Epictetus Views On Christians.
Epictetus Views On Christians.
Epictetus Views On Christians.
fi
Huttunen, Niko
2017
http://hdl.handle.net/10138/308698
acceptedVersion
Niko Huttunen
The earliest Roman sources on Christians are dated to the beginning of the second
century. Tacitus (Annales 15:44), Suetonius (Nero 16.2), and Pliny the Younger
(Epistulae ad Trajanum 10.96) are the sources that are quoted time and again. Their
actually refer to them (Discourses 2.9.19–21 and 4.7.6). Both instances are easily
confused with Judaism, which has led some scholars astray. There are also
philological difficulties that require profound consideration. I will show that Epictetus
and Pliny the Younger. I suggest that this is due to the philosophical elements in
Christian teachings.
Epictetus lived around 50–130 CE. He was born as a slave and was brought
early on to serve in Rome in close contact with Nero’s court.1 Later he was freed, then
banished from Rome during the reign of Domitian. Thereafter Epictetus founded a
became famous for his teaching, the school attracted students from the Roman well-
to-do families. Among those students was Arrian of Nicomedia, who attended
Epictetus’ lectures for some years in the first decades of the second century. His notes
are our primary source of Epictetus’ teaching. Nicopolis is mentioned in the Epistle to
1
For these contacts, see F. Millar, “Epictetus and the Imperial Court,” JRS 55 (1965):141–48. The
following presentation of Epictetus’ career and his Discourses is based on N. Huttunen, Paul and
Epictetus on Law: A Comparison (LNTS 405; London: T&T Clark, 2009), 4–5.
Titus (3:12), though it is not clear whether there was a Christian community in
Epictetus’ lifetime. The city, however, was an important harbour on the route to
Rome, and it surely did not avoid Christian influences.2 We also know that Epictetus
as being among the criminal superstitions. Scholars have often taken these three
Granger Cook analyses these three and some other Roman texts on Christians in his
book Roman Attitudes Toward the Christians: From Claudius to Hadrian. The result
Probably the Roman intellectuals and governors like Tacitus and Pliny
were so disgusted at the phenomenon of Christianity that they lacked the
inclination to make any profound explorations into the nature of early
Christian faith, morality, and ritual practice. What I have sought to do
during this project is develop a sympathy for the Romans’ shock when
they had to deal with this ‘other’ – these Christians who were so difficult
to conceive using the categories they were familiar with.3
Cook’s profound study on the texts of Tacitus, Suetonius, and Pliny adds considerably
overall Roman view. One would get another picture when reading two of Epictetus’
texts, Discourses 2.9.19–21 and 4.7.6. Cook passes over the latter briefly,4 while he
does not mention the former at all. His procedure is indicative of a more general
2
For Nicopolis’ character as a city, see for example J.D. Quinn, The Letter to Titus: A New Translation
with Notes and Commentary and an Introduction to Titus, I and II Timothy, the Pastoral Epistles (AB
35; New York: Doubleday, 1990), 255.
3
J.G. Cook, Roman Attitudes Toward the Christians: From Claudius to Hadrian (WUNT 261;
Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2010), 2.
4
Cook, Roman Attitudes Toward the Christians, 173.
Adolf Bonhöffer’s classic Epiktet und das Neue Testament, which deals with parallel
texts in depth but delivers only a short discussion on Discourses 4.7.6; furthermore, it
passes over the other passage with superficial references.5 Scholars routinely refer to
Christians, and it is understandable that he passes over the theme with brief remarks.
Long supposes that Epictetus mentions Christians,7 but he shares Bonhöffer’s view of
the very remote relationship between Epictetus’ thinking and the New Testament:
“Notwithstanding striking verbal parallels, there is no strong reason to think that one
has directly influenced the other.”8 As we see here, the discussion on Epictetus’ view
questioned Epictetus’ Stoic orthodoxy, Bonhöffer claims in an offended tone that his
own scholarly life’s work was dedicated to proving that Epictetus presents “the pure,
the genuine and the coherent theory of the old Stoicism.”9 Here we see a tendency in
Bonhöffer which is later questioned. Long points out that, despite the fact that
5
A. Bonhöffer, Epiktet und das Neue Testament (Religionsgeschichtliche Versuche und Vorarbeiten
10; Gießen: Verlag von Alfred Töpelmann (vormals J. Ricker), 1911), 41–44, 72, 273.
6
For the significance of Bonhöffer’s view on the subsequent study, see J. Hershbell, “The Stoicism of
Epictetus: Twentieth Century Perspectives,” in ANRW II.36.3 (ed. W. Haase and H. Temporini; Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter, 1989), 2150–63, 2161.
7
A.A. Long, Epictetus: A Stoic and Socratic Guide to Life (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002), 17, 110.
8
Long, Epictetus, 35.
9
“Ich darf wolhl darauf hinweisen, daß meine wissenschaftliche Lebensarbeit hauptsächlich dem
Nachweis gewidmet ist, daß wir dem kostbaren Vermächtnis, das uns Arrian von seinem Lehrer
hinterlassen hat, im wesentlichen die reine, unverfälschte und konsequente Lehre der alten Stoa, deren
ursprüngiche Zeugnisse uns fast ganz verloren gegangen sind, vor uns haben” (Bonhöffer, “Epiktet und
das Neue Testament,” ZNW 13 (1912): 281–92, 282; my English translation).
Bonhöffer’s works are “indispensable for close study of Epictetus relation to the Stoic
I claim that Bonhöffer’s tendency also affects his assessment of the passages
on Christians. The most eye-catching example is the word πάθος in its positive
meaning (Discourses 2.9.20). I will return to this term below. At this moment, it is
enough to note that the Stoics usually understood it in the negative sense. Bonhöffer
generally claims that “Epictetus’ conception of the essence and the origin of the πάθη
is compeletely similar to the old and the genuine Stoicism.”11 Surprisingly, he does
not discuss Discourses 2.9.20 in his lengthy chapter on the passions. I cannot avoid
would have contributed to ruining this rigid view of Stoic orthodoxy. As this view is
In his Epiktet und das Neue Testament, Bonhöffer shot down all attempts to
find Christian influences in Epictetus’ texts. His main object of attack was Theodor
speech, Zahn proposed that Epictetus had known the New Testament writings and
embraced ideas from it “as long as they are not in contrast to his dogma.”13 Thus Zahn
10
Long, Epictetus, 36.
11
“Epictets Ansicht über das Wesen und den Ursprung der πάθη entspricht vollständig den
Anschauungen der Alten, echten Stoa” (Bonhöffer, Epictet und die Stoa. Untersuchungen zur stoischen
Philosophie (Stuttgart: Verlag von Ferdinand Enke, 1890), 278; my English translation).
12
T. Zahn, Der Stoiker Epiktet und sein Verhältnis zum Christentum. Rede beim Eintritt des
Prorektorats der Königlich Bayerischen Friedrich-Alexanders-Universität Erlangen am 3. November
1894 gehalten (Erlangen: Deichert’sche Verlagsbuchhandlung Nachf, 1895). Since the king of Bavaria
was the honorary principal, whom Zahn blesses at the end of this speech, the office of the vice-
principal meant in practice that he handled the tasks of the principal.
13
“Aber auch religiöse Ideen und Lebensregeln des Neuen Testaments konnten den Epiktet ansprechen
und, soweit sie seinem Dogma nicht geradezu widersprachen, von ihm angeeignet warden” (Zahn, Der
Stoiker Epiktet, 29; my English translation).
differed from Christians on many points and that “he did not become a Christian,
because he was a Stoic and wished to die as a Stoic.” He was not even a friend of
Christianity or Christians.14 This was a moderate statement, but it was too much for
Bonhöffer. Zahn claimed that Epictetus’ views were not fully coherent, which is
partly based on an article by Franz Mörth,16 who had already criticised Zahn – shoots
Epictetus.17
A few years after Bonhöffer’s Epiktet und das Neue Testament, Douglas S.
Sharp published his Epictetus and the New Testament. Sharp concluded that “it is
doubtful whether Epictetus was acquainted with the New Testament.” The linguistic
similarities are mostly due to the fact that both are written in the koine of their time.18
The case was closed, and Bonhöffer has become the main authority on the consensus
since then. However, there is one caveat in Bonhöffer’s profound work, which has yet
to be investigated in detail: the two passages, Discourses 2.9.19–21 and 4.7.6, which
14
Zahn Der Stoiker Epiktet, 33–34.
15
Zahn Der Stoiker Epiktet, 10.
16
F. Mörth, “Epiktet und sein Verhältnis zum Christentum,” in Jahresbericht des mit hohem
Ministerial-Erlaβ vom 20. Jänner 1895, Z 29,755, mit dem Öffentlichkeitsrecht beliehenen
fürstbischöflichen Gymnasiums am Seckauer Diözesan-Knabenseminar Carolinum-Augustineum in
Graz am Schlusse des Schuljahres 1908/1909 (Graz: Selbstverlag des f.-b. Knabenseminars, 1909), 1–
22.
17
Zahn, Der Stoiker Epiktet, 29–34; Mörth “Epiktet;” Bonhöffer, Epiktet, 30–42.
18
D.S. Sharp, Epictetus and the New Testament (London: Charles H. Kelly, 1914), 135, 137. One may
also note that even a larger common background produces parallels, which at first sight are striking. A
good example is Ζήτει καὶ εὑρήσεις (Discourses 4.1.51), which closely resembles ζητεῖτε καὶ εὑρήσετε
(Matthew 7:7; Luke 11:9). Mörth (“Epiktet,” 22) already notes that even Plato uses a similar phrase. L.
Willms (Epiktets Diatribe Über die Freiheit [4.1]. Einleitung, Übersetzung, Kommentar. Band 1–2
[Wissenschaftliche Kommentare zu Griechischen und lateinischen Schriftstellern; Heidelberg:
Universitätverlag Winter, 2011], 263–65) sees numerous parallels for this saying in philosophical texts.
Thus, on closer analysis this striking parallel does not provide any ground for the theory that Epictetus
was influenced by the New Testament.
more or less clearly speak of Christians. Quite surprisingly, they have been left
A close reading of these two passages will show against all doubt that they
speak of Christians and that Epictetus knew something about Christians and their
teachings. He even borrowed some expressions from them, which is the most
interesting result for further study. As Epictetus cited Christian expressions, there may
be more of them in the Discourses. This reopens a discussion that Bonhöffer and
some others had closed a hundred years ago. Moreover, a close reading of these
passages also shows that the Roman attitude towards Christians was not only hostile,
but that there was room for a more relaxed assessments than what Tacitus, Suetonius,
who loosens the discussion. This situation is certainly due to the philosophical
In the beginning of Discourses 4.7, Epictetus speaks of children and lunatics who do
not fear the tyrant, his guards, and their swords. Because of their lack of
understanding, children and lunatics can be fearless before such threats (sections 1–5).
From lunatics Epictetus proceeds to the Galileans, who are also fearless: “Therefore,
if madness can produce this attitude of mind toward the things which have just been
mentioned, and also habit, as with the Galileans, cannot reason and demonstration
teach a man that God has made all things in the universe?” (εἶτα ὑπὸ μανίας μὲν
δύναταί τις οὕτως διατεθῆναι πρὸς ταῦτα καὶ ὑπὸ ἔθους οἱ Γαλιλαῖοι· ὑπὸ λόγου δὲ
καὶ ἀποδείξεως οὐδεὶς δύναται μαθεῖν ὅτι ὁ θεὸς πάντα πεποίηκεν τὰ ἐν τῷ κόσμῳ,
the beginning of an extensive argumentation that one can attain fearlessness through
philosophical demonstration (sections 6–11). Children, lunatics, and Galileans are just
a starting point for this argumentation; as they do not fear the tyrant, the guards, and
the swords, the fear does not automatically follow from certain outer circumstances.
Fear or fearlessness is rather up to the person who feels or does not feel the fear.
Epictetus concludes that this fact makes it meaningful to seek philosophical reasons
for fearlessness.
Thus Epictetus uses children, lunatics, and Galileans to introduce the audience
to the philosophical discussion. They are not the center of his focus; therefore the
reference to them is just a passing one. Does Epictetus really mean ‘Christians’ when
interpretation: the Galileans are Zealots. He referred to the fact that during the Jewish
War Epictetus lived in Rome, where it was possible to learn the details of the war in
Palestine. Hengel also notes that, according to Josephus, the Jewish resistance
movement sicarii – which he lumps together with the Zealots – became very famous
19
Bonhöffer Epiktet, 41–43. Similarly, for example, Zahn Der Stoiker Epiktet,, 26–27; K. Hartmann,
“Arrian und Epiktet,” Njahrb 8 (1905): 248–75, 267; Mörth “Epiktet,” 21; W.A. Oldfather, See
sources: Epictetus (1928a), xxvi; (1928b), 363 note 1; H.W.F. Stellwag, See sources: Epictetus (1933),
173; H. Karpp, “Christennamen,” in RAC 2 (ed. T. Klauser et al.; Stuttgart: Anton Hiersemann, 1954),
1114–38, 1131; M. Spanneut, “Epiktet,” in RAC V (ed. T. Klauser et al.; Stuttgart: Anton Hiersemann,
1962), 599–681, 628; J.N. Sevenster, “Education or Conversion: Epictetus and the Gospels,” NovT 8
(1966): 247–62, 254–55; S. Benko, “Pagan Criticism of Christianity During the First Two Centuries
A.D.,” in ANRW II.23.2 (ed. W. Haase and H. Temporini; Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1980), 1055–118,
1077; Benko, Pagan Rome and the Early Christians (London: B.T. Batsford, 1985), 40; Hershbell
“The Stoicism of Epictetus,” 2161; T. Engberg-Pedersen, Cosmology and Self in the Apostle Paul. The
Material Spirit (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 132–33.
20
M. Hengel, Die Zeloten. Untersuchungen zur Jüdischen Freiheitsbewegung in der Zeit von Herodes I
bis 70 n.Chr. 2. (2d rev. ed.; AGJU 1; Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1976),,60–61. Hengel, however, makes a
The German historian Eduard Meyer already tackled the hypothesis of the
Galileans as Zealots in the beginning of the twentieth century. He denied it, as one
cannot reliably explain how Epictetus could incidentally refer to a group that had been
defeated several decades earlier. Meyer suggested that “Galileans” must refer to the
students being lectured to without further explication. Christians are the clearest
This being the case, some scholars have seen the words οἱ Γαλιλαῖοι as a later
addition, since Epictetus must have seen the Christian grounds for fearlessness as
being negative rather than as just a habit. Alternatively, the word “habit” is emended
to some more negative term.22 However, all the emendations of the text are highly
not appreciate Christians in such a way that one should doubt its non-Christian
origin.23 Syntactically (μέν – δέ) Christians are on the side of the lunatics against
distinction between the sicarii and the Zealots in another place (Die Zeloten, 49). S. Applebaum (“The
Zealots: the Case for Revaluation,” JRS 61 [1971]: 155–70, 164) had identified Galileans with Zealots
before Hengel. It is also unreliable to think that Galileans refer to some other resistance movement
during the Jewish war (for such a hypothesis, see S. Zeitlin, “Who were the Galileans? New Light on
Josephus' Activities in Galilee,” JQR 64 [1974]:189–203).
21
E. Meyer, Ursprung und Anfänge des Christentums in drei Bänden III: Die Apostelgeschichte und
die Anfänge des Christentums (Stuttgart: J.G. Cotta'sche Buchhandlung Nachfolger, 1923), 530 n. 1.
There was also a quite unknown Jewish group called Galileans in the second century (Justin Martyr,
Dialogue with Trypho 80; Eusebius, Ecclesiastical History 4.22.7). Though this group seems to be
somewhat critical towards the state authorities (mishnah Yadayim 4:8), as Epictetus’ fearless Galileans
before the tyrant, it is still unreliable to assume that Epictetus would incidentally refer to this kind of
minor group.
22
I. Schweighäuser (See sources: Epictetus [1799a–d/1800], 1799c, 913–915) and J. Barnes (Logic and
the Imperial Stoa [Philosophia Antiqua: A Series of Studies on Ancient Philosophy 75; Leiden: Brill,
1997], 63 n. 157) have seen οἱ Γαλιλαῖοι as an emendation. Several scholars have been inclined to
change the word ἔθους to a more negative one. See the textual apparatus in Schenkl’s edition; K.
Meiser, “Zu Epiktet IV 7,6,” Hermes 45 (1910): 160; P. Corssen, “Zu Epiktet, Διατριβαί IV 7,6,”
BphWS 30 (1910): 832; A.J. Kronenberg, “Zu Epiktet IV 7,6,” BphWS 30 (1910):1623.
23
Cf. the account of Christ in Josephus’ Jewish Antiquities, which is surely a Christian addition or – if
Josephus himself wrote something about Jesus – fully rewritten by some Christian. The tone is
unmistakably that of a Christian: “About this time there lived Jesus, a wise man, if indeed one ought to
call him a man. For he was one who wrought surprising feats and was a teacher of such people as
accept the truth gladly. He won over many Jews and many of the Greeks. He was the Messiah. When
Pilate, upon hearing him accused by men of the highest standing amongst us had condemned him to be
crucified, those who had at first come to love him did not give up their affection for him. On the third
those whose fearlessness is based on reason and demonstration. Thus, Christians are
and the Christians: the latter are not mad, but rather habit is the apparent reason for
their fearlessness.24
Epictetus perhaps “means that the Christians were brought up more or less blindly,
that is, without ‘reason and demonstration’, to have their strange beliefs.”25 This is
true, but one can be more precise. Zahn saw this clearly when he noted that “the habit
to good – and the question is about this here – is something which Epictetus holds in
no little reverence.”26 The word ἔθος and its cognate ἐθίζω are technical terms in
consideration. Habits are developed from birth, and as they are strongly rooted, it is
difficult to change them. Epictetus says, “In the course of years we have acquired the
habit (εἰθίσμεθα) of doing the opposite of what we learn and have in use opinions
which are the opposite of the correct ones” (Discourses 2.9.14; trans. W. A.
To fight bad habits one can use contrary habits (Discourses 1.27.4–6; trans.
day he appeared to them restored to life, for the prophets of God had prophesied these and countless
other marvelous things about him. And the tribe of the Christians, so called after him, has still to this
day not disappeared” (Josephus, Jewish Antiquities 18.63–64; trans. L. H. Feldman, LCL.). Ulrich
Victor (“Das Testimonium Flavianum. Ein authentischer Text des Josephus,” NovT 52 (2010): 72–82)
has recently defended the authenticity of this passage. While he argues with certain success that the
words “if indeed one ought to call him a man” are a fixed topos in antiquity and that “the Messiah”
should be understood as a proper name “Christ,” he does not explain how a Jew would admit that
prophets were speaking of Christ. This idea sounds too Christian to have come from Josephus’ pen.
24
Zahn, Der Stoiker Epiktet, 27.
25
Engberg-Pedersen, Cosmology and Self, 133.
26
“Die Gewöhnung zum Guten – und um ein solches handelt es sich hier – schätzt Epiktet nicht
gering” (Zahn, Der Stoiker Epiktet, 41 n. 27; my English translation).
27
It may be added that Epictetus also uses the word ἕξις as an equivalent of ἔθος. For habit in
Epictetus, see B.L. Hijmans, Jr., ἌΣΚΗΣΙΣ. Notes on Epictetus’ Educational System (WTS 2; Assen:
Van Gorcum, 1959), 64–65; and Huttunen, Paul and Epictetus, 127–28.
(κανόνες). 28 One should memorise them in order to have them at hand in practical
situations; for example, “When death appears to be an evil, we must have ready at
hand [the canons] ‘It is a duty to avoid evils’ and ‘Death is an inevitable thing’”
(Discourses 1.27.7; trans. W. A. Oldfather, LCL, revised). The short canons recall the
deeper philosophical truths and thus help the person to maintain his or her
philosophical character.
that Christians had canons of their own. And they really had.29 For example, the
7:19).30 Epictetus acknowledged that Christian canons are not pure madness, though
they were surely strange beliefs to him. In Epictetus’ ranking, Christian fearlessness is
an admirable result derived from the wrong reasons. His words do not reflect the
Christianity very deeply. However, he seems to know more than he says and to expect
the same knowledge from his audience. Otherwise a passing reference could not be
understandable. Zahn has rightly noted this point.31 It becomes very clear that
Epictetus and his audience had some contacts with Christianity when we turn our
28
For the canons in Epictetus, see R.J. Newman, “Cotidie Meditare: Theory and Practice of the
Meditatio in Imperial Stoicism,” in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt: Geschichte und
Kultur Roms im Spiegel der neueren Forschung II.36.3 (ed. W. Haase and H. Temporini; Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter, 1989), 1473–1517, esp. 1496–1502.
29
For the use of the word κανών in Christian writings, see for example H.W. Beyer, “Κανών,” in
TDNT 3 (ed. Gerhard Kittel; trans. G. W. Bromiley; Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 1974), 596–
602.
30
Fourth Maccabees says, in the good Stoic way, that vicious emotions (πάθη) are ruled by those, who
“philosophise the whole canon of the philosophy” (πρός ὅλον τὸν τῆς φιλοσοφίας κανόνα φιλοσοφῶν)
(4 Maccabees 7:21–22; my translation).
31
Zahn, Der Stoiker Epiktet, 27.
2. Christians as Baptised Jews
In Discourses 2.9 Epictetus claims that a Stoic philosopher should not only speak of
(19) Why, then, do you call yourself a Stoic, why do you deceive the
multitude, why do you being a Jew act the parts of Greeks? (20) Do you
not see in what sense men are severally called Jew, Syrian, or Egyptian?
For example, whenever we see a man halting between two faiths, we are
in the habit of saying, “He is not Jew, he is only acting the part.” But
when he adopts the pathos33 of the man who has been baptized and has
made his choice, then he both is a Jew in fact and is also called one. (21)
So we are also counterfeit “baptists,” Jews in words, but in deeds
something else, not in sympathy with our own words,34 far from applying
the principles which we profess, yet priding ourselves upon them as being
men who know them.
Epictetus speaks of two kinds of Jews. First, there are Jews whose deeds do not
follow their words. Second, there are real Jews whose deeds follow their words after
baptism and choice. I claim that the latter group actually refers to Christians. In order
to demonstrate this, I first go through some text-critical problems and then proceed to
The text-critical problems are not due to the manuscript, but rather to the
32
See also Bonhöffer, Epictet und die Stoa, 11–13; Long, Epictetus, 107–12.
33
Possible translations of this Greek word are discussed below.
34
An alternative translation for the ‘words’ is ‘reason’, but the context prefers the former.
manuscript text. In section 19 the basic identity is that of a Jew who does not practice.
In section 20, however, there is a non-Jew who is playing the part of a Jew. Finally, in
section 21 Epictetus speaks of persons who are Jews with respect to their words while
they are non-Jews with respect to their deeds. So the question is: Did Epictetus deliver
Section 21 can be seen in either way. Thus the real tension is between sections
19 and 20. An editor of Epictetus’ Discourses, Heinrich Schenkl, solved this tension
with an emendation in section 19.35 Instead of reading with the manuscript that “you”
are a Jew acting the part of Greeks (Ἰουδαῖος ὢν Ἕλληνας), he emended the text to
say that “you” are a Greek acting the part of a Jew (Ἰουδαῖον ὢν Ἕλλην). Schenkl’s
respect play the part of Jews, but who should become Jews in every respect. Scholars
reading the emended text have usually presented it as a reference to the Gentile God-
fearers who are assumed to become proselytes.36 This had created the odd feature that
the conversion to Judaism was based on proselyte baptism, without a word about
circumcision. Scholars have been at pains to explain this, either by finding a covert
problem, however, is not in the manuscript text, but rather in Schenkl’s and
Oldfather’s editions.
35
For the earlier emendations, see Schenkl’s text critical notes.
36
See, for example J.G. Gager, The Origins of Anti-Semitism: Attitudes Toward Judaism in Pagan and
Christian Antiquity (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983), 77.
37
J. Ysebaert (Greek Baptismal Terminology: Its Origins and Early Development [Græcitas
Christianorum Primæva 1; Nijmegen: Dekker & van de Vegt N.V., 1962], 20 n. 2) proposes that pathos
denotes the circumcision and Sharp (Epictetus, 134–35) that the participle ᾑρημένου means that.
Conversion without circumcision is proposed by N. McEleney (“Conversion, Circumcision and the
Law,” NTS 20 (1974): 319–41, 332) but rejected by J. Nolland (“Uncircumcised Proselytes?” JSJ 12
(1981): 173–94; 179–82).
The manuscript reading is admittedly difficult but nevertheless
understandable. It is clear that the Jew is a metaphor for the Stoic. As Epictetus
assumes that his audience consists of Stoics, the basic identity in the metaphor is that
of “being a Jew” (section 19). This is Epictetus’ own understanding. As these “Jews”
are non-practicing ones, they deceive the multitude (οἱ πολλοί). In section 20
Epictetus presents the understanding of the multitude: when words and deeds are in
tension with each other, the common people base their understanding on deeds and,
consequently, see the basic identity as that of a non-Jew (section 20). In section 21,
Epictetus admits that a Jew becomes a real Jew when his or her deeds are concomitant
The manuscript text does not speak of non-Jews becoming Jews. Therefore the
of two kinds of Jews. The manuscript provides a situation where Jews who are not
following their faith are supposed to make a change in their conduct after baptism and
choice. I claim that the baptised Jews are actually Christians. The word βεβαμμένου is
in the perfect tense, denoting “a completed action the effects of which still continue in
the present.”38 The perfect tense rules out renewed purification rites and indicates a
single baptism which has an ongoing effect.39 As Epictetus is not speaking of non-
Jews becoming Jews, there is no question of a proselyte baptism. One cannot avoid
However, there is not only one baptism. In section 21 Epictetus says, “we are
38
H.W. Smyth, Greek Grammar (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1984), 434 (§ 1945). This is the
basic meaning of the perfect tense. Smyth also lists other meanings, but the context of Epictetus’
passage does not indicate any of them. It is safest and most natural to keep the basic meaning here.
39
On the purification rites, see for example J. Thomas, “Baptistes,” in RAC I (ed. T. Klauser et al.;
Stuttgart: Anton Hiersemann, 1950), 1167–1172; E.P. Sanders, Judaism: Practice and Belief 63 BCE –
66CE (London: SCM Press, 1992), 222–30.
else” (trans. Oldfather, LCL). As there is no mention of baptists earlier, we should
assume that the counterfeit baptists are negative counterparts for the Jews who have
adopted the πάθος of the baptised person. This comparison also presumes that the
word βαπτιστής means a baptised person. Although we usually tend to think that this
word denotes the person who baptises in contrast to the baptised one, this kind of
differentiation is not necessary. The word can also denote persons who practice self-
immersion.40 In theory, it could denote both the one who takes the proselyte baptism
and the one who practices the repeated ablutions of mainstream Judaism (see, e.g.,
Leviticus 15; Numbers 19). The latter is the probable alternative, as the passage by no
The prefix παρα- denotes that there is something wrong in these baptisms. The
invalid.41 This seems to reflect disputes over baptism: all the Jews have invalid
baptisms (section 21), while real Jews have a valid baptism (section 20). As the valid
baptism is the Christian baptism, Epictetus reproduces the Christian and anti-Jewish
view. Justin Martyr makes plain that Christians do not accept Jewish ablutions but
prefer the Christian baptism (Dialogue with Trypho 14.1; 19.2). There is something
similar going on in Epictetus’ metaphorical contrast between the counterfeit Jews and
the real Jews.42 Epictetus’ words for Christians, who are the real Jews, undoubtedly
40
See the names of certain Jewish sects; K. Rudolph, “The Baptist Sects,” in The Cambridge History of
Judaism 3 (ed. W. Horbury, W.D. Davies, and J. Sturdy; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1999), 471–500).
41
This is the earliest occurrence of the word παραβαπτιστής. Later we encounter it in the church
fathers, who use it to refer to the persons who commit schismatic baptisms; G.H.W. Lampe, A Patristic
Greek Lexicon (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961): παραβαπτιστής.
42
Rudolph (“The Baptist Sects,” 482) speaks of a rivalry between Christian and proselyte baptism.
43
L.H. Feldman, Virhe. Vain pääasiakirja.Jew and Gentile in the Ancient World: Attitudes and
Interactions From Alexander to Justinian (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), 196–200; S.G.
3. Loan Words
I have already mentioned that the word πάθος is one that instantly catches the eye of
the one who knows Epictetus’ philosophy or Stoic philosophy in general. In Stoic
philosophy it denotes the morally questionable passions. Epictetus also uses it in this
negative sense – except here.44 Keeping this general background in mind, it is odd that
Epictetus makes a moral example of a Jew with the πάθος. One can suppose that
Epictetus’ use of a loan word is visible in the fact that it creates tensions in the
passage. The πάθος is qualified as the πάθος of the person who is baptised and who
has made the choice. This expression assumes that the person has the πάθος after the
baptism and the choice. Surprisingly, Epictetus adds that a person should also adopt
the πάθος that he or she has already received as a baptised person and as a person who
has made the choice. The baptism and the choice, which qualify the πάθος, do not fit
The πάθος acquired through baptism and choice is certainly considered too
ritualistic by Epictetus, who tends to prefer rational operations. For example, it is not
enough to attend the Eleusinian mysteries. He says that one should also understand
“that all these things were established by men of old time for the purpose of education
and for the amendment of our life” (Discourses 3.21.15; trans. W. A. Oldfather,
Wilson, Related Strangers: Jews and Christians 70–170 C.E. (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1995):
295–96.
44
Other occurrences include: Discourses 1.4.26; 1.27.10; 2.18.11; 3.1.8; 3.2.3 (two times); 4.1.57;
4.8.28; fr. 20. For the Stoic definition of πάθος, see M. Forschner, Die stoische Ethik. Über den
Zusammenhang von Natur-, Sprach- und Moralphilosophie im altstoischen System (Darmstadt:
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1995),,114–23; and T. Brennan, “The Old Stoic Theory of
Emotions,” in The Emotions in Hellenistic Philosophy (ed. T. Engberg-Pedersen and J. Sihvola; The
New Synthese Historical Library 46; Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998), 21–70, esp. 21–
39. Bonhöffer (Epictet und die Stoa, 276–84) has analysed Epictetus’ use of the Stoic philosophy on
πάθος rather than the use of the word itself.
LCL).45 A similar moral emphasis is visible when he speaks about baptism. One does
not get the πάθος through the ritual of baptism, but through conscious adoption. Thus
the baptism and the choice have lost their significance in Epictetus’ thinking.
βεβαμμένου καὶ ᾑρημένου is best understood as a loan expression. The word πάθος
has a deviant meaning here; βάπτω and the perfect tense of ᾑρημένου are hapax
legomena in the Epictetan corpus. The other expression related to the baptism, the
Unfortunately, we cannot show any exact source for these loan words.
Generally speaking, they fit well within the Christian usage. The word βαπτιστής and
Christian texts, with two exceptions. Those two are Epictetus and Josephus. In
Epictetus it seems to be a Christian loan word, and Josephus uses it when speaking of
“John called the Baptist” (Jewish Antiquities 18.116). Thus the word ‘baptist’ occurs
When it comes to choice, one can note that Justin Martyr speaks of it in the
also influenced Epictetus, who was older than Justin. According to Justin, the
converts are baptised so that they become children of free choice (προαιρέσεως) and
knowledge. They have chosen (ἑλομένῳ) the rebirth (First Apology 61.10.). Justin
speaks of Christ’s πάθος, meaning his suffering (e.g., Dialogue with Trypho 74.3;
45
H.-J. Klauck, The Religious Context of Early Christianity: A Guide to Graeco-Roman Religions
(London: T&T Clark, 2003),103–05.
97.3), but not in the context of a baptised Christian. In this respect, better analogies
For Ignatius the πάθος is an important concept, and its root is in Christ’s
πάθος – that is, Christ’s suffering.46 Christ’s πάθος is the constituent for the Christian
communities (see, e.g., the introductory salutations in Ignatius, To the Ephesians and
To the Trallians). It also ensures the effect of baptism, as Christ was baptised so that
he could cleanse water through his suffering (Ignatius, To the Ephesians 18.2).47
Ignatius also speaks of choice and πάθος in the same context. He says that Christians
should freely choose (αὐθαιρέτως) death and thus join in Christ’s suffering (Ignatius,
To the Magnesians 5.2). Ignatius presents no clear source for Epictetus’ loan words.
text. Epictetus may refer to Christians who are ready for suffering because of their
beliefs. This interpretation fits in well with what Epictetus says of the Galileans’
Discourses 4.7.6 shows quite clearly that Epictetus knew Christians and their use of
canons in habituation. The passage on Jews and real Jews (Discourses 2.9.19–21)
utilises Christian views. Epictetus even borrows expressions from some unknown
Christian source, whether textual or not. What is interesting in these two passages is
the fact that Epictetus mentions Christians in passing. Granted that these passages do
not betray any interest in Christianity per se, but they do betray a self-evident
46
W. Bauer and H. Paulsen, Die Briefe des Ignatius von Antiochia und der Polykarpbrief (Die
Apostolischen Väter II; Handbuch zum Neuen Testament 18; Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck),
1985), 21; W.R. Schoedel, Ignatius of Antioch: A Commentary on the Letters of Ignatius Of Antioch
(Hermeneia; Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1985), 85–86.
47
Bauer and Paulsen, Die Briefe des Ignatius, 42.
knowledge of Christians, even among the audience. Epictetus does not explain who
the Christians are or what their beliefs are. He seems to expect that his audience
knows enough to understand his points. He even expects that the audience knows the
knowledge of Christians.
Adolf Bonhöffer closed over a century ago. The discussion, however, should be
framed anew. Bonhöffer is right when he supposes that Epictetus would not have
however, shows that Epictetus used different motifs from everyday life to illustrate
his Stoic philosophy. Christians were presented as examples of fearless people whose
words and deeds were in harmony. As Epictetus even uses some expressions from
Christian sources, one can legitimately ask whether there might be even more in the
Discourses. The case closed by Bonhöffer should be opened again, but in a reframed
version.
New Testament. There is much more early Christian literature, which is relevant for
the comparison. Epictetus’ πάθος has a good equivalent in Ignatius’ epistles. Second,
after Mörth’s, Bonhöffer’s, and Sharp’s evaluations, one should not simply pick up
parallels and make claims of dependences in a parallelomanic way. This was Zahn’s
elements in Christian literature. On the other hand, the fact that Epictetus cites
48
Bonhöffer, Epiktet, 72–81.
Christian expressions increases the probability that some similarities are due to
In order not to fall into the trap of parallelomania, one should concentrate on
those Epictetan passages that include a special hint – for example, that of quietly
waiting for the cross in Discourses 2.2.19–20. In that context, Epictetus blames those
who incite the judges in court. This procedure will ruin the case. On the other hand, if
one likes and wants to provoke the judges, why not keep quiet? “Why do you mount
the platform at all, why answer the summons? For if you wish to be crucified, wait
and the cross will come” (εἰ γὰρ σταυρωθῆναι θέλεις, ἔκδεξαι καὶ ἥξει ὁ σταυρός).
There are two points here which attract interest. First, one should wait for the cross
without answering the summons, like Jesus, who did not “answer, not even to a single
charge, so that the governor was greatly amazed” (Matthew 27:14). Second, the
students were from well-to-do families, presumably Roman citizens who were
practically never punished with the cross.49 To be sentenced to death on the cross is
just a theoretical or symbolic idea for them. Does Epictetus hint to Jesus as an
example, as he openly refers to Socrates’ example just before the reference to the
cross? A further analysis of this and possibly other passages may show whether or not
one can find more contacts between Epictetus and early Christians, in addition to
John Granger Cook tried to develop sympathy for the Romans’ shock in the
face of the otherness of Christianity. His profound and excellent book tells us how
Tacitus, Suetonius, and Pliny beheld Christians with disgust. However, Epictetus
shows that the Romans did not only feel pure disgust when observing Christians.
49
On the rare exceptions, see M. Hengel, Crucifiction in the Ancient World and the Folly of the
Message of the Cross (London: SCM Press, 1977):,39–45.
While Pliny thought that Christianity was madness (amentia, Epistulae ad Trajanum
10.96.4), Epictetus held a different view. Epictetus thought that Christians and
madmen had similarly inadequate philosophical grounds for fearlessness, but he did
not lump these groups together. He admits that the Galileans bravely attained virtuous
conduct through habituation. In this respect, Christians are braver than the common
people, who are not trained for a fearless encounter with threats. Thus Epictetus’
This raises the question of the relationship between early Christian religion
people, close to the category of philosophy. Christians are not madmen, but they are
not fully philosophers either. They do not belong to the multitude, but rather to the
Jews who practice what they preach and who can be compared to real Stoics with
been acquainted with philosophical themes since Paul,50 and in the second century
there are clear examples of Christian philosophers, Justin Martyr being the main
one.51 There are also other examples of moderate accounts of Christians among the
pagan philosophers during the late second century.52 It is possible that the
50
For Paul and philosophy, see for example A.J. Malherbe, Paul and the Popular Philosophers
(Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989); T. Engberg-Pedersen, Paul and the Stoics (Louisville:
Westminster John Knox Press, 2000); and Engberg-Pedersen, Cosmology and Self; G.H. van Kooten,
Paul’s Anthropology in Context: The Image of God, Assimilation to God, and Tripartite Man in
Ancient Judaism, Ancient Philosphy and Early Christianity (Wissenschaftliche Untersuchungen zum
Neuen Testament 232; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2008); E. Wasserman, The Death of the Soul in
Romans 7. Sin, Death, and the Law in Light of Hellenistic Moral Psychology (Wissenschaftliche
Untersuchungen zum Neuen Testament 2. Reihe 256; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2008); Huttunen, Paul
and Epictetus; R.M. Thorsteinsson, Roman Christianity and Roman Stoicism: A Comparative Study of
Ancient Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).
51
On Justin’s Christian philosophy, see Thorsteinsson, “By Philosophy Alone: Reassessing Justin’s
Christianity and His Turn from Platonism,” Early Christianity 3 (2012): 492–517..
52
Huttunen, “In the Category of Philosophy? Christians in Early pagan Accounts,” in Others and the
Construction of Early Christian Identities (ed. Raimo Hakola, Nina Nikki, and Ulla Tervahauta;
Publications of the Finnish Exegetical Society 106; Helsinki, 2013), 239–281.
philosophical elements in Christian teachings induced different philosophical