Lecture 8 - Sovereignty (I)
Lecture 8 - Sovereignty (I)
Lecture 8 - Sovereignty (I)
Roger Masterman
_____________________________________________________________________
Essential Reading:
Masterman and Murray, Ch.6 (NB: this chapter relates to the topic of sovereignty as
a whole); Turpin and Tomkins, ch.2.2-2.2.5 (pp.62-109).
Recommended Reading:
M. Elliott, ‘Parliamentary Sovereignty in a Changing Constitutional Landscape’ in J.
Jowell and C. O’Cinneide (eds), The Changing Constitution (9th edn) (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2019)
_____________________________________________________________________
Key Issues:
The commentator A.V. Dicey is arguably most renowned for his influential work on
parliamentary sovereignty; the legally unlimited power of Parliament. There are
two dimensions to the classic Diceyan reading of parliamentary sovereignty:
(1) The positive aspect holds that Parliament possesses unlimited law-making
power.
(2) The negative aspect holds that no other body has the authority to challenge
the validity of an Act of Parliament.
1
(a) A summary of the traditional doctrine as expounded by Dicey:
Parliament has the right to make or unmake any law whatever (‘the positive
aspect’); and
no person or body outside Parliament is recognised by the law as having a
right to override or set aside any legislation of Parliament at all (‘the negative
aspect’).
“… Parliament may remodel the British constitution, prolong its own life,
legislate ex post facto, legalise illegalities, provide for individual cases,
interfere with contracts and authorise the seizure of property, give dictatorial
powers to the Government, dissolve the United Kingdom or the British
Commonwealth, introduce communism or socialism or individualism or
facism, entirely without legal remedy.” (Ivor Jennings, The Law and the
Constitution (4th ed, 1952) (emphasis added))
(b) The limits of the doctrine: it goes to the lack of legal restraints on Parliament
only:
“It is often said that it would be unconstitutional for… Parliament to do certain things,
meaning that the moral, political or other reasons against doing them are so strong
that most people would regard it as highly improper if Parliament did these things.
But that does not mean that it is beyond the power of Parliament to do these things.
If Parliament chose to do any of them, the courts could not hold the Act of
Parliament invalid.” (Madzimbamuto v Lardner-Burke [1969] 1 AC 526)
(c) How the courts accept parliamentary sovereignty in practice: the doctrines of
express and implied repeal
Ellen Street Estates v Minister of Health [1934] 1 KB 590: “Parliament can alter an Act
previously passed … it can do so by repealing in terms the previous Act … and it can
do it also in another way – namely, by enacting a provision which is clearly
inconsistent with the previous Act.” (per Scrutton J).
2
Implied Repeal – where two statutory provisions are inconsistent with each other,
the provision passed later in time while prevail. The courts will take the later
provision to have “impliedly repealed” the earlier.
Key Issues:
Dicey himself did recognise the political limitations to Parliament’s unfettered legal
power: ‘[there are] many enactments … which Parliament never would and (to speak
plainly) never could pass.’ (A. V. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the
Constitution).
“If [we are to acknowledge a source of political authority that may restrict
Parliament’s legislative latitude] legal sovereignty is not sovereignty at all. It
is not supreme power. It is a legal concept, a form of expression which
lawyers use to express the relations between Parliament and the courts. It
means that the courts will recognise as law the rules which Parliament makes
by legislation …”
(a) Three meanings of the positive aspect (Parliament can “make or unmake any
law”):
There is no law that Parliament cannot change (there is, therefore, no concept
of entrenchment in UK constitutional law):
3
There is therefore no distinction between “constitutional” and other laws on
the traditional account (the constitution is therefore synonymous with, and a
result of, the ordinary law of the land);
The evidence:
“De Lolme’s remark that Parliament can do anything except make a man into
a woman and a woman into a man is often quoted. But, like many of the
remarks which de Lolme made, it is wrong … Though it is true that Parliament
cannot change the course of nature, it is equally true that it cannot in fact do
all sorts of things. The supremacy of Parliament is a legal fiction, and legal
fiction can assume anything.” (Ivor Jennings, The Law and the Constitution).
The evidence:
The Courts have – since the civil war – denied that a general power to
invalidate primary legislation exists. For instance: “… it is not for the court to
say that a parliamentary enactment, the highest law in this country, is illegal”
(Cheney v Conn [1968] 1 All ER 779, 782).
Nor does the executive have the capacity to amend the law: “The idea that ...
the Executive has power to prescribe or alter the law to be administered by
the Courts of law in this country is out of harmony with the principles of our
Constitution” (The Zamora [1916] 2 AC 77, 90).
4
And see also:
“… in many cases, the common law will controul Acts of Parliament, and
sometimes adjudge them to be utterly void: for when an Act of Parliament is
against common right or reason, or repugnant, or impossible to be
performed, the common law will controul it, and adjudge such Act to be
void.” (Dr Bonham’s Case (1609), Coke CJ).
“'I do not exclude the possibility that in the very unlikely event that a
parliamentary majority abusively sought to entrench its power by a
curtailment of the franchise or similar device, the common law, informed by
principles of democracy and the rule of law and international norms, would
be able to declare such legislation unlawful” (Moohan v Lord Advocate [2015]
AC 901, [35].