Mythical Realism
Mythical Realism
Mythical Realism
Theodore Brelsford
Emory University
Atlanta, Georgia, USA
Abstract
INTRODUCTION
264
THEODORE BRELSFORD 265
1
I presume that religious education within other faith traditions similarly seeks
to nurture faith in those traditions. I note that religious education in schools in the
United Kingdom and many other European countries presents a different kind of
context and necessitates different kinds of goals.
2
Counter to popular usage of the terms myth and mythical to denote falsity, I
use these terms as they are used in classical philosophy and modern religious studies
to denote narrative explanations and descriptions of the realities of our existence in
the largest possible perspective and context (e.g., stories of creation, origins of good
and evil, ultimate sources of life), paradigmatically including superhuman agents and
non-historical events.
266 MYTHICAL REALIST ORIENTATION FOR RE
intuition and the well established fact that persons cannot float up-
wards unsupported, and counter to the intuitive fact that bodies do
not regain life and reappear after death.
Facts are observable and verifiable events and phenomena in ev-
eryday life (e.g., it is a fact that persons die and their bodies naturally
disintegrate thereafter). Counterfactual beliefs are counter to such
facts (e.g., the Christian belief in the resurrection of the body). In-
tuitions are evolved common sensibilities about the world around us
(e.g., all agents—things to which we ascribe thought and will—have
bodies). Counterintuitive beliefs run counter to such intuitions (e.g.,
some agents—for example angels and God in contemporary popular
belief—have no physical body).
The adaptive advantages of mythic understanding as embodied in
religious belief systems presents a baffling problem for understanding
human thought and society from an evolutionary perspective. As Scott
Atran puts it, all religions include “costly and hard-to-fake commitment
to a counterfactual and counterintuitive world of supernatural agents
. . . ” (2002, 4). And, virtually all human societies across human history
seem thoroughly imbued with religious views of the world.
Evolutionary theories of mind insist that (as also with the rest of
the body) cognitive traits survive and flourish only if, and precisely be-
cause, they have notable adaptive advantages—they promote in some
way the survival and flourishing of organisms with that trait. The ad-
vantages of believing in and committing one’s life to “a counterfactual
and counterintuitive world of supernatural agents” are not at all clear.
Yet religions and religious beliefs are ubiquitous throughout all human
societies past and present. In fact, as Atran puts it “the psychology that
leads to such beliefs is common to us all,” including modern scientific
thinkers who would eschew religion (8).
In cognitive science theories of religion the most prominent cur-
rent way of understanding this perplexing human propensity to hold
ardently to counterintuitive beliefs is to understand religion as a by-
product of traits initially evolved for other purposes (known as “exap-
tation”). For example, humans evolved hyper-active agency detection,
causing us to see agents and ascribe agency when no agent is there—
such as seeing faces in clouds, or mistaking a tree stump for a bear—
because there is survival advantage in over-detecting, and survival dis-
advantage in under-detecting agents around us. This “explains” the
ubiquitous human perception of, and belief in supernatural agents
(cf. Boyer 2001). But, as Atran points out, such theories fail to ade-
quately explain the extraordinary motivation and commitment entailed
270 MYTHICAL REALIST ORIENTATION FOR RE
in religious belief (for example, why is belief in Santa Claus held dif-
ferently for most people from belief in God? And why is there such
ardent and persistent belief at all in a God whose agency remains ever
difficult or impossible to physically verify?).
Other attempts to understand and explain the benefits of religion
from an evolutionary perspective include commitment theories, expe-
riential theories, and performance theories. Commitment theories of
religion focus on ways institutions and cultures rely on religious belief
systems in order to sustain and enforce rules and norms. But these
theories tend not to attend well to ways cognitive structures and pat-
terns shape belief. And they do not really explain why religious beliefs
tend to garner more steadfast and enduring commitment than do most
political, economic, or scientific systems of belief.
Experiential theories of religion attempt to “explain” religion in
terms of neuro-physiological processes traceable to religious experi-
ences of trance, meditation, revelation, and so forth. But these have no
real explanatory power at all—the fact that a certain area of the brain
is associated with a certain religious experience such as meditation
provides no insight into what or why religion is.
Performance theories attend to the psychodynamics of liturgy and
ritual practice, focusing on normative functions of ceremonial prac-
tices, but neglect “cognitive processes of categorization, reasoning, and
decision making that underlie all religious beliefs and commitments
and that make such beliefs and commitments comprehensible” (Atran
2002,14).
The point here is that much effort has gone into explaining re-
ligion, yet it remains difficult to explain, and in fact remains an em-
barrassment. As Atran puts it, the psychology that causes such beliefs
is “common to us all.” Cognitive scientists widely agree that religious
perceptions of the world occur commonly to believers and unbelievers
alike. Indeed it is demonstrably more difficult to sustain a purely scien-
tific worldview than to sustain a religious worldview; commitment to a
non-theistic scientific viewpoint requires dedicated effort and a tightly
controlled system of formal education and social support, whereas re-
ligion seems to just spring up everywhere (cf. Barrett 2004). It is an
embarrassment, or at least an uncomfortable fact for many scientific
thinkers that we humans (all) have an overwhelming propensity to be-
lieve in and live by counterfactual and counterintuitive understandings
of the world.
There are two seemingly contrary propositions in this claim that
scientific thinkers experience embarrassment or discomfort when
THEODORE BRELSFORD 271
natural cycles of locust gestation and infestation along the Nile might
reinforce a literal understanding of the plague of locusts described in
Exodus 10?
3
The difference between religious fanaticism and religious heroism is sometimes
a delicate judgment and is always a matter of perspective. Joseph Smith, for example,
is a hero to Mormons and a fanatic to many non-Mormons.
THEODORE BRELSFORD 275
4
Several months after presenting this article at the November 2006 REA meeting,
and after the article was already accepted for publication in this journal, I discovered
in a conversation with a colleague in another field that Paul Avis uses the term “mythic
realism” toward the end of his book God and the Creative Imagination (1999). Al-
though Avis does not provide a definition of the term and does not address any of the
pedagogical concerns that are the focus of my attention, his use of “mythic realism”
and my use of “mythical realism” seem to cohere well. For Avis “mythic realism” has
to do with acknowledging “the metaphorical, symbolic and mythological status of the
language of faith without letting go of the point that such language can be believed
with a good conscience through an act of imaginative assent” (169). Further, he ar-
gues (against Bultmann and Hick) that there are intrinsic connections between biblical
myths and divine reality and that we must respect “the givenness of the historical forms
of divine revelation” (163). In other words he advocates frank acknowledgement that
we are thinking and speaking mythically whenever we think and speak of God, but
because myth “is the only way in which the most significant aspects of human history
can be presented to us” we must trust in and rely on such myths for meaningful un-
derstanding of God. I am in basic agreement with Avis and may have drawn on him
more significantly in this article if I had read his work sooner.
276 MYTHICAL REALIST ORIENTATION FOR RE
their value and importance are well known to religious educators. The
Bible begins with stories of creation and such stories have been a
primary medium for passing on faith and carrying forth tradition for
millennia. Anne Wimberly’s focus on “story linking” strategies (2005);
Thomas Groome’s attention to the centrality of “Christian Story and
Vision” (1998); and Walter Breuggemann’s insistence on the primacy
of story modes for Torah education (1982) are a few examples of keen
awareness of the profound importance of stories and story telling and
narrative pedagogies in religious education.
I wish only to note that our basic Christian stories are primarily
mythic in nature and that to learn the stories is to learn the myth; to
learn to relate one’s life story to the larger story is to learn to con-
nect oneself to the myth; to learn to see the world of one’s everyday
experience in relation to the stories of Christian faith is to learn to
live life through Christian myths. A primary goal of Christian educa-
tion is to help persons become skillful at doing this. And, in order to
do this well and thoroughly it is helpful to recognize that in doing so
we are nurturing counterintuitive thinking. Recognizing that we are
nurturing counterintuitive thinking and recognizing that counterintu-
itive thinking must co-exist with intuitive thinking may enable us to
find ways to help persons hold counterintuitive and intuitive beliefs
together constructively, rather than fleeing from the stories of faith in
order to “graduate out of church” as adults and into the “real” world,
or retreat from the real world into forms of fundamentalism where
myths are conflated with reality.
Another way to nurture mythical realism is to nurture wonder,
awe, and imagination. Anabel Proffit’s focus on wonder (1998) and
Maria Harris’s work on religious imagination (1991) are examples of
religious educators who have strongly sensed the values of this kind
of religious education. Wonder is the capacity to sense the sacred in
the world of our experiences—to perceive manifestations of the myth
within the reality around us. The capacity for imagination is, quite
literally, the capacity to see in one’s mind what is not before one’s eyes.
If one cannot imagine well, one can never well see the metaphysical
dramas at play in the physical world or even in the textual world of
the Bible. We must nurture imagination and wonder and awe if we
are to nurture mythical sensibilities at all. But we must also hold the
imagination accountable to material and experiential realities if we are
to nurture mythical realism.
A third way of nurturing mythical realism is to nurture the prac-
tice of holding religious/mythic imagination and intuitive awareness
THEODORE BRELSFORD 277
CONCLUSION
REFERENCES
Atran, Scott. 2002. In Gods we trust: The evolutionary landscape of religion. Oxford, New York:
Oxford University Press.
Avis, Paul. 1999. God and the Creative Imagination: Metaphor, symbol and myth in religion and
theology. London, New York: Routledge.
Barrett, Justin L. 2004. Why would anyone believe in God? Walnut Creek, CA: Altamira Press.
278 MYTHICAL REALIST ORIENTATION FOR RE
Becoming human: Evolution and the rise of human intelligence. 2006. Scientific American. Special
Issue.
Boyer, Pascal. 2001. Religion explained: The evolutionary origins of religious thought. New York:
Basic Books.
Brelsford, Theodore. 2005. Lessons for religious education from cognitive science of religion,
Religious Education 100(2), 174–191.
Brueggemann, Walter. 1982. The Creative word: Canon as model for biblical education. Augsburg
Fortress Press.
Groome, Thomas H. 1998. Sharing faith: A comprehensive approach to religious education and
pastoral ministry. San Francisco: Harpes.
Harris, Maria. 1991. Teaching and religious imagination: An essay in the theology of teaching.
San Francisco: Harper San Francisco.
Melchert, Charles F. 1998. Wise teaching: Biblical wisdom and educational ministry. San Fran-
cisco. Harrisburg, PA: Trinity Press International.
Proffitt, Anabel. 1998. The Importance of Wonder in Religious Education, Religious Education,
93, 97–112.
Sloane, D. Jason. 2004. Theological Incorrectness: Why religious people believe what they
shouldn’t. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wimberly, Ann Streaty. 2005. Soul stories: African American Christian education. Nashville, TN:
Abingdon Press.