SSRN 2995488
SSRN 2995488
SSRN 2995488
Why didn't the [Sentencing] Commission sit down and really go and ra-
tionalize this thing and not just take history? The short answer to that
is: we couldn't. We couldn't because there are such good arguments all
over the place pointing in opposite directions. . . . Try listing all the
crimes that there are in rank order of punishable merit.... Then collect
results from your friends and see if they all match. I will tell you they
won't.
2
JUSTICE STEPHEN BREYER
* Karl N. Llewellyn Distinguished Service Professor of Jurisprudence, Law School and De-
partment of Political Science, University of Chicago. This essay is an expansion of certain sec-
tions of the first of my 1994 Tanner Lectures on Human Values, delivered at Harvard University
in November 1994; the lectures themselves will appear under the title PoliticalConflict and Legal
Agreement, in 17 THE TANNER LECTURES ON HTMAN VALUES (Grethe B. Peterson ed., forth-
coming 1996). I am especially grateful to my audiences at Harvard for their extraordinary gra-
ciousness and for their probing comments and questions. Of the many people who offered help
on that occasion, I single out for special thanks my commentators Jean Hampton and Jeremy
Waldron, and also Joshua Cohen, Christine Korsgaard, Martha Minow, Martha Nussbaum, John
Rawls, Tim Scanlon, and Amartya Sen. For extremely helpful comments on the manuscript, I am
grateful to Bruce Ackerman, Ruth Chang, Joshua Cohen, Jon Eister, Charles Fried, Amy Gut-
mann, Don Herzog, Stephen Holmes, Elena Kagan, Dan Kahan, Larry Lessig, Saul Levmore,
William Meadow, Frank Michelman, Martha Minow, Martha Nussbaum, Susan Moller Okin,
Wiktor Osiatynski, Richard Posner, Joseph Raz, Frederick Schauer, Stephen Schulhofer, Anne-
Marie Slaughter, Mark Tushnet, Candace Vogler, and Lloyd Weinreb. I am also indebted to par-
ticipants in a work-in-progress lunch at the University of Chicago and to members of legal theory
workshops at Oxford University and the University of California, Berkeley. I am also grateful to
Sophie Clark for research assistance. Parts of this commentary will appear in a book, LEGAL
REASONING AND POUTICAL CONFLICT (forthcoming 1996).
1 John S. Mill, Bentham, in UTILITARLISM AND OTHER ESSAYS 132, 170 (Alan Ryan ed.,
1987).
2 Justice Breyer is quoted in Jeffrey Rosen, Breyer Restraint, NEw REPUBLIC,July 1I, 1994,
at 19, 25.
'733
Electronic
Electronic copy copy available
available at:at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=2995488
https://ssrn.com/abstract=2995488
1734 HARVARD LAW REVIEW [Vol. io8:x733
INTRODUCTION
3 Nomination of Ruth Bader Ginsburg to Be Associate Justice of the Supreme Court of the
United States: Hearings Before the Senate Judiciary Comm., io3d Cong., ist Sess. 18o (x993)
(statement of then-Judge Ruth Bader Ginsburg).
4 Of course I am referring here to JOHN RAWLS, PoITICAL LIBERALISM (1993) and the sur-
rounding debate. For instructive discussion, see Joshua Cohen, Moral Pluralism and Political
Consensus, in THE IDEA OF DEMOCRACY 270 (David Copp, Jean Hampton & John Roemer eds.,
1993); Jean Hampton, The Moral Commitments of Liberalism, in THE IDEA OF DEMOCRACY,
cited above, at 292; and JOSEPH RAZ, Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence, in
ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN 45 (1994).
5 RAWLS, supra note 4, at 133.
6 See id. at 133-72.
7 Joshua Cohen, A More Democratic Liberalism, 92 MICH. L. REV. 1503, 1546 (1994) (sum-
marizing RAvI.s, cited above in note 4).
Electronic
Electronic copy copy available
available at:at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=2995488
https://ssrn.com/abstract=2995488
1995] INCOMPLETELY THEORIZED AGREEMENTS 1735
phy to questions in metaphysics. (On Rawls' view, see RAwLS, cited above in note 4, at xix-xx.)
Just as the political philosopher may attempt not to take a stand on metaphysical questions, so
the lawyer, the judge, or the political participant may urge outcomes that make it unnecessary to
solve large questions in political philosophy. In a liberal society committed to allowing people of
different fundamental views to live together with mutual respect, the Rawisian strategy may
sometimes founder on confusion, limitations of time and capacity, and fears that political liber-
alism is itself too sectarian to serve as a defining political creed. I do not mean to suggest that
the Rawlsian project is unable to surmount these concerns. Certainly there must be constraints
on the content of incompletely theorized agreements, and those constraints take the form of ab-
stractions. But I do mean to suggest that participants in liberal political culture often seek agree-
ment on what to do rather than exactly how to think. When they reach these agreements from
diverse starting points, they can promote liberal goals in a way that has some distinctive advan-
tages. I do not attempt here to sort out all of the relations between the idea of an overlapping
consensus and the notions I have in mind; more detailed discussion will appear in SUNSTEIN,
LEGAL REASONING AND POLITICAL CONFLICT, cited above in note *.
9 I am thus emphasizing relative rather than absolute particularity. See infra pp. 1739-41.
It is also possible that people may agree on abstraction while disagreeing on particulars, a kind of
incompletely theorized agreement that also has legal uses. See infra p. 1739.
10 There is an exception, having to do with certain kinds of invidious or palpably confused
abstractions. See infra p. 1747.
11 Interesting issues of collective choice lurk in the background here. Important problems of
cycling, strategic behavior, and path dependence may arise in multimember bodies containing
people with divergent rationales, each of whom wants to make his rationale part of law. See
generally KENNETH J. ARRow, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUEs passim (2d ed. 1963)
(analyzing problems of public choice). There may also be complex bargaining issues as some
officials or judges seek to implement a broad theory as part of the outcome, while others seek a
narrow theory, and still others are undecided between the two. These important issues are be-
yond the scope of the present discussion, though it would be most illuminating to have a better
grasp, theoretically and empirically, of the sorts of bargaining games that occur when officials and
judges decide on the scope of the theory to accompany an outcome. Cf. DOUGLAS G. BAIRD,
ROBERT H. GERTNER & RANDAL C. PICKER, GAME THEORY AND THE LAW 6-49 (1994) (apply-
ing game theory models to analyze how players choose among different legal regimes).
12 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
13 For exceptions, se6 the discussion below at pp. 1754-60.
16 For a valuable discussion, see Henry S. Richardson, Specifying Norms as a Way to Resolve
Concrete Ethical Problems, x9 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 279, 306 (iggo).
17 Thus, such terms as "equality" and "freedom" are "essentially contested" in the sense made
famous by W.B. Gallie, Essentially Contested Concepts, 56 PRoc. ARISTOTELIAN Soc'Y 167
(ig9-56).
case rightly reflects the fact that any regulation of abortion would be
ineffective in promoting its own purposes. We can find incompletely
theorized political agreements on particular outcomes in many areas of
law and politics - on both sides of the affirmative action controversy,
both sides of the dispute over the death penalty, and in all facets of
the debate over health care reform.
C. Rules and Analogies
There are two especially important methods by which law might
resolve disputes without obtaining agreement on first principles: rules
and analogies. Both of these methods attempt to promote a major
goal of a heterogeneous society: to make it possible to obtain agreement
where agreement is necessary, and to make it unnecessary to obtain
agreement where agreement is impossible.
For purposes of law, reliance on rules might be incompletely theo-
rized in three different ways. People might agree that rules are bind-
ing without having a full or agreed-upon account of why this is so.
They can often agree on what rules mean even when they agree on
very little else.2 7 They can even agree that certain rules are good
without agreeing on exactly why they are good. And in the face of
persistent disagreement or uncertainty about what morality generally
requires, people can sometimes reason about particular cases by refer-
ence to analogies. They point to cases in which their judgments are
firm, and proceed from those firm judgments to the more difficult
ones. From different foundations, they may be able to agree on the
plausibility of an analogical claim because they share a judgment
about a governing low-level principle in the face of disagreement
about the abstractions underlying that principle.
We might consider, in this regard, Justice Stephen Breyer's discus-
sion of one of the key compromises reached by the seven members of
the United States Sentencing Commission.2 8 As Justice Breyer de-
scribes it, a central issue was how to proceed in the face of disparate
theoretical commitments. Some people asked the Commission to fol-
low an approach to punishment based on "just deserts" - an ap-
proach that would rank criminal conduct in terms of severity. But
different commissioners had different views about how different crimes
should be ranked, and a rational system was unlikely to follow from a
collaborative ranking effort. Other people urged the Commission to
use a model of deterrence. There was, however, no empirical evidence
to link detailed variations in punishment to prevention of crime.
27 Of course, substantive disagreements may break out during interpretation. See FREDERICK
SCHAUER, PLAYING BY THE RULES 207-28 (i99i); Cass R. Sunstein, Problems with Rules, 83
CAL. L. REv. (forthcoming July 1995).
28 See Stephen G. Breyer, The FederalSentencing Guidelines and the Key Compromises upon
Which They Rest, 17 HOFSTRA L. REv. 1, 15-i8 (1988).
Though Justice Breyer does not stress the point, it seems clear that the
seven members of the Commission were unlikely to agree that deter- 29
rence provides a full account of the aims of criminal sentencing.
In these circumstances, what route did the Commission follow? In
fact, the Commission adopted no general view about the appropriate
aims of criminal sentencing. Instead, the Commission adopted a rule
- one founded on precedent: "It decided to base the Guidelines pri-
marily upon typical, or average, actual past practice."30 The Commis-
sion reached an incompletely theorized agreement on the value of
starting (and usually ending) with past averages. Hence unusual judi-
cial sentences would be filtered out through adoption of typical or av-
erage practices. Consciously articulated explanations, involving low-
level reasons, were used to support particular departures from the
past. Justice Breyer saw this effort as a necessary means of obtaining
agreement and rationality within a multimember body 31
charged with
avoiding unjustifiably wide variations in sentencing.
The example suggests a quite general point. Through both analo-
gies and rules, it is often possible to achieve convergence on particular
disputes without resolving large-scale issues of the right or the good.
For judges and officials at least, this is an important virtue.
The fact that we can obtain an agreement of this sort - about the
usefulness and meaning of a rule or the existence of a sound analogy
- is no guarantee of a good outcome, whatever may be our criteria
for deciding whether an outcome is good. The fact that there is agree-
ment about a rule does not mean that the rule is desirable. Perhaps
the rule is bad, or perhaps the judgments that go into its interpreta-
tion are bad. The resolution of the Sentencing Commission deserves
approval only if average practices were not pervasively unjust. Per-
haps the Sentencing Commission incorporated judgments that were
based on ignorance, confusion, or prejudice.3 2 Perhaps a more33
deeply
theorized approach would have produced better guidelines.
Some of the same things may be said about analogies. People in
positions of authority may agree that a ban on same-sex marriages is
analogous to a ban on marriages between uncles and nieces. But the
analogy may be misconceived because there are relevant differences,
because the similarities are far from decisive, or because the principle
that accounts for the judgment of similarity cannot be sustained. The
fact that people agree that case A is analogous to case B does not
29 See id. at 17.
30 Id.
31 See id. at 18; supra p. 1733.
32 For arguments to this effect, see Albert IV. Alschuler, The Failure of Sentencing Guidelines:
A Plea for Less Aggregation, 58 U. Cm. L. REv. 9o, 905-07 ('99'); Daniel J. Freed, Federal
Sentencing in the Wake of Guidelines: Unacceptable Limits on the Discretion of Sentencers, ios
YALE L.J. 1683, 1703-05 (z992).
33 I do not discuss the choice between rules and rulelessness here.
34 I have discussed some of these points in the specific context of analogical thinking. See
Sunstein, supra note 24. I try here to broaden and generalize the discussion and also to correct
some ambiguities and errors in that discussion.
S4 The point counts against Dworkin's Hercules metaphor, see DWORKIN, supra note z5, at
239-4o, and also against efforts to find an analogy between legal reasoning and the search for
reflective equilibrium.
SS See Scalia, supra note 53, at 1177-8o; cf. Sunstein, supra note 27 (criticizing extravagant
enthusiasm for rules).
comes based on grounds that have not been stated publicly. If judges
on a panel have actually agreed on a general theory, and if they are
truly committed to it, they should say so (even if, for reasons I have
suggested, they should usually be reluctant to commit). Judges and the
general community will learn much more if they are able to discuss
the true motivating grounds for outcomes. All these are valid consid-
erations, and nothing I am saying here denies their importance.
B. Judges, Theory, and the Rule of Law
There is an association between the effort to attain incompletely
theorized agreements and the rule of law ideal. Insofar as our system
prizes rule by law rather than rule by individual human beings, it tries
to constrain judgments before particular decisions are made. Indeed, a
prime purpose of the rule of law is to rule off limits certain deep ideas
of the right or the good, at least in the sense that those ideas ought not
to be invoked by officials occupying particular social roles, 6 Among
the forbidden or presumptively forbidden ideas are, often, high-level
views that are taken as too hubristic or sectarian for judges precisely
because they are so high-level. The presumption against high-level
theories is an aspect of the ideal of the rule of law to the extent that it
is an effort to limit the exercise of judicial discretion at the point of
application.
In this way, we might begin to make distinctions between the role
of high theory in the courtroom and the role of high theory in the
political branches; these distinctions are central to the claims I am
making here. In democratic arenas, there is no taboo, presumptive or
otherwise, against invoking high-level theories of the good or the
right.5 7 Such theories have played a role in many social movements
with defining effects on American constitutionalism, including the
Civil War, the New Deal, the women's movement, the civil rights
movement, and the environmental movement.5 8 Many of the most ab-
56 See HERZOG, supra note 42, at no0-47 (connecting the law-politics distinction with the
need to distinguish between the sphere of adjudication and the sphere of legislation).
57 I am putting to one side the questions raised by "comprehensive views." See RAWLS, supra
note 4, at 13-14, 175.
S8 See BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE 44-80 (1991). It might be responded that there
are many cases in which high principle was invoked judicially - consider, for example, the fairly
dramatic and rapid shift in the treatment of sex equality. See GEOFFREY R. STONE, Louis M.
SEIDMAN, CASS R. SUNSTEiN & MARK V. TUSHNET, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 676-7i8 (2d ed.
iggi). In cases of this sort, the Court does use principles of a relatively high-level, even if it
thinks analogically. High-level arguments can certainly be found in some important constitutional
cases, including, for example, DeShaney v. Winnebago County Dep't of Social Servs., 489 U.S.
x89 (x989), in which the Court accepted a large-scale view of the state as "passive" rather than
"affirmative." See id. at r95-97. Note, however, that the Court, in invoking theories, is usually
likely to be following democratic trends rather than initiating new ones, and indeed, in the area of
sex discrimination, the Court was building self-consciously on democratic developments. See, e.g.,
Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S. 677, 687-88 (r973). It is notable, too, that the Court was also
reluctant to develop a theory to account for its new approach to sex equality, but relied instead on
a set of relevant factors. See id. at 682-87. (1 am grateful to Susan Moller Okin for raising this
issue.)
s9 Carson is probably the most contentious example on this list, but her book was in many
ways the foundation of the environmental movement. See RACHEL CARSON, SILENT SPRING
277--97 (1962); Averting a Death Foretold, NEWSWEEK, Nov. 28, 1994, at 72, 72-73.
60 See GERALD N. ROSENBERG, THE HOLLOW HOPE: CAN COURTS BRING ABOUT SOCIAL
CHANGE?, 5-7, 336-38, 342-43 (iggi) (discussing problems in judge-led reform).
61 Examples are offered in R. SHEP MELNICK, REGULATION AND THE COURTS: THE CASE OF
THE CLEAN AIR ACT 110-12, 176-78, 19O-92 (983), and DONALD L. HOROWITZ, THE COURTS
AND SOCIAL POLICY 260-73 (1977). The point is described from the theoretical point of view in
Lon L. Fuller, The Forms and Limits of Adjudication, 92 HARv. L. REV. 353, 393-405 (1978), and
JOSEPH RAz, The Inner Logic of the Law, in ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DoMAIN, cited above in note
4, at 222, 222-25.
62 See Sunstein, supra note 24, at 767-69, 78o-82 (claiming that analogy and low-level princi-
ples need not be conservative).
judges," and American history itself, suggest that courts will rarely at-
tempt to replicate the Warren Court's role. And judges who use such
theories may well blunder. Judges are not trained as political philoso-
phers, and in many cases, use of abstractions not developed by close
63
reference to particular problems has led to major mistakes.
Even more fundamentally, judges lack a democratic pedigree, and
it is in the absence of such a pedigree that the system of precedent,
analogy, and incompletely theorized agreement has such an important
place. The right to a democratic system is one of the rights to which
people are entitled, and in such a system, judicial invocation of large
theories to support large decisions against democratic processes should
be a rare event.6 4 To be sure, judges have a duty to interpret the
Constitution, and that duty authorizes them to invoke relatively large-
scale principles, seen as part and parcel of the Constitution as demo-
cratically ratified. Many people think that judicial activity is best
characterized by reference to use of such principles, 65 and it would be
wrong to deny that there are occasions on which this practice occurs
and is legitimate.
To identify those occasions, it would be necessary to develop a full
theory of legal interpretation. For present purposes, I urge something
more modest. Most judicial activity does not involve constitutional in-
terpretation, and the ordinary work of common law decision and stat-
utory interpretation calls for low-level principles. Indeed,
constitutional argument is itself based largely on low-level principles,
not on high theory, except on those rare occasions when more ambi-
tious thinking becomes necessary to resolve a case, or when the case
for the ambitious theory is so insistent that a range of judges do and
should converge on it.66
At this point, it should be remarked that incompletely theorized
agreements are not necessarily conservative, and it would therefore be
63 Consider the large-scale reference to the passive state in DeShaney v. Winnebago County
Dep't of Social Servs., 489 U.S. i89, i95-97 (1989), a view that cannot withstand analysis in light
of the role of the state in protecting property rights, contract rights, and rights of plaintiffs in
certain settings. See David P. Currie, Positive and Negative ConstitutionalRights, 53 U. CHI. L.
REv. 864, 872-80, 886-87 (1986); David A. Strauss, Due Process, Government Inaction, and Pri-
vate Wrongs, 1989 Sup. CT. REV. 53, 72-76.
64 Of course the point must be qualified by reference to the democratic failures of existing
majoritarian arrangements. For variations on this theme, see JOHN H. ELY, DEMOCRACY AND
DsmTRUST I05-24 (2980), and CASS R. SUNSTEIN, THE PARTIAL CONSTITUTION 133-53 (1993).
6S This is the vision of judicial review in ACKERMAN, cited above in note 58, at 4, 38-39,
131-32, 284. Note that it differs dramatically from the understanding in DwOmKIN, cited above in
note IS, at 355-99, in the sense that Ackerman insists that the large-scale principles have sources
in actual judgments of "we the people." There is, however, a commonality between Ackerman
and Dworkin in the sense that both see the use of such principles as a large part of the Court's
work. It is along that dimension that I am doubting both of their accounts.
66 See infra p. 1766 (discussing the phenomenon of contested views becoming uncontested and
vice versa).
offers full particularity because, by their very nature, reasons are more
abstract than the outcomes that they justify. Once offered publicly,
reasons may therefore apply to cases that the court, in justifying a
particular decision, does not have before it.72 This is why reason-giv-
ing promotes planning. Perhaps the most famous (or infamous) illus-
tration of full particularity comes from Justice Stewart:
I shall not today attempt further to define the kinds of material I under-
stand to be embraced within that shorthand description [of hard-core
pornography]; and perhaps I could never succeed in intelligibly doing so.
But I know73it when I see it, and the motion picture involved in this case
is not that.
All well-functioning legal systems value the enterprise of reason-
giving. But there is a good reason to be wary of reason-giving: rea-
sons may be both over- and under-inclusive. In this way, reasons are
like rules, which are also over- and under-inclusive if measured by
reference to their justifications. 7 4 Whenever a court offers reasons,
there is a risk of future regret - not simply because the court may be
confined in a subsequent case and thus have to avoid inconsistency,
but because the reasons offered in case A may turn out, on reflection,
to generate a standard, a principle, or. a rule that collides with the
court's considered judgment about case B. The constraint produced
by the reason may limit discretion and promote predictability, but it
may also produce a bad result.
The distinction between holding and dictum helps reduce this
problem. Indeed, the distinction squarely addresses the problem of ex-
cessively theorized judgments, and it helps to ensure that legal deci-
sions are incompletely theorized. If we understand the holding to be
the narrowest possible basis for the decision, a subsequent court is
able to offer sufficiently narrow reasons for the outcome in the previ-
ous case - that is, reasons that ensure that the outcome in the previ-
ous case does not apply to a case that is genuinely different. In
initially giving a reason, court one may be unaware of possible appli-
cations that will falsify that reason because of its imprecision and ex-
cessive generality. But court two, able to offer some narrower and
better-fitting explanation for the outcome, can eliminate the difficulty.
It can label the excessive generality "dicta."
There is another difficulty with reason-giving. One might some-
times know something without knowing the reasons for it. For exam-
72 Consider John Dewey's rendition of "the old story of the layman who was appointed to a
position in India where he would have to pass in his official capacity on various matters in
controversies between natives. Upon consulting a legal friend, he was told to use his common-
sense and announce his decisions firmly; in the majority of cases his natural decision as to what
was fair and reasonable would suffice. But, his friend added: 'Never try to give reasons, for they
will usually be wrong.'" John Dewey, Logical Method and Law, io CORNELL L.Q. 17, 17 (1924).
73 Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.S. 184, r97 (1964) (Stewart, J., concurring).
74 See SCHAUER, supra note 27, at 31-34.
pie, one may know that this is Martin's face, and no other face,
without knowing, exactly, why one knows that fact. Or one might
know that a certain act would be wrong, without knowing, exactly,
why it would be wrong. It is certainly possible to know that some-
thing is true without knowing why it is true.
Is there an analogy in law? No simple answer would make sense.
As I have suggested, a special quality of most legal systems is a pre-
sumptive requirement of reasons for legal outcomes. This requirement
makes it hard to prize a capacity to know what the law is without
knowing why it is as it is, or how a case should come out without
knowing why it should come out that way. On the other hand, some
people think that many of our judgments about similarity and dissimi-
larity - a key to legal reasoning - do not rest on reasons but instead
simply constitute our descriptive and normative worlds. 75 Conceiva-
bly, there is an aspect of socialization into law that enables people to
see that case A is "like" case B, and not at all "like" case C, without
always having much of an account of why this is so.
More concretely, it is possible that experienced judges, like exper-
ienced lawyers, develop a faculty - best described as wisdom, percep-
tion, or judgment - that allows them to reach decisions very well and
very quickly. This is a distinctive faculty. It seems to be associated
with the ready and sympathetic apprehension of a wide range of di-
verse particulars and with an appreciation of the appropriate weight
to be given to each.7 6 Certainly, we can imagine a class of people who
have a wonderful capacity to tell whether one case is relevantly like
another, or to decide who should win cases, but who lack much of a
capacity to explain what underlies their ultimate judgments, or their
convictions about relevant similarity and difference. They are not the-
orists at all. But they have a "good ear," unlike some others who have
a "tin ear" for law.
Perhaps it would ultimately be possible for such people (or at least
outside observers) to explain what underlies these good apprehensions,
but this may not be so. It is important not to mystify these issues.
What is asserted to be a capacity for perception may in fact be a
product of bias or confusion, and reason-giving helps diminish this
risk. The faculty of wisdom, perception, or judgment probably
82 If the judge has thought the relevant issues through in an ambitious way and made the
moral judgments that are raised by the issue (to the extent that they are legally relevant), we may
have more assurance that the process of adjudication is reliable, in the sense that it is likely to
lead to results that are just. What I am emphasizing is that the judge might sign an opinion that
contains a more modest account.
83 I should say that I do not know to what extent this counts as a criticism of Dworkin, since
Dworkin presents Hercules as a thought experiment, and it is unclear to what extent Hercules'
approach is supposed to be an ideal for real-world judges. To my knowledge, Dworkin has not
discussed the question of appropriate levels of abstraction in legal justification. But see supra
note 81 (noting Dworkin's suggestion that, in constitutional law, the relevant justification is
"drawn from the most philosophical reaches of political theory").
84 See DwomaN, supra note i5, at 264-65; see also id. at 380-81 (referring to the need "to
gain the votes of other justices and to make their joint decision sufficiently acceptable to the
community so that it can continue to act in the spirit of a community of principle at the constitu-
tional level").
85 Id. at 265.
tial." But Hercules' "judgments of fit and political morality are made
on the same material and have the same character as theirs."8 6
It is these points that I am denying here. The decisions of ordinary
judges are based on different material and have a different character.
They are less deeply theorized not only because of limits of time and
capacity, but also because of the distinctive morality of judging in a
pluralistic society. I will qualify this claim below.8 7 But for the mo-
ment, I suggest that the ordinary judge is no Hercules with less time
on his hands, but a different sort of figure altogether.
B. Conceptual Ascent?
Borrowing from Henry Sidgwick's suggestions about method in
ethics, 8 8 advocates of ambitious thinking might respond in the follow-
ing way. There is often good reason for judges to raise the level of
abstraction and ultimately to resort to large-scale theory. As a practi-
cal matter, discrete judgments about particular cases will often prove
inadequate.8 9 Sometimes, people do not have clear intuitions about
how cases should come out. Sometimes, seemingly similar cases pro-
voke different reactions, and it is necessary to raise the level of theo-
retical ambition to explain whether those different reactions are
justified or to show that the seemingly similar cases are different after
all. Sometimes, different people simply disagree. By looking at
broader principles, we may be able to mediate the disagreement. In
any case, there is a problem of explaining our considered judgments
about particular cases - to make sure that they are not just an acci-
dent9 O - and at some point, the law may well want to offer that
explanation.
Ambitious thinkers might therefore urge that low-level principles
may conflict with one another or be demonstrably wrong. In these
circumstances, judges might well resort to higher theory. When our
modest judge joins an opinion that is incompletely theorized, he must
rely on a reason or a principle that justifies one outcome rather than
another. Perhaps the principle is wrong because it fails to fit with
other cases, or because it is not defensible as a matter of political mo-
rality.9 1 A distinguished judge will seek to add a good deal in the way
of both width and depth by exploring other cases and by deepening
the theoretical ambition of his analysis. He will therefore experience a
kind of conceptual ascent in which the more or less isolated and small
86 Id.
87 See infra pp. 1765-66.
88 See SIDGWICK, supra note 69, at 96-zo4.
89 See id. at oo.
90 "[T]he resulting code seems an accidental aggregate of precepts, which stands in need of
some rational synthesis." Id. at 102.
91 See DwoRKIN, supra note is, at 251-54 (discussing local priority).
92 See, e.g., DWORXIN, supra note 15, at 276-312 (discussing the law of tort); POSNER, supra
note i, passim.
93 See AMY GuTmANN & DENNIS THOMPSON, DEMOCRACY AND DISAGREEMENT (forthcom-
ing 1995).
94 See RAZ, Relevance of Coherence, supra note 49, at 298-303.
95 In Rawls' understanding of the search for reflective equilibrium, we consult "our considered
convictions at all levels of generality; no one level, say that of abstract principle or that of partic-
ular judgments in particular cases, is viewed as foundational. They all may have an initial credi-
bility." RAwLS, supra note 4, at 8 n.8.
96 See, e.g., BRUCE A. ACKERMAN, PRIVATE PROPERTY AND THE CONSTITUTION 15-20 (1977)
(comparing "Scientific Policymakers" with "Ordinary Observers"); POSNER, supra note x, at
23-24 (arguing that economic theory often underlies opinions that appear to be based on other
grounds).
97 For illuminating remarks on abstractions, see RAWLS, cited above in note 4, at 44-46.
Rawls thinks that we turn to abstractions "when we are torn within ourselves." Id. at 44. This is
undoubtedly true, but sometimes we turn instead to particulars when we are so torn.
102 A challenge to this view can be found in Joseph Raz's illuminating discussion of coherence,
but in my view, Raz concludes too quickly that "speaking with one voice" is not an independent
ideal, and I think that he rejects too quickly the view that judges should reason from cases with
which they disagree as a matter of morality. See RAZ, Relevance of Coherence, supra note 49, at
297-98. Raz emphasizes the problems created when judges reason from cases that embody bad
moral judgments. The answer to Raz's claim is institutional. Judges should reason from previ-
ously decided cases not because it is good to sacrifice good moral values, but because the judge's
conception of good moral values is not always reliable, and because keeping (local) faith with
precedent is a way of disciplining the judges, promoting predictability, and ensuring a form of
equality. Of course, the extent to which a particular judge should keep faith with a past decision
(which she believes wrong) cannot be decided in the abstract What I am suggesting is that
decisions that the judge believes wrong may not in fact be wrong, and that the obligation to
reason from past cases makes best sense if it is seen as questioning the (ordinary) judge's ability
to make this judgment well.
103See, e.g., Continental T.V., Inc. v. GTE Sylvania Inc., 433 U.S. 36, 56-59 (1977).
104 See, e.g., James C. Miller III & Paul Pauter, Predation:The Changing View in Ecofiomics
and the Law, 28 J. LAW & ECON. 495, 495-502 (1985) (diicussing the prominent role that eco-
nomic analysis and scholarly research have played in shaping antitrust predation law).
105 The best example may be the law of free speech. See Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357,
372, 375-78 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring); Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 624, 630-31
(1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting). Note, however, that even here, no unitary theory of free speech is
offered, and nothing very much like a philosophical account appears in the relevant opinions.
In the areas of free speech and discrimination, some such process has
occurred, resulting in occasionally ambitious claims, even if it would
be far too much to say that full theorization or coherence can be
10 6
found.
An especially interesting phenomenon occurs when a once-contesta-
ble analogy becomes part of the uncontested background for ordinary
legal work - or when the uncontested background is drawn into
sharp question, sometimes via analogies. Thus, for example, the view
that bans on racial intermarriage are "like" segregation laws is now
taken largely for granted; it is part of the way that lawyers order their
conceptual world. So too, perhaps, with the view that sex discrimina-
tion is "like" race discrimination - a view that would have been un-
thinkable in Supreme Court opinions as late as, say, i965. Ordinarily,
the slippage from the uncontested to the contested occurs in law
through encounters with particular cases that reveal gaps or problems
with the conventional view.1 0 7 In American law, views that once were
taken as natural - or not even as views at all - sometimes become
dislodged in this way. The original attack on the monarchical legacy
took this form;108 so too did the attack on racial hierarchy; so too did
the New Deal, which depended on an insistence that common law cat-
egories were far from natural and prepolitical but instead were a con-
scious social choice.' 0 9 Eventually, the contested can become
uncontroversial as new categories emerge and harden through repeated
encounters with particular cases.
Now turn to the question of what judges should do. I have urged
that there are reasons for judges to offer the least ambitious argument
necessary to resolve cases, in the hope that different people from their
diverse standpoints can converge on that argument, and with the be-
lief that abstractions may prove troublesome for later cases. But if
judges can agree on an abstraction, and if the abstraction can be
shown to be a good one, judicial acceptance of that abstraction may
hardly be troubling but, on the contrary, an occasion for celebra-
106 See, e.g., City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 439-47 (xg85) (fail-
ing to offer a full theory of equality); New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 27o-83
(1964) (failing to offer a full theory of free speech).
107 See, e.g., Reed v. Reed, 404 U.S. 71, 76-77 (1971) (challenging preexisting acceptance of sex
discrimination); New York imes, 376 U.S. at 268-69 (finding libel law subject to the First
Amendment); Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483, 495 (1954) (overruling Plessy v. Ferguson,
163 U.S. 537 (I896)).
10 Gordon Wood's description of this development traces the shift from the earlier view: "So
distinctive and so separated was the aristocracy from ordinary folk that many still thought the
two groups represented two orders of being. . . . Ordinary people were thought to be different
physically, and because of varying diets and living conditions, no doubt in many cases they were
different. People often assumed that a handsome child, though apparently a commoner, had to be
some gentleman's bastard offspring." GORDON S. 'WOOD, THE RADICALISm[ OF THE AMERICAN
REVOLUTION 27 (1992).
109 See SUNSTEIN, sup'a note 64, at 4o-67.
110 Consider, for example, Alexander Meiklejohn's suggestion that New York 7imes Co. v. Sul-
livan was "an occasion for dancing in the streets," as reported in Harry Kalven, Jr., The New
York Times Case: A Note on "The Central Meaning of the First Amendment," 1964 SuP. CT.REV.
191, 221 n.125.
IIIThere are intrapersonal parallels. In our ethical lives as individuals, each of us may avoid
choice among theories if we do not need to choose in order to decide what to do in particular
cases. But the interpersonal case is perhaps more vivid.
112 See STONE, SEIDMAN, SUNSTEIN & TUsHNET, supra note 58, at 787-807.
113 See West Coast Hotel Co. v. Parrish, 300 U.S. 379, 391-93 (1937); Nebbia v. New York,
291 U.S. 502, 535-39 (1934).
any general theory and exposes its limits. Over time, an area of law
may become more theorized or less so; over long periods of time, it
may go from one to the other, and back again.
If all this is right, we ought not to think of incompletely theorized
agreements on particulars as a kind of unfortunate second-best,
adopted for a world in which people disagree, are confused or biased,
and have limited time. The alleged first-best - Hercules, or the (ex-
hausted?) judge who has reached reflective equilibrium - calls for an
extra-human conception of law. It is extra-human because it is so ob-
viously unsuited to the real world. To say the least, it is hard to know
whether a top-down or highly theorized approach is appropriate for
morality. But often, at least, it is easy to know that such an approach
is inappropriate for law. The institutional features of the legal system
- a human institution with distinctive constraints - require an ac-
count of law that is highly sensitive to the characteristics of the system
in which it is situated. Among those characteristics are confusion or
uncertainty about general theory, deep disputes about the right and
the good, and a pressing need to make a wide range of particular
decisions.
B. Disagreement
What of disagreement? The discussion thus far has focused mostly
on the need to obtain agreement or convergence. This is only part of
the picture. In law, as in politics, disagreement can be a productive
and creative force - revealing error, showing gaps, moving discussion
in appropriate directions. The American political order has placed a
high premium on "government by discussion,"" 4 and when the process
is working well, this is true for the judiciary as well as for other insti-
tutions. Progress in politics and even law is often fueled by failures of
convergence and by sharp disagreement on both the particular and the
general.
It should be unnecessary to emphasize that legal disagreements
may have many legitimate sources. Two of these sources are especially
important. First, people may share general commitments but disagree
on particular outcomes. This is no less pervasive a social phenomenon
than its converse, which I have stressed here. People may think, for
example, that it is wrong to take innocent life, but disagree about
whether the Constitution protects the right to have an abortion. They
may think that everyone has a right to be free from invidious discrimi-
nation, but disagree about the legitimacy of affirmative action. It is
common to find agreement on the general alongside disagreement on
the particular.
Henry Hart and Albert Sacks of course defended the view, influen-
tial for the last generation, that courts engage in principled reasoning
I's See HENRY M. HART, JR. & ALBERT M. SACKS, THE LEGAL PROCESS: BASIC PROBLEMS
INTHE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW 643-46 (William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Philip P. Frickey
eds., 1994).
116 RONALD DwoRKiN, The Forum of Principle, in A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 33, 69-71 (1985);
see also supra note 81. Note in this regard that Dworkin's discussion of "passivism" in constitu-
tional law, see DwORKIN, supra note IS, at 369-79, does not deal with the need for devices to
limit the power of judicial review in light of the judges' likely biases and institutional weaknesses,
and it fails to see the possibility that, because of those weaknesses, there is a gap between the
actual meaning of the Constitution and judicial pronouncements about that meaning. See id. at
370; cf Lawrence G. Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional
Norms, 91 HARv. L. REv. 1212, 1213-28 (1978) (discussing that gap). The presumption in favor
of theoretical modesty is one way of disciplining judicial power in light of judicial weaknesses.
117 See ACKERMAN, supra note 58, at 40-56.
11aBrown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483, 495 (i954), is, of course, the most important
example.