy that systems of instinct or impulse (programmed
circuitry, nodes) give rise to distinctive behavioral functions (sensors,
propulsion, etc.) on the Enterprise. But under conditions of adapta-
tion or adjustment (the effects of the “magnascopic storm”), these
behavioral functions—the equivalent of Deweyan habits—are modified
by need. The Enterprise’s emergent intelligence distinguishes itself
from its basis in pre-emergent systems by exhibiting behaviors of
self-replication, self-preservation, and self-expression that seem to
fill that need. The extent of these functions may be debated; but from
the Deweyan standpoint, the primary reason why we would treat this
new life form still “merely” as a non-autonomous artifact would be
that we are mistakenly focusing on what counts as a precondition
340 KEVIN S. DECKER
4. A Kantian Alternative
Fortunately, for those of us who like to teach Kant as the brilliant
thinker ahead of his time that he was, Kant himself indicates a path in
his later work that does not depend upon the problematic metaphysical
formulations of the Groundwork. In this respect, it is helpful to teach
the naturalistic alternative to Kant’s view of autonomy explained above
in conjunction with certain passages from the third Critique on the
power of judgment.33 In the second part, the “Critique of Teleological
Judgement,” Kant modifies his earlier view about the strict dichotomy
between natural laws and freedom that had been central to the first two
Critiques. For Kant, the scientific sticking point is the reproduction of
organisms, which not only obey natural laws, but further demonstrate
three levels of reproductive behavior that inanimate things do not. A
living creature demonstrates the capacity to reproduce others of its
own kind generically (the progeny is always of the same genus) and
re-produce itself as an individual (growth); furthermore, each part of
a living organism “generates itself in such a way that the preservation
of the one is reciprocally dependent on the preservation of the other.”34
Kant himself recognizes the basis for collective self-organization—what
would much later be called emergence—when he concludes,
An organized being is thus not a mere machine, for that has only a motive
power, while the organized being possesses in itself a formative power, and in-
KANT, DEWEY, AND CAPTAIN PICARD 341
deed one that it communicates to the matter, which does not have it (it organizes
the latter): thus it has a self-propagating formative power, which cannot be
explained through the capacity for movement alone (that is, mechanism).35
This turn to emergence in the final Critique should not surprise us;
Kant, like Dewey, shared a passionate interest in the scientific discov-
eries of his day. Both thinkers struggled to provide a philosophical
framework (not a foundation) for scientific knowledge. Both thinkers
were deeply concerned, albeit for different reasons, with the status of
freedom and value in a world increasingly being overdetermined by
fact. We can see, though, in the technological and metaphorical myster-
ies of Star Trek: The Next Generation’s “Emergence,” a reflection of
their differences regarding the relative significance of autonomy versus
emergent intelligence in the self-determination of moral creatures.36
Notes
1. In Fred Feldman, Introductory Ethics (Upper Saddle River, N.J.: Prentice Hall,
1978).
2. Mill, Utilitarianism (Boston: Willard Small, 1899), 120–21.
3. Many thanks to an anonymous referee for Teaching Philosophy for pointing out
this second avenue of criticism.
4. Philippa Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” Philosophical
Review 81 (July 1972): 305–16, 309.
5. For a different view of the relationship of these two thinkers, see Robert Pippin,
“Kant,” in A Companion to Continental Philosophy, ed. Simon Critchely and William A.
Schroeder (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 1999), 35–56.
6. See Daniel Dennett, Freedom Evolves (New York: Viking, 2003).
7. See George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Philosophy in the Flesh (New York: Basic
Books, 1999), chap. 14, “Morality,” especially pp. 328–34.
8. Although this seems like a narrow focus for criticism, autonomy is not only one
of Kant’s most crucial concepts—closely tied as it is to his meta-ethical discussion of
freedom as a practical postulate of morality—but it has been taken up in various forms
and plays a vital role in discussions within literature of applied ethics; see, for example,
Julian Savulescu, “Rational Desires and the Limitation of Life-Sustaining Treatment,”
Bioethics 8:3 (1994): 191–222.
9. Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, in Practical Philosophy, trans.
and ed. Mary Gregor (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 83, 85; Ak 4:433,
4:436.
10. Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives.”
11. Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 82; Ak 4:432.
12. Ibid., 392; Ak 6:236.
13. A good example is Mary Midgley’s treatment of the moral lives of higher mam-
mals in Utopias, Dolphins and Computers: Problems of Philosophical Plumbing (New
York: Routledge, 1996).
342 KEVIN S. DECKER
14. From the “Inside Star Trek with Gene Roddenberry” bonus CD included with
the twentieth-anniversary edition of the soundtrack to Star Trek: The Motion Picture
(Columbia/Legacy, 1998); for more on the philosophical themes of the various Star Trek
movies and spin-offs, see Star Trek and Philosophy, ed. Jason T. Eberl and Kevin S.
Decker (Chicago: Open Court Publishing, 2008).
15. Many of the conclusions of this paper are supported by Daniel Dennett’s excellent
book Freedom Evolves; the interested reader might compare this list of features with the
conclusions drawn by Dennett about what mathematician John Horton Conway’s “Game
of Life” simulation tells us about the emergence of agency. See Freedom Evolves, chap.
2, “A Tool for Thinking About Determinism.”
16. Lakoff and Johnson, Philosophy in the Flesh, 332.
17. Christine Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends (New York: Cambridge,
1996), 65.
18. Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 79; Ak 4:428.
19. William James, “The Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life,” in The Writings of
William James: A Comprehensive Edition, ed. John J. McDermott (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1977), 617; italics in original.
20. See John Dewey, “The Naturalization of Intelligence,” in The Quest for Certainty,
vol. 4 of John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925–1953, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale,
Ill.: Southern Illinois University Press, 1988).
21. John Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, in John Dewey: The Later Works,
1924–1953, vol. 12, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale, Ill.: Southern Illinois University
Press, 1991), 17.
22. John Dewey, “Philosophies of Freedom,” in John Dewey: The Later Works,
1924–1953, vol. 3, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale, Ill.: Southern Illinois University
Press, 1984), 109.
23. Ibid.
24. This is pace Daniel Savage, who attempts in the first chapter of John Dewey’s
Liberalism to construct a Deweyan conception of autonomy without realizing the deep
unsuitability of the word for what Dewey is trying to do; Daniel Savage, John Dewey’s
Liberalism (Carbondale, Ill.: Southern Illinois University Press, 2002), 17–39.
25. See John Dewey and James Hayden Tufts, Ethics, 2nd ed., in John Dewey: The
Later Works, 1924–1953, vol. 7, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale, Ill.: Southern Illinois
University Press, 1989), 305.
26. Ibid. 306.
27. John Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct, in John Dewey: The Middle Works,
1899–1924, vol. 14, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale, Ill.: Southern Illinois University
Press, 1988), 123.
28. For instructors who want to explore emergence in the context of Dewey and Den-
nett, there are more resources in popular culture than simply the episode “Emergence.”
Similar themes emerge in both the sixth season Star Trek: The Next Generation episode,
“Quality of Life,” which focuses on the evolution of self-interested behavior in machines
called “Exocomps”; it’s also profitable to contrast the development of the personality
and abilities of the android Data with his “less-evolved” twin B4 in the feature film Star
Trek: Nemesis (Stuart Baird, director, 2002) and to examine the path taken by the sentient
computer V’Ger in Star Trek: The Motion Picture (Robert Wise, director, 1979). Some
non-Star Trek recommendations include: exploring the actions and motivations of HAL,
the mission computer in 2001: A Space Odyssey (Stanley Kubrick, director, 1968); ex-
KANT, DEWEY, AND CAPTAIN PICARD 343
amining the metaphorical sense in which Eliza Doolittle “emerges” under the tutelage of
Dr. Henry Higgins in Bernard Shaw’s Pygmalion; and looking at the human prejudices
that stand in the way of admitting that anthropomorphic machines may have transcended
the programming of their creators in BladeRunner (Ridley Scott, director, 1982) and the
re-envisioned Battlestar Galactica television series (2003–2009). For a philosophical
introduction to this issue in Battlestar, see Jerold J. Abrams, “Embracing the ‘Children of
Humanity’: How to Prevent the Next Cylon War,” in Battlestar Galactica and Philosophy,
ed. Jason T. Eberl (Blackwell, 2008), 75–86.
29. Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals,; Ak 4.
30. Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct, 32.
31. Evan Thompson, Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind
(Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press/Harvard, 2007), 61.
32. See also Dennett, Freedom Evolves.
33. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
34. Ibid., 243; Ak 5: 371.
35. Ibid., 246; Ak 5: 374.
36. I appreciate the comments of both Lisa Cassidy of Ramapo College, New Jersey,
and another, anonymous, reviewer; their insights made this paper substantially better.
Special thanks to Jason T. Eberl for comments and editorial advice.
Kevin S. Decker, 266 Patterson Hall, Eastern Washington University, Cheney, Washington
99004; kdecker@ewu.edu