Huber, Wolfgang: Human Rights and Globalisation - Are Human Rights A "Western" Concept or A Universalistic Principle?
Huber, Wolfgang: Human Rights and Globalisation - Are Human Rights A "Western" Concept or A Universalistic Principle?
Huber, Wolfgang: Human Rights and Globalisation - Are Human Rights A "Western" Concept or A Universalistic Principle?
Huber, Wolfgang
Honorary Professor at the Faculty of Theology
Stellenbosch University
ABSTRACT
This paper represents an edited version of the authors’ STIAS lecture
at the Stellenbosch University in 2014. It deals with the global human
rights discourse, as the integrity of human persons all around the world
is at stake, showing the necessity and the universality of human rights.
Therefore the author explores two basic kinds of attitudes towards human
rights, namely 1) forms of human rights optimism – e.g. the argument
that globalisation as such leads to a universal acknowledgement of them
– and 2) variants of human rights scepticism, in which the author sees
those rights practically disregarded, the “Western” concept challenged, and
a human rights exceptionalism spreading. Subsequently he asks for what
kind of universality of human rights we may argue and how cosmopolitan
ethics may support this universality.
117
HUBER, WOLFGANG
1. INTRODUCTION
The first two pages of the Cape Times on a single day show how endangered human
rights are in the present time. These two pages report among other news on the
“unspeakable suffering of children” in Syria, the “mass torture of Iraqi women”, the
“public lynching of a suspected ex-rebel by soldiers” in the Central African Republic,
the drowning of seven illegal migrants “as they tried to swim to the Spanish enclave
of Ceuta from a beach in neighbouring Morocco”, the conflict about the rights of
parliament in the Ukraine, the investigation on an “alleged massacre of dozens
of civilians by army troops” during the bloody civil war in El Salvador in 1981,
and finally the violent protests in different parts of South Africa in 2014, that have
“claimed nine lives, allegedly at the hands of police, in five weeks” (Cape Times,
Friday, February 7, 2014, p. 1f.).
In all these cases, reported on one single day on the first two pages of a newspaper,
basic human rights are at stake. When we receive those reports on torture, sexual
abuse or recruitment of children for combat, the illegal detention of women for
months or years, their ill-treatment and rape by security forces, the application
of lynch law, the desperate ways of refugees to help themselves, the disregard of
the status of non-combatants, the violent reaction of the police to violent excesses
of protest – when we reflect these attacks on the integrity of human persons it
becomes difficult to doubt the content, the necessity and the universality of human
rights. Whenever elementary rights are bluntly violated these rights themselves
gain evidence. Scepticism regarding these rights seems even to be cynical. It seems
comparably cynical to ignore the extension and the intensity of human rights
violations in our times.
However different kinds of attitudes characterise the human rights discourse in
our days. On the one hand we observe different forms of human rights optimism
guided by the conviction that globalisation, economic progress and legal measures
foster human rights. On the other hand we observe also some variants of human
rights scepticism, for instance regarding the amount of human rights violations, the
weaknesses of traditional foundations of human rights or the pluralism of world
cultures, which is seen as incompatible with the idea of universal human rights.
In the following I will briefly look on today’s human rights optimism and then
move to the sceptical arguments. I will then ask more specifically for what kind
of universality of human rights we may argue and how cosmopolitan ethics may
support this universality.
Before we enter the avenue marked by these points we have to remember that human
rights are not a passe-partout for all problems at hand. The most obvious limitation is
that human rights do not immediately describe our obligations and responsibilities
to the fabric of a community. Neither the protection of civil and political rights nor
the promotion of social, economic and cultural rights is sufficient for the coherence
of society. Daniel E. Lee and Elizabeth J. Lee correctly state in using a quote of
theologian Karl Barth that goes back more than half a century: “It is far easier
to make rights claims of a confrontational nature than it is to weave the fabric of
community, fabric that includes the bonds of obligations and responsibilities as well
as affirmations of individual rights. The task of weaving the fabric of community is
even more daunting in an era of globalization in which we have, to use the language
of the theologian Karl Barth, both near neighbours and distant neighbours” (Lee/
Lee 2010:34). But in correctly trying to avoid an overestimation of the range of
human rights, we should also avoid the other mistake – namely to underestimate
them. They are the decisive protection-shield for the inalienable dignity of human
persons. They express in an incomparably clear manner that no human person can
only be seen as an instrument of a foreign will or as an object of foreign domination.
Moreover every human person has to be seen as an end in itself and as the subject
of her own life story.
Whether this understanding of the individual human person gifted with an inviolable
dignity is appropriate and can be preserved under the conditions of globalisation is
one of the crucial questions of our times. It is difficult to evade this question, but it
is also difficult to find answers.
growth and welfare on the basis of free market economies. This expectation was
often repeated in the years after 1990. But it became in many ways falsified over the
last two decades. Economic progress is not stable at all, as recent crises demonstrate.
Economic growth produces a social division that eventually endangers democratic
commitment. And there is no automatic transition from free market economy to
democracy, China being the most prominent example for that. Some may speculate
on the question how long the coexistence of a capitalistic free market and an
authoritarian one party-regime will endure in China. But even when this country
eventually will move in later years to a democratic form of government it will be
difficult to explain this move following the deterministic model of market economy
inevitably leading to democracy and human rights.
In addition we have to remark at this point that human rights optimists work with
a rather restricted concept of these rights. They concentrate in general on a part
of civil and political rights, namely on the negative freedom rights. They see them
mainly as rights that protect the individual against the misuse of state power. They
concentrate on the rights of “possessive individualism” and the protection of the
physical integrity of the individual person. The deterministic view of history as
an economy-driven continuous progress is therefore combined with a restricted
individualistic concept of human rights.
We may observe that such a kind of economic determinism exists also in an
opposite sense. The counterpart to an optimistic picture of history as progress is
the pessimistic picture of history as decline. This decline may even be described
as inevitable as the progress. We all know intellectual paintings of today’s global
realities of comparably deterministic character but of opposite content. They declare
that globalisation irreversibly leads to the distortion of human rights. The central
argument is the increase of social disparity, the marginalising of a trans-national
precariat, the coincidence between the enormous wealth of a small minority and the
depressing poverty of billions of people on our globe (Fraser 2011).
It is necessary to put these realities at the centre of our awareness. But that does not
automatically mean that we interpret them in the scheme of an inverse progress
theory, namely the conception of an inevitable history of decline. To the contrary:
Whoever chooses this pattern of interpretation runs the risk to follow exactly the
same structure of economic determinism which one wants to overcome, but merely
in the opposite direction.
http://ngtt.co.za 121
HUBER, WOLFGANG
How is the picture when we look on it from a conceptual perspective, from the
perspective of justification?
equal dignity to her. The term “image of God” became central for that approach.
Taking into account that such an approach may not develop a convincing or even
binding force for adherents of other religions or for persons without religion Jewish
and Christian theologians felt obliged to offer the concept of the human person
created in the image of God as a point of reference for the inherent equal dignity of
all.
But there is a vast variety of interpretations proposed in newer theological literature
for the meaning of the term “image of God”: the domination of humanity over the
non-human nature (dominium terrae), the dialogical connection of human beings
with God und their fellow human beings, the compassionate solidarity with all
the other creatures, the calling to witness God’s revelation to the world, to name
only some of them (Welker 2006:327). The variability of interpretations indicates
a metaphorical richness of this tradition, but does not so easily lead to a clear
and unambiguous concept of human dignity. Therefore some argue that religious
references in general and especially the image of God-metaphor make human
dignity an “empty formula” (Pöschl/Kondylis 1992: 637ff.). The sentences on human
dignity and its inviolable and inalienable character are therefore seen by some as
“program sentences” without any concrete impact for certain fields of application.
Any clear contours of human dignity seem to disappear under such kind of critique.
The consequences for problems of high relevance, for instance in the fields of life
sciences and medicine, are enormous. A German legal expert commented already
ten years ago: “Human dignity was inviolable” (Böckenförde 2003, my italics).
Whoever is confronted with the big questions of bioethics has to deal again and
again with the future of human dignity.
Discourses on the proper meaning of human dignity are important. But no single
religious or philosophical interpretation can serve as the one and only foundation
of human rights. We have rather to develop an “overlapping consensus” (Rawls
1986:133-172). People have to critically reflect their specific worldviews in a direction
that strengthens not only their own religious or cultural identity but promotes at the
same time shared values and mutually respected rights. Only through an overlapping
consensus among different interpretations the idea of universal human rights can
gain plausibility. By such a discourse the values inherent in different traditions can
be generalised. They are not universal just from the beginning, but take part in a
pluralism of values. It is mostly the experience of their violation what provokes the
process of “value generalisation”, as Hans Joas, a well-known German sociologist,
calls it (Joas 2008, cf. Joas 2000, 2013). For that purpose openness for different
foundations is crucial for any idea of universal human rights. For anyone who is
convinced that his or her reasons to accept universal human rights are the most
http://ngtt.co.za 125
HUBER, WOLFGANG
2012 that African problems should be solved “the African way, not the white man’s
way”. And he added: “Let us not be influenced by other cultures and try to think the
lawyers are going to help. … We are Africans. We cannot change to be something
else” (SAPA, November 2, 2012, quoted by Smit 2014). Cultural relativism puts into
question the universality as well as the indivisibility of human rights. Is there a way
out?
and wealth, colour and race, belief and conviction. They asked for a human right in
the most elementary sense of the word, a right given with the human existence as
such. They asked for the right to be treated as human beings, or, as Hannah Arendt
expressed it so convincingly: “the right to have rights” (Arendt 1949:754-770; Arendt
1993:452ff.).
Arendt’s formulation refers not to the struggles of the 18th century, in which the
first catalogues of human rights were formulated. She coined the formula of “the
right to have rights” in the time in which the United Nations were founded and
the Universal Declaration of Human Rights was proclaimed. Arendt refers to the
experience of refugees from Nazi-Germany, the Soviet Union or other places, which
had no rights in the country where they asked for refuge. What are the rights of a
stateless refugee? Should he or she not at least have a right to have rights?
This experience coincided with the traumatic events of the 20th century leading
to the mass murder of European Jews by Nazi Germany and to genocidal actions
also in other parts of the world since the Herero-unrest in 1904 or the Armenian
catastrophe of 1915. Once again the suffering of people and the compassion with
their destiny made obvious that we cannot speak about rights without applying them
to every human person. It is not pure contingency that the first convention on a
specific aspect of human rights was proclaimed by the United Nations the day before
the vote on the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. It was the Convention on
the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide of December 9, 1948
(Brownlie/Goodwin-Gill 2006:284-287). The next convention that followed in 1951
was the Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees of 1951 (Brownlie/Goodwin-
Gill 2006:288-303). It is true that the idea of universal human rights emerged from
the abysses of the “moral history of the twentieth century” (Glober 2001). It is this
history that gives Jonathan Shay’s statement its severe evidence: “The understanding
of trauma can form a solid basis for a science of human rights” (Shay 1994:209).
It may not be too difficult to develop an understanding for this kind of “new
genealogy of human rights” in a South African context. The suffering of the majority
of South Africans under the Apartheid regime, the solidarity with its victims, the
growing revolt against this deprivation of rights and the compassion of people and
groups around the world attributed to human rights their specific weight for the
new South Africa. Therefore it has to be remembered that the universality of human
rights is in the first instance due to suffering and compassion.
There are strong reasons to support this approach to the universality of human rights
from a theological perspective. A Christian understanding of the human person
takes especially into account the vulnerability of humans and looks on the status
of a society from the perspective of the most vulnerable members of this society
(Koopman 2007). It considers the inviolability of human dignity with the eyes of
those whose dignity is endangered by hunger and illness, poverty and loneliness,
refuge und migration, violence and war. The preferential option for the vulnerable
and their suffering is mandatory for a Christian perspective on human dignity and
human rights.
reciprocity. “The standpoint of the ‘concrete other’ … requires us to view each and
every being as an individual with an affective-emotional constitution, concrete
history, and individual as well as collective identity” (Benhabib 2011:69). The
concrete other needs our compassion and solidarity; our relation to him follows the
rule to love your neighbour, even your enemy. The relation to the “concrete other” is
guided by the norms of empathy and solidarity.
A justification of human rights on the basis of mutual recognition of communicative
freedom is preferable not only on philosophical but also on theological grounds. It
takes the egalitarian universalism seriously that binds philosophical and theological
ethics together. It concentrates on one “principle of rights” that is universalistic,
namely the right to have rights. It distinguishes from this principle the “schedule
of rights” that substantiates this principle with respect to different dimensions and
regarding specific contexts (Benhabib 2011:73-75, 79-82). The codification of human
rights on global, regional and national levels and the work on their protection and
implementation are good examples for this difference between the principle of rights
and the schedule of rights. So I should not say that human rights are universalistic
principles but that they rest on a universalistic principle of rights. I call this principle
universalistic because it is a principle of moral justification and not simply of legal
validity.
It is evident that this approach transcends a purely individualistic justification of
human rights. This justification is rather grounded in a relational understanding
of the human person entering dialogues with others and cooperating with them
on common grounds. It includes an element of self-transcendence insofar the
communicative freedom of the other is respected independently of the extent to
which the other is able or willing to make use of this communicative freedom.
For a last remark I return to the way in which Seyla Benhabib makes reference to
Hannah Arendt and Raphael Lemkin. Arendt learned from her analysis of totalitarian
regimes what Lemkin learned from his confrontation with the genocide: Whoever
wipes plurality off our life-world destroys this world itself. This means that our
perception of the world depends on the plurality of perspectives. In extinguishing
one of those perspectives we destroy the world. As much as we have to mourn the
victims of violence brought to death by tyranny or war, we also have to lament that
we lost a perspective on the world, a part of the world as such. Therefore we have
to defend the plurality of perspectives on the world represented by people in their
individual diversity as well as in the variety of their cultures and religions. Equality
therefore means the equality of the different. The inherent dignity of every human
person provokes our recognition of the different (Huber 2011).
brought into motion and finally became decided by the South African Constitutional
Court in 2002. Nowadays South Africa has the largest publicly provided AIDS
treatment programme in the world – a tremendous example of the possible effect
of cosmopolitan human rights campaigns emerging from civil society (Wolff 2011;
Cameron 2014:139-200).
• The rights of “non-citizens”
Finally we return to Hannah Arendt’s and Seyla Benhabib’s insight that the core of
human rights is the right to have rights. A central issue with respect to human rights
is nowadays the question which rights could and should be given to non-citizens,
among whom we have to distinguish a lot of different groups: stateless persons,
asylum seekers, rejected asylum seekers, refugees, migrants and trafficked persons,
to name the most important of them (Weissbrodt 2008). The degree to which a
society accepts and respects the rights of those groups depends to a high degree not
only on their legal status in the respective country, but also on the willingness of civil
society to take care of them.
The globalisation of our days puts cosmopolitan ethics (or, as some prefer to say:
global ethics) at the centre of ethical reflection. The core of cosmopolitan ethics is
empathy. For a long time empathy like altruism, compassion and solidarity were
seen as abstract and unrealistic expectations with regard to human behaviour. But
in this respect we experience a paradigm shift in the scientific debate. Empathy
is deeply rooted in the evolution of humankind (de Waal 2009). The capacity for
mutual understanding develops early in childhood (Hrdy 2009). The question is
not how such a capacity can emerge but what makes it to disappear. The painful
question, as Carol Gilligan poses it, is how we lose the capacity to love (Gilligan 2014).
Theology has to take this reversal of the question very seriously, because theological
anthropology begins with the insight that the human person is relational in essence.
The relational character of the human person stays therefore at the centre of the
theological understanding of human rights (Botman 2006) and is the starting point
for a theological reflection on cosmopolitan ethics. Therefore cosmopolitan ethics
does not ignore the more narrow forms of community, because for the relational
character of the human person the experience of belonging is of central importance
(De Villiers 2014). But it overcomes all kinds of exclusivism that emphasises the
value of the narrow communities at the expense of those who do not belong to
them. It takes seriously what Martin Luther King observed already in his Letter
from Birmingham Jail half a century ago: “We are caught in an inescapable network
of mutuality, tied in a single garment of destiny. What affects one directly affects all
indirectly“ (quoted by Gilligan 2011).
Cosmopolitan ethics has to make this paradigm shift its point of departure. But
it has also to take into account that for all ethics “the ought implies the can”
(Lee/Lee 2010:76f.). Nobody can take care of all distant neighbours at the same
time. Cosmopolitanism is, however, a necessary critical principle in avoiding an
exclusivism that also in our days often takes totalitarian forms denying the rights
of disrespected people (Benhabib 2011:8-19). Cosmopolitanism takes seriously that
everybody matters equally and that human persons have a right to have rights not
only as citizens of their respective states but “in virtue of their humanity” (Benhabib
2011:13).
REFERENCES
Ackermann, Laurie. 2012. Human Dignity. Lodestar for Equality in South Africa,
Cape Town: Juta & Company.
Apel, Karl-Otto. 1973. Transformation der Philosophie II. Das Apriori der
Kommunikationsgemeinschaft, Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp.
Arendt, Hannah. 1949. Es gibt nur ein einziges Menschenrecht, in: Die Wandlung
4, 1949, 754-770.
--- 1993. Elemente und Ursprünge totaler Herrschaft, 3. Aufl. München: Piper.
De Villiers, Etienne. 2014. Christian and cosmopolitan ethics: Friends or foes?, in:
Maria Rovisco/Sebastian Kim (eds.): Cosmopolitanism, Religion and the Public
Sphere, London/New York: Routledge 2014, 161-174.
De Waal, Frans. 2009. The Age of Empathy. Nature’s Lessons for a Kinder Society,
New York, NY: Harmony Books.
Donnelly, Jack. 2003. Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, 3. ed. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
--- 2007. The Relative Universality of Human Rights, in: Human Rights Quarterly
29, 2007, 281-306.
Forst, Rainer. 2010. The Justification of Human Rights and the Basis Right to
Justification. A Reflexive Approach, in: Ethics 120, 2010, 711-740.
Fraser, Nancy. 2011. Social Exclusion, Global Poverty, and Scales of (In)justice:
Rethinking Law and Poverty in a Globalizing World. in: Stellenbosch Law
Review 22, 2011, 452-462, also in: Liebenberg, Sandra/Geo Quinot (Eds.): Law
and Poverty. Perspectives from South Africa and Beyond, Claremont: Juta 2012,
10-20.
Fukuyama, Francis. 1992. The End of History and the Last Man, New York, NY:
Free Press.
Hrdy, Sarah Blaffer. 2009. Mothers and Others. The Evolutionary Origins of Mutual
Understanding, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Huber, Wolfgang. 2011. The Dignity of the Different. Towards a Christian Ethics
for Pluralistic Societies, in: Len Hansen/Nico Koopman/Robert Vosloo (eds.):
Living Theology. Essays Presented to Dirk J. Smit, Wellington: Bible Media 2011,
427-440.
--- 2012. Christian Responsibility and Communicative Freedom. A challenge for the
future of pluralistic societies. Collected essays, ed. by Willem Fourie, Münster:
Lit.
Joas, Hans. 2000. The Genesis of Values, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
--- 2008. Value Generalization – Limitations and Possibilities of a Communication
about Values, in: Zeitschrift für Wirtschafts- und Unternehmensethik, 9, 2008,
88-96.
--- 2013. The Sacredness of the Person. A New Genealogy of Human Rights,
Washington: Georgetown University Press.
Kant, Immanuel. 1957. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, in: Kant-
Studienausgabe, Bd. IV, Wiesbaden: Insel 1956, 7-102.
--- 1964. Zum ewigen Frieden. Ein philosophischer Entwurf, in: Kant-
Studienausgabe, Bd. VI, Wiesbaden: Insel 1964, 191-251.
Kuruvilla, Shyama a.o. 2012. The Millenium Development Goals and Human
Rights: Realizing Shared Commitments, in: Human Rights Quarterly 34, 2012,
143-177.
Lee, Daniel E./Elizabeth J. Lee. 2010. Human Rights and the Ethics of Globalization,
Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.
http://ngtt.co.za 135
HUBER, WOLFGANG
Liebenberg, Sandra/Geo Quinot (eds.). 2012. Law and Poverty. Perspectives from
South Africa and Beyond, Cape Town: Juta.
Omar, Rashied. 2014. It’s time to reclaim our honour. Violence against women and
children, in: Cape Times, February 13, 2014, 13.
Pogge, Thomas. 2008. World Poverty and Human Rights, 2nd ed. Cambridge UK:
Polity.
Rawls, John. 1986. Political Liberalism. Expanded edition, New York: Columbia
University Press.
Reuter, Hans-Richard. 2013. Recht und Frieden. Beiträge zur politischen Ethik,
Leipzig.
Selya, Roger Mark. 2012. A Geography of Human Rights Abuses, in: Human Rights
Quarterly 34, 2012, 1045-1083.
Smit, Dirk J. 2014. “Whose Law?” South African Struggles with Notions of Justice.
Contribution to “Religion und Menschenrechte”, Humboldt Universität zu
Berlin.
Shay, Jonathan. 1994. Achilles in Vietnam: Combat Trauma and the Undoing of
Character, New York, NY: Scribner.
Wolff, Jonathan. 2011. The human right to health, in: Benatar, Solomon/Gillian
Brock (eds.): Global Health and Global Health Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press 2011, 108-118.
KEY WORDS
Christian Ethics
Communicative Freedom
Cosmopolitanism
Human Rights
Universalism
CONTACT DETAILS
Prof. Wolfgang Huber
w-k.huber@t-online.de
http://ngtt.co.za 137