Dokumen - Pub - The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology Oxford Handbooks 9780199289202 0199289204
Dokumen - Pub - The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology Oxford Handbooks 9780199289202 0199289204
Dokumen - Pub - The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology Oxford Handbooks 9780199289202 0199289204
PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY
THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF
PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY
Edited by
THOMAS P. FLINT
and
MICHAEL C. REA
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research,
scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide in
You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer
ISBN 978–0–19–928920–2
1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2
To Michael J. Loux
CONTENTS
List of Contributors
Introduction
THOMAS P. FLINT AND MICHAEL C. REA
6. Omniscience
EDWARD WIERENGA
7. Divine Eternity
WILLIAM LANE CRAIG
8. Omnipotence
BRIAN LEFTOW
9. Omnipresence
HUD HUDSON
16. Theodicy
MICHAEL J. MURRAY
17. Skeptical Theism and the Problem of Evil
MICHAEL BERGMANN
Index
LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS
THE rst half of the twentieth century was a dark time for
philosophical theology. Sharp divisions were developing among
philosophers over the proper aims and ambitions for philosophical
theorizing and the proper methods for approaching philosophical
problems. But many philosophers were united in thinking, for
di erent reasons, that the methods of philosophy are incapable of
putting us in touch with theoretically interesting truths about God.
To be sure, doubts of this sort never gained a sure foothold in
Catholic universities, which maintained the theological focus
evident from their founding. But, for a variety of reasons, the
scholasticism practiced in these institutions went on in virtual
isolation from the philosophical trends dominant at the great secular
universities of Europe and America. There, doubt reigned about the
possibility of fruitful interaction between philosophy and religion.
Since philosophical theology (as we understand it) is aimed
primarily at theoretical understanding of the nature and attributes
of God, and God’s relationship to the world and things in the world,
the prevailing skepticism about our ability to learn about God
through philosophical reasoning left philosophical theology on the
wane.
The chapters in the rst part treat questions about the authority
of scripture, tradition, and the church; the nature and mechanisms
of divine revelation; and the nature of theology. We also include a
chapter on theology and mystery, a topic that we think has not yet
received its due in the analytic tradition.
NOTES
1. Wilfrid Sellars, ‘Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind’, in his
Science, Perception, and Reality (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul), 127-96, at 173.
3. We say only ‘mostly’ for two reasons. First, not everything that
would count as philosophical theology is non-empirical. G. K.
Chesterton famously remarked that the doctrine of original sin
is the one doctrine of Christianity that admits of direct
empirical veri cation. Or, more seriously, consider e.g.
Richard Swinburne’s defense of belief in the resurrection of
Jesus in The Resurrection of God Incarnate (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2003). Second, because even outside the
aforementioned Catholic institutions, a number of scholars
kept alive (though more in the popular than in the academic
realm) the great perennial questions in philosophical theology,
C. S. Lewis being the most prominent example.
11. The editors would like to thank Claire Brown for her excellent
work on the index to this volume. Her endeavours were
supported by a grant from the Institute for Scholarship in the
Liberal Arts, College of Arts and Letters, University of Notre
Dame.
PART I
THEOLOGICAL PROLEGOMENA
CHAPTER 1
RICHARD SWINBURNE
CHRISTIANITY, Islam, and Judaism all claim that God has given
humans a revelation. Divine revelation may be either of God, or by
God of propositional truth. Traditionally Christianity has claimed
that the Christian revelation has involved both of these. God
revealed himself in his acts in history; for example in the miracles
by which he preserved the people of ancient Israel, and above all by
becoming incarnate (that is human) as Jesus Christ, who was
cruci ed and rose from the dead. And God also revealed to us
propositional truths by the teaching of Jesus and his church. Some
modern theologians have denied that Christianity involves any
propositional revelation, but there can be little doubt that from the
second century (and in my view from the rst century) until the
eighteenth century, Christians and non-Christians were virtually
unanimous in supposing that it claimed to have such a revelation,
and so it is worthwhile investigating its traditional claim. It is in any
case very hard to see how it would be of great use to us for God to
reveal himself in history (e.g. in the Exodus, or in the life, death,
and resurrection of Jesus) unless we could understand the cosmic
signi cance of what happened—e.g. that Jesus was God incarnate
and that his life and death constituted an atonement for our sins.
And how are we to know that unless with the history God provides
its interpretation?
In other words, the way to nd out what the Bible meant was
not to use secular historical methods to discover the ‘original
meaning’ of the text as written of its human author. Since God was
the ultimate author of the Bible, it was what he meant the text to
mean that was its meaning as a revealed text. The Fathers did
normally suppose that the human author also understood this, but
they allowed that he might be writing something that he did not
understand. To understand what God meant by the written word,
we need to take into account God’s beliefs. We know, the Fathers
claimed, two kinds of beliefs that God has—God believes central
Christian doctrines, and God believes all truths about history and
science. (Secular science and history, when very well established,
provides us with strong evidence about God’s beliefs about the
latter.) So if anything in Scripture seems to contradict these beliefs,
they argued, it must be understood in a metaphorical way. This
result follows from normal rules for understanding a sentence of
ordinary human discourse. If someone utters some sentence which,
taken literally, they know to be false, and they know that (much of)
their audience knows to be false, then they cannot mean it to be
taken literally. If I say to others about our human friend Larry,
‘Larry is an elephant’, this must be understood metaphorically. And
so if God is the ultimate author of Scripture and its intended
audience is not merely its original hearers and readers, but the
church of many future centuries, then it must be interpreted in the
light not merely of Christian doctrine, but of future scienti c
knowledge. But the Fathers would have said, if such a possibility
had occurred to them, that in the case of a con ict as to how to
interpret a Scriptural passage between an interpretation guided by
their prior understanding of central Christian doctrines and an
interpretation guided by current established ‘scienti c knowledge’,
that the former took precedence. For God had revealed central
Christian doctrines to his church before ever the New Testament
was written; purported scienti c knowledge was fallible. But how
most scriptural passages should be interpreted was not regarded as
xed by already recognized central Christian doctrines.
One verse that all the Fathers refused to take literally on the
ground of its incompatibility with Christian moral teaching was
Psalm 137: 9 which says of the Babylon which held the Jews in
captivity, ‘Happy shall they be who take your little ones and dash
them against the rock.’ A verse from the Psalms which some of the
Fathers refused to take literally on scienti c grounds was Psalm 136:
6 which gives thanks to God ‘who spread out the earth on the
waters’ on the grounds that science showed that earth did not oat
on water.7 And in a wide sense of ‘science’ it was on scienti c
grounds that some of the Fathers rejected the literal understanding
of the Genesis 1 claim that God made the world in six days. For
there could not, they claimed, be days before the sun existed, and
Genesis claimed that the sun was created on the fourth day.
Augustine’s basic rule deriving from Origen was applied throughout
the Middle Ages. Beryl Smalley has written that ‘to write a history
of Origenist in uence on the West would be tantamount to writing a
history of Western exegesis’,8 and she could have added Eastern
exegesis as well.
What was at issue was surely which position ts best the overall
pattern of the teaching of the New Testament, whose content was
itself determined by a prior understanding of the nature of central
Christian doctrines. And the inference from scriptural passages to a
doctrinal de nition that ts best their overall pattern is not a
deductive inference. It is a probabilistic inference of a kind used by
historians of thought in their systematizations of the work of some
thinker which t most of what he is alleged to have a rmed (taken
in its most natural sense) better than any other simple account, but
which may not t all of what he is alleged to have a rmed. The
historian then deals with any such recalcitrant sentences in one of
three ways. First, he may claim that the thinker must have
understood the recalcitrant sentences in a way other than a normal
way. Secondly, he may claim that the thinker did not write these
sentences—the record is inaccurate. Or thirdly, the historian may
claim that his suggested principles t almost everything the thinker
wrote so well, that the thinker would have come to deny the
statements expressed by the recalcitrant sentences if their
incompatibility with his general viewpoint was pointed out to him.
But when dealing with the Bible, believed by con icting interpreters
to be a true record of the teaching of God, only the rst way is
available. A sentence, such as the saying of Jesus ‘the Father is
greater than I’, incompatible with one such systematization if
understood in the most natural way, was interpreted in a less
natural way than the most natural way—for example as reporting
Jesus saying that the Father was greater than Jesus in so far as Jesus
was human (that is, in his human nature).
And how was the church that had this vital role in establishing
true doctrine to be identi ed? While certainly the fact that some
ecclesial body gave the most plausible overall interpretation of the
‘deposit of faith’ was used as a criterion for determining the identity
of the church and so for which new doctrine should be adopted, the
criterion of that ecclesial body’s past approval of some plausibly
derived doctrine could not be used as the sole test for the identity of
the church without hopeless circularity. There was a further
criterion recognized by all. An ecclesial body was the church in so
far as it had continuity of organization with the apostolic church:
that is, in so far as its church leaders were commissioned by other
church leaders and so on back to the apostles. Again there were
di erences about the kind of commissioning required. (Did bishops
need to be ordained by bishops? Was the recognition of a bishop’s
authority by the Pope required for that authority to be legitimate?)
But all agreed that some body was only part of the church in so far
as it had some continuity with the apostolic church.
II
Christian doctrines about what God is like and how he has acted
have come to us through the church’s tradition of interpreting
Scripture, and without the historical process I have described in
section I there would be no Christian doctrines to assess. But why
should we believe these doctrines to be true? No doubt in the case
of some of them there are considerations of pure reason that make it
to some extent probable that the doctrines are true. For example we
might expect a God who saw us su ering to become incarnate
(become a human) in order to show solidarity with us by sharing
our su ering. But such a priori reasoning seldom seems conclusive;
and it will not in any case tell us where and when any divine actions
were done, for example in which human God became incarnate. God
needs to reveal these truths to us. So the question remains why, if at
all, we are justi ed in believing that Scripture interpreted in a
certain way is God’s revelation. For anyone’s belief in Christian
doctrines depends in large measure on such a belief.
It follows from all this that the fact that a doctrine has been
developed by the church through the process of derivation from
Scripture described in section I, which the church recognized as the
proper process for this, is substantial reason for supposing that that
doctrine is true. So Scripture turns out to have an authority far
greater than that of a normal historical source. (I believe that the
apparatus of the calculus of probability can be used to elucidate the
structure of the above historical argument, and gives us reason to
suppose that that argument gives a high probability to the truth of
Christian doctrines. In Warranted Christian Belief23 Alvin Plantinga
produced an argument from ‘dwindling probabilities’ purporting to
show that a historical argument of the type I have produced will
give only a fairly low probability to Christian doctrines. In an
Appendix to the second edition of Revelation, I claim that Plantinga’s
argument based on his criticism of the rst edition of that book
misunderstands my argument, and is not cogent.)
If, however, God (or any other intentional agent) did not create
us (and Plantinga is seeking an account of warrant that does not
presuppose that God created us), then there is a big problem about
how (1) is to be understood. For Evolution (or any other inanimate
cause) is not an agent who has intentions (despite the incautious
talk by some biologists about our organs having ‘design plans’). The
only sense I can give to claims that Evolution ‘meant’ something to
function in a certain way, or that it ‘designed’ it to function in a
certain environment or to produce certain beliefs, is that it caused it
to function in that way in that environment so as to produce those
beliefs. So cognitive faculties function properly if they function in
the way Evolution causes them to function; their design plan is
‘aimed’ at the production of true beliefs only in so far as it does
produce true beliefs in that environment; and an environment is
‘su ciently similar’ to that for which the faculties were ‘designed’
only in so far as they produce true beliefs equally well in that new
environment. And so the whole edi ce collapses on to (4): a belief is
warranted if it is produced by cognitive faculties in an environment
in which they produce true beliefs as frequently as in their original
environment in which they produced mostly true beliefs. This is a
form of simple reliabilism—and the normal form of reliabilism that
is open to the generality problem, for there is no creator’s ‘intention’
by which the type of ‘cognitive faculty’ and the ‘environment’ in
which it was originally reliable can be selected from the whole
range of other types of cognitive faculty and types of environment
to which the token process and the token environment in which it
originally operated belong. (Is the cognitive faculty ‘perception’ or
‘vision’? Is the environment the earth, or merely a particular human
community? And so on.)
NOTES
4. Epistolae 4. 31.
25. For his general theory of warrant, see Alvin Plantinga, Warrant:
The Current Debate and Warrrant and Proper Function (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1993). In the text I summarize
Plantinga’s summary of his theory, ibid. 194. For Plantinga’s
application of his theory to Christian doctrines, see his
Warranted Christian Belief (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2000).
30. I discuss the kind of ‘faith’ necessary for salvation, and how
this di ers from belief, in my Faith and Reason, 2nd edn.
(Oxford: Clarendon, 2005).
CHAPTER 2
STEPHEN T. DAVIS
II
What is the purpose of divine revelation? It is to achieve God’s aims
in creation. Pre-eminently, God desires that human beings freely
love, worship, and obey God, and (as the answer to Question 1 of
the Westminster Shorter Catechism says), ‘enjoy him forever’.
Revelation, then, is not primarily for the purpose of imparting
information, issuing commands, or initiating ceremonies, although it
does all those things. Revelation exists for the essential purpose of
establishing a personal and loving relationship between God and
human beings.
• What are the consequences of glorifying God, and what are the
consequences of not doing so?
Thus there are many things that human beings do not naturally
know or at least cannot easily come to know on their own and that
they must know, if God’s aims are to be realized (1 Cor. 15: 1–4;
Heb. 11: 6; 1 John 1: 1–3). Accordingly, one of the things that God
must do is nd a way to answer these and other questions.
III
There are many ways in which God might choose to reveal a given
message (let’s call it M) to some human being (let’s say Jones). Here
are a few: (1) God might create Jones in such a way as to be
naturally disposed to believe M. (2) God might telepathically cause
Jones to think or come to believe or at least cognitively entertain M.
(3) God might appoint someone as a spokesperson and cause that
person to say or write M to Jones. (4) God might cause Jones to
dream M. (5) God might miraculously bring it about that Jones sees
M written on a wall. (6) God might do some non-linguistic deed or
action whose proper interpretation or deep meaning is M.
It does seem, a priori, that there are both values and problems in
either approach. Actions are sometimes more impressive, powerful,
gripping, and graphic than words. Just saying that you love your
spouse or child is typically less convincing than showing it. Yet the
problem with revelatory actions is that they seem more readily
susceptible to being misinterpreted, changed in the retelling of
them, and (unless they are written down) forgotten over time.
Perhaps words are often less powerful than deeds; but revelatory
words are valuable because they are not quite so easily
misinterpreted, are easier to preserve and pass on, and once
preserved are not quite so easily forgotten. These last two points are
important given God’s redemptive aims, i.e. given the assumption
that God would intend at least some revelations to be for the bene t
of other folk beside the original receivers or witnesses (see Psalm
22: 29–31).
IV
The text that Christians call the Bible is in part a record and
interpretation of original revelation. By reading the Bible it is
possible to learn some of what God has done in the past. Much of
what the biblical writers recorded need not have been
supernaturally revealed to them—doubtless they learned about
some of the events and words that they recorded by quite ordinary
means. The standard Christian claim is that recorded revelation, like
original revelation, ceased long ago—when the last book of the
Bible was completed. Since then presumably other Christian
writings—sermons, hymns, liturgies, creeds, and perhaps even
theological essays—were written under God’s in uence.
Pronouncements of some of the early ecumenical councils have, in
my view, a certain degree of normativity for Christians. But, as a
Protestant, I do not hold that they are theologically authoritative for
all Christians in the same sense that the Bible is.11
The much wider claim that the writers of the texts that we call
the Bible were so guided that what they wrote was what the Spirit
of God would have them write is called inspiration. Traditionally,
inspiration has to do with the in uence of the Holy Spirit on the
writers of the Bible so that what they wrote was, in some sense, the
word of God. Several of the biblical writers were convinced that
inspiration occurs. In 1 Corinthians 2: 9–15, Paul quoted an Old
Testament text, and then said: ‘These things God has revealed to us
through the Spirit.’ And 2 Peter 1: 20–1 speaks of scriptural
prophecy in this way: ‘No prophecy ever came by human will, but
men and women moved by the Holy Spirit spoke from God.’
But serious di culties face those who wish to write about this
topic. Most of them fall under this heading: the notion of inspiration
must t the kind of document that the Bible actually is.21 First, an
acceptable notion of inspiration must t the fact that while some
biblical writers (e.g. Paul, the Old Testament prophets) were at
times conscious of having a ‘word’ from God, others were not. Some
biblical writers seem to have been conscious simply of having
gathered information from various sources, and some of those
sources were incomplete or defective.22 Second, an acceptable
notion of inspiration must t the fact that in the Bible there are
distinct traditions about the same events and discrepancies between
them.23 There are not just numerical and historical discrepancies,
and not just apparently misidenti ed or misinterpreted quotations of
the Old Testament in the New Testament. There are also theological
discrepancies, or at least apparent ones. Third, an acceptable notion
of inspiration must t the fact that some biblical books had a long
history of composition and that the very notion of ‘the author’ is
irrelevant.
6. Secular inspiration. Although this theory does not fall under the
prophetic model of inspiration, there is another possibility along the
route that we have been roughly traveling from stronger to less
robust theories. Possibly the Bible is an entirely human book and, so
far as origin is concerned, there is no intrinsic di erence between
the Bible and any other book. To the extent that biblical inspiration
occurred at all (and some liberal Protestants reject the notion
entirely), perhaps the writers of the Bible were ‘inspired’ in some
sense not unlike the way the writers of great but entirely secular
books were inspired. Perhaps God uses the book called the Bible for
religious purposes more than God uses other books; perhaps the
church accepts the Bible as more authoritative than other books; but
there was no special divine in uence on the writings of the Bible
per se. The reasons usually given for abandoning robust notions of
inspiration are (1) the discrepancies in the Bible, and (2) the fact
that the Bible seems to speak approvingly of such practices as
slavery, the oppression of women, mass murder, the torture of
prisoners, and polygamy.31
VII
The Bible is thus the means of biblical inspiration rather than its
locus or terminus. Biblical inspiration depends on the faith
perspective of the reader of the Bible; it is the way in which a
believer or Christian community recognizes the indispensable role of
the Bible in redemption. Trembath admits that inspiration is not
totally independent of the words of the Bible, ‘but neither is it a
property which applies exhaustively to those words’. The phrase
‘biblical inspiration’, he says, is an abbreviated reference to ‘the
experience of salvation by God through Christ as mediated through
the Bible’ (p. 111; see also p. 62).
Few Christians will allow that there was no such process. For if
not, the Bible will have no special status among the world’s books
apart from the functional point about its having shaped the
Christian experience of salvation more than any other book. Yet
even if we grant that the Bible has this unique functional status for
the church, the question remains whether it has any special
ontological status. Is it or is it not intrinsically di erent from other
books? Is the Bible, in and of itself, unique? After all, some people
have been powerfully moved by The Iliad or The Apology or Anna
Karenina. And some people’s experience of Christian salvation has
been powerfully shaped by the Summa Theologica or The Institutes of
the Christian Religion or Mere Christianity.
VIII
IX
Let us return to the point that the various books of the Bible
seem to have reached their nal form in di erent ways, and that
several such books had no one human author. In such cases, if
biblical inspiration is to make any sense, it must be that several
people were inspired, i.e. the Holy Spirit in uenced more than one
person. Perhaps inspiration a ected, say, the original prophetic
speaker (ensuring that the prophet spoke the words God intended to
reveal), the nal editor (assuming that this is a di erent person) of
the biblical book (ensuring that what it says is appropriate for God’s
purposes for it), and perhaps other people between them.
NOTES
14. Ancient Israel was similarly puzzled over its election as God’s
people. In Deuteronomy 7: 7–8a, the best explanation that
they could nd was a kind of tautology: God loved Israel
because God loved Israel.
19. This point is well argued in W. S. Anglin, Free Will and Christian
Faith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), 187–92.
21. See Raymond Brown, The Critical Meaning of the Bible (New
York: Paulist Press, 1981), 7–14.
22. See James Orr, Revelation and Inspiration (Grand Rapids: Baker
Book House, 1969; original edn. London: Duckworth & Co.,
1910), 164–5, 179–81.
25. For a discussion of it, see Robert Gnuse, The Authority of the
Bible (New York: Paulist Press, 1985), 42–6.
26. Craig’s Theory is found in his ‘“Men Moved by the Holy Spirit
Spoke from God” (2 Peter 1: 21): A Middle Knowledge
Perspective on Biblical Inspiration’, Philosophia Christi, ser 2,
1/1(1999), 45–82.
DEL RATZSCH
INTRODUCTION
THE natural sciences have profoundly shaped modern life and have
notoriously generated challenges for religious belief—even being
credited by some with having destroyed religion’s rational
defensibility. Most people, however, see both science and religion as
having important truths to tell us, and try to t both into a coherent
world-view. Among that wider group, some see science and religion
as occupying separate, isolated territories, with any alleged con icts
resulting from failure to respect proper boundaries, while others see
varying relationships and legitimate (or illegitimate) interactions
between the two. The competing views arise from a history, of
course—a history widely misconstrued.
Brief History
PROVISIONAL TYPOLOGIES
B. Con ict (or warfare): Science and religion operate in the same
(or overlapping) domains, make con icting claims and/or demands.
At most one of the two is rationally legitimate, their basic con icts
being ultimately irreconcilable. A person cannot, with competence
and integrity, be a practitioner of both.
Independence (Separation)
The popular cultural perception is that religion has not fared well in
its contacts with science, and it is commonly suspected that
religion’s problem has resulted from attempts to speak in areas
where it has no rightful authority or competence. But (on
Independence views) were science and religion to stay in their
appropriate domains, there would be no problem. The only issue
would involve locating the relevant boundaries and identifying what
lay within each.
There are indeed religious issues that appear to have no overlap
with any scienti c issues and vice versa. But Independence does not
seem adequate as a general position. For one thing, as indicated
earlier, not only were science and religion not independent
historically, but had they been, the early history of science might
have been quite di erent—and not in a positive way. For another,
no one knows how to delineate hard boundaries to science (or
religion)—demarcation issues being as intractable as ever.
[T]here were three things above all for which I sought the cause as
to why it was this way and not another—the number, the
dimensions, and the motions of the orbs. I have dared to carry out
this search because of the beautiful correspondence of the immobile
Sun, the xed stars, and the intermediate space with God the Father,
the Son, and the Holy Spirit.6
Methodological Naturalism
and
Complementarity
and that
Boundaries
Once the barriers are lowered and science and religion are
construed as potential competitors in the same (explanatory) tasks
in the same arena, interaction and con ict become very real—some
would say inevitable—possibilities. There is naturally disagreement
over who gets eviscerated in such con ict, but some cautions are in
order. First, con ict of content requires realist conceptions of both
science and religion. (Realist views in this context are, roughly,
those according to which truths and entities of the relevant sorts do
exist, that discovering truths involving such entities constitutes an
important aim, and that such truths or something near to them are
sometimes actually secured.) Thus, neither non-realist views of
science nor non-realist views of religion will serve the con ict
thesis.13 Second, neither outdated history and philosophy of science
nor uninformed views of religion will do. Much of the perception of
historical con ict is sheer invention. The loci classici for that
perception (for instance Draper’s and White’s books14) are polemics
with ‘history’ manipulated or manufactured to match
preconceptions. And some purveyors of more recent popular screeds
on science and religion have exhibited equal ‘respect’ for historical
fact when it stands in the way of preconception.15 Of course, the
mere fact of science/religion con ict would not reveal which side
was mistaken. Sorting that out would take further work.
Foundations
Various commentators claim that science rests upon a
presupposition of philosophical naturalism, note that that contradicts
the belief of most religions in supernaturalism, and conclude that
the very project of science is ‘diametrically opposed’ to any religious
belief worth its salt.17
then
c. arguing that such causes/sources, so aimed, cannot provide
rational justi cation for the beliefs generated.
But making a case here requires showing that the alleged source
is the actual source, is not aimed at truth, is thus unreliable, etc.
None is trivial, and Freud failed miserably on the rst at least. More
recently, there have been a number of attempts to defeat the
rational legitimacy of religious belief by citing evolutionary theory
as fully explaining the emergence, and/or the preservation, of
religious beliefs. Explanatory proposals vary. For instance, some
argue that religious belief is/was just an evolutionary spandrel,19
with no special evolutionary upside.20 Others, e.g. David Sloan
Wilson, argue that religion was preserved for its group-selective
advantages,21 while Daniel Dennett argues that religion in the form
of early animism arose out of a Hyperactive Agent Detection Device
(HADD), and served tness by making the welter of experiences of
nature not only cognitively more manageable but even
predictable.22
[F]or over two centuries religion has been on the defensive …The
period has been one of unprecedented intellectual progress…Each
such [advance] has found the religious thinkers unprepared.
Something which has been proclaimed to be [theologically] vital,
has nally, after struggle, distress, and anathema, been modi ed
and otherwise interpreted…The…continuous repetition of this
undigni ed retreat, during many generations, has at last almost
entirely destroyed the intellectual authority of religious thinkers.26
On this view, the bits and pieces that have crumbled away from the
religious conceptual scheme might not individually have been
essential to religious belief, but over the longer haul they constitute
a dismal track record of serial failure.
More generally, there still are gaps in our scienti c pictures, and
it takes a-historical hubris (or massively undersupported
philosophically avored induction) to claim that science has, does,
can, or ever will explain everything having to do with the cosmos.
Recurrent claims that we nally have in hand all necessary
materials for completing the scienti c picture have just as
recurrently failed. Moreover, Kuhn argued that revolutionary
advances sometimes reopen scienti c issues previously thought to be
settled. Closed gaps may thus be an unstable launching platform for
critiques.
b. Randomness. It has also been claimed that the key role played
by randomness in such central theories as evolution and quantum
mechanics undermines the religiously central doctrine that the
cosmos, life, and humans are products of deliberate purpose. That
claim does not stand up to scrutiny,28 and in fact (as will emerge
later) the very randomness alleged to be religiously problematic can
serve some theologically important functions.
Styles of Rationality
Deeper Integration
Among the scholars who suggest this deeper Integration picture are
theologian Thomas Torrance and philosopher Roy Clouser. I shall
brie y describe Clouser’s view in order to provide a glimpse of what
such a theory might look like.
WIDER PICTURES
CONCLUSION
All this inter-infusion conjoined with the lack of absolute boundaries
between science and non-science means that science/religion issues
will not be the clean, simple, no-strings-dangling phenomenon many
would like them to be. There is unlikely to be any single elegant, all-
encompassing solution—at least any available to us humans. Just as
there may be aspects of nature forever beyond our cognitive
capacities, just as there may be religious facts forever beyond our
understanding, some facets of the actual relationship between
science and religion may be forever beyond us as well. There may
always be tensions and loose ends. But that is true in nearly every
human endeavor—whether involving science, religion, theology,
philosophy, or world-views. Indeed, given human history,
propensities, and nitude, the slick tidiness of any proposed
science/religion resolution (or dissolution) is very probably
legitimate cause for epistemological alarm.
NOTES
10. J. Wentzel van Huyssteen employs this phrase more than once
in Duet or Duel: Theology and Science in a Postmodern World
(Harrisburg: Trinity), e.g. 56, 77. Many others, e.g. Alan G.
Padgett, Science and the Study of God (Grand Rapids:
Eerdmans, 2003), 81, concur.
14. J. W. Draper, History of the Con ict Between Religion and Science
(1875), and A. D. White, History of the Warfare of Science with
Theology in Christendom (1896).
15. The Galileo, Scopes, Bruno, and other frequently cited cases
contain in their currently popular versions vast quantities of
invention.
18. Although I will not pursue the issue here, some argue that
there are—or can be—non-supernaturalistic religions.
Buddhism is sometimes cited as an example, and some
philosophers argue for the possibility of an ‘anthropic theism’
involving a ‘deity’ who while powerful, knowing, etc., is
wholly natural (see e.g. Peter Forrest, God without the
Supernatural: A Defense of Scienti c Theism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell,
1996). However, I am restricting discussion to
supernaturalistic systems.
24. See his 3 July 1881 letter to William Graham, in The Life and
Letters of Charles Darwin, ed. Francis Darwin (New York: n.p.,
1889).
34. Panentheists disagree about what the view is. The basic
description is: ‘the world is in God, but does not exhaust God’.
But the ‘in’ is metaphorical, with no agreement on what the
metaphor means. In discussing God’s relation to and action in
the world, panentheists often use the analogy of the world
being ‘God’s body’—God’s action in the world being analogous
to the human mind’s relation to the human body.
37. John Haught, Science and Religion, e.g. 4, 18. Others, including
e.g. Clayton, Polking-horne, van Huyssteen, and Peacocke,
often sound like this.
40. Ibid. 4.
43. e.g. Serious Talk, 53–4;id., Quarks, Chaos, and Christianity (New
York: Crossroads, 1994), 71. Polkinghorne in some places
seems a bit ambivalent about this view.
53. See e.g. J. M. Schwartz and S. Begley, The Mind and the Brain
(New York: Regan, 2002), 67 ., and Pinker, 371 ., for
discussion.
57. Sir Denys Haig Wilkinson, ‘The Quarks and Captain Ahab’,
Schi Memorial Lecture, Stanford, 1977.
58. There are exceptions on both ends. For the former see e.g.
Andrew Pickering, in Constructing Quarks (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1984), and for the latter see e.g. Richard
Dawkins, Peter Atkins, et al.
60. Imre Lakatos, Larry Laudan, et al. have led important parts of
the charge here.
WILLIAM J. WAINWRIGHT
And John Toland asserts that Christian theologians and priests have
gone even further than the hierophants of the ancient mystery cults.
The latter swore their initiates to secrecy but their mysteries were
intelligible in themselves. Only Christians dared maintain that their
doctrines were mysterious in a more radical sense, ‘that is,
inconceivable in themselves, however clearly revealed’.2
Hume’s and Toland’s explanations of this phenomenon di er.3
Whatever one thinks of their explanations, however, there is little
doubt that the appeal to, and adoration of, mystery is a
characteristic feature of much Christian thought and practice. The
Pseudo-Dionysius, for example, begins his Mystical Theology by
asking the Trinity to guide him to the ‘most exalted’ and hidden
secrets of Scripture ‘which exceedeth light and more than exceedeth
knowledge, where…the mysteries of heavenly truth lie hidden in the
dazzling obscurity of the secret silence, outshining all brilliance with
the intensity of their darkness’.4
suppose…we forget Paul and the prophets for the moment, [and]
mount up to the heavens…Do you think that the angels in heaven
talk over and ask each other questions about the divine essence? By
no means! What are the angels doing? They give glory to God, they
adore him, they chant without ceasing their triumphal and mystical
hymns with a deep feeling of religious awe. Some sing: ‘Glory to
God in the highest;’ the seraphim chant: ‘Holy, holy, holy,’ and they
turn away their eyes because they cannot endure God’s presence as
he comes down to adapt himself to them in
condescension. (Chrysostom 65–6)
II
Alston o ers four reasons for what he calls the ‘Divine Mystery
Thesis’, namely, that ‘God is inevitably so mysterious to us, to our
rational capacities…that nothing we can think, believe, or say about
him is strictly true of God as he is in himself.’ These reasons include
the experiences of the great Christian mystics and the doctrine of
simplicity to which I shall turn in a moment. The others are, rst,
‘the puzzles, paradoxes, and insoluble problems which theological
thought [about the Trinity, for example] seems so frequently to
lead’; and, second, our limited capacities: ‘If we think about the
relation of human cognitive powers to the absolutely in nite source
of all that is other than itself, it seems reasonable to suppose that
the former would not be in a position to get an account of the latter
that is exactly correct, even in certain abstract respects’21 (Alston
100–1). Or as Edwards argues: ‘A very great superiority, even in
beings of the same nature as ourselves’, makes many of their
actions, intentions, and assertions ‘incomprehensible and attended
with inexplicable intricacies’. Witness the relation that ‘little
children’ bear to ‘adult persons’, for example, or the ‘vulgar’ to
‘learned men, [or] great philosophers and mathematicians’. God ‘is
in nitely diverse from and above all in his nature’, however. So if
God vouchsafes a revelation of himself (of his triune nature, say)
‘which is entirely diverse [not only] from anything we do now
experience in our present state, but from anything that we can be
conscious or immediately sensible of in any state whatsoever that
our nature can be in, then especially may mysteries be expected in
such a revelation’.22
According to John the Scot, for example, God knows himself but
does not know what he is. John’s reasons for this are essentially
these: to know what God is, one would have to grasp God’s essence;
God ‘is not essence’, though, ‘but More than Essence and the in nite
Cause of all essences, and not only in nite but the In nity of all
in nite essence, and More than in nity’. God is beyond essence
because essences are the sorts of thing that can be captured or
expressed in de nitions, and de nitions proceed by marking out a
thing’s boundaries. God has no boundaries, however, since he is
in nite or limitless. Not even God, then, can know what God is. But
this does not imply that God is ignorant (because ‘He does not
understand of Himself what He is’) nor does it imply that God is
impotent (because ‘He is unable to de ne His Substance’). For God
has no what.24 Nor does it imply that ‘God does not know himself’,
or know himself as in nite, and as indeed ‘above every nite thing
and every in nite thing and beyond nitude and in nity’.25 (John
the Scot, Bk. 2. 585A-590D).
John’s case for the claim that God has no essence or ‘what’
depends on the following subargument. If a de nition is to succeed
in distinguishing its de niendum from other things, it must exclude
the item being de ned from other things. An ‘absolutely in nite’
God would exclude nothing, however, since if it did exclude
something, it would have limits and thus not be ‘absolutely in nite
(or limitless).
In Proslogion 15, Anselm exclaims: ‘Lord, not only are you that
than which a greater cannot be thought, but you are also something
greater than can be thought. For since it is possible to think that
there is such a one, if you were not this same being something
greater than you could be thought—which cannot be.’28
Being such that one cannot think it is not itself a perfection if for
no other reason than because our inability to think something
(adequately capture it in concepts) may be a function of its
imperfection. Plato’s Receptacle, or Aristotle’s or Plotinus’s hyle, are
examples.31 Again, a thing might be too complicated or too hidden
for our intellects to comprehend it. The true nature of the physical
universe might be an example. It doesn’t follow that its
impenetrability to nite intellects is a good-making feature of it.
III
At one extreme are the views of deists such as Charles Blount who
assert that ‘that rule which is necessary for our future happiness
ought to be generally made known to all men…Therefore, no
revealed religion’, with its attendant mysteries, ‘is necessary for
human happiness.’35 John Toland and other deists think that,
because God’s perfection entails his ‘justice and reasonableness’,
‘nothing in true Christianity…is either contrary to or above reason
…Nothing in true Christianity’, therefore, ‘can be a mystery—a
proposition or notion impenetrable to ordinary, human intellectual
capacities.’36
At the other extreme lies Pierre Bayle who professes faith in the
Christian mysteries but insists on their contra-rationality. The
doctrine of the Trinity, for example, contradicts the self-evident
principle that if x = y and y = z then x = y = z, for any x, y, and
z. And more generally, ‘there is a clear incompatibility between
accepting the Cartesian standard of clarity and distinctness’, which
Bayle believes to be appropriate in philosophy, ‘and accepting the
Christian doctrine [s]…Mysteries…are necessarily non-evident’.37
Hence, while faith ‘produces a perfect certitude…its object will
never be evident. Knowledge, on the other hand, produces together
both complete evidence of the object and full certitude of
conviction.’ So ‘if a Christian…undertakes to maintain the mystery
of the Trinity’, for instance, ‘against a philosopher, he would oppose
a non-evident object to evident objections’.38
IV
But suppose that we grant that the veil between God and ourselves
cannot be removed in this life. Will we, indeed, can we, behold God
unveiled in the next? Some texts suggest that we will. Paul, for
example, asserts that while ‘we now see only puzzling re ections in
a mirror, we shall then see face to face’. Our ‘knowledge now is
partial’ but ‘then it will be whole, like God’s knowledge of me’ (1
Corinthians 13: 12). Does the beati c vision, then, include an
unclouded vision of God’s essence? Some Christian theologians, at
least, have thought not.65
NOTES
19. Rudolf Otto, The Idea of the Holy, trans. John W. Harvey
(NewYork: Oxford University Press, 1958), 26.
23. Thomas Aquinas, On the Truth of the Catholic Faith, Book Four:
Salvation, trans. Charles J. O’Neil (Garden City: Doubleday,
1957), 35–7, my emphasis. While the general thrust of this
passage is clear enough, it does raise an important question to
which we will return later. For if God ‘improportionately’
transcends all nite things, as Aquinas says, why think that
freedom from connection with sensibles will be su cient to
remove the mystery or darkness that surrounds God ‘s nature?
24. So there is nothing God has that God doesn’t know, and no task
that someone could perform (such as de ning God’s essence)
that God cannot do.
25. The idea here is presumably this. Finitude and in nity contrast
with, and hence circumscribe, each other. An in nite line or
quantity isn’t a nite line or quantity, and vice versa, and is, in
that sense, limited. In nite lines or quantities are thus only
limitless in certain respects. God, by contrast, is limitless in all
respects.
27. John’s claim that God has no essence also rests upon the
traditional notion that a good de nition states a thing’s genus
and di erentia and/or proceeds by locating the de niendum
within the Aristotelian categories. If God is simple and/or
transcends the Aristotelian categories, then neither of these
requirements can be met. What is unclear, however, is just
why de nitions must meet either of these requirements. Does
‘God = df. a being greater than which none can be thought’
do so, for example? I doubt that it does, but a traditionalist
could reply that it doesn’t capture God’s essence either and, for
that reason, isn’t a so-called ‘real de nition’.
28. Anselm, St. Anselm’s Proslogion, with a Reply on Behalf of the
Fool by Gaunilo and the Author’s Reply to Gaunilo, trans. M. J.
Charlesworth (Oxford: Clarendon, 1965), 137.
30. Ibid.189.
32. Not only is God’s joy or happiness greater than any nite joy or
happiness, no nite joy or happiness is half as great, or two-
thirds as great, or almost as great as God’s.
34. Strictly speaking, the latter two cases are also cases in which
being greater than can be thought is a consequence of God ‘s
rst-order properties. For (as we saw in n. 33), since God’s
simplicity depends on his rst-order properties, so too does the
property of being greater than can be thought which is a
consequence of it; and mystery, in Rahner’s view, is
presumably a rst-order property of the divine essence (?).
36. Byrne, ibid. 54, 71. Toland allowed that revelation might be a
‘source’ of true propositions but insisted that ‘once such truths
come to my notice by revelation’, they must pass the bar of
human reason, i.e. I must be able to make out their truth for
myself on the basis of publicly available evidence. More
radical questioners of revealed religion refused to grant ‘even
this limited role to’ tradition since doing so would preclude
some people from salvation (those who lived before the
decisive moment or kairos, for example) (ibid. 72–4).
But even if God’s justice and reasonableness were to
preclude his making human salvation depend on assent to
mystery, why should it preclude either the possibility that
certain truths about him are irreducibly mysterious or his
communicating those truths to us? Perhaps it wouldn’t. But
the deists’ con dence in the transparency of a just and
reasonable religion doesn’t comport well with either the
existence or communication of irreducibly mysterious truths.
In any case, if knowledge of them isn’t necessary for salvation,
then (from the deists’ point of view) their communication is
super uous at best and, at worst, a distraction from what is
truly important.
40. Ibid.56–9.
41. For a related objection see Toland: ‘The very supposition, that
reason might authorize one thing, and the Spirit of God
[Scripture] another, throws us into inevitable skepticism. For
if contradictions can be true, the authority of reason is called
into question. And if the authority of reason is called into
question, then so too is the authority of Scripture since the
latter rests on the former. ‘We believe the Scripture to be
divine, not upon its own bare assertion [or upon an inner
impulse or intuition, or the so-called testimony of the Holy
Spirit], but from a real testimony consisting in the evidence of
the thing contained therein; from undoubted e ects, and not
from words and letters’ (Toland 30, 32). We believe Scripture,
in other words, because what it tells us—that God exists, that
we are immortal, that the best o ering we can give God is a
moral life—is intrinsically evident to reason. However
inadequate this account of the authority of Scripture may be,
Toland has put his thumb on a real problem. For calling
reason’s authority into question undercuts any attempt to o er
rational arguments for relying on Scripture, including not only
standard appeals to miracles, ful lled prophecy, and so on, but
also existential or pragmatic arguments such as Bayle’s.
42. Toland’s rst response is this: to the claim that while doctrines
such as the Trinity are indeed ‘not contrary to sound reason…
no man’s reason is sound’, Toland objects that even though the
reason of most people is indeed unsound, the de facto defects
of human reason can be remedied without divine assistance.
For we can learn to ‘compare ideas, distinguish clear from
obscure conceptions, suspend our judgments about
uncertainties, and yield only to evidence’ (Toland 57, 60). One
may reasonably doubt whether these measures are su cient to
restore an impaired or fallen intellect, however. They clearly
are not if, as I have argued elsewhere, a rightly disposed heart
is needed to reason rightly about religion and other value-
laden matters. See my Reason and the Heart: A Prolegomena to a
Critique of Passional Reason (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press, 1995).
51. As we shall see, e.g. John Chrysostom clearly thinks that God’s
essence can’t be known by even the most exalted of creatures.
The cherubim and seraphim themselves know God only by
‘ gures’.
65. Or, more cautiously, have said things that imply that it doesn’t.
66. Thomas Aquinas, de Potentia, q. 7 a. 5. Quoted in Karl Rahner,
‘The Concept of Mystery in Catholic Theology’, Theological
Investigations (New York: Seabury, 1974), iv. 58–9 (henceforth
Rahner).
67. Namely, that our minds are ‘not proportionate to the divine
substance’.
80. See e.g. the eucharistic hymn adapted from the Liturgy of St
James that begins ‘Let all mortal esh keep silence and with
fear and trembling stand.’
81. On the whole, because God presumably isn’t ‘numbed’ or
‘chilled’ by the sight of his own being.
DIVINE ATTRIBUTES
CHAPTER 5
JEFFREY E. BRQWER
In this chapter, I take the rst steps necessary for restoring the
doctrine of divine simplicity to its former glory, arguing that its
widespread rejection in contemporary philosophy and theology is
certainly premature, perhaps ultimately unwarranted. There can be
no question that this doctrine comes with substantial and
controversial commitments in metaphysics. But in each case, I shall
argue, these commitments are perfectly respectable, having been
ably defended and taken very seriously on independent grounds in
the contemporary literature. If my argument is successful, it will be
clear that this doctrine—together with the conception of divine
aseity that traditionally motivates it—deserves more attention than
it has yet received at the hands of contemporary philosophers and
theologians.
A human being cannot be his justice, though he can have his justice.
For the same reason, a just human being is not understood as being
his justice (existens iustitia), but as having his justice. By contrast, it
is not properly said that the supreme nature has its justice, but is its
justice. Hence when the supreme nature is called just, it is properly
understood as being its justice, rather than as having its justice.12
(Monologion 16)
But we are not quite out of the woods yet. For as we have seen, the
problem of contingency arises for ascriptions of contingent divine
knowledge as well as volition. Initially, the problem here might
seem no more worrisome than in the case of divine volition. Just as
we can treat predications involving contingent divine volition as
extrinsic, so too it might seem that we can do the same in the case
of contingent divine knowledge. Consider a speci c instance of the
type mentioned at G7 above:
The truth of a predication like G7a would seem to require only two
things: (1) that God stand in a certain cognitive relation to the
contingent truth that human beings exist; and (2) that human beings
do in fact exist. But if that’s right, then predications such as G7a will
be extrinsic after all. And assuming our treatment of this sort of
predication generalizes, we would appear to have a general solution
to the problem of contingency for divine knowledge as well as for
divine volition.37
But note that there is a question that arises here that does not
arise for our treatment of divine volition—one that has to do with
the consistency of this account with divine aseity. For whether or
not predications such as G7a are extrinsic, they appear to make God
dependent on something distinct from himself—namely, the objects
of his contingent knowledge. After all, if God knows that human
beings exist, he seems to know this because they exist.
(G7b) God knows that Smith is freely choosing to mow his lawn.
(G7c) God knows that Smith would freely choose to mow his lawn, if
created and placed in his current circumstances.
And here we seem to run up against a predication whose truth really
does violate divine aseity. For what Smith would freely do, if
created and placed in various circumstances, is generally taken by
Molinists to be a brute contingent truth about Smith (or better,
about Smith’s individual essence, which is an abstract object
existing independently of God). Evidently, therefore, the truth of
G7c, and hence the truth of G7b, ultimately requires God to be
dependent on something distinct from himself.38
4. CONCLUSION
My aim in this chapter has been to show that the doctrine of divine
simplicity deserves further consideration than it has yet received
from contemporary philosophers and theologians. If I have achieved
my aim, it will be clear that the standard objections to this doctrine
can all be answered: the doctrine is neither incoherent nor
incompatible with contingent divine volition and knowledge. Of
course, this by itself does not give us reason to accept the doctrine
as true. But it does, I hope, go considerable distance toward showing
its acceptability. Moreover, insofar as negative attitudes toward
simplicity have contributed to the neglect of the considerations
motivating it historically, I hope that my defense will also
encourage their reevaluation. Contemporary philosophers and
theologians often reject traditional views about divine aseity
precisely because they lead to the doctrine of divine simplicity. But
this is a mistake. Indeed, quite apart from simplicity, such views
deserve our attention insofar as they lie at the very heart of the
traditional theism, which is still widely taken for granted, both by
those who follow Anselm in thinking of God as ‘that than which
nothing greater can be conceived’ and by those who follow Aquinas
in thinking of him as ‘that which explains all motion, change, and
contingency’.
NOTES
5. Summa Theologiae 1. 2. 3.
7. Again, cf. Plantinga 1980 for the locus classicus for this sort of
objection.
10. Cf. e.g. Leftow 1999; Mann 1982, 1983; Rogers 1996; Stump
and Kretzmann 1985; Vallicella 1992.
11. It is sometimes suggested that these expressions could refer to
states of a airs—that is, to the exempli cation of the
properties by their subjects (cf. Plantinga 1980). But this
suggestion is of little use, from the point of view of divine
simplicity, since identifying God with a state of a airs seems
just as absurd as identifying him with a property. For further
discussion, cf. Brower 2008.
15. This answer is apparently one whose time has come. Cf. e.g.
Bergmann and Brower 2006; Pruss forthcoming; and Oppy
2003. For a defense of the claim that truthmakers are not only
su cient, but also necessary for making sense of divine
simplicity, cf. Brower 2008.
18. Here I follow Rodriguez-Pereyra 2002: 34, who argues that the
best we can do is to say that an entity E is a truthmaker for a
predication P if and only if E is an entity in virtue of which P is
true, and then illustrate what we mean by ‘being true in virtue
of’ with examples.
24. Cf. Fox 1987 for defense of the claim that medieval
philosophers operate within some form of truthmaker account
of predication. Cf. Klima 2004 for a defense of the claim that
they also typically adopt some form of trope theory of
properties.
27. Cf. e.g. Bigelow 1988: 128–34 and Lewis 2001 for an account
in terms of the super-venience of truth on being.
28. Cf. e.g. Armstrong 1997 and Rodriguez-Pereyra 2005.
29. Again, once we’ve ruled out the possibility of their referring to
states of a airs. Cf. n. 11 above.
32. Cf. e.g. Craig 2001; O’Connor 1999; Pruss forthcoming; Stump
and Kretzmann 1985; and Stump 2003. This objection is also
taken seriously by traditional proponents of simplicity. Cf. e.g.
Aquinas’s discussion in Summa Theologiae 1.19. 3.
34. I’m assuming that in God’s case his reasons for creating remain
the same across all possible worlds, and hence that the only
thing that varies is the particular set of reasons he acts on.
37. Indeed, assuming (as I shall throughout) that divine beliefs can
be explained along the same lines as divine knowledge, we
would appear to have a solution to the problem of contingency
for them (and perhaps all contingent divine mental states) as
well. For a di erent account of divine beliefs, one which treats
them di erently from divine knowledge and requires a fairly
radical form of externalism about content, cf. Pruss
forthcoming.
38. One could try to avoid this problem by adopting a form of what
is known as ‘the-istic activism’—that is, the view that all
abstracta (including individual essences) are mental states of
God. In that case, what Smith would freely do, if created and
placed in various circumstances, would be a brute contingent
truth about God (or God’s mental states). Although this might
seem to help from the point of view of divine aseity (though
cf. Bergmann and Brower 2006 for reservations even about
this), it would be of no use for preserving divine simplicity.
For such brute truths would appear to involve true
predications of God (or God’s ideas) that are not only
contingent but also intrinsic. As we have seen, however, these
are precisely the sorts of predications about God that divine
simplicity excludes.
REFERENCES
LEFTOW, BRIAN (1999). ‘Is God an Abstract Object’, Noûs 24: 581–98.
OMNISCIENCE
EDWARD WIERENGA
Among the principal sources of the idea that God is omniscient are
the numerous biblical passages that attribute vast knowledge to
God. Thomas Aquinas, in his discussion of the knowledge of God
(1945 Summa Theologiae (ST) I. q. 14), cites such texts as Rom. 11:
33 (‘O the depths of the riches and wisdom and knowledge of
God!’), Job 12: 13 (‘With God are wisdom and strength; he has
counsel and understanding.’), and Heb. 4: 13 (‘And before him no
creature is hidden, but all are naked and laid bare to [his] eyes…’).
Another source of the attribution of omniscience to God derives
from ‘perfect being theology’, usually attributed to St Anselm.
Anselm’s ontological argument attempts to prove the existence of a
being than which no greater can be thought. Re ection on the
concept of a greatest conceivable or a greatest possible being yields
the conclusion that such a being possesses all perfections. In
Anselm’s formulation, ‘God is whatever it is better to be than not’
(1998b: 5), and although the intellectual attribute Anselm derived
from this formula is that God is wise (1998a: 15), later philosophers
included complete knowledge among the perfections.
DEFINING OMNISCIENCE
Knowledge de re
What we know changes as time goes by. And what we know when
we use presenttense sentences, or sentences with such temporal
indexicals as ‘now’ or ‘today’, often seems particularly eeting or
ephemeral. We can use a sentence such as
(3) ‘I am in hospital’
(5) I am in hospital.
(8) If a person must perform an action, then the person does not
do so freely.
which is true, but so taken the conclusion does not follow. The
conclusion does follow if the premise is
But from (14) and (12) it follows that there is nothing anyone can
do to make (14) false. In particular, there is nothing Jones himself
can do to make (14) false. Mowing his lawn tomorrow is a chore he
is unable to shirk. So Jones is not free with respect to mowing his
lawn tomorrow. This argument may, of course, be generalized to
cover any human action that God has foreknown.
The philosophical literature on this topic is voluminous. Many
important papers are collected in Fischer (1989); see also Hasker
(1989), Zagzebski (1991), and Wierenga (1989) for engagement
with and further references to that literature. Responses fall into
several di erent categories. One response is to accept the conclusion
that divine foreknowledge is incompatible with human free action
but to attempt to mitigate it by claiming that God’s omniscience
does not include foreknowledge. This was the response of Boethius
(1999), who held that God’s mode of existence was that of eternity,
‘the complete possession all at once of illimitable life’ (see Stump
and Kretzmann, 1981). Thus, although God knows everything that
ever happens, it is not foreknowledge from his eternal perspective.
Aquinas, too, seemed to have thought that the correct response to
the problem was to appeal to divine eternity. More recently, Stump
and Kretzmann (1991) speak of ‘the eternity solution’. But, as
several philosophers have argued (Plantinga 1986; Zagzebski 1991;
Wierenga 1989), whatever the merits of the doctrine of divine
eternity, it does not by itself solve the problem raised by this
argument. The reason is that an exactly analogous argument can be
constructed in terms of the past truth of God’s eternal knowledge of
propositions about our future. The defender of divine eternity would
need to say something about that argument, so we should nd out
what that is so that we can see whether it applies to the present
argument.
Another response also accepts the conclusion of the argument
but denies both that God has foreknowledge and that he has any
other way of knowing the future free actions of creatures. This view
has become increasingly popular in recent years. A limited version
of it was defended by Peter Geach (1977), who held that God lacks
foreknowledge of future free actions of creatures unless those
actions result from ‘present trends and tendencies’. Swinburne
(1993) agrees, at least on the assumption that God is contingent,
that he does not have knowledge of future free actions. Ho man
and Rosenkrantz (2002) develop a detailed analysis of omniscience,
intentionally limiting God’s knowledge of the contingent future to
those truths that are ‘causally inevitable’. Finally, William Hasker
(1989) and others associated with the ‘Open Theism’ movement (see
Pinnock et al. (1994)) are insistent that God leaves the future open
so as to leave room for human freedom. Nevertheless, denying that
God has foreknowledge (without substituting eternal knowledge or
some other kind of cognition for it) seems a retreat from the
traditional conception of the God of the philosophers, and it
certainly seems di cult to see how a signi cant doctrine of
providence could be developed without including knowledge of the
future in omniscience.
(15) Twenty years ago Ralph correctly believed that the sun will
rise on 1 January 2010
The nal option is to deny (12), the claim that no one can make
an accidentally necessary proposition false. More carefully, it is
open to hold that from the fact that there is nothing Jones can do to
make
false, it does not follow that he is not free with respect to mowing
his lawn tomorrow. This response will be congenial to compatibilists
—those who hold that free action is compatible with causal
determinism. But it will be much less palatable to those who think
that free will is libertarian.
Middle Knowledge
CONCLUSION
REFERENCES
CHISHOLM, R. (1976), ‘Knowledge and Belief: “De Dicto” and “De Se”’
Philosophical Studies 29: 1–20.
DAVIS, S. (1983). Logic and the Nature of God. Grand Rapids: Wm. B.
Eerdmans.
DIVINE ETERNITY
‘GOD’, declares the prophet Isaiah, ‘is the high and lofty One who
inhabits eternity’ (Isa. 57:15). But being a prophet and not a
philosophical theologian, Isaiah did not pause to re ect up on the
nature of divine eternity. Minimally, to be eternal means to exist
without beginning and end. To say that God is eternal means
minimally that he never came into being and will never go out of
being. To exist eternally is to exist permanently.1
or
Then we add
(2) If God is simple or immutable, then he is not temporal,
How can we make sense of this claim? The most plausible move
for the defender of divine timelessness to make will be to hold that
the four-dimensional spacetime manifold exists tenselessly and that
God transcends that manifold. A good many physicists and
philosophers of time and space embrace such a tenseless view of
time (spacetime realism). Such a view makes sense of the traditional
claim that all events in time are present to God and therefore known
to him via his scientia visionis.
Neither can we say that God exists in the ‘now’ associated with
the time of every inertial frame, for this would obliterate the unity
of God’s consciousness. In order to preserve God’s personal
consciousness, it must not be fragmented and scattered among the
inertial frames in the universe. But if God’s time cannot be
identi ed with the time of a single frame or of a plurality of frames,
then God must not be in time at all; that is to say, he exists
timelessly.
(11) God does not exist in either the time associated with a
single inertial frame or the times associated with a plurality
of inertial frames.
But what about (9)? The di culty with this premise is that it
fails to take into account the fact that STR is a restricted theory of
relativity and therefore is correct only within prescribed limits. It is
a theory that deals with uniform motion only. The analysis of non-
uniform motion, such as acceleration and rotation, is provided by
the General Theory of Relativity (GTR). STR cannot therefore be
expected to give us the nal word about the nature of time and
space; indeed, within the context of GTR a new and important
conception of time emerges.
(14) The most perfect being has the most perfect mode of
existence.
(15) Therefore, God has the most perfect mode of existence.
One way to escape this argument is to deny (23). This might not
appear to be a very promising strategy, since it seems obvious that
God is related to his creatures insofar as he sustains them, knows
them, and loves them. Remarkably, however, it was precisely this
premise that medieval theologians such as Aquinas denied. Thomas
agrees with (24). On his view, relational properties involving God
and creatures, like God’s being Lord, rst begin to exist at the
moment at which the creatures come into being (ST Ia q. 13 a. 7).
Hence, if God stands in real relations to his creatures, he acquires
those relational properties de novo at the moment of creation and
thus undergoes change. And anything that changes, even
extrinsically, must be in time. Thomas escapes the conclusion that
God is therefore temporal by denying that God stands in any real
relation to the world. Since God is absolutely simple, he stands in no
relations to anything, for relations would introduce complexity into
God’s being. Aquinas holds, paradoxically, that while creatures are
really related to God, God is not really related to creatures. The
relation of God to creatures exists only in our minds, not in reality.
On Aquinas’s view, then, God undergoes no extrinsic change in
creating the world. He just exists, and creation is creatures’ coming
into existence with a real relation to God of being caused by God.
This is certainly an extraordinary doctrine. Wholly apart from its
reliance on divine simplicity, the doctrine of no real relations is very
problematic. God’s sustaining the world is a causal relation rooted
in the active power and intrinsic properties of God as First Cause.
Thus, to say the world is really related to God by the relation is
sustained by, but that God is not really related to the world by the
relation is sustaining, seems unintelligible. It is to say that one can
have real e ects without a real cause—which seems self-
contradictory or incomprehensible.
We have seen that God’s action in the temporal world gives us good
grounds for concluding God to be temporal in view of the extrinsic
change he undergoes through his changing relations with the world.
But the existence of a temporal world also seems to entail intrinsic
change in God in view of his knowledge of what is happening in the
temporal world. For since what is happening in the world is in
constant ux, so also must God’s knowledge be in constant ux.
Defenders of divine temporality have argued that a timeless God
cannot know certain tensed facts about the world—for example,
what is happening now—and therefore, since God is omniscient, he
must be temporal.
The attempt to deny (28) thus seems to fare no better than the
e ort to refute (29). If God is omniscient, then given the existence
of a temporal world, he cannot be ignorant of tensed facts. It follows
that God is not timeless, which is to say, he is temporal. So in
addition to the argument from divine action in the world, we now
have a second powerful argument based on God’s changing
knowledge of tensed facts for thinking that God is in time.
NOTES
1. For an analysis of what it means to be permanent, see Brian
Leftow, Time and Eternity, Cornell Studies in the Philosophy of
Religion (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991), 133; cf.
Quentin Smith, ‘A New Typology of Temporal and Atemporal
Permanence’, Noûs 23 (1989), 307–30. According to Leftow an
entity is permanent if and only if it exists and has no rst or
last nite period of existence, and there are no moments
before or after it exists.
2. James Barr, Biblical Words for Time (London: SCM, 1962), 149.
16. Stephen T. Davis, Logic and the Nature of God (Grand Rapids:
Wm. B. Eerdmans, 1983), 20; Delmas Lewis, ‘Eternity Again: A
Reply to Stump and Kretzmann’, International Journal for
Philosophy of Religion 15 (1984), 74–6;Paul Helm, Eternal God
(Oxford: Clarendon, 1988), 32–3; William Hasker, God, Time,
and Knowledge (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989), 164–6;
John C. Yates, The Timelessness of God (Lanham: University
Press of America, 1990), 128–30; Brian Leftow, Time and
Eternity, Cornell Studies in Philosophy of Religion (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 1991), 170–2; Garrett J. DeWeese,
God and the Nature of Time, Ashgate Philosophy of Religion
Series (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2004), 164.
OMNIPOTENCE
BRIAN LEFTOW
THE doctrine that God is omnipotent takes its rise from Scriptural
texts:
These texts concern two linked topics. One is how much power God
has to put behind actions: enough that nothing is too hard, enough
to do whatever he pleases. Let’s call this ‘how strong God is’.1 The
other is how much God can do: ‘all things’. The link is obvious: we
measure strength by what tasks it is adequate to perform, and God is
so strong he can do all things. There are two distinct topics here
because strength does not consist in or entail abilities to accomplish
tasks. I might be physically and mentally strong enough to win a
chess match, but be unable to do so because I do not know the rules
or have not practiced. I might be strong enough to lift a skunk, but
unable because an allergic reaction causes me to pass out when I get
within range. Again, two people might be able to accomplish the
same tasks; if one does them easily and the other strains to equal the
rst, there is a di erence between them, which intuitively does not
consist in the range of tasks they are able to perform.2
Augustine often discusses the paradox that a God who ‘can do all
things’ can’t do some things we can do. He writes that God
is omnipotent to make all things He may have willed to make. [But]
He cannot die [or] sin [or] deceive [or] be deceived…were He able
to do these, He would not be omnipotent.8 Neither is His power
diminished when we say that He cannot die or [err]—for this is in
such a way impossible to Him, that if it were possible for Him, He
would be of less power. But…He is rightly called omnipotent though
He can neither die nor [err]. For He is called omnipotent on account
of His doing what He wills, not on account of His su ering what He
wills not; for if that should befall Him, He would by no means be
omnipotent. Wherefore He cannot do something for the very reason
that He is omnipotent.9
He who can do these things [be corrupted, lie, etc.] can do what is
not good for himself and what he ought not to do. And the more he
can do these things…the less power he has against…adversity and
perversity. He, therefore, who can do such things, can do them not
by power but by impotence.10
WIERENGA
(1) (it is possible in W that both there has been the initial
segment of W up to t and x strongly actualizes A at t) ⊃ (at t
in W x can strongly actualize A).
Christians believe that one human, Jesus, was also divine. The
orthodox Chalcedonian view has been that this entails that one
human was omnipotent; those with this sort of Christology, then,
can’t claim that being human is incompatible with being
omnipotent, and so, one might think, can’t say that being human
entails the lack of any power whatsoever. Further, the same will
hold for any nature God the Son might have taken on. However,
even if being human is compatible with being omnipotent, it does
not follow that just any human could have been omnipotent. In fact,
no human not actually assumed by a divine Person could have been.
For God is no body-snatcher. But had God the Son taken over the
body and soul that would otherwise have been mine to make
himself human, he would in e ect have stolen my natural
endowment. Further, actual humans are actually substances. Jesus’
body and soul do not on their own constitute a substance. They are
not independent existents; they exist only as adjuncts supported in
being by the substance who is God the Son. It is implausible that
being a substance is a contingent property—that something that is a
substance could have failed to be one. If this is correct, one can’t use
the Incarnation to argue against there actually being essentially
limited agents: no actual human could have been omnipotent in
virtue of having been the vehicle of a divine incarnation. One can
see this more simply still: had my body and soul been used for the
Incarnation, I would not have existed. The person in my body would
have been not me, but God the Son. So God’s becoming incarnate in
my body and soul would not entail that I was omnipotent.
Again, one strand of Christianity might see the claim that some
agents are essentially limited as controversial. Picking up on a few
New Testament texts, Eastern Orthodoxy believes that salvation
involves eventual ‘dei cation’. Richard Swinburne approvingly
interprets Maximus the Confessor’s version of this as implying that
the blessed in heaven become omniscient, omnipotent, and perfectly
good.35 But if God can make us so, the question arises of whether
there are any sorts of agent he can’t do this for: perhaps he could
deify rabbits, frogs…. Be this as it may, much turns on how the idea
of being made omnipotent is parsed out. A perfectly good God
would not grant omnipotence without also granting su cient
knowledge and goodness to use it properly or else hemming in its
use by a use of his own power: an omnipotent but evil, partly
corrupt, or partly ignorant being left free to act as it pleased would
be an evil too great to reconcile with God’s existence. On a weak
reading, becoming omnipotent could mean simply that God so
reforms the blessed’s characters and informs their knowledge that
they no longer make prayers whose granting would in the long run
go counter to the best good God has in mind, and God accordingly
grants all their prayers: anything they choose to bring about in this
way, they succeed in bringing about. This sort of ‘becoming
omnipotent’ would be limited to things possibly with su cient
cognitive complexity to pray, and would leave any essential intrinsic
limitations an agent had in place, since the agent’s intrinsic powers
would not be heightened one whit. And it is not in my view genuine
omnipotence at all: the agents in question remain intrinsically of a
sort to be frustrated by external limitations, and can succeed in
what they do only by external help. True omnipotence, I suggest
below, is not compatible with these things.
On a strong reading, being made omnipotent would mean being
granted a new intrinsic property in virtue of which one henceforth
has that much power.36 Duns Scotus and others would argue that
this is impossible—that there cannot be two such omnipotent beings
—but I cannot delve into this here. Still, what could this intrinsic
property be? Being omnipotent is a matter of having powers. One
has powers in virtue of having an underlying categorical attribute
which supports or subvenes them.37 In God’s case, the underlying
categorical is deity. It is not clear or at all intuitive that any other
underlying nature could support omnipotence. But to bestow a case
of deity on a creature would be to make a created thing a God. It is
plausibly part of the divine nature to be uncreated. I therefore
suggest that God just cannot make another being intrinsically
omnipotent. It follows that every non-divine nature essentially
involves some limitation of power: even if there is no particular
power such that the nature guarantees that the being bearing it
lacks that one, the nature guarantees that there are some powers the
being does not have. It follows further that for every non-divine
being, there can be powers such that God cannot give that being
those powers: if I were improved up to (so to speak) one power
short of omnipotence, God couldn’t give me that last power.
Further, if I’m right in this last, every created being has at least the
non-trivial essential property of being non-divine, and this su ces,
as I’ve said, to involve essential limitation. But of course it’s
plausible that we have other, positive non-trivial essential
properties. I am human. So while any chicken embryo has the
ability to grow by natural processes into a chicken, I do not; while
any cat has the ability to clean its own cat-fur, I do not. Plausibly I
am essentially human; if I am, God can’t give either ability to me.
We can also generate essential limitations without substantive
essentialism about non-world-indexed properties. I have not just
abilities, but world-indexed abilities: if in W I can run, I also can-
run-in-W. All world-indexed attributes are essential. Thus any
world-indexed ability I lack, even God can’t give me. Finally,
Wierenga’s claim, again, is that for any agent who lacks certain
abilities, it is possible that God give it those abilities. But God, as
we’ve seen, lacks abilities to die and err. If he is essentially eternal
and omniscient, he cannot give himself these. Thus Wierenga’s
response fails, and on his de nition, McEar is omnipotent.
FLINT/FREDDOSO
Consider the conjunctive state of a airs the cat comes in and if Jones
were in C at t, he would freely decide at t to let out the dog…suppose
now that S is omnipotent. Since [this] state of a airs…does not
belong to Ls, it follows from (FF) that an omnipotent being can
bring (it) about…though it cannot bring about one of the
conjuncts…consider…the disjunctive state of a airs if Jones were in
C at t, he would freely decide at t to let out the dog or if Jones were in C
at t, he would freely decide at t to go to the bathroom…(this) does not
belong to Ls, and so it follows from (FF) that an omnipotent being
can bring [it] about…even though (it) can bring about neither of
the disjuncts. Not good.42
The rst is a problem given the falsity of (HR), for this suggests that
something can bring about a conjunctive state of a airs only by
bringing about both conjuncts or something relevantly like bringing
about both conjuncts.43 One can address both by asking how CFs get
included in a true world-type. In standard counterfactual logics, if p.
q, then p q. So it seems that by making p . q true, one makes it true
that p q. Flint and Freddoso allow this in the case of CFs at one
point:
Any free being will have some say in determining which world-type
is true … since Jones is free to decide whether … to write … to his
wife, it is up to him whether the true world-type includes (that) if
Jones were in C at t, he would freely decide at t to (write) to his
wife … However, the vast majority of the counterfactuals which go
to make up a world-type relate to beings other than Jones, and
Jones … is powerless to make such counterfactuals true or false.44
Flint and Freddoso deny that anyone other than Jones can a ect the
truth-value of a CF about Jones.45 But they also allow that ‘a
person’s power is … in large measure … his ability to in uence the
free actions of others … e.g. by restricting their options … or by
persuading or dissuading them’.46 If so, then if there are CFs about
Jones, someone not Jones can bring it about that a CF about Jones
is true. Let’s distinguish complete from incomplete circumstances of
a free choice. A complete circumstance of a free choice K is the
entire history (in Flint and Freddoso’s sense) of the world prior to t,
plus those states of a airs obtaining at t whose obtaining in no way
depends on what is freely chosen in K. If complete circumstances
are sets of states of a airs, an incomplete circumstance for K is any
non-empty subset of its complete circumstance. There are CFs for
both complete and incomplete circumstances. Someone not Jones
can bring it about that a CF for an incomplete circumstance is true.
Let the incompleteness in the circumstance for K be that it excludes
everything I do so to persuade Jones, not in C, that
One might reply that this is irrelevant, because what Oppy has in
mind is not whose the lifting power is, but rather the bringing-about
of the state of a airs four humans lift the car by their muscle power
and nothing, including an omnipotent being, helps them. But if an
omnipotent being is part of W’s history, as Oppy assumes, in no
possible world sharing W’s history at t do four humans bring this
about by themselves. Humans cannot block the in uence of
someone omnipotent: if S chose to help them, they could do nothing
about it. Thus four humans raise the car by their own muscle-power
only if S cooperates by leaving them alone—only if S’s refraining
from action is part of the causal history of their joint action. With S
lurking in the background, humans cannot e ect the second
conjunct—and if p obtains and one brings about q, that is not
su cient to entail that one brings it about that p . q. So this is not a
state of a airs they can bring about by human muscle-power alone.
If S cannot do so either, then, this counts nothing against S’s
omnipotence on (FF), for this state of a airs fails (III). Oppy replies:
A way out is not hard to spot. We must answer the question ‘by
what or whom?’ as (FF) does. But we must also jettison Wierenga
and (FF)’s claim that to assess omnipotence in W at t, only worlds
which share W’s history at t matter. This is what makes Lonely
McEar di cult. The thought behind the claim is that it is now
impossible to bring about anything incompatible with the past’s
having been as it was: if it was the case that P, now or in the future
nothing can occur that entails that it was the case that ¬P, nor can
the contents of the past be shifted. As this is so, Wierenga and (FF)
think, it does not count against someone’s claim to omnipotence
that he/she is unable to do so.61 They infer that the only power that
matters for being omnipotent at t in W is power having which is
compatible with t’s past in W. But there are other ways to deal with
the xity of the past. One is simply to note that power to bring
about (say) that the Germans lost World War II (or anything
entailing this) is not intrinsic: to have this power, one must be sited
either before World War II or outside time, and so whether one has
it depends on one’s circumstances. As we’ve seen, intrinsic power
alone counts for omnipotence; extrinsic powers, or their lack, are
irrelevant. This being so, there is no need to jigger one’s de nition
of omnipotence to allow for the past’s xity. What matters is simply
that the omnipotent being have all such intrinsic powers as would
allow it to bring about a German loss were it appropriately sited. To
parse the consensus view, then, let us simply speak of states of
a airs with the modal property of being strongly actualized in some
possible world. If the states of a airs relevant for counting as
omnipotent are those actualized in some possible world, not in some
possible world sharing history with W, this keeps McEar at bay.
Still, the consensus view on its own won’t do, however parsed. The
most basic problem with (FF) is one it shares with almost all
de nitions of omnipotence since Aquinas: it speaks only of the
omnipotent being’s range of action, not its strength or power. We
can agree in advance of any detailed account of omnipotence that
an omnipotent being is as powerful as it is possible to be: no one
could be more powerful than someone omnipotent. But now
consider two deities, Schmod and God. Schmod ‘can do all things’,
but nds some of them hard (though not ‘too hard’). God can do all
Schmod can, but nds none of it hard. One legitimate explanation of
this is that God is stronger. If someone is stronger than Schmod,
Schmod is not omnipotent, even if Schmod ‘can do all things’. If this
is a coherent example, a de nition of omnipotence needs to assure
maximal strength; talk of range alone is inadequate.
WIELENBERG
RANGE
Some try to meet the students’ concern by arguing that there are
no ‘things God can’t do’, because if a state of a airs is absolutely
impossible, there is no act or task of bringing it about. Actions or
tasks (they say) are by de nition things someone can do. If a state of
a airs is absolutely impossible, nobody can bring it about. So there
is no act or task of doing this69—and so, the argument concludes, no
act or task God cannot do. But students tend not to feel comfortable
with this. And perhaps there is something to their feeling. For one
thing, it’s now more usual to de ne omnipotence in terms of the
range of states of a airs God can bring about.70 Discomfort with
acts or tasks God can’t do may well transmit itself to talk of states of
a airs he can’t bring about, and there is no way to deal with this
analogous to the act/task move. Moreover, perhaps the modal part
of our description of an act or task (‘can do’) smuggles something in
illicitly. We have the sentence
(RS) It is not the case that something is both round and square.
(RS) says something true. The contradictory of a truth is not
nonsense but a falsehood. So (RS)’s contradictory,
The shortest answer here is that (G) says nothing at all about
whether it is in God to have the range of the possible other than it
actually is. So (G) carries none of the suggested consequences.
Further, if (G) is true and it is in God to make the range of the
possible other than it actually is, it does not follow that it is in God
to make the range of the possible so small as to threaten his
omnipotence.74 Even if it is in God to have the range of the possible
be other than it is, his nature could constrain the way he could vary
its range. Further, if there is a problem here, it arises as we consider
restricted ranges for the possible, whether or not God is the reason
for them. If the real problem is making God’s power hostage to the
range of the possible, one could be pardoned for seeing (G) precisely
as an antidote to this. Thus I take (G) as one conjunct in my nal
account of omnipotence.
AN ACCOUNT OF OMNIPOTENCE
NOTES
1. Hill often links power and strength, as at 2005: 149, but he’s
not consistent: ibid. 134.
11. I Sent. d. 42 c. 3.
16. e.g. ST Ia q. 25 a. 4.
17. QD de Potentia 1. 6.
25. Thus when Patrick Grim writes that the ‘genuinely traditional
and unlimited notion of omnipotence’ is that of being able to
perform any task speci able without contradiction and that
‘the task of defending’ this ‘seems to have been abandoned’
(2007: 204, 200, 201), he makes at least two mistakes. If
anything quali es as a traditional concept of omnipotence, it is
not what Grim says. I’m tempted to say that Grim’s concept
does not go back further than twentieth-century misreadings
of Aquinas. And the task of defending the genuine traditional
account, or an only slightly cleaned-up version of it, is still
ongoing.
30. Tom Flint pointed out the third reading, and the problem that
ensues on it.
31. Mackie (in Urban and Walton 1978: 77–8) raised the issue
McEar raises without making up an example involving a
particular individual. Plantinga (1967: 170) introduced McEar
without naming him. LaCroix (1977: 187) added the name.
Mavrodes (1977: 280) pointed out the importance of McEar’s
having his limits essentially. Flint and Freddoso (1983: 110 n.
4) discovered McEar’s medieval ancestry.
33. For the ‘part of’ part of this see also Hill (2005: 136 n. 19).
37. Or else the power and its base are really just two aspects of a
single attribute. As this quali cation does not a ect the rest of
my argument, I henceforth ignore it.
39. Ibid.96.
40. Ibid.97.
43. If S brings it about that p, and it is the case that p . q, but S did
not bring it about that q, q has no cause, a full cause other
than S, a partial cause not including S, or a partial cause
including S. If no cause, one can infer that S brings it about
that p . q only via something relevantly like (HR). If q has a
full cause other than S, then as we’ve seen, it is not the case
that S brought it about that p . q. If q has only a partial cause
not including S, what to say will be a function of what we say
in cases where there is no cause and cases in which there is a
full cause other than S, and so whether S brought it about that
p . q again will hinge partly on the fate of (HR) and relevantly
similar principles: if (HR) is false, and relevantly similar
principles are false, then S did not bring it about that p . q,
given that where there is a full cause other than S, S did not
bring it about that p . q. If q has only a partial cause including
S, the possibilities multiply dizzyingly:
44. Flint and Freddoso (1983: 97, 94). Note 22 could be read as
expressing an intention to be neutral on this issue, but the text
does not seem neutral. If the text does let us make some CFs
true, Flint’s later writing on Molinism retracts this.
45. Ibid.95.
46. Ibid.86.
47. This also vitiates one of Oppy’s examples. Accepting the Flint-
Freddoso claim that only Jones can a ect (2)’s truth-value,
Oppy suggests that the state of a airs (everyone in the room is
free with respect to giving to Oxfam at t) > (everyone in the
room freely chooses to give to Oxfam at t) can only be brought
about jointly by everyone in the room. But one su ciently
persuasive person can bring it about. The persuader need
merely cause the emotional dispositions of those in the room
so to change that were they asked, they would give—or else
give reasons they all freely adopt.
55. One might ask here why just one has this ability if both satisfy
(FF). One answer might be that Jones strongly likes one of
them and strongly dislikes another. Of course both, being
omnipotent, might easily e ace Jones’s likes and dislikes, but
this would be relevantly like brainwashing and so would
defeat the claims that Jones freely accepts reasons given and
that the case is purely one of persuasion.
57. If there are true CFs, and an omnipotent being does not wholly
control their truth-value, these are contingent and can impede
its will too. I suggest that the right conclusion here is that a
Molinist God cannot be omnipotent.
61. Flint and Freddoso (1983: 87–9); Wierenga (1989: 16–17, 25–
6).
68. ‘Help’ allows for facts God cannot establish on his own: for it to
be a fact that I feed some sh, I must do the feeding.
71. Some might say they can’t understand this save by tacitly
introducing the modal ‘can do’ again. If this is your plight, we
might approach this in terms of conditional modalities. All
possible tasks are tasks someone could do just if (RS) were
true. Impossible tasks are those someone could do just if (RS)
were false.
72. At any rate, it’s the most cogent root I can ascribe to it. Worries
based on biblical texts such as ‘with God all things are
possible’ (Matt. 19: 26) seem to me misplaced. For nothing in
such texts suggests a particular reading of ‘all things’.
73. (FI) is not the only intuition we have in this vicinity. We might
also think that
(O), (U), and (G) are co-tenable, for it is co-tenable with (G)
that it not be up to God what states of a airs there are and
that God have placed every state of a airs in his power’s
range. Had he done so, he would have set no limits to his
power, and everything would be possible. Con ict emerges if
we conjoin (O), (U), (G), and the claim that some states of
a airs are impossible. But in this con ict, if there are any
impossibilities, (O) or (U) should lose. If we reject (G), God’s
power is limited from without by facts of impossibility—and
intuitively limits imposed from without, over which one has
no control, are worse than self-imposed limits whose extent
one in some way controls. One might object that there being a
stock of states of a airs whose content is not up to God is itself
a non-self-imposed limit. But if this is right, then equally any
stock whose content God set would constitute a self-imposed
limit on his power. As one or another must be the case, it
would seem to follow that any extent of divine power involves
some limitation—in which case either (O) is false or
omnipotence is impossible. I incline either to reject (O) or to
question the objection.
76. One could hold that a greater degree of power still would
consist in being able to add to the stock of states of a airs
available to bear modal status. I would happily redo the
de nition so as to include this note.
REFERENCES
AUGUSTINE, De Symbolo.
——— (1950). The City of God, trans. Marcus Dods. New York:
Random House.
DAVIS, STEPHEN (1983). Logic and the Nature of God. Grand Rapids:
Eerdmans.
——— (1968). Space and Time. London: Macmillan and Co., Ltd.
OMNIPRESENCE
HUD HUDSON
I. PRELIMINARIES
‘In no way at all,’ says the atheist, ‘for no divine being exists.’ ‘In
no way at all,’ says the relationalist, ‘for regions do not exist.’2 Let
us put on hold these dismissive answers in the ensuing discussion
and openly acknowledge a working assumption of theism and
substantivalism for the remainder of the chapter. Thus, for present
purposes, we shall count ourselves among the realists about God
and regions.3
Still, we must not forget our list of puzzles, which have certainly
discouraged any appeal to the perfectly natural and fundamental,
external relation of occupation as the key to omnipresence. A
reminder:
There are many ways into our topic. Let us begin by posing a
pair of questions about locations:
These are excellent and di cult questions, and I have neither the
space nor expertise to enter here the controversies with which they
are associated. I will remark in closing, however, that once again
the relation of entension may serve as a promising source of
resolution for some of those debates. Even if one took the
Anselmian/Thomistic accounts to su ce for omnipresence,
entension remains available to provide partial readings of additional
special claims of location such as Christ’s presence in the Eucharist
or the speci c comings and goings of the Holy Spirit. Accordingly, if
the ‘located at’ in the principle noted above ranges over these very
di erent types of occupation, even the Trinitarian may embrace the
individuation principle without apology.
10. Wierenga 2006 and 1997. For the record, scholars are divided
on whether Anselm and Aquinas really advocate the non-
occupation accounts as a substitution for (as opposed to an
addition to) a literal reading of omnipresence, and Robert
Pasnau (in private communication) has made an interesting
case for the combined view.
22. Why the fanciness? Why not just say ‘x entends’ means ‘x is
located at a non-point-sized region and is a mereological
simple’? This won’t do, for the proposed de niens would then
apply to three of the four di erent ways an object may be
thought to be related to regions (to be discussed below), and
one of the main aims of this section is to clearly distinguish
those di erent ways.
25. See Sider (forthcoming) who argues in this fashion not only for
the possibility of a single object occupying more than one
region but also for the possibility of a single region hosting
more than one object. Again, though, perhaps this establishes
at best a presumption in favor of the relevant thesis which
may be trumped by good arguments against multiple
occupancy or co-location.
27. One quali cation: should it turn out that there is no maximally
inclusive region (i.e. if every space is a proper subregion of a
larger space), then entension is disquali ed owing to its
de nitional link to being entirely located somewhere or other,
and omnipresence would simply amount to being wholly
present at each of the in nitely many contained regions.
REFERENCES
CASATI, ROBERTO, and VARZI, Achille (1999). Parts and Places: The
Structures of Spatial Representation. Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford
Books.
MORAL PERFECTION
LAURA GARCIA
But the moral attributes of God have come under attack as well.
William Rowe argues that perfect being theology is logically
incompatible with divine freedom.3 His case for this claim requires
the following two principles:
(b) If one action is better than another, then God cannot choose
the less perfect action over the more perfect action.4
Principle (a) assumes that there is some way of assessing the overall
value or desirability of possible worlds. Rowe admits that it may be
logically impossible for there to be a best of all possible worlds, but
he concludes from this that, given principles (a) and (b), God is not
free to create a world at all. In such a situation, God cannot choose
something less than the best, yet necessarily any world he creates
will be less good than some other one he could create. If it turns out
that, contrary to what we’ve assumed so far, there is a best possible
world, then God is morally required to create that world. He will
not be free to refrain from creating, nor will he be free to choose
among a variety of logically possible alternative worlds.
The Church … regards this world, and all that is in it, as a mere
shadow, as dust and ashes, compared with the value of one single
soul. She holds that, unless she can, in her own way, do good to
souls, it is no use her doing anything; she holds that it were better
for sun and moon to drop from heaven, for the earth to fail, and for
all the many millions who are upon it to die of starvation in
extremest agony, so far as temporal a iction goes, than that one
soul, I will not say, should be lost, but should commit one single
venial sin, should tell one willful untruth, though it harmed no one,
or steal one poor farthing without excuse. She considers the action
of this world and the action of the soul simply incommensurate,
viewed in their respective spheres.10
This passage suggests that the most important goods for human
persons are ones that cannot be achieved without their free
participation. St Augustine claims that ‘God, who created you
without you, will not save you without you.’11 On this view,
maximizing the good for a given person requires that person’s free
cooperation and continues to depend upon it throughout his or her
earthly life. Further, one person’s hardships may be an occasion for
another person’s moral growth or conversion, so that a divine being
must choose among many di erent kinds of goods—maximizing
some may be incompatible with maximizing others, and there is no
guarantee that di erent kinds of goods will be commensurable with
one another. Given these di culties within the consequentialist
model, then, there is reason to search for a more satisfactory
explication of divine moral perfection.
A Combination Theory
Some philosophers, aware of the di culties in both the duty and the
consequentialist models, attempt to combine the two in the hope of
counteracting the weaknesses of each with the strengths of the
other. One such attempt is sketched in some detail by T. J. Mawson:
‘God’s perfect goodness then is his perfectly ful lling his duties
toward his creatures and, furthermore, whenever there is a logically
possible best thing for him to do for them, his doing that too, his
perfectly loving them.’20 Mawson takes it for granted that God
ful lls all his duties, and that he ful lls them necessarily, so he
disagrees with Morris’s claim that having duties requires that one is
free to act against them. Both Morris and Mawson note that an
omnipotent and omniscient being necessarily ful lls his duties, then,
but Mawson claims this is not because God lacks an important kind
of freedom but because he has perfect freedom. ‘These properties
[omnipotence and omniscience] entail that there is nothing that
constrains God’s actions (no external power that can trump his will
and no ignorance that can misdirect it).’21 Hence a perfectly free
being necessarily ful lls all his duties. The e ectiveness of this
solution depends on whether one nds it essential to the concept of
a morally good action that the agent be free to fail to perform it,
since on Mawson’s view God acts dutifully as an automatic and
logically necessary e ect of his recognizing the right action to
perform and having the power to perform it.
While God has no need to create, Thomas does say that, having
created human beings, God necessarily wills their good. He cannot
hate anything that he has made.27 Since God is the highest good, the
greatest good for human persons is to know and love God and to
live in his presence forever. Hence, this is the destiny that God wills
for each person.
We saw earlier that the duty model of divine goodness hit a snag
over the question of whether a perfect being could be free to act
against a requirement of duty. Perfect-being theologians are inclined
to answer this question in the negative, though this puts a strain on
the idea that God has duties in the ordinary sense. There are at least
four possible solutions to that problem. First, retain the standard
duty model and surrender perfect-being theology, so that it is
possible for God to act against a moral duty (adding perhaps that he
never actually does so). While some theistic philosophers might nd
this acceptable, those committed to perfect-being theology would
vigorously oppose it. Second, retain the essential moral perfection of
God and surrender the freedom requirement of the duty model, so
that even a being who necessarily ful lls his duties quali es as
morally perfect. While this move is attractive in some ways, it sits
uneasily with important components of the duty model, e.g., that
ful lling one’s duties is worthy of moral praise, or that duties are
inherently prescriptive (since for a perfect being they will simply be
descriptive). A third solution, that of Thomas Morris, retains both
perfect-being theology and the freedom requirement of the duty
model but argues that a being who necessarily acts according to
duty can still be called perfectly good by extension, as long as his
actions are not coerced by anything outside his nature. This solution
has promise, but it runs counter to the spirit of the duty model. Any
necessitation of one’s actions, whether from without or within,
undermines the prescriptive element essential to the duty model.
CONCLUSION
What the apostle Paul says to the early Christians is also the
purpose of all created things, that they ‘exist for the praise of his
glory’.32 St Thomas adds that human persons arrive at this end only
by imitating the moral perfection of God, loving him above all,
loving ourselves as we ought, and loving others as God does, for
their own sake. Wishing others well, in this perspective, means
especially wanting them to obtain the highest of all goods,
friendship with God. Some criticize Christians for a perceived lack
of attention to the material and economic needs of those around
them, and certainly these are essential to a person’s welfare. But one
cannot blame Christians for working even harder to bring others
closer to God, to a good that is unsurpassable, imperishable, and can
never be taken away. Using St Paul’s language, C. S. Lewis spoke
eloquently about the ‘weight of glory’, the in nite value and eternal
destiny of each human being that requires us to treat others with
respect, and even with a form of reverence.33 Since divine goodness
is, among other things, a model for human goodness, our attitudes
toward others should be more like those of God, ready to o er
mercy and forgiveness, to share the burdens and sorrows of those
around us, to reach out to those in need, and to defend the weak
and despised. While our e orts may not always succeed, believers
hope in a God who uses all their e orts to accomplish his will and
whose love for each human being is beyond our imagining.
NOTES
6. Thomas Flint points out that this is true only if God knows the
truth-values of counterfactuals of freedom, i.e. propositions of
the form: In circumstances C, agent S freely chooses action A. As
we have seen, Peter Geach (and some others) denies that God
can know with certainty the truth-values of such propositions.
13. See Janine Idziak (ed.), Divine Command Morality: Historical and
Contemporary Readings (New York: Edwin Mellen, 1979),
especially the essay by Philip Quinn. Also see Robert M.
Adams, ‘Divine Command Metaethics Modi ed Again’, Journal
of Religious Ethics 7 (1979), 71–9, and William P. Alston, ‘What
Euthyphro Should Have Said’, in William Craig (ed.),
Philosophy of Religion: A Reader and Guide (New Brunswick:
Rutgers University Press, 2002), 283–98.
21. Ibid.67.
22. On the other hand, if God’s duties to each individual might
prevent him from maximizing overall value (or from achieving
the relevant consequentialist objective), the duty model could
result in a di erent outcome than the consequentialist model.
24. For a fuller explication and defense of this virtue theory see J.
L. A. Garcia, ‘Interpersonal Virtues: Whose Interest Do They
Serve?’, American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 71 (1997),
31–60.
29. ‘We know that all things work together for those who love God,
who are called according to his purpose’. Romans 8: 28.
31. Such freedom wills the highest good (namely, God) and
necessarily possesses this good, as being one and the same
with it.
ROBIN COLLINS
I. INTRODUCTION
The Issue
This perplexity can be broken down into two questions: (1) Why did
God create a world that had to undergo a very long developmental
process to give rise to life, and then conscious, moral agents, instead
of creating a world that was fully formed from the beginning? And
(2) Why did this developmental process, whether or not it was
guided by God, involve so many apparent accidents and chance
events, which has led to so much su ering and death over millions
of years? Doesn’t this seem contrary to the character of an all good,
all loving God who has a providential purpose for creation?
In the last twenty years, the most common answer given by those
writing in the area of science and religion as to why God used a
partly chance-driven evolutionary process to create the world is that
such a process is required for creation to be truly independent of
God. Scientist-theologian John Polkinghorne, for example, says that
he believes the only possible solution to the wastefulness of
evolution and other sorts of natural evil ‘lies in a variation of the
free-will defence, applied to the whole created order. In his great act
of creation I believe that God allows the physical world to be itself,
not in Manichaean opposition to him, but in that independence
which is Love’s gift of freedom to the one beloved…. The cosmos is
given the opportunity to be itself (1989: 67). On the next page,
Polkinghorne goes on to state that ‘God accords to the processes of
the world the same respect he accords to the actions of humanity’
(ibid. 68). Elsewhere Polkinghorne (1998: 14) summarizes his free
process defence as the claim that ‘a world allowed to make itself is
better than the puppet theatre of a Cosmic Tyrant’. Polkinghorne’s
free-process defence, therefore, is an attempt to extend the free will
theodicy—the idea that God has given his creatures free will and
thus must allow them to do evil—to creation as a whole.2
Michael Murray criticizes Haught’s claim that the universe could not
be truly independent of God if God created it in an instant. As
Murray (forthcoming, ch. 6) rightly points out, if an artist creates a
fully-formed painting, the painting is still a truly distinct entity from
the artist. Although Haught is not explicit about what exactly he
means by autonomy, perhaps a more charitable interpretation of
Haught’s idea of independence is that the universe be allowed to
‘make itself’. As Haught (2000: 41) says elsewhere, ‘A world given a
lease to become more and more autonomous, even to help create
itself and eventually attain the status of human consciousness, has
much more integrity and value than any conceivable world
determined in every respect by a “divine designer”.’ Under this
interpretation, Haught could be seen as extending both the free will
theodicy and the soul-making theodicy to the universe itself (as
Polkinghorne also seems to do). In the soul-making theodicy, God
creates a universe in which natural and moral evil can occur so that
human beings can develop a freely formed virtuous character by
acting virtuously in response to evil. If God simply created our
characters fully formed, then we would not have been allowed to
‘make ourselves’. Indeed, the soul-making theodicy can be seen as
an extension of the free will theodicy: it could be argued that one
major reason that free will is valuable is that it gives us the
opportunity partly to choose our own character.
The worry here is that both Polkinghorne and Haught are overly
anthropomorphizing nature: eliminate the semi-anthropomorphic
metaphors, and the idea of creation ‘making itself’ seems to lose
much, if not all, of its appeal. The reason is that it is unclear what is
supposed to be good about creation making itself, once we de-
anthropomorphize nature. In the case of human freedom, we have a
strong intuition that moral responsibility requires free will and that
moral agency is a great good in and of itself. Further, arguably,
beings without free will could not authentically love God (or even
one another) if God determined all their choices. Presumably,
however, non-human creation neither has moral agency nor does it
love God (except, perhaps, some higher non-human animals), or at
least not unless one adopts a radically di erent view of nature than
delivered by modern science: namely, a view in which non-human,
non-higher-animal creation does have a will and can make choices.
Neither Haught nor Polkinghorne, however, advocates such a view.3
My own highly speculative proposal begins with the claim that the
evolutionary process allows for certain types of interconnection
between humans and non-human creation that are potentially of
signi cant value. I do not claim that these interconnections provide
the sole reason for God’s creating by means of a seemingly chance-
driven evolutionary process, only that they provide one reason. We
will rst explicate what these interconnections are, and then present
some reasons for thinking that they are of value. The three types of
interconnections that we will consider are what I will call emergent,
ancestral, and redemptive interconnections.
Emergent Interconnection
Ancestral Interconnections
Under this idea, therefore, the fact that the universe is ‘subject to
decay’—and hence su ering and death occur in it—is because it is
governed by a set of laws, whether those laws are deterministic or
indeterministic. Only if God becomes directly and constantly
involved with the universe (beyond simply sustaining it) could this
process of decay be stopped; even by God’s carefully choosing the
universe’s laws and initial conditions, avoiding some sort of
imperfection might be impossible.8 My suggestion, therefore, is that
God has left it up to human beings to help bring about this further
divine involvement with the universe that is necessary for it not to
be subject to decay.
What will this sharing in the divine life be like? Beyond the
claim that the universe would no longer be subject to decay, one
can only speculate. Perhaps the fabric of the universe would be in
perfect harmony with the wills and thoughts of resurrected human
beings. Further, perhaps all su ciently sentient animals will
become fully conscious in some way, taking on new forms that are
in continuity with their current bodies, but which are also radically
di erent, with current forms of metamorphosis being only a
foretaste. It might even be the case that the universe itself gains a
‘soul’ of some sort, with which human beings could be in
communion.9
At this point, one might ask: couldn’t we still play a major role in
creation’s ultimate ful llment even if God created it in a perfect
state? For example, through watering and tending an oak tree from
its being a seedling to a fully mature tree, one can contribute to its
nal perfection as a fully grown oak, even though at every stage of
the oak’s development it could be said to be perfect for that stage of
development. By analogy, then, it seems that God could have
created the universe in an immature, yet perfect state, and then
have given human beings the opportunity to become co-creators
with God to bring it to ful llment.
Summary
Our next question is: why think that the three types of
interconnections with creation elaborated above would be of value?
One answer is that such interconnections pave the way for a deeper
intercommunion with creation, an intercommunion in which
creation in some sense becomes part of what we are, and ultimately
through us is taken into the divine life. To see how this might take
place, we will begin by looking at four analogies.
I suggest that the core value in being partly responsible for our
own souls is that our character becomes more fully our own in a
way that would otherwise not be possible. The reason, I suggest, is
that our ‘deepest choosing self’—that is, our self considered as the
underlying agent that makes choices—gets interwoven and
connected with those aspects of our character that we help develop
through our actions.10 Finally, by co-creating our character with
God’s grace in Christ, there is an interweaving between Christ, our
agency, and our character, so that not only does our character
become deeply our own, but in some sense through Christ God’s
character and life also become deeply our own.
At this point, one might ask: couldn’t the creation be part of who
we are even if God made it instantaneously and fully formed? Yes,
to a certain extent, since it would be connected to us: our bodily
existence would be dependent on the material processes around us,
and in turn we would a ect the universe. It is plausible to suppose,
however, that in this circumstance its connection with us would not
be nearly as deep: it would lack the ancestral and redemptive
interconnection discussed above. This would, I suggest, take away
from the depth of intercommunion with creation and the depth to
which it would become part of our own selves, at least given the
assumption that intercommunion is built o the right sort of
previously established interconnections. Of course, as mentioned
previously, an incomplete but non-evolutionary world could still
have similar redemptive interconnections, but it would still lack the
ancestral interconnections discussed above.
Further, this idea can help make sense of why God allows evil
and the doctrine of original sin. Elsewhere, I have constructed both
a theodicy and an account of original sin based on this idea, both of
which I will brie y summarize here.11 I call my theodicy the
connection-building theodicy (CBT) and claim that it o ers at least a
partial explanation for God’s allowing evil. This theodicy begins
with the assumption that positive connections between individuals,
such as connections of appreciation for being helped in times of
su ering, of being forgiven of sin, of being helped out of spiritual
and moral darkness, and the like, are of intrinsic value, a value in
which all the parties involved in the connection share. Further, it
hypothesizes that these connections of appreciation and intimacy
have the potential of being an ongoing part of one’s life for all
eternity. For example, when all things are brought to light, we will
have an ongoing appreciation for those who self-sacri cially helped
us in times of su ering, since we will always remember what they
did. Accordingly, I claim, the goodness of this connection keeps
growing, becoming of very large, if not of in nite, value, thus
outweighing the nite evils that God must allow in order for the
types of connections in question to exist.
V. CONCLUSION
I have argued that God’s creating human beings and other living
organisms through an evolutionary process allows for richer and
deeper sorts of interconnections between humans and non-human
creation than would otherwise be possible. I have presented reasons
for thinking that these interconnections are of signi cant value, the
main reason being that they allow for creation to become more
deeply united with ourselves, in fact so united that there exists a
deep communion between us and the rest of creation. This
communion is not only an intrinsic good, but it enriches us, since
part of this communion is creation becoming part of our very self,
and thus we consciously share in the richness of creation. As a nal
comment, it is important to note that this idea that communion with
nature is a great good and an ideal to be sought after has made
intuitive sense to many people in the past and across cultures,
although of course they did not view it from within an evolutionary
framework. For instance, consider the Western Inscription. Written by
Chang Tsai (1020–79), this was one of the most in uential writings
in China, especially for the Neo-Confucian philosophy that
dominated Chinese thought from around AD 1000 until the early
twentieth century. This text proclaims that ‘Heaven is my father and
Earth is my mother, and even such a small creature as I nds an
intimate place in their midst. Therefore that which lls the universe
I regard as my body and that which directs the universe I consider
as my nature. All people are my brothers and sisters, and all things
are my companions.’ (Quoted in Chan 1963: 497.) The modern
academic West has largely lost touch with this intuition since being
in the grip of an overly mechanical, reductive view of nature, a view
that I argue elsewhere is severely called into question by quantum
mechanics and general relativity (Collins 2006).12
NOTES
REFERENCES
BRADSHAW, DAVID (2004). Aristotle East and West: Metaphysics and the
Division of Christendom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
——— (2001). ‘Kenotic Creation and Divine Action’, in id. (ed.), The
Work of Love: Creation as Kenosis. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 90–
106.
——— (2002). The God of Hope and the End of the World. New
Haven: Yale University Press.
DIVINE PROVIDENCE
THOMAS P. FLINT
INTRODUCTION
The questions that freedom poses for divine control are thus
varied and serious. No less serious are those that freedom raises for
God’s knowledge. If we’re free, don’t we have to set de nite limits
to God’s knowledge, especially to his foreknowledge? How could he
know what a free being is going to do before that free being decides
to do it? If God already knows, infallibly and unchangeably, what
I’m going to do long before I do it—even long before I’m born—how
could I possibly do otherwise? Mustn’t we, then, concede that a God
who leaves some of his creatures free surrenders not only the
control, but also the knowledge that the traditional picture of
providence a ords him?
God, the great Creator of all things, doth uphold, direct, dispose,
and govern all creatures, actions, and things, from the greatest even
to the least, by his most wise and holy providence, according to his
infallible foreknowledge, and the free and immutable counsel of his
own will, to the praise of the glory of his wisdom, power, justice,
goodness, and mercy.
According to this tradition, God is not merely the one who brought
all things into being. All aspects of his creation depend upon his
sustaining presence, and all (great and small) are subject to his
control. As the last line of the passage makes clear, God’s plan for
the world is not merely all-encompassing, but fully in accord with
the divine perfections of justice, goodness, and mercy. And that
plan, the quotation clearly implies, is not one that God makes up as
he goes along. Rather, he foreknows all that will occur, and thus
(one would assume) is neither surprised by what happens nor forced
to alter his intentions as events move in directions unanticipated by
him.
I hope as well that enough has been said to see why there at
least appears to be a tension between providence (understood in the
strong traditional manner delineated above) and freedom
(interpreted in a libertarian manner). On the one hand, providence
postulates complete divine foreknowledge of and control over all
that occurs, including human actions. Libertarianism, on the other
hand, insists that external determination of an action is
incompatible with that action’s being free. To endorse providence,
then, it seems we need to deny that there are any free actions, at
least as understood by libertarians; to endorse libertarian freedom, it
seems we must deny (or at least limit) God’s providence. Given this
apparent tension, it is not surprising that Christians have attempted
to rectify matters by surrendering (or at least signi cantly
modifying) one or the other of the two positions that seem to lead to
our quandary. Let us now turn to the two directions in which these
attempts might be taken.
to the extent God does not exert active control over my decisions,
whether through other events or direct involvement, He does not
control them at all. He can therefore achieve His ends only by
reacting to what I do, and to that extent His plans are subordinated
to mine. In addition to weakening His sovereignty, this situation
also threatens God’s omniscience. It suggests He can know how I
will act in the circumstances in which I am placed only by observing
my actions. As creator, He is in the dark. He can know what the
possibilities are, but if my freedom makes for more than one, then
even His knowledge of the world He is creating appears to depend
on my action—an unsatisfactory situation to say the least. These
problems can be avoided if God is able to exercise creative control
in my actual choice.9
For the Thomist, then, God’s sovereignty requires that God have
control over our actions greater than libertarians have typically
allowed. Some Thomists suggest that God’s arranging of natural
causes that determine our actions is fully in accord with their
freedom. But this, to my understanding, has never been more than a
minority view among Thomists. Libertarians are right, they say, in
resisting the common contemporary compatibilist view of freedom
—the view that actions that are functions of the laws of nature and
prior states of the natural world can still be free provided that the
crucial determining events are of the right sort (such as the agent’s
own, fully embraced beliefs and desires) and bring about the action
in the normal way.10 What libertarians have failed fully to
appreciate, though, is that God is not just another natural cause.
God’s relation to his universe is utterly unique, and his determining
of his creatures’ actions no more robs them of their freedom than
does (say) Euripides’ authorial determination of Medea’s actions
mean that she lacks freedom within the world of the play. As
Aquinas famously put it:
There are, then, many directions in which the Thomist might go,
and the arguments quickly and predictably become quite complex.18
Still, many (probably most) Christians nd this approach
unsatisfactory. For them, surrendering a libertarian picture of
freedom is too high a price to pay to resolve the tension between
freedom and providence. If one still feels that the apparent
incompatibility between the two is genuine, the only remaining
route of escape is to amend the strong, traditional notion of
providence that we earlier described. And this route takes us to
Open Theism.
we naturally assume that the idea is that, had the world gone as it
in fact did up until noon yesterday, and had I then asked you to join
me, you’d have agreed. We’re not, for example, asking how you
would have reacted had I asked you to lunch at noon after
performing some action (say, insulting you vilely at 11:45) that, as a
matter of fact, I didn’t perform. With some counterfactuals, of
course, the consequent is stated in a manner no more precise than
the antecedent. Take, for example, the memorable words sung by
Tevye in Fiddler on the Roof:
Now, pretend that you (unlike Hasker) are a skeptic concerning non-
conditional future contingent propositions (such as Framboise will
freely order a raspberry sundae tomorrow). You’re perfectly willing to
agree that things were and are a certain way, but not willing
(because of human freedom and/or God’s freedom and/or quantum
indeterminacy and/or whatever) to grant that things will be a certain
way. If so, you’d be apt to think that (GP) is unduly complicated, for
there are no concrete states of a airs that will exist. (There are lots
that might exist, but none that de nitely will.) So you decide to help
Hasker out. Instead of saying that a thing ‘exists’ just in case it
‘exists’ now, or has existed, or will exist, you suggest, we should
really say that something ‘exists if and only if it exists now or has
existed—period. Instead of the painfully swollen (GP), you say, all
we need is a thinner, more modest principle:
(GP–), you note, seems to work just as well against the Molinist as
the original (GP) did. So Hasker, you conclude, should look upon
the move to (GP–) as but a friendly amendment strengthening his
argument.
It’s fairly obvious, though, that Hasker would view this alteration
as anything but friendly. Excluding counterfactuals of creaturely
freedom from the realm of the contingently true is not enough to
make a grounding principle plausible for Hasker; it also needs to
include all those contingent propositions that should rank as
grounded. Since (GP–) wouldn’t allow us to say that Framboise will
freely order a raspberry sundae tomorrow is true, and since we need a
grounding principle that does allow such truths, we need the bee er
(GP), not the comparatively emaciated (GP–).
But, of course, what’s good for the Openist goose is good for the
Molinist gander. Suppose the Molinist assumes that contingent
truths need grounding. He, like Hasker, will assume as well that he
knows some of the major classes of such truths. He knows that there
are non-conditional contingent truths about the past and about the
present; he knows (let’s assume) that there are laws of nature and
‘would-probably’ conditionals; he knows that there are non-
conditional contingent truths about the future; and he knows that
there are true counterfactuals of creaturely freedom. Like Hasker, then,
he won’t start with a grounding principle and use it to decide
whether or not the members of one of these classes of propositions
are in fact contingent truths. Things work the other way around.
He’ll start with the classes of propositions he feels con dent about
and fashion a grounding principle that will (at a minimum) not rule
any of them out. Counterfactuals of creaturely freedom would be
ungrounded if (GP) were an adequate account of grounding, but so
what? Since it doesn’t let them in, it just follows that it s not
adequate. What we need is a bee er principle, one that
acknowledges that grounding states or events include not only ones
that do, did, or will exist, but ones that would exist (under speci ed
conditions). What we need, in other words, is something more on
the order of
CONCLUSION
I have argued that theories of divine providence are of three basic
types. Each such type has its advantages and its disadvantages. Each
has had numerous able and creative defenders. As with most
philosophical disputes, one can hardly expect this debate to come to
an end. I suspect that the eld of battle may shift more clearly in the
coming years to considerations of which view, when applied to
speci c doctrines (such as the Incarnation), o ers us the most
satisfying overall position. Still, it seems quite likely that all three
positions will continue to be defended (and attacked) for the
foreseeable future.
NOTES
1. For the rest of this chapter, I will speak of the Christian notion
of providence. In general (though with some obvious
exceptions), what I say would apply equally well within the
Jewish or Muslim traditions.
7. I will, by and large, henceforth dispense with this quali er, but
the reader should understand it to be tacitly present in most of
the following discussion.
8. The language here is borrowed from my colleague David
Burrell. See e.g. his Freedom and Creation in Three Traditions
(Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1993), 112.
12. The words quoted are from McCann, ‘Divine Sovereignty’, 593.
20. Though Openists agree that God cannot know (or even believe)
propositions about what free creatures will freely do, they
di er as to whether or not there are any such propositions that
are in fact true. For an interesting discussion of the
alternatives, see Dale Tuggy, ‘Three Roads to Open Theism’,
Faith and Philosophy 24 (2007), 28–51.
23. It’s also worth noting that an Open Theist could view a God
who constantly uses his knowledge of would-probably
conditionals to interfere with human events as a tad too
manipulative. For an interesting presentation of such a view,
see James Rissler, ‘Open Theism: Does God Risk or Hope?’,
Religious Studies 42 (2006), 63–74.
24. For a fuller discussion of this issue, see William Hasker, God,
Time, and Knowledge (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988),
194–6, and my Divine Providence, 100–2.
28. See especially Hasker, Providence, Evil and the Openness of God,
‘Appendix: Replies to My Critics.
38. See Alvin Plantinga, ‘On Ockham’s Way Out’, Faith and
Philosophy 3 (1986), 235–69.
PETITIONARY PRAYER
SCOTT A. DAVISON
No. On the one hand, this account demands too much. Imagine—
just for the sake of the argument; I shall argue below that this
scenario is problematic—that I pray for a certain person to recover
from a serious illness, and that God answers my prayer by healing
this person. But suppose that as it happens, if I had not prayed for
this, then you would have prayed for it instead, and God would
have answered your prayer by healing this person in exactly the
same way. Do we really want to say that my prayer was not
answered in the actual sequence of things, just because the recovery
in question would have happened even if I had not prayed for it?
Clearly not. So in order for a prayer to be answered, it is not
necessary that if the person had not prayed for the event in
question, then it would not have occurred.4
If something like this were to happen, then it would be true that the
event in question would not have happened if I had not prayed for
it. But in this kind of case, we need not say that my prayer was
answered by God, since the very act of praying for the victims could
lead to comfort for the hurricane victims all by itself, even if God
did not exist.5 So in order for a prayer to be answered, it is not
su cient that if the person had not prayed for the event in question,
then it would not have occurred.
2. A REASONS ACCOUNT
Let us suppose that in the end, I chose to attend art school. How
might I explain why I made this decision? I will want to nd a
statement of the form ‘I chose art school because—’, where I can ll
in the blank with a plausible reason. What constraints would we
want to impose upon di erent ways of trying to complete this
statement? At the very least, we would like the statement as a whole
to be a true description of my reasons for choosing art school over
the other alternatives.
Imagine for the sake of the argument that someone asks God to
bring about the occurrence of some event E. Suppose also that God
has a number of good reasons for bringing about E already, and now
that someone has prayed for E to occur, God has yet another reason
for bringing about E.14 To complete the story, let us imagine that
God freely brings about the occurrence of E (in the libertarian sense
of ‘freely’). Could this qualify as a case of answered prayer?
Since God brings about E freely, God could have decided instead
not to bring about E, in those very same circumstances, even though
God had all the same reasons for bringing about E that God actually
possesses.15 But then how can the sum total of God’s reasons for
bringing about E possibly explain God’s decision to bring about E?
After all, those same reasons are compatible with God’s choosing
not to bring about E, so they do not explain why God chose to bring
about E as opposed to choosing not to bring about E.16 Since the
sum total of God’s reasons for bringing about E cannot explain why
God chose to bring it about, neither can any subset of those reasons,
including the o ering of the prayer for E. So it is not the case that
God brought about E at least in part because of the prayer, which
implies that this is not a case of answered prayer after all. Let us call
this ‘the divine freedom problem’ of petitionary prayer.
Some traditional theists have held the view that God must always
do what is best,20 that God is obligated to do everything possible to
maximize value in every situation.21 If this were so, then of course
God would be obligated to do anything for which anyone prays if
such prayers happen to specify the maximum value available in a
given situation. But in nearly all these cases,22 God will be obligated
to bring about those same states of a airs even if nobody prays for
them,23 which implies that God’s bringing about those states of
a airs would not qualify as answers to prayers, since the o ering of
prayer would not play an important enough role among God’s
reasons for bringing them about (according to the reasons account
of answered prayer developed above).
Choi claims that God might not maximize the goodness in every
human life in order to leave room for the improvement of our lives
due to divine rewards and acts of human love. E cacious
petitionary prayers express praiseworthy attitudes, which God
would naturally choose to reward (2003: 9–10).42 Choi claims that
‘[petitionary] prayerlessness betrays a practical lack of faith and
trust in God’ (ibid. 11), but as we shall see below, this is not
necessarily the case. And there are ways other than petitionary
prayer to manifest praiseworthy attitudes.
First, consider the claim that one’s relationship with God would
be de cient in some way without answered prayers.45 Why should
this be so? What should matter here is not that God brings about
good things for people in response to petitionary prayers, but rather
that God loves them and provides for them, whether or not they ask
for anything speci cally. There is something inappropriately
egocentric to insist that one be a cause (in some sense) of God’s
action in the world, rather than simply being grateful for God’s
provident care. Traditional theists believe that every good thing
comes from God (ultimately, if not directly), and none of the
problems outlined here with petitionary prayer applies to other
kinds of prayers, such as prayers of thanksgiving.
NOTES
3. For instance, see Swinburne 1998: 115; Flint 1998: 222, 226;
Murray 2004: 243; and Basinger 2004: 255. The exception to
the rule here is Flint (1998: 227 n. 22), who thinks that
counterfactual dependence is probably not su cient for
answered prayer.
6. As Michael Rea has pointed out to me, ‘good’ here must mean
something like ‘good, all things considered’, as opposed to
‘intrinsically good’.
11. I shall ignore here the question of whether or not God creates
the values at stake in all situations (see Davison 1991a). I do
not assume in this chapter that God is morally obligated to
maximize the value in each situation; I shall say more about
this below, in sect. 4.
15. For those who are fond of talking this way, if God acts freely in
the actual world, then there is a possible world in which God
does otherwise, and God’s reasons and circumstances are the
same in that possible world as they are in the actual world
before the point of the decision to do otherwise.
18. I say here that ‘nothing in the world’ could determine God’s
actions, but some theists are inclined to believe that God’s
actions are determined by God’s own nature, thereby avoiding
both a libertarian account of God’s freedom and the view that
God’s actions are determined by something in the world.
(Thanks to Kate Rogers for reminding me of this fact.) This
view implies that if a person prays for the right thing in the
right circumstances, then given God’s nature, God cannot
refuse to answer the prayer. I nd this conclusion to be highly
at odds with traditional theism, but there is no doubt that the
problems of petitionary prayer may force traditional theists to
take a hard look at the nature of divine freedom. For more on
this question, see the discussions mentioned in n. 8 and the
detailed and provocative discussion of divine freedom in Rowe
2004.
19. Michael Rea has pointed out to me that there are several
responses one could make to this argument: (a) libertarianism
is false, in which case God needn’t be free in the libertarian
sense; (b) libertarianism is true, and the problems can be
solved (even though we can’t yet see how), in which case
there’s no special worry in the divine case. I can add two other
possible replies to his list: (c) we can live with this problem in
the human realm, but not with the puzzles it creates with
respect to God and answered prayer; (d) traditional theists
who believe (naturally enough) that God is free in the
libertarian sense have inconsistent beliefs, but it’s not clear
what they should do about it. These are all interesting
responses. For the record, I am not arguing here that there is a
special problem for freedom and explanation in the divine
case, just that there is a problem in the divine case, given the
way that most traditional theists think about divine freedom,
and that the reasons account enables us to appreciate it in a
new way.
21. Here I shall ignore the di erence between saying that God
must do what is best and saying that God is obligated to do
what is best. Thanks to Michael Rea for reminding me of the
di erence.
22. I say that this is true in nearly all cases because Thomas P. Flint
has pointed out that there are cases in which the very o ering
of the prayer changes the circumstances, and hence changes
what would be the best outcome in a situation (see Flint 1998:
222). In these cases, though, God is responding to the change
in the circumstances caused by the o ering of the prayer,
rather than responding to the o ering of the prayer per se, and
so they do not seem to be cases of answered prayer, either,
according to the reasons account. (I shall say more about this
kind of case below in sect. 5.)
24. This line of thinking suggests that the divine goodness problem
might lead to another practical problem for petitionary prayer
for those who nd it hard to believe that God would adopt this
sort of policy; see n. 13 above for a discussion of other
practical problems of prayer.
32. Since there is no way to know that God regularly enlightens the
minds of petitioners when a prayer is answered (and fails to do
so when the prayers in question were not answered but God
decided to bring about the events in question anyway), one
could always wonder whether one’s belief that God had
answered a prayer was true or justi ed. If God had
enlightened one’s mind, then it would be justi ed (but only
according to an externalist conception of justi cation: see n.
26 above) and true. But if one had simply tried to explain to
oneself what had happened after the o ering of a prayer in a
psychologically or spiritually satisfying fashion, even though
God had not enlightened one’s mind because God had brought
about the event in question for independent reasons, then
one’s belief would be false and unjusti ed.
34. It is worth noting in passing that people actually draw all kinds
of ridiculous conclusions about God on the basis of their
experiences involving prayer. The point here is that none of
these conclusions is justi ed.
41. See Choi 2003. In practice, of course, people pray only for
those things that lie beyond their immediate control; nobody
prays that God would pass the salt, for instance.
42. See ibid. Lawrence Masek 2000: 274 . makes a similar point.
43. ‘It’s so much easier to pray for a bore than to go and see him’:
Lewis 1963: 66.
REFERENCES
ADAMS, ROBERT M. (2002). Finite and In nite Goods. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
KANE, ROBERT (1985). Free Will and Values. Albany, NY: State
University of New York Press.
LEHRER, KEITH (1990). Theory of Knowledge. Boulder, Colo.:
Westmont.
MARK C. MURPHY
By ‘morality’ I mean the set of all of the valid norms of the form
‘x is morally required to φ’, where x ranges over human beings and
φ over action-types, and where to be morally required is to be
categorically reason-giving, overriding, and justi able from an
impartial point of view.2 (I assume this set of norms is nonempty.)
Some such norms may be universally quanti ed, and unquali ed
(e.g. for all x, x is morally required to φ); some such norms may be
universally quanti ed, and quali ed (e.g. for all x, any x who is P is
morally required to φ); some such norms may be particular (e.g. A
[who is an x]is morally required to φ). To be a moral fact is to be an
obtaining state of a airs of the form ‘x’s being morally required to
φ’, whether of this universal or particular form. On this stipulative
de nition, then, assuming that they obtain, all the following states
of a airs are moral facts: everyone’s being morally required not to kill
the innocent; the well-o ’s being morally required to aid to the less-well-
o ; and Bob Dylan’s being morally required not to break promises.
Our question is whether every moral fact is (or must be, or even can
be) explained by facts about God. What, though, are the available
strategies for explaining moral facts?
Consider the following moral fact, and how one might explain it.
It is a fact that Mark Murphy is morally required to show up to
teach his classes at Georgetown University. There is an obvious
explanation for this fact. The obvious explanation is that people are
morally required to do what they agree to do, and Mark Murphy has
agreed to show up to teach his classes at Georgetown University.
This moral fact and its explanation are trivial. What is important
is the structure of the explanation for moral facts suggested by the
example. One way that we often explain a moral fact is by
subsuming that moral fact under another moral fact of broader
extension, together with a supplementary non-moral fact. The
relevant relationship between the more particular moral fact to be
explained and the more general moral fact that does the explaining
is that of instantiation, in that the more particular moral fact is an
instance of the more general fact: because Mark Murphy has made
the agreement to show up to teach his classes, Mark Murphy’s being
morally required to show up to teach his classes is an instance of Mark
Murphy’s being morally required to do what he has agreed to do. Call
this model of explanation of moral facts explanation by way of
moral subsumption.6
I want to make three points about this model of explanation. The
rst is that one might well explain a number of moral facts by
appeal to non-moral facts about God’s existence, nature, or activity
conjoined with a general moral fact about how persons are morally
required to respond to God or to facts about God’s existence, nature,
or activity. One might claim that it is wrong to torture humans
because it is wrong to express disrespect for what is an image of the
divine perfection, humans are images of the divine perfection, and
to torture expresses disrespect for humans. One might claim that it
is wrong to ignore the plight of those undeservedly in need because
God has commanded us to look after those undeservedly in need,
and people are morally required to do what God commands. It is
clear that in these cases, the requirements not to torture and to
assist the needy are explained by appeal to non-moral facts about
God (humans are images of God; God has given a certain command)
that allows a more speci c moral norm to be subsumed as an
instance of a more general norm.
Let us turn, then, to those moral facts that are not explainable by
way of moral subsumption. Suppose it is true that all these moral
facts are theistically explained. If so, then ThEM will be true. For
every moral fact explainable by way of moral subsumption is
ultimately explained by way of some fact not explainable by moral
subsumption. If all the facts not explainable by moral subsumption
are theistically explained, and if the conditional point in the
previous paragraph is correct, then ThEM will turn out to be true.
Here is another option. One might claim that of the moral facts
not explained via subsumption, some of them are self-explanatory.
Alexander Pruss writes that a fact is self-explanatory if
understanding the fact, and that it obtains, is su cient for
understanding why it obtains.9 As I mentioned above, I want the
notion of explanation here not to be observer-relative, and Pruss’s
de nition seems to make it so. But this is easily handled. We can say
that we are in a position to judge that some fact is self-explanatory
if we are in a position to know, upon understanding some fact and
that it obtains, why it obtains. Our understanding why something
obtains upon knowing that it obtains is our basic test for the self-
explanatory, though it is surely prone to err by failing to identify
some facts as self-explanatory that really are.
One might think it obvious that if some of these moral facts are
self-explanatory, then ThEM must be false: for if some of these
moral facts are self-explained, then they are not explained by God’s
existence, nature, or activity, and that contradicts ThEM. But there
is at least an initially plausible way of bringing ThEM and the thesis
that some moral facts are self-explanatory into consistency.
Here’s a model for the consistency of ThEM and the self-
explanatory character of some moral facts. Suppose that there is a
single moral fact that explains all moral facts distinct from it.
Suppose, for example, that the fact that people are morally required
to obey God explains all other moral facts; for every other morally
required act-type, it has its status as such in virtue of being
commanded by God. Why are we morally required to refrain from
telling lies? Because we are morally required to obey God, and God
commanded us not to tell lies. And so forth.
One might plausibly make two claims about this moral fact. The
rst is that it is self-explanatory. If one grasps that the state of
a airs people’s being morally required to obey God obtains, then one is
in a position to see why it obtains. James Rachels writes:
To bear the title ‘God’ …a being must have certain quali cations.
He must, for example, be all-powerful and perfectly good in
addition to being perfectly wise. And in the same vein, to apply the
title ‘God’ to a being is to recognise him as one to be obeyed…. And
to recognise any being as God is to acknowledge that he has
unlimited authority, and an unlimited claim on one’s allegiance….
That God is not to be judged, challenged, de ed, or disobeyed, is at
bottom a truth of logic.10
Rachels holds both that people are morally required to obey God is
self-evident (its truth is immediately knowable a priori) and self-
explanatory (why it is true is a matter of logic).
The second thing that one might claim about this moral fact is
that it is also a theistic fact. It is a fact about God: God is such that
people are morally required to obey him. This is not a mere rigged-
up contingent fact, like God’s being such that there are three paper
clips on Murphy’s desk, or even a rigged-up necessary fact, like
God’s being such that three is a prime number. This is a fact about
God, one might claim, a fact about how people are to relate to him.
And so, on this view, it is a fact about God’s existence and nature,
and thus quali es as a theistic fact.
As far as I can see, there is only one route of escape for one who
wants to claim that people are morally required to obey God is a
theistic fact. My argument has been that it does not follow from the
moral requirement’s telling us how to respond to God that it is a
theistic fact. But there are other ways that one might argue for this
being a theistic fact. If the property being morally required turns out
to be itself a theistic property, then the moral fact people are morally
required to obey God would be God’s-existence-involving. But on this
view the moral fact’s being God’s-existence-involving is not due to
its being a fact about how we should respond to God, as opposed to
how we should respond to each other, or ourselves, or dogs, or the
environment. (I will discuss this account of moral properties in
further detail below.) And even if it were to turn out that the best
account of the property being morally required is that this property is
a theistic property, that would do nothing to deal with the objection
that the moral fact in question is not self-explanatory.
Let us put to the side for the moment the possibility of defending
ThEM in terms of moral facts that are both theistic and self-
explanatory. There are various ways to divide up the sorts of theistic
explanations of moral facts that remain for consideration. One way
to divide them up is by the sort of theistic facts included in the
explanans: whether these theistic facts are facts about God’s
intrinsic nature, for example, or whether they are facts about God’s
free activity. Another way to distinguish them is by the sort of
explanatory relationship that holds between the theistic and moral
facts: whether the explanatory relationship is causal, for example, or
perhaps constitutive. Another way to divide them up is by whether
the explanatory relationship between theistic and moral facts is
immediate or mediated by other sorts of facts.
Take the Aristotelian view rst. One might claim that just as we
appeal to the intentions of a minded being to explain what counts as
the successful functioning of an artifact, we need to appeal to the
intentions of a minded being to explain what counts as the proper
actualization of the human being.
By contrast, on the Hobbesian view: one could say that what lls
the role that God’s ‘maker’s intentions’ have in the Aristotelian view
is the presence of desire in the human—so that there is a gap
between the way humans are, and the way that they must be if they
are to be ful lled. What’s more, some of these desires are necessarily
possessed by humans, and central to their motivational structures.
The special explanation of the moral in the Hobbesian scheme is to
be located in God’s making some creatures that have appetites,
indeed appetites that are characteristic of members of that kind.24
Why think this? Like Adams’s view, Zagzebski’s begins with a set
of claims that is not distinctively theistic: that in the construction of
ethical theories we should begin not with concept-analysis but with
cases, and in particular with exemplars of good persons.36 Starting
with clear cases of good persons, we can initially de ne good
outcomes, acts, traits, and motivations in terms of what good
persons would seek, want, and do. Such starting points are fully
compatible with a philosophical inquiry into what makes someone a
good person, just as starting our inquiry into tigers may rightly
begin with paradigm cases of tigers and starting our inquiry into
water may rightly begin with paradigm cases of water. But once we
take these starting points and situate them within a framework of
theistic belief, it is clear that our paradigm of good personhood is
chosen, so to speak, for us; we cannot but think of God as an
exemplar of a good person (unless one wants to deny God’s
personhood altogether), and we cannot think of God as simply one
good person among others. God will have to be at the center of the
view, and the best theory that places God at the center of the view,
Zagzebski thinks, will make God’s motivations central and de ning
of the good, and thus of moral requirement. All this turns out to
generate non-subsumed moral requirements that are necessary,
given (a) the necessity of the divine motivations, (b) the
characterization of good human motivation in terms of divine
motivation, and (c) the de nition of obligation as what must be
done by one who is properly motivated.
DIYINE AUTHORITY
I have been concerned thus far to see what sorts of strategies are
promising ways to defend ThEM. The strategies that I have been
discussing are global strategies, strategies to show that all non-
subsumed moral facts possess a common theistic explanation. But
there are ways to try to support ThEM, or to approach it, without
employing a global strategy. One might try to defend the full or
approximate truth of ThEM by appeal to speci c moral facts, the
application of which invariably requires a theistic fact. The most
common such strategy is an appeal to God’s status as legitimate
commander—we humans are under a moral requirement to obey
God, and so if God commands us to perform some action, then we
are morally required to perform that action.43
DA, the principle that God has rightful authority over us, can be
employed in a number of ways—some more ambitious, some less
ambitious—in one’s overall account of how moral facts are to be
explained. One might treat the fact that DA is true as a supreme and
architectonic moral principle. On this view, which one might call
normative divine command theory, that DA is the case is the sole non-
subsumed moral fact, and so serves as that moral fact that explains
every subsumed moral fact. For example, if it is true that one is
morally required not to lie, the explanation is that people are
morally required to obey God, and God has told us not to lie. But
this is not the only way that one might appeal to DA. One might
treat its obtaining as a supreme moral fact without holding that it is
the sole non-subsumed moral fact. On this view, while there are
moral facts that are not subsumed under the fact that DA obtains,
DA is nevertheless superior to the other principles, either by
qualifying them (for example, every distinct moral principle carries
the rider ‘unless God gives a command incompatible with this’) or
by being lexically ordered over them (that is, one’s primary duty is
to obey God; only once this is accomplished can one move on to the
ful llment of other moral principles). On this view, the principle
that we are morally required to obey God controls the application of
all other moral principles (and is not itself controlled by any of
them), but does not ground the validity of those principles. On yet a
third view, DA is not supreme; it is one principle among others.
(One might nd implausible this view, thinking that it would
suggest that God could give a command that it would be permissible
to disobey; and one might balk at that suggestion. But the allegedly
untoward consequence does not at all follow: it may be that God
necessarily would not give a command that requires violation of
other moral principles.) On one version of this third view, DA is a
moral principle that is not subsumed under a more fundamental
moral principle or principles; on another version, it is so
subsumed.46
There are two obvious points to be made here. The rst is that,
as I indicated earlier, even the strongest version of DA, on which DA
is the sole non-subsumed moral principle, would not of itself
establish ThEM. For it could be that DA lacks a theistic explanation
—it could be that we do not need to resort to any theistic facts—
facts about God’s existence, nature, or activity—to explain why DA
is true. The second is that the extent to which DA can explain the
range of moral facts depends on where DA is placed within the
system of moral facts. So when we turn, as we now will turn, to the
question of whether we should hold that DA is true, we should also
ask what these arguments for DA’s truth would tell us about
whether (1) DA is supreme and uniquely non-subsumed, or (2) it is
supreme and non-subsumed, but not uniquely so, or (3) it is not
supreme and non-subsumed, or (4) it is itself subsumed.
There are three bases from which arguments for God’s authority
have been launched. One of these bases we have already
encountered: a general account of how theistic facts are
explanatorily related to moral facts. On such an account, one aims
to show that given God’s explanatory relationship to the moral
order, it follows that God has authority over created rational beings.
A second of these bases is an appeal to the divine nature. On such
an account, one aims to show that given God’s perfection, it follows
that God is authoritative. A third is an appeal to widely held moral
principles by which DA is subsumed. On such an account, one
argues that given some correct moral principle or principles, alone
or in conjunction with facts that hold across all possible worlds in
which there are created rational beings, DA follows. But in my view
no extant argument tting within these schemas establishes the
correctness of DA.47
One might suppose that the a rmation of one of the views of God’s
relationship to morality discussed in the previous section would
surely be su cient to establish God’s authority. If morality as a
whole is dependent on God, one might think, then surely a fortiori
God has authority over created rational beings. But this is a mistake.
Quinn’s causation view does not entail DA, for example. Even if
one holds that every moral state of a airs that obtains is caused to
obtain by a free act of God’s, that would not show that humans are
morally required to obey God. God might, for example, have willed
only the moral requirements humans are morally required not to
coerce one another and humans are morally required not to defraud one
another to obtain. If so, then there would have been no moral
requirement to obey God; the fact that God tells someone to do
something would not make any action morally required. Only if God
were also to will humans are morally required to obey God would
obedience be a required act. The same holds true of the natural law
theories that place mediating natural facts as o ering explanations
of moral facts: that God is ultimately responsible for the moral
requirements to which created rational beings are subject does not
entail that those created rational beings are required to obey God.
Some have held, for example, that created rational beings are
God’s handiwork, and so are divine property. Of the number of
di culties for this position, the preeminent is that, of the plausible
rationales that we have for holding that being someone’s handiwork
establishes it the maker’s property, none of them goes through in
cases in which treating the handiwork as the maker’s property
necessarily involves an interference with another rational being’s
autonomy. The best case for holding that your making something
gives you rightful title to it and its use is that if in making that thing
you make others worse o in no way, including their freedom to act
at their discretion, it would be an unjust deprivation of your
freedom to be unable to make something for your own use and
enjoyment. But claiming rightful title over a human being itself
constitutes a deprivation of that human’s freedom to act at his or
her discretion. So on the best account of why making generates
rightful title, God’s making humans fails to explain God’s rightful
title over us.
This is less than we would hope for. But we should note that
other attempts to provide top-down philosophical accounts of
common authority relationships—in particular, the parent/child and
state/citizen—have su ered failures similar to that with which I
have charged the top-down arguments for divine authority.52 It may
well be that we are forced either reluctantly to accept the limited
usefulness of these bottom-up accounts of authority or to reject, in a
disturbingly wholesale way, the presence of these seemingly
paradigmatic authority relationships.
NOTES
I am grateful to Mike Rea, Tom Flint, Trenton Merricks, Alex
Pruss, Errol Pierre-Louis, Ryan Lupton, and Chuck Mackel for
their comments on earlier drafts of this chapter.
19. For accounts of God’s role in the dissolving of the salt by the
water alternative to that o ered by the occasionalist, see
Freddoso 1994.
26. Adams (1999: 281–2) does hold, though, that were there no
God, or if God were not good, then something else (for
example, the hypothetical intentions of an ideal observer)
might t the semantically indicated role of the morally
obligatory.
27. Ibid.257.
28. Ibid.233.
29. Ibid.245–6.
30. Ibid.232.
34. Ibid.129–220.
36. Ibid.40–50.
37. Ibid.51.
38. Ibid.41.
42. Ibid.225–6.
44. For a discussion of how God commands, see Adams 1999: 262–
70; for a more general account of God’s performance of speech
acts, see Wolterstor 1995.
49. One might say that it diminishes God’s power if God cannot
place us under moral requirements by giving us commands.
But it is no diminution of God’s power to say that there are
some things that God cannot do by way of doing other things
—at least, that God cannot do some things by way of other
things unless God has realized the further conditions that
enable this connection to hold. It does not diminish God’s
power to say, and to say truly, that God can create stop signs
by making octagonal red pieces of metal only if the world that
God has made includes the social practice of having red
octagonal pieces of metal as signs to stop. The point is that
whether God’s commands bring about moral requirements
may depend on certain background conditions obtaining (for
example, the existence of a distinct sort of rational being),
background conditions that are up to God’s discretion, the
failure of which to obtain precludes God’s commands from
being moral requirements.
REFERENCES
GEACH, PETER (1969). ‘The Moral Law and the Law of God’, in God
and the Soul. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 117–29.
PAUL DRAPER
INTRODUCTION
In this chapter, I will focus on questions about evil that are both
theological and doxastic, and more speci cally alethic—i.e.
questions about whether what we know about evil can be used to
establish the falsity or probable falsity of the belief or proposition
that God exists. Such a focus is natural for an agnostic (like me).1
More generally, it is natural for anyone who is engaged in genuine
inquiry about whether or not God exists. Such inquiry inevitably
raises questions such as: does the evil in the world provide the
resources for proving that God does not exist (e.g. because it can be
shown to be logically incompatible with God’s existence)? If not,
does it nevertheless provide some evidence against God’s existence
(in the sense that it lowers the probability of God’s existing)? If it
does, then how strong is this evidence? And if this evidence is
strong (in the sense that it decreases the ratio of the probability of
theism to the probability of its denial many-fold), is it also
signi cant (in the sense that it makes a large di erence to the
probability of theism being true)? Answers to these questions are no
doubt relevant to many other doxastic problems of evil (and to
a ective and practical problems as well), but alethic problems of
evil are not identical to any of those other problems. For example,
no alethic problem is identical to the problem of whether or not the
evil in the world renders belief in God irrational. After all, a false or
probably false belief can be rational (in more than one distinct sense
of that word); and a true or probably true belief can, of course, be
irrational.
MT ARGUMENTS
One might object here that no good, no matter how great, could
justify allowing such horri c evils as the torturing of innocent
children. (The character Ivan in Fyodor Dostoevsky’s The Brothers
Karamazov is often interpreted to be making this claim.) Indeed,
some philosophers (e.g. D. Z. Phillips 2004) seem to object to the
whole notion of an ‘outweighing’ good. To be sure, this notion
should be rejected if it implies that all value can be measured on a
single numerical scale or if it presupposes a crude consequentialist
understanding of morality. It need not be interpreted in this way,
however. In fact, it is even compatible with the position that no
good, no matter how great, ‘outweighs’ the harm done to an
individual unless it bene ts that individual. This last point is
important because, for all we know, (1) there may exist goods far
more valuable than any we can imagine, (2) these goods may
logically imply the existence or risk of horri c evils, and (3) these
goods may (if there is life after death) include among their
bene ciaries the victims of horri c evils. If this possibility is taken
seriously (and admittedly not all philosophers think it should be
taken seriously or even that it is a possibility), then it is hard to be
con dent that the notion of an outweighing good breaks down in the
face of horri c evil, especially given how imprecise and fallible our
moral intuitions are. Therefore, since I believe this possibility should
be taken seriously, I do not see how it is possible to construct a
convincing logical argument from evil against theism, and for that
reason the rest of the arguments from evil I discuss in this chapter
will be evidential ones.4
(R) For all goods g that we know of, g does not justify God in
permitting horri c su ering.
Although Otte himself does not put it exactly this way, the
problem he identi ed is that the evidence statement R very subtly
understates what we know about the relationship of goods we know
of to horri c su ering. This makes it appear that there is a stronger
case against theism based on ‘inscrutable evils’ than there really is.
To see why, compare R with
(R*) For all goods g that we know of, either God exists and g does
not justify God in permitting horri c su ering, or God does
not exist and, if God were to exist, then g would not justify
God in permitting horri c su ering.
I then turn this prima facie case for premise 2 into an ultima
facie one by arguing for two further claims. The rst is that,
contrary to what the theodicist would have us believe, the known
moral roles played by pain and pleasure in the world do not
signi cantly raise the probability of O given theism. They may raise
the probability of certain individual facts reported by O (e.g. the
fact that su ering sometimes leads to improved moral character),
but only by making other facts reported by O even more surprising
(e.g. the fact that su ering is often demoralizing). The second claim
is that, contrary to what the skeptical theist would have us believe,
the possibility of God having moral reasons unknown to us to permit
O does not undermine my case for premise 2, because God’s having
reasons to permit O that are unknown to us is no more likely
antecedently than God’s having reasons to prevent O that are
unknown to us.
The idea here is that, if B is, for example, some Christian belief, then
P(e/T) will be an average of P(e/T&B) and P(e/T&∼B). What makes
it an average is the fact that P(B) + P(∼B) = 1. But it is not
necessarily a straight average because P(B/T) and P(∼B/T) may not
each equal Thus, for example, if P(B/T) = and P(∼B/T) = then
P(e/T&B) is given twice as much weight as P(e/T&B) in calculating
the average.
Consider, for example, the belief that there is life after death (L’
for short). Suppose that P(L/T) were very high and also that
P(O/L&T) were much greater than P(O/HI). Then the second
premise of my evidential argument from evil would be false,
because P(O/T) = P(L/T) x P(O/L&T) + P(∼L/T) x P(O/∼L&T).
Of course, while I do believe that P(L/T) is high, I don’t believe for a
moment that P(O/L&T) is much greater than P(O/HI). The
hypothesis that we will survive death explains very little of what we
know about pain and pleasure. The point I want to make here,
however, is that there is a precise method for evaluating the
relevance of other religious and non-religious beliefs to Bayesian
arguments from evil. The same method should be used to evaluate
how successful various theodicies or defenses are in undermining
(the second premise of) a Bayesian argument from evil.
NOTES
11. Consider the following two statements: (1) ‘ball #1 is red and
ball #2 is red’ and (2) ‘ball #1 is red and ball #2 is green’.
These two statements are equally speci c, but the rst is
intrinsically more probable than the second because it is more
coherent.
REFERENCES
ALSTON, W.(1991). ‘The Inductive Argument from Evil and the
Human Cognitive Condition’, Philosophical Perspectives 5: 29–67.
——— (1991). ‘Evil and the Proper Basicality of Belief in God’, Faith
and Philosophy 8:135–47.
——— (2007). ‘The Argument from Evil’, in Paul Copan and Chad
Meister (eds.), Philosophy
THEODICY
MICHAEL J. MURRAY
INTRODUCTION
DURING a recent visit to Germany, Pope Benedict XVI visited the Nazi
death camp at Auschwitz. While surveying the memorial to the
nearly 1.5 million victims, he found himself at a loss for words of
explanation or consolation: ‘In this place, words fail. In the end,
there can only be dread silence—a silence which is itself a heartfelt
cry to God … How could you tolerate all this?’ Washington Post
columnist Richard Cohen commented as follows:
Religious people can wrestle with the Pope’s remarks. What does it
mean that God was silent? That he approved? That he liked what he
saw? That he didn’t give a damn? You tell me. And what does it
mean that he could ‘tolerate all this’? That the Nazis were OK by
him? That even the murder of Catholic clergy was no cause of
intercession? I am at a loss to explain this. I cannot believe in such a
God. (Cohen 2006: A10)
Theists and atheists alike seem to agree that evil does indeed count
against the existence of God. And it is not merely the vast quantities
of evil that stagger belief. In addition, it seems that the types and
distribution of evil t poorly with the claim that the world is
providentially directed by an all-good, all-powerful creator. While
we might admit that a comprehensive divine plan for the universe
could be expected to include some evil, how can we be expected to
accept that senseless torture, degrading sexual abuse, catastrophic
tsunamis, and so on are also components of such a plan? And what
is more, how can theists explain the fact that the distribution of evil
seems almost entirely random? Vice and su ering on the one hand,
and virtue and happiness on the other, do not seem proportional in
this life, a fact acknowledged by religious believers and atheists
alike. In the words of the Hebrew prophet Jeremiah: ‘You are
always righteous, O LORD, when I bring a case before you. Yet I
would speak with you about your justice: Why does the way of the
wicked prosper? Why do all the faithless live at ease?’ (Jer. 12: 3).
Needless to say, the pattern of evil we nd in the world does not
exactly t our initial expectations of what a world would look like if
theism were true.
From Leibniz’s time until the mid-1970s, the word ‘theodicy’ was
used to describe attempts of this sort to explain God’s permission of
evil. Since the mid-1970s however, the word has taken on a more
re ned sense among philosophers of religion, a change that can be
attributed to Alvin Plantinga’s book God, Freedom and Evil (1974). In
this work, Plantinga distinguishes between two types of
explanations of evil that theists might construct. The rst type is
o ered in response to arguments that the coexistence of God and
evil is impossible. Explanations of this sort, which Plantinga calls
‘defenses’, need only show the logical compatibility of God and evil.
The second type aims to provide plausible and perhaps even likely-
to-be-true explanations of evil, explanations that show that the
existence of evil is not unlikely given the existence of God (or
perhaps given the existence of God and some additional plausible
and/or likely-to-be-true claims). Plantinga labeled explanations of
this latter sort ‘theodicies’ (ibid. 27–8). Plantinga’s distinction has
left a lasting mark on the eld and indeed, in the contemporary
literature, philosophers of religion use the term ‘theodicy’ in this
narrower sense, and it is in this sense that it will be addressed in
this chapter.
RECENT DETERRENTS TO THEODICY
Second, since God cannot foresee the future, he leaves the door
open, when creating, to the possibility that that world will
ultimately turn out to be lled with free creatures who willfully
despise God and scorn their neighbors. As a result, open theists are
not entitled to claim—though they often do—that God can create
with su cient con dence that things will not ultimately come to
ruin. In addition, given God’s lack of foresight, there are two
possible outcomes that might arise in a world with free creatures,
either of which should provide su cient reason for God to refrain
from creating at all. First, if the world might come to ruin as
described, then it might come to have evils that are not outweighed
by the goods the world contains. Second, if God cannot foresee how
creatures will freely choose, those creatures might choose to do
things that it is not within God’s rights to permit. In either case, it
would be impermissible for God to risk creating at all.
Finally, even if it is true that there are some evils that God
cannot prevent because they cannot be foreseen, there are other
evils that God can foresee and yet still permits, even on open
theism. Because of this, the open theist’s explanation of evil has less
vindicating power than one might have initially thought. Elsewhere,
Michael Rea and I have expressed this worry as follows:
(P) For any innocent person S, God has the right to allow S to
su er only if there’s some outweighing good that S wouldn’t
enjoy if God didn’t allow S so to su er.
Others have argued instead that the principle applies only under
conditions that make it inapplicable to God. For example, one
person (X) can justly allow another person (Y) to su er even when
the su ering does not yield a net bene t for Y, under the following
conditions: (a) X is in a position of lawful authority over Y and any
others who stand to gain or lose from Y’s su ering; (b) X is
responsible for the welfare of Y and these others; (c) the good to be
gained by allowing Y to su er substantially outweighs the su ering
experienced by Y; and (d) there is no other way to obtain the goods
produced by allowing Y’s su ering without permitting some
situation in which the overall balance of goods and evils is worse.
For example, the state might be permitted to quarantine a patient
with a virulent and incurable disease, perhaps without the bene t of
even being able to receive medical treatment, in order to protect
other citizens from contracting the disease. Since God has lawful
authority over us that exceeds the authority of the state, and since
God is responsible for the well-being of the entirety of his creation,
God too might be in a rightful position to allow there to be
uncompensated victims of su ering if that were necessary for
securing certain outweighing goods (van Inwagen 1995: 121).7
Successful theodicies must show that the evils they treat are
connected to securing outweighing goods. Thus in this case we
ought to ask: is it reasonable to think that evils of divine
punishment secure greater goods? Answering that question depends
on what punishment is supposed to be good for. Defenders of the
punishment theodicy have argued that punishment can be good for
one (or more) of four things: rehabilitation, deterrence, societal
protection, and retribution.
Now let’s imagine that God is faced with the prospect of creating
a universe. Wanting to ll the creation with the greatest types of
good, God decides to create a world containing a number of
creatures with free choice. Can God create a world with such freely
choosing creatures who never choose to do wrong? Maybe or maybe
not. We just don’t know. When God considers all the possible
universes he can create with free creatures in them, it just might
turn out that in every one of them, at least one of the creatures (or
perhaps even every one of the creatures) in them chooses to do
wrong. And if that’s right, then God cannot create a world that
contains the good of free choice but that also has no evil in it. In
this case, putting up with moral evil is the price God in fact must
pay in order to get a universe with the very great good of creatures
with free choice.8
The rst question to ask here is: What would it look like if God
were to do so? I intend to pull the trigger to shoot you but suddenly
nd that my nger is paralyzed, or… I intend to steal the car but
when I rear back to throw the brick at the car window to gain entry,
I suddenly fall asleep. Would this su ce? In one sense it would.
Were the world so con gured, I would not be able to bring about
any evil beyond my evil choices. Unfortunately, the result of such an
arrangement is that, before long, I would not be able to make evil
choices either. The reason for this is that my experience will make it
clear to me that doing evil is in fact impossible. We can see this by
considering an example. When I was 5 years old, I and a few friends
decided that we would jump from a concrete wall and y. After
twenty minutes of consistent failure and sore fannies, we could see
that ying was not in our future. To the best of my knowledge, no
one in that group has since been tempted to y o a concrete wall.
Indeed, I suspect none of my kindergarten companions could now
even form the intention to y o the wall. They know by their
experience that doing so is as impossible as leaping to the moon or
swallowing the ocean. If God were simply to block the evil
consequences as the virtual playpen scenario advocates, choosing
evil would be no more possible for us than choosing to y is for us
in the actual world.9
Could the laws of nature have been con gured to yield a world
that has a substantially better overall balance of good than our
world? To show that such a better world is possible, we would need
to describe a regular, lawlike world that (a) contains goodness of
the sorts (either the same sorts or equivalent or better sorts) and
amounts found in the actual world and which (b) contains
substantially less natural evil than the actual world. There are two
problems with trying to o er such a description. First, there is good
reason to think that there is not much wiggle room in the way the
laws and constants of the world are structured. One fairly recent
discovery of scientists is that the cosmos seems to be balanced on a
razor’s edge in such a way that were the laws and constants that
govern its activity slightly di erent, the cosmos would be unable to
sustain intelligent life (Barr 2003: 118–38). This provides us with
some good reason to suppose that if the universe is going to be
capable of supporting life, it will have to be governed by laws and
constants similar to those we nd in the actual world.10 Second,
even if a better set of laws could be speci ed, it is doubtful that we
could know this. Knowing such a thing would require knowing how
changes we propose to certain laws and constants would impact not
only the natural evils we are trying to prevent, but other laws of
nature and the goods and evils that arise from their mutual
interactions. It is unreasonable to think we could unscramble such
things and thus unreasonable to think that the laws might be
changed to yield a better world with less natural evil.
Soul-Making Theodicies
Animal su ering is all the more vexing when we realize that the
theodicies considered so far do not o er much help in explaining it.
Even if some of the explanations take us some way towards
explaining the reality of animal su ering (some animal su ering is
caused by the evil free choices of humans, for example), most of it is
still entirely unexplained. In general, there are two facts about
animal su ering that seem to make it especially resistant to
explanation using traditional theodicies. First, most animal su ering
predates the advent of human beings. As a result, any theodicy that
aims to explain evil as a consequence or precondition of human free
choice, soul-making, and the like is going to struggle to explain
animal su ering. Second, there does not seem to be any reason on
the earlier described theodicies that God would have to create
animals capable of experiencing pain and su ering in the rst place.
If a world with natural regularities is one in which organisms might
sometimes become innocent victims of the forces of nature, it might
be better, all things considered, not to out t non-human animals
with the tools that allow them to experience pain and su ering in
the rst place.
First, some theists have tried to account for the reality of animal
pain and su ering not as a result of the misuse of human free choice
but rather as a result of the misuse of the free choice of non-human
free creatures. There is a long tradition in western theism of
supposing the existence of creatures (demons, for example) with
free choice whose existence predates human existence. If such
beings did or do exist, they might perhaps have had powers
su cient to steer evolutionary history in a way that allowed for
non-human animals to have the capacity to experience pain and
su ering, as well as to in ict actual pain and su ering on them
(Boyd 2001).
NOTES
10. One might object that, while it might not be possible to have a
world that sustains life and preserves the other’s goods
dependent on lawlike regularity without allowing the
possibility of natural evil that causes injury, injury and injury
avoidance need not involve the qualitatively unpleasant
sensations of pain. This objection is addressed in detail in
Murray 2008: ch.4.
REFERENCES
ECCLES, SIR JOHN (1990). The Human Psyche. New York: Springer-
Verlag.
HICK, JOHN (1977). Evil and the God of Love. New York: Macmillan.
MICHAEL BERGMANN
(1) There are some evils that are such that humans can’t think of
any God-justifying reason for permitting them.1
Some say the term ‘skeptical theism’ is a bad name for the view
under consideration here. The main complaint is that one needn’t be
a theist to object to the above argument in the way skeptical theists
do.2I agree that one needn’t be a theist to object to the above
argument in the way skeptical theists do. But I don’t think that
makes ‘skeptical theism’ a bad name for the view. Skeptical theism
has both a skeptical component and a theistic component. The
theistic component is just theism, the view that there exists an
omnipotent, omniscient, wholly good, eternal person—i.e. a perfect
being of the sort endorsed by the western monotheisms. The
skeptical component advocates skepticism about the realm of
potentially God-justifying reasons—a degree of skepticism that leads
to a denial of the cogency of such noseeum inferences as the one
above from (1) to (2). (Wykstra 1996: 126 calls this a ‘noseeum
inference’ because it says that since we don’t see ’um, they probably
ain’t there.) And although non-theists won’t endorse skeptical
theism given its theistic component, many think that non-theists
should—and some do—endorse its skeptical component, which is
why they can agree with the objection in the previous paragraph.
Moreover, it makes perfect sense that those who rst made popular
this sort of move in response to the above argument from evil were
called ‘skeptical theists’: they were, after all, theists; and their
advocacy of skepticism about certain matters relevant to God’s ways
was a striking feature of their view. It was only natural, then, to call
the view they espoused ‘skeptical theism’.
(ST2) We have no good reason for thinking that the possible evils
we know of are representative of the possible evils there
are.
(ST3) We have no good reason for thinking that the entailment
relations we know of between possible goods and the
permission of possible evils are representative of the
entailment relations there are between possible goods and
the permission of possible evils.5
Analogies are often used to support and drive home the skeptical
theist’s point. We can’t use our failure to see any insects in the
garage (when taking a look from the street) to conclude that it’s
unlikely that there are any insects in the garage. We can’t use our
failure to discover any rational agents on other planets to conclude
that it’s unlikely that there are some on some other planet. We can’t
(if we’re chess novices) use our failure to detect a good reason for a
particular chess move made by a world champion chess player to
conclude that it’s unlikely that there is any good reason for that
chess move. Likewise, say skeptical theists, we can’t use our failure
to discern any God-justifying reason for permitting (E2) to conclude
that it’s unlikely that there is any God-justifying reason for
permitting (E2). There’s nothing unreasonable or excessive about
the skepticism involved in the cases of the insects, extraterrestrial
life, or chess champion. Skepticism in those cases doesn’t seem to
force us to accept other more extreme and unpalatable sorts of
skepticism. Likewise, says the skeptical theist, there’s nothing
unreasonable or excessive about the skepticism involved in the case
of God-justifying reasons for permitting (E2).
(ST1) and (ST2) suggest that we don’t have good reason to deny
that there is, among the unknown goods and evils, a God-justifying
reason for permitting (E2). (ST3), on the other hand, suggests that
we don’t have good reason to deny that there is, among the known
goods and evils, a God-justifying reason for permitting (E2). There’s
another skeptical thesis, the import of which is similar to (ST3)’s:
(ST4) We have no good reason for thinking that the total moral
value or disvalue we perceive in certain complex states of
a airs accurately re ects the total moral value or disvalue
they really have.9
The question raised here is: in comparing some of the very complex
goods and evils we know of that are unrelated to the concerns of
everyday life, why think we are able to grasp them su ciently to
make the value comparisons needed to determine whether securing
or preventing them could justify the permission of the evils around
us? If we can’t grasp them su ciently to make such value
comparisons, then our failure to think of a God-justifying reason for
permitting some evil might be due to our failure to recognize that
some good we know of outweighs (or that some evil we know of is
worse than) the evil in question. Less emphasis is placed on (ST4) in
the literature and it’s not needed to make the skeptical theist’s
point. But it’s worth mentioning (ST4) as an additional
consideration that supports the lesson taught by (ST3)—namely,
that there may be a God-justifying reason for permitting (E1) and
(E2) among the goods and evils we know of. Using van Inwagen’s
terminology, (ST4) expresses skepticism about our grasp of the
intrinsic value (or, as Alston puts it, the nature) of at least some of
the goods and evils we know of while (ST3) expresses skepticism
about our grasp of the extrinsic value (or, as Alston puts it, the
conditions of realization) of the goods and evils we know of.10
There are many di erent arguments from evil. For some it’s pretty
clear that the skeptical theist’s skepticism applies whereas for others
it’s controversial whether it applies.11 (Whether there are some
arguments from evil to which it clearly doesn’t apply is a question I
won’t address in this chapter.) Let’s begin by looking at three
arguments—all by William Rowe—to which the skeptical theist’s
skepticism seems quite clearly to apply.
This is basically how Rowe’s 1979 argument from evil goes. The
skeptical theist’s skepticism straightforwardly challenges the
inference from (A1) to (A2). The fact that we can’t think of any
God-justifying reasons for permitting (E1) and (E2) doesn’t make it
probable that there aren’t any—any more than the fact that we can’t
see any insects in the garage (from our vantage point standing in the
street) makes it probable that there aren’t any insects in the garage.
Does the skeptical theist’s skepticism raise any di culties for this
argument? Here’s a way in which it might: (B1) is false if there are
God-justifying reasons to permit a period of divine hiddenness
(that’s what I’ll call a period of time during which a human, who is
capable of relating personally to God and is not culpably in a
contrary position, fails to believe in God). For if there were such
reasons, then, if God existed, he would permit periods of divine
hiddenness, contrary to what (B1) says. After all, God, being
perfectly loving, would want what is best for his creatures. So long
as it isn’t intrinsically wrong to permit a period of divine hiddenness
regardless of the bene ts it might produce (and there seems to be no
good reason for thinking this is the case), God would do so if doing
so would bring about a greater good or prevent a worse evil. But
(ST1)–(ST4) suggest that we’re simply in the dark about whether
(and how likely it is that) there are any God-justifying reasons for
permitting a period of divine hiddenness. Thus, since we know that
the existence of a (potentially) God-justifying reason for permitting
divine hiddenness entails the falsity of (B1), and we are in the dark
about the truth and the likelihood of the claim that there exists such
a reason, it follows that we are likewise in the dark about the truth
and likelihood of (B1).
(E4) the evil of there being the distribution of pain and pleasure
that we know there is in the world.
It’s clear that there are evils worse than (E3) (e.g. that human never
experiencing the beati c vision; if God were forced to in ict one or
the other on a beloved creature, he would in ict (E3)). And it’s clear
that there are goods that outweigh (E3) (e.g. that human
experiencing the beati c vision; if God wanted one of his creatures
to experience the beati c vision and could do so only by permitting
that creature to undergo (E3), he would permit it). The same points
apply to (E4). But could an omnipotent being be forced to permit
(E3) or (E4) or something as bad, in order to obtain some
outweighing good? (ST3) suggests we are seriously in the dark
about the answer to this question. Insofar as we have no reasons for
thinking the entailments we know of between possible goods and
evils are representative of the entailments there are between goods
and evils, we simply aren’t in a position to comment in an informed
way about how likely it is that an omnipotent being would be forced
to permit (E3) or (E4) or something as bad, in order to obtain some
outweighing good. What do Schellenberg and Draper have to say
about this? What reasons do they give for thinking it’s false or
unlikely that God would permit (E3) or (E4) that might possibly
double as reasons to think it is unlikely or false that any
outweighing possible good entails the permission of (E3) or (E4) or
something as bad?
This charge does not stick. It’s true that, given (ST1)–(ST4), we
can’t determine merely by trying to consider the consequences of goods
and evils whether a certain amount or kind of su ering is such that
there couldn’t be a God-justifying reason to permit it. But there are
other ways of determining this that don’t rely on considerations of
consequences. Tooley has proposed, as a premise in one of his
arguments from evil, the principle that God would permit horri c
su ering only for the bene t of the su erer.34 I don’t nd that
particular moral principle plausible.35 But there are others like it
that seem more promising. Swinburne (1998: 229–36) argues that a
perfectly good God would not permit su ering unless the su erer’s
life is on the whole a good one (notice that this is a weaker
requirement than Tooley’s according to which the reason the
su ering is permitted must be to bene t the su erer). It’s true that
Swinburne is no friend of skeptical theism, but I see no reason why
those endorsing the skeptical theist’s skepticism couldn’t
consistently accept this principle Swinburne proposes (since we can
see the truth of such general principles even if we can’t see what all
the consequences of the goods and evils we know of are). And by
accepting this principle, skeptical theists would have reason to say
that a good God would not permit a human life to be literally
nothing more than a series of agonizing moments from birth to death.
Why can’t the proponent of the argument from evil make the
same sort of move? Why can’t she say that we know independently
that there’s no God-justifying reason for permitting evils such as
(E1) and (E2)—not by surveying possible goods, possible evils, and
entailments between them but in some other way? That’s certainly a
strategy worth considering. But what we need is some plausible
suggestion of what that independent way of knowing might be. And
in the case of the arguments from evil we’ve been considering, no
such suggestion is forthcoming. It’s not plausible to claim that we
know independently that such a supremely loving and resourceful
being as God is likely to prevent evils such as (E1) and (E2) or (E3)
and (E4) mentioned above in connection with Draper and
Schellenberg). What we seem to know independently is that a
perfect being de nitely wouldn’t permit (E1)–(E4) without a God-
justifying reason for doing so. But this doesn’t enable us to know
independently that God is likely to prevent (E1)–(E4), not unless we
have some independent way of knowing that it is unlikely for there to
be a God-justifying reason for permitting those evils. But plausible
suggestions of independent ways of knowing that—ways that don’t
rely on our failure to think of any such reasons upon considering
possible goods, possible evils, and entailments between them—are
in short supply.
NOTES
12. (E1) and (E2) are the evils of the horri c deaths of the fawn
and the 5-year-old girl, both mentioned earlier in this chapter.
13. This summary of the argument given in his 1988 and 1991 is
from Rowe 1996: 262–3.
14. And by Rowe’s lights too, it seems. See ibid. 267 where he says
tha the thinks’ this argument is, at best, a weak argument’ and
he proposes ‘to abandon this argument altogether’.
34. From this he concludes that God would not permit animals to
su er lonely, horri c deaths since, he thinks, they cannot
bene t from them. See Tooley 1991: 111. Stump 1985, 1990
also endorses a principle like this, though, unlike Tooley, she
maintains it while defending theism against arguments from
evil rather than using it to argue for atheism.
35. See van Inwagen 1988: 121–2 and Swinburne 1998: 223–36 for
some reasons to doubt it.
37. My own account of how we know (E5) and (E6) aren’t actual is
discussed in Bergmann 2006: 206–11.
REFERENCES
ALSTON, WILLIAM (1991). ‘The Inductive Argument from Evil and the
Human Cognitive Condition’, Philosophical Perspectives 5: 29–67;
repr. in Howard-Snyder 1996b: 97–125. Page references are to
the reprint.
PLANTINGA, ALVIN (1967). God and Other Minds. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
——— (1991). ‘The Problem of Evil, the Problem of Air, and the
Problem of Silence’ Philosophical Perspectives 5: 135–65; repr. in
Howard-Snyder 1996b: 151–74. Page references are to the
reprint.
WILKS, IAN (2004). ‘The Structure of the Contemporary Debate on the
Problem of Evil’, Religious Studies 40: 307–21.
THE TRINITY
MICHAEL C. REA
ONE of the central mysteries of the Christian faith concerns the tri-
unity of God. According to traditional Christian doctrine, God is
three persons who are somehow consubstantial—one in substance.
The persons are the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit. Each
person possesses all the traditional divine attributes—omnipotence,
omniscience, perfect goodness, eternality, and so on. And yet (in the
words of the Athanasian Creed), ‘they are not three eternals, but
there is one eternal …there are not three almighties, but there is one
almighty …there are not three Gods, but there is one God.’1 But
what does all of this really mean? And how could it possibly be
true?
Now this is the catholic faith, that we worship one God in Trinity,
and the Trinity in unity, without either confusing the persons or
dividing the substance. For the Father’s person is one, the Son’s
another, the Holy Spirit’s another; but the Godhead of the Father,
the Son, and the Holy Spirit is one, their glory equal, their majesty
co-eternal. Such as the Father is, such is the Son, such also the Holy
Spirit…. Thus the Father is God, the Son God, and the Holy Spirit
God; and yet there are not three Gods, but there is one God. Thus
the Father is Lord, the Son Lord, the Holy Spirit Lord; and yet there
are not three Lords but there is one Lord…. Because just as we are
obliged by Christian truth to acknowledge each person separately
both God and Lord, so we are forbidden by the catholic religion to
speak of three Gods or Lords. (Kelly 1964: 17–20, repr. in Leith
1972: 705)
The Athanasian Creed is widely regarded as manifesting a bias
toward ‘Latin’ theories of the Trinity (see sect. 2 below).
In the two passages just quoted, we have the three central tenets
of the doctrine:4
The logical problem of the Trinity is just the fact that (T1)–(T3)
appear to be mutually inconsistent. There are various ways of trying
to demonstrate the inconsistency, but the one I favor focuses on the
(apparent) meaning of consubstantiality. To say that x and y are
consubstantial, or of the same substance is, it seems, just to say that
x and y share a common nature—i.e. they are members of one and
the same kind. To say that two divine beings are consubstantial,
then, would be to say that the two beings in question are identical
with respect to their divinity: neither is subordinate to the other; they
are not divine in di erent ways; and if one is a God, then the other
one is too. (Note, by the way, that ‘God’ functions in (T1) above as a
kind-term, like man, and not as a name, like Fred. Thus, though it
looks a bit odd, it makes perfect sense to speak of the Father as a
God. If ‘God’ were functioning as a name, then (T1) would be saying
something very much like ‘There is exactly one YHWH,’ which isn’t
so much a monotheistic claim as a rather strange way of asserting
the existence of YHWH.)
Given all this, the logical problem of the Trinity can be expressed
as follows:
(LPT5) Therefore: It is not the case that there is exactly one God.
(From (LPT2), (LPT3), (LPT4))
***Contradiction
The only way out of the contradiction is either to give up one of the
tenets of the doctrine of the Trinity or to give up (LPT4).
At this juncture, some will wonder why Christians don’t just give
up on one of the tenets of the doctrine of the Trinity. After all, the
doctrine isn’t explicitly taught in the Christian Scriptures, and the
precise language in which it is expressed wasn’t settled until the
fourth century.7 So why not just abandon (say) (T2) or (T3)? What
reasons are there for accepting traditional Trinitarian doctrine?
Some have argued that the doctrine of the Trinity (or something
like it) can be established via a priori argument.8 But the main
reason Christians take themselves to be committed to (T1)–(T3) is
that they seem to be implied both by Christian practice and by
central claims in the Christian Scriptures.9 For example, both the
Old and New Testaments make it clear that there is only one being
who deserves worship and who deserves such titles as ‘God
Almighty’ or ‘the one true God’; and Jesus refers to this being as ‘our
heavenly Father’.10 Hence (T1). Moreover, though Jesus says things
such as ‘I and the Father are one’, it is clear that, from the point of
view of the New Testament, Jesus (the Son) and the Father are
distinct.11 Jesus prays to the Father; claims to submit to the Father’s
will; is blessed by the Father; and so on. Likewise, the Holy Spirit is
distinct from the Father and Son: the Spirit is sent by the Son and is
said to intercede for us with the Father. Hence (T2). And yet the
New Testament advocates worshipping Jesus (the Son) and the Holy
Spirit;12 we nd Jesus saying such things as, ‘Anyone who has seen
me has seen the Father’; and we nd the apostle Peter saying (of
someone who has lied to the Holy Spirit), ‘You have not lied to men,
but to God.’13 In short, there is pressure to say that the Son and
Spirit are divine—and not in some derivative, or degenerate sense,
but truly divine, like the Father. The only clear way to say this
without contradicting (T1), however, is to say that the Son and the
Spirit are consubstantial with the Father: the divinity of the Father,
which is the ‘substance’ of the Father (more on this later), is no
di erent from the divinity of the Son. Hence (T3).14
Subordinationism is the view that neither the Son nor the Spirit
is truly and fully divine. Either they are not divine at all, or their
divinity is somehow subordinate to that of the Father. They are gods
of a sort, but lesser gods. Subordinationism is ruled out by such
language as ‘true God from true God’ or, more explicitly, ‘the Father
is God, the Son is God, and the Holy Spirit is God’.
Modalism is the view that the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are
merely di erent aspects or manifestations of God—di erent modes of
appearance by which God makes himself known. If modalism were
true, then the terms ‘Father’, ‘Son’, and ‘Holy Spirit would be
analogous to terms such as ‘Superman’ and ‘Clark Kent’. The
substance called ‘Superman’ is strictly identical to the substance
called ‘Clark Kent’. But there is, nevertheless, a distinction to be
drawn. The Superman-disguise is di erent from the Clark-Kent-
disguise; and so it makes perfect sense to say that Superman and
Clark Kent are di erent manifestations of Kal El (the Kryptonian who
is both Superman and Clark Kent), or di erent modes in which Kal
El appears. If modalism is true, then precisely the same sort of thing
can be said about the terms ‘God the Father’, ‘God the Son’, and
‘God the Holy Spirit’. Insofar as they are distinct, Father, Son, and
Holy Spirit do not fall into the category of substance; rather, they
fall into the category of ‘aspect’ or ‘property’.
In this section, I want to lay out some of the main strategies for
solving the problem of the Trinity. Since the end of the nineteenth
century, it has been common to divide the landscape of views into
two camps: Latin (or Western) Trinitarianism (LT) and Greek (or
Eastern) Trinitarianism (GT).15 Those who divide the territory this
way tell roughly the following story about their classi catory
scheme: the Latin tradition traces its historical roots through the
western church. It is epitomized in the work of such theologians as
St Augustine and St Thomas Aquinas; it takes the unity of the
Godhead as given and seeks to explain the plurality in God (rather
than vice versa); and those in the tradition tend to gravitate toward
psychological analogies. The Greek tradition, on the other hand,
traces its roots through the eastern church; it is epitomized in the
work of the Cappadocian Fathers; it takes the plurality of the divine
persons as given and seeks to explain their unity; and those in the
tradition tend to favor social analogies.16 (GT is commonly
identi ed with ‘social trinitarianism’, discussed below.)
In the two main parts of this section, I’ll present some of the
more well-known LT and GT models of the Trinity. Though each of
these models is intended to guide us toward a solution to the logical
problem of the Trinity, we’ll see that all of them fall short.
Moreover, I’ll argue that the most popular contemporary view,
social trinitarianism, depends heavily for its plausibility upon one of
the central claims involved in the LT-GT classi catory scheme:
namely, the claim that the Greek tradition, starting with the
Cappadocian Fathers, favored ‘social analogies’ as ways of
explicating the doctrine of the Trinity. This done, I’ll go on in sect. 3
to present my own view of the Trinity—a version of the so-called
‘Relative Identity’ solution (which I’ll also save for discussion in
sect. 3) that transcends the alleged LT-GT divide. I’ll also present
alternative readings of Augustine and the Cappadocian Fathers that
identify their views as ancestors of mine. Ultimately, my conclusion
will be that, of all the models considered herein, the view defended
in sect. 3 has the best claim to being orthodox and in accord with
the views of the earliest defenders of the Creed of Nicaea.
Case 1: L = M = R = Jane
Alternatively, we might think that what the names ‘L’, ‘M’, and ‘R’
refer to are three distinct events in the life of Jane. In that case,
there are, after all, three Rockettes, and each Rockette is an event:
If (as I believe) Jane has no temporal parts, then not just a temporal
part of Jane, but Jane as a whole, appears at each point in the
chorus line, and what the line contains many of are segments or
episodes of Jane’s life-events. This may sound odd. After all,
Rockettes dance. Events do not. But what you see are many
dancings of one substance. What makes the line a line is the fact
that these many events go on in it, in a particular set of relations.
Each Rockette is Jane. But in these many events, Jane is there many
times over. (ibid. 308, emphasis mine)
The quoted passage says that ‘what there are many of’ is events; and
it speaks of Rockettes in the plural. Thus, Case 2 looks like the
correct interpretation. On the other hand, each Rockette is Jane.
Thus, Case 1 looks like the correct interpretation. But it is
impossible for both interpretations to be correct. So it is hard to
know what to make of what Leftow is saying here.
Elsewhere, however, he says a bit more. ‘Perhaps’, he says, ‘the
triune Persons are event-based persons founded on a generating
substance, God’ (2007: 373–4). An event-based person is, roughly, a
person whose existence is constituted by the occurrence of an event:
what it is for the person to exist is for that event to occur in a
particular substance (ibid. 367–8). In the case of Jane, then, L, M,
and R are presumably supposed to be analogous to event-based
persons. Jane (the generating substance) exists in each of the three,
as Leftow says at the end of the quoted passage above; but she is not
strictly identical to any of the three. Likewise, God exists in each of
the event-based persons that together constitute the Trinity.
1. Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are not numerically the same
substance. Rather, the persons of the Trinity are consubstantial
only in the sense that they share a common nature; and the
sharing is to be understood straightforwardly on analogy with
the way in which three human beings share a common nature.
(c) Being the only members of the community that rules the
cosmos.
(f) Enjoying perfect love and harmony of will with one another,
unlike the members of pagan pantheons.
Most social trinitarians in fact opt for a combination of these,
and most (but not all) of the combinations include at least (a), (b),
and (c). So, for example, Richard Swinburne (1994) focuses on the
fact that YHWH is a composite individual or society whose parts or
members stand in the relations identi ed in (e) and (f).30 But, of
course, he wouldn’t deny that they stand in (b) and (c) as well. J. P.
Moreland and William Lane Craig (2003) focus primarily on (a). On
their view, YHWH is composed of the Persons in a sense analogous
to the way in which the three-headed dog Cerberus, guardian of the
underworld in Greek mythology, might be thought to be composed
of three ‘centers of consciousness’ (ibid. 593). On their view, the
three conscious parts of Cerberus are not dogs; there is only one dog
—Cerberus. But the centers of consciousness are canine, just as any
other part of Cerberus is (derivatively) canine. One dog, then; three
derivatively canine individuals. Likewise in the Trinity: one God;
three derivatively divine individuals. Monotheism is thus secured by
the fact that the Persons are parts of a single fully divine being.
Cornelius Plantinga Jr. (1989: 31), on the other hand, argues that
social Trinitarians may ‘cling to respectability as monotheists’
simply by a rming that the persons are related in the ways
described by (b), (c), and (d). His idea seems to be that monotheism
is true, no matter how many gods there are, so long as all gods
derive their divinity from one source, or share a single divine nature
(as we humans share a single human nature), or are joined together
as a divine family, monarchy, or community. There are other
suggestions in the literature; but they tend to run along very similar
lines.
(P1) Necessarily, if x and y are not identical, then x and y are not
numerically the same substance.
If (P1) is false, then (LPT4) simply ignores the possibility that x and
y are distinct but (perhaps by virtue of their consubstantiality) one
and the same God. In other words, (LPT4) presupposes that it is
impossible for an object a and an object b to be numerically the
same F without being absolutely identical. Give up that
presupposition, and the argument that depends on (LPT4) fails.
RI2 is not needed for solving the problem of the Trinity; but some
philosophers—notably, Peter Geach—endorse it for other reasons,
and it serves as independent motivation for RI1.40
Let us esh out the story just a bit further. Aristotle maintained
that every material object is a compound of matter and form. The
form might be thought of as a complex organizational property—not
a mere shape, as the term suggests in English, but something much
richer. For Aristotle, the form of a thing was its nature; and forms,
like concrete things (though not in exactly the same sense), count as
substances. Thus, on his view, St Peter would be a compound whose
constituents were some matter and the form, humanity, or human
nature. St Paul would be a compound whose constituents were that
same form, but di erent matter.42 Peter and Paul would thus be ‘of
one substance’ on the Aristotelian view; though (unlike Gregory of
Nyssa) Aristotle would not have spoken of Peter and Paul as being
numerically the same man, nor would he have regarded them as
numerically the same substance. With some minor modi cations
(plus the non-Aristotelian assumption that statues and pillars are
substances, just like men are) Aristotle’s view would permit us to say
that the statue and the pillar are numerically the same substance,
even though they would not be ‘of the same substance’ since they
would not share the same form, or nature. They would be
numerically the same substance, one material object, but distinct
matter-form compounds. They would be the same without being
identical.
So far so good; but there is one loose end that remains to be tied.
What is it that plays the role of matter in the Trinity? And is it a
substance itself? Here I want to o er only a partial view that might
be developed in a variety of di erent ways. What plays the role of
matter in the Trinity is the divine nature; and the divine nature is a
substance. It is not a fourth substance, for reasons already discussed;
nor is it a fourth person (since it is not a compound of ‘matter’ plus
a person-de ning-property). But it is a substance, since (again,
taking cues from Aristotle) natures are substances. What I don’t want
to take a position on here is the question of what, exactly, a nature
is. Is it concrete or abstract? Is it particular or universal? Is it a
property or something else? These questions I will not answer. I
think that they must be answered in a way that allows the divine
persons to be concrete particular non-properties; but I think that
there are various ways of answering these questions that are
compatible with that view.
This completes my presentation of the constitution view. We are
now in a position to see how the view connects with the views of
fourth- and fth-century defenders of Nicaea. At the heart of the
constitution view is the idea that the divine persons are compounds
whose constituents are a shared divine nature, which plays the role
of Aristotelian matter, and a person-de ning property (like being the
Son, or being Begotten) that plays the role of form. But this is almost
exactly the view that Richard Cross identi es as the fundamental
point of agreement between eastern and western views of the
Trinity. According to Cross, east and west agreed that (a) the divine
nature is a property, and (b) one and the same divine nature is a
constituent of each of the divine persons—i.e. it is the point at
which they overlap.46
To us there is One God, for the Godhead is One …For one [Person]
is not more and another less God; nor is One before and another
after; nor are They divided in will or parted in power; nor can you
nd here any of the qualities of divisible things; but the Godhead is,
to speak concisely, undivided in separate Persons.…[D]o not the
Greeks also believe in one Godhead, as their more advanced
philosophers declare? And with us, Humanity is one, namely the
entire race; but yet they have many gods, not One, just as there are
many men. But in this case the common nature has a unity which is
only conceivable in thought; and the individuals are parted from
one another very far indeed, both by time and by dispositions and
by power. For we are not only compound beings, but contrasted
beings, both with one another and with ourselves; nor do we remain
entirely the same [over time].
For they maintained that the homoousion set forth the idea both of
essence and of what is derived from it, so that the essence, when
divided, confers the title of co-essential on the parts into which it is
divided. This explanation has some reason in the case of bronze and
coins made therefrom, but in the case of God the Father and God
the Son there is no question of substance anterior or even
underlying both; the mere thought and utterance of such a thing is
the last extravagance of impiety. (ibid. viii. 155)
NOTES
5. I take this straight from the rst line of the Nicene Creed. The
rst line can be translated in ways di erent from what I have
reproduced here; but every credible way of translating it
strongly suggests that the Father is somehow the same as God.
10. See e.g. Exod. 20: 3–5; Isa. 42: 8; Matt. 5: 9–13, 7: 21; and
John 2: 16.
11. Compare John 10: 30; Matt. 24: 36; Luke 22: 42; and John 1:
14, 18.
16. Cf. e.g. Brown 1985; Cary 1995; Cross 2002; La Cugna 1986,
1991; and Placher 1983: 79.
17. See e.g. Ayres 2004; Barnes 1995a, b, 1998; Cary 1995;
Coakley 1999; and Cross 2002. The idea isn’t that there is no
di erence whatsoever between eastern and western, or Latin
and Greek, conceptions of the Trinity, but that the di erences
aren’t nearly as sharp as they are commonly construed, that
they aren’t aptly characterized as di erences over ‘starting
points’ or as a fundamental di erence in attitudes toward
‘social’ and ‘psychological’ analogies.
19. On the Trinity, Bk. 10 chs. 10–12 and Bk. 15 ch. 3; Scha and
Wace 1887/1999: iii. 140–3, 200–2. He characterizes the
latter analogy as a ‘more subtle’ treatment of the matter than
the former.
20. Cf. Brown 1985: ch. 7; LaCugna 1991: ch. 3; O’Collins 1999:
ch. 7; Richardson 1955.
21. Moreland and Craig 2003: 585 say that Aquinas ‘pushes the
Augustinian analogy to its apparent limit’. But this makes it
sound as if the ‘subsistent relations view’ isn’t present in
Augustine. I myself don’t mean to suggest that, however. All I
mean to suggest is that it is not explicit in Augustine.
23. I think that the objection can be met, and that the way to do
it is to develop Aquinas’s view along the lines of the view
described in sect. 3. But I won’t attempt to do that here.
31. See esp. Brower 2004a; Clark 1996; Feser 1997; and Leftow
1999.
33. Or one might just try to sink it with the weight of other
objections. And there are other objections in the literature—
see e.g. Tuggy 2003, 2004. My own view, though, is that even
after these further objections have been piled on, the
cumulative case is not dialectically strong enough apart from
the two further tasks just mentioned.
34. See e.g. Howard-Snyder 2003; Leftow 1999; Rea 2006; and
Tuggy 2003.
38. See Brower and Rea 2005a, b. See also Brower 2004b.
40. See e.g. Geach 1967, 1980: sects. 30, 34, 110.
43. Or, if you like, a lump of matter. See Brower and Rea 2005a:
504 n. 10 for discussion.
45. One might want to say that it is the Father who plays the role
of underlier, that the Son is a compound of the Father and the
property being Begotten, and that the Spirit is a compound of
the Father (or the Son) and the property of Proceeding. Thisview
is suggested by passages in Augustine, and was rst brought to
my attention by Anne Peterson. I take it as a variation on the
present theme, rather than a genuine rival to the view I am
defending.
48. I want to avoid views that rule out shared agency; but I don’t
myself want to commit to it. For, of course, it raises serious
questions. The Son prays to the Father. Does the Father do so
as well? Proponents of shared agency will say ‘yes, but not in
the same way.’ (See e.g. Hasker 1970: 29.) Trying to make
good sense of this response, however, would require another
paper.
49. On the Trinity Bk. 11 ch. 2; in Scha and Wace 1887/1999: iii.
145–6.
51. See e.g. Gregory Nazianzen’s analogy of three suns in his Fifth
Theological Oration, ch. 14, and the rainbow analogy in Basil of
Caesarea’s Epistle 38 (generally regarded as having been
written by Gregory of Nyssa rather than by Basil).
REFERENCES
——— (1994). ‘Could There Be More Than One Lord?’ Faith and
Philosophy 11: 357–78.
CAIN, JAMES (1989). ‘The Doctrine of the Trinity and the Logic of
Relative Identity’, Religious Studies 25: 141–52.
KELLY, J.N.D. (trans.) (1964). The Athanasian Creed. London: Adam &
Charles Black. -(1972). Early Christian Creeds, 3rd edn. New
York: Longman.
——— (1991). God For Us: The Trinity and Christian Life. San
Francisco: Harper San Francisco.
MOLTMANN, JÜRGEN (1981). The Trinity and the Kingdom: The Doctrine
of God, trans. Margaret Kohl. San Francisco: Harper San
Francisco.
VAN INWAGEN, Peter (1988). ‘And Yet They Are Not Three Gods But
One God’, in Thomas Morris (ed.), Philosophy and the Christian
Faith. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 241–78.
OLIVER D. CRISP
The ransom theory (expressed in the sort of story just given) was
dusted down in the mid-twentieth century by the Scandinavian
theologian Gustaf Aulén, whose book Christus Victor claimed that
the ransom model was the ‘classic’ view of the atonement, which
had been overlaid by centuries of theological accretions.3 He
maintains that this classic view is superior to later accounts of the
work of Christ and should be preferred to other ways of thinking
about the atonement. Aulén’s work has been widely discussed,
particularly amongst systematic theologians. But it is not without
problems.
One concern with Aulén’s work is that it is not obvious that the
ransom view is the ‘classic’ account of the atonement, or the best or
most comprehensive way of thinking about the nature of atonement.
That would have to be argued for. Even if the ransom view is the
majority position amongst the Fathers, this does not automatically
give it a privileged status above other theories of the atonement.
The venerable pedigree of a given theory is not, after all, a cast-iron
guarantee of its being the best explanation of the data. A second
problem is that the ransom theory involves a rather naive account of
the relationship between the Fall, human sin, and enslavement to
the Devil, with unpleasant overtones of God being implicated in an
act of deception. That said, the conceptual hard core of the doctrine
is that Christ’s work is remedial, being the price required to
‘purchase’ or ‘buy back’ some number of fallen humanity enslaved
to evil. It is perfectly feasible to set out such a doctrine without the
paraphernalia of the story about deceiving the Devil. Then, Christ’s
work would bring about the reconciliation of some number of fallen
humanity, including their release from the power of evil—the
language about the personi cation of evil having been removed.
This would have the advantage of divesting the theory of the
unwelcome consequence of God’s involvement in deception.
However, if the core of the theory can be stated without the need
for personi ed evil, to whom is the ransom price of Christ’s work
paid? It might be possible to ‘amend’ the theory in the direction of a
satisfaction account of the atonement at this point. In which case
God, whose moral governance has been impugned by human sin (let
us say), requires the ‘ransom’ as the price for human wickedness.
Taken in this way, Christ’s work is not so much a question of paying
the ransom demand of the Devil as paying the price demanded by
the divine moral law for human sin. This moral demand might be
thought a ‘ransom’ in a loose, non-philosophical sense, since it
involves payment of a price set in order to bring about the
reconciliation of some number of fallen human beings. But it is not
a ransom in the sense of a payment made to a diabolical entity that
has enslaved humanity.
We begin with the idea that Adam and his progeny are
(somehow) one metaphysical entity such that God may justly pass
on the moral consequences of Adam’s sin to his heirs because they
are all members of one persisting entity, or object, that we might
call Fallen Humanity. To be clear, this object is composed only of
Adam and his progeny all of whom are ‘parts’26 or phases in the life
of the whole entity. On the sort of view of Fallen Humanity I have
in mind, if the rst ‘part’ of the object sins, later ‘parts’ of the same
object (including all of humanity after Adam) have a vitiated moral
nature as a result of the action of Adam. It is rather like an acorn
that is infected with some disease that then a ects all the later
stages in the life of the sapling and tree into which it grows.27
Of course, it does not follow that just because Adam and his
progeny are ‘parts’ of one persisting object, Adam’s progeny share
the same morally vitiated condition as Adam. Nor does it follow that
just because an acorn is infected with some disease all the later
stages in the life of the tree into which it grows are a ected by this
disease. Some diseases might only a ect the rst phase of the life of
the tree, rather than all phases of its life. But the sort of reasoning I
have in mind is o ered as a possible explanation of how original sin
is transmitted from one generation to the next from some rst
human parents. It is true that later phases of the life of a persisting
entity may not be a ected by what happens in an earlier phase of
the same life. But the Augustinian realist story is concerned to make
sense of the claim that just such an arrangement does obtain in the
case of Adam and his progeny. All that needs to be granted here is
that it is possible for a given entity to have phases of its life that are
a ected by earlier phases of its life, and that all phases of the life of
a given persisting entity may be a ected by what happens to one of
the rst ‘parts’ or phases of that entity. This seems plausible just as
it seems plausible to think that an infected acorn may grow into a
tree that is diseased in every subsequent phase of its existence. And
this ts with the Augustinian realist story of original sin I am
drawing upon.28
Still, even if there are diseases that a ect the life of the tree in
all its phases, the disease a icting the life of the mature oak is not
necessarily the same as the disease a ecting the life of the sapling,
or the acorn. But suppose it is the same disease introduced to the
acorn that a ects all the later phases of the life of the oak into
which it grows. Is the corruption a ecting the oak the same as the
corruption a ecting the acorn? Much depends here on the ontology
one adopts. If one thinks persisting objects are wholly present at
each moment of their existence, then one might think that this is the
same disease. But if one thinks that the acorn and oak are di erent
temporal parts of one perduring four-dimensional whole object, then
one has a reason for thinking the disease a ecting the oak is not
numerically the same as that a ecting the acorn. For presumably
any disease persisting through time has temporal parts just as the
tree it infects has. And the temporal parts of a given thing are said
to be numerically distinct. So the fact that on this way of thinking
the oak tree does not have numerically the same disease as the
sapling does not pose any particular problem that defenders of
temporal parts are not already familiar with.
But this may not be the only metaphysical story consistent with
Augustinian realism. Perhaps one can say both that objects that
persist through time are normally wholly present at each moment of
their existence, and that in the case of the transmission of original
sin the human species propagates sin through natural generation.
Construed along the lines of traducianism, this means that I have
Adam’s sin and guilt because my soul is either a fraction of the soul
Adam possessed (if souls are generated through ssion) or the
product of the soul of at least one of my parents, going all the way
back to Adam (if souls are parturient). Though ‘individualized’ or
otherwise brought about through natural generation, I retain the
property of original sin that has been passed on to me, as would be
the case with inherited physical diseases. The important di erence
between inherited disease and original sin, on this way of thinking,
is that my soul was present when Adam sinned as part of the
‘unindividualized’ soul that Adam possessed. Or, perhaps, the ‘seed’
of my soul was present in the soul of Adam, if souls are parturient
rather than ssiparous (compare Heb. 7: 10). So I am guilty of
Adam’s sin on account of possessing a fraction of Adam’s soul or
‘seed’ thereof that is now ‘individualized’ through soul- ssion or
parturition. But it seems consistent with this theological account of
the manner by which sin is transmitted to say that persisting objects
are wholly present at each moment of their existence. If this is right,
then an Augustinian realist account of the transmission of original
sin can be underpinned by more than one metaphysical account of
persisting objects, depending on what the Augustinian realist thinks
about the mechanism by which sin is transmitted.
But here the analogy between Adam and Christ begins to break
down. For, according to the Augustinian realist account of the
transmission of sin, Adam as the rst human can a ect the moral
condition of all subsequent humans in a way that some later human
being could not (because some earlier humans would already have
perished, or be beyond the in uence of this later person, or could
not be in possession of the whole ‘unindividualized’ soul that Adam
had, or whatever). However, Christ’s in uence cannot just follow
the arrow of time, moving from the moment his atonement is
complete to include all those who are elect that exist after that time.
Were this the case, then we would have no reason to think that
anyone who lived temporally prior to Christ’s act of atonement was
amongst the elect. But, of course, Scripture says otherwise, with
Hebrews 11 recounting a great cloud of witnesses for the faith in the
Old Testament, and Paul in 1 Corinthians 10 speaking of the
presence of Christ with the children of Israel wandering in the
desert, that drank from the rock (at Meribah) that was Christ. So, a
realist account of the atonement must also be able to include within
the ambit of salvation those of the elect who lived prior to Christ.
The explanation goes like this. At the cross Christ has transferred
to him the penal consequences of the sin of the derivatively elect—
that is, the derivatively elect members of Redeemed Humanity. At
that moment, he takes the penal consequences for which they are
guilty, as one ‘part’ of the larger metaphysical whole. As a result he
su ers for that sin. Having made atonement by expiating human sin
in his own person, the members of Redeemed Humanity for whose
sin he has atoned are reconciled to God.
OBJECTIONS
NOTES
My thanks to Gavin D’Costa, Tom Flint, Paul Helm, Daniel
Hill, Joseph Jedwab, Brian Leftow, Mike Rea, Bill Schweitzer
and Richard Swinburne for their comments on or concerning
the argument of previous drafts of this chapter. Thanks too to
the members of the Systematic Theology Seminar in the
Faculty of Divinity, Cambridge University, The Joseph Butler
Society, Oriel College, Oxford, and the Theology Seminar at St,
Mary’s College, University of St Andrews, where earlier
versions of the latter part of this chapter were read in 2007.
7. ‘But the obligation rests with man, and no one else, to make
the payment referred to. Otherwise mankind is not making
recompense.’ Cur Deus Homo 2. 6. Cf. 2. 7 in St Anselm 1998:
320–1.
8. Swinburne 1989.
13. Franks 1962: 366 says that for Faustus Socinus, ‘the death of
Christ operates to redeem us in so far as it is an example of
obedience, leads us to trust God, and gives us hope of
deliverance from punishment’. The major work on the
atonement by Faustus Socinus is De Jesu Christo Servatore
(1594). A recent historical-theological reassessment of Socinus’
importance can be found in Gomes 1993.
23. The idea that God imputes Adamic sin and/or guilt to Adam’s
progeny is found in much, though not all, Reformed theology.
‘Realism’ is a somewhat plastic term, having a variety of
di erent applications in the current philosophical literature.
But, as I indicate here, Augustinian realism uses the term in a
rather di erent way from current analytical discussions about
realism vs. anti-realism.
REFFEREMCE
BYNUM, CAROLINE WALKER (2004). ‘The Power in the Blood: Sacri ce,
Satisfaction, and Substitution in Late Medieval Soteriology’, in
Stephen T. Davis, Daniel Kendall, and Gerald O’Collins (eds.),
The Redemption. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 177–86.
THE INCARNATION
RICHARD CROSS
The view of Chalcedon, then, is that one and the same person—the
second person of the Trinity (the ‘Word’, identical with the ‘Lord
Jesus Christ’, according to the nal list of Christological titles)—
exists ‘in two natures’, divine and human.1 One of the views that the
Council opposes is that known as Nestorianism, according to which
there are somehow two distinct subjects in Christ—one divine, and
one human. The point of rejecting this view is to ensure that the
divine person—the second person of the Trinity—is the subject not
only of divine but also of human attributes or properties. Now, the
Council does not de ne its terms, and some recent theological
commentators maintain that it gives no more than particular
syntactic rules governing the use of the terms ‘person’ and ‘nature’.
But it seems to me—as it has seemed to most recent philosophical
commentators—that the linguistic rules are secondary to some
apparently substantive metaphysical claims: namely, that there is
some divine subject of properties—the second person of the Trinity
—that gains human properties (a human nature). Clearly, the
metaphysics leaves open just what a nature is—for example, a
universal or a particular—and as we shall see, this issue crops up in
a number of recent discussions too.
The rst is the one that the medieval theologians knew as the
‘reduplicative’ analysis (see Cross 2002: 193-5). On the
reduplicative analysis, ‘S qua N is F’ should be understood as ‘“In
virtue of being N, S is F”’ (Senor 2002: 229). This understanding, as
the medievals noticed, does nothing to help deal with putative
contradictions:
Jesus Christ qua man read in the synagogue before Jesus Christ
qua man carried his cross,
‘a and b could be the same F but not the same G (where “F” and “G”
stand in for sortal terms, or general count nouns with associated
criteria for individuation and reidenti cation)’ (Morris 1986: 28).
Peter van Inwagen, for example, has argued that the doctrine of the
Incarnation can be shown to be ‘free from formal contradiction’ (van
Inwagen 1994: 225) if we adopt such an account, such that two
distinct beings could be the same person (ibid. 217). Equally, the
position allows for one being to be (e.g.) human and the other non-
human without contradiction, and one being to be (e.g.) passible
and the other impassible without contradiction, while yet allowing
both beings to be one and the same person (ibid. 221-3). This is a
version of the speci cative analysis outlined in the previous section,
since it treats the two beings in Christ as subjects distinct from each
other, though not from the divine person with which each severally
is identical. But unlike that analysis, it does not rely on a
mereological account of the Incarnation, since the two beings
postulated to be the same person in van Inwagen’s account are not
parts of that person. Rather, each being is severally the same person
as the second person of the Trinity and as Jesus of Nazareth (ibid.
217-18).3
There are various ways in which this kind of approach can have
some appeal. For example, it could do so if we were to adopt some
more wide-ranging anti-realism: if we were to adopt, for example,
the view that there are no theory-independent facts about the
natures of things, or the distinctions of one thing from another.
Many, though not all, theologians nd such anti-realism at the very
least counterintuitive, and in any case some anti-realists would be
more than happy to deny relative identity: relative to each theory
about how to cut up the world, identity remains absolute. In fact,
van Inwagen’s own working out of the doctrine along these lines
does not involve making any explicitly anti-realist claims. What it
does involve is accepting a logic of relative identity that lacks a rule
permitting inferences that conform to the principle of the
indiscernibility of identicals. The logic thus licences the use of
premises that can violate the principle of the indiscernibility of
identicals: something that most philosophers would be reluctant to
accept. So van Inwagen’s approach is ultimately of very limited
appeal. And as he himself notes, even if we accept his account,
much work would be left to be done: I [do] not claim to have
penetrated the mystery of the Incarnation, but at most to have
shown that that doctrine can be stated without formal contradiction’
(ibid. 202). The interest of the logic turns out to be restricted to its
application—and the philosophical price would be felt by many to
be too high.
Leftow is clearly right to think that his view allows full use of
qua-quali ers, but his way of construing the part-whole relationship
seems nevertheless to engender certain Christological di culties. In
particular, on his proposal it is hard to see how the second person of
the Trinity could be the subject of human attributes. We can see this
by considering a close relation to Leftow’s view found in the early
church, namely the view of Nestorius’s (explicitly condemned at the
Council of Ephesus in 431 CE) that we should hold not that Mary
was the mother of God (theotokos), but rather that she was the
mother of Christ (Christotokos). The claim that Mary was mother of
Christ is true, according to Nestorius, in virtue of the fact that Mary
was the mother of the man Jesus who, along with the second person
of the Trinity, constituted Christ, such that the second person of the
Trinity is a part of Christ, not identical with him. The problem here,
identi ed by Nestorius’s main orthodox opponent, Cyril of
Alexandria, is that the second person of the Trinity is not himself
the subject of human attributes. (Hence Mary is not his mother.) I
conclude that Leftow’s impressive strategy avoids the problems of
contradiction only at too high a price—the danger of a Nestorian
denial that the Son of God (as opposed to the whole of which he is a
part) is human, or has human attributes, at all.
4. RESTRICTION SOLUTIONS
Our criteria for use of the word ‘human’ are just not precise enough
for there to be a right answer as to whether the possession of
powers far beyond those of normal humans [e.g. a power to move
mountains on distant continents just by willing, or to know what is
going on in distant galaxies without using a telescope or listening to
what others tell him] would rule out someone from being a human.
(Swinburne 1994: 28)
The point here is that something that is fully but not merely human
lacks certain imperfect properties commonly (but not necessarily)
associated with human beings: for example, contingency,
peccability, fallibility, limitations on power. These properties are
had by persons that are merely human, but not by other human
persons. It seems to me that this is the correct way forward, and in
principle there seems to be no reason why we should assume that a
being that fails to exemplify these common limitations fails to be
human.
5. TWO-MINDS SOLUTIONS
Swinburne spells out what this implies for the case of Christ. In
becoming incarnate, the divine person takes on a human belief-
system, one that comes to include a set of propositions that would
under normal circumstances form the beliefs of a human person. In
the case of Christ, this set of propositions forms merely inclinations
to belief, for some of the propositions (the false ones) do not
constitute the divine person’s world-view.14 Christ’s human actions
(including ‘thoughts consciously entertained connected with the
brain’) are performed ‘in the light of his human belief system’
(ibid.). Christ, then, is one person with two consciousnesses. But
while remaining essentially omniscient, and consciously so, the
divine person consciously keeps this knowledge from forming part
of the human belief-system. So Christ’s human actions are
performed on the basis of a belief-system that, rst, does not include
the belief that the belief-system is included in the divine belief-
system in this way; and, secondly, includes some inclinations to
false beliefs. But since inclinations to belief are not beliefs, there is
no danger of the divine person’s having false beliefs: as Swinburne
(ibid.) puts it, ‘his divine knowledge-system will inevitably include
the knowledge that his human system contains the beliefs [i.e.,
inclinations to belief] that it does; and it will include those among
the latter which are true’. And since the inclinations to belief in the
human belief-system are not beliefs, there is no worry about two
mental subjects: beliefs that p, on the one hand, and inclinations to
believe that not- p, on the other, can belong to one and the same
mental subject, namely, in this case, the divine person.
NOTES
Thanks to the editors of the volume for comments, and
especially to Brian Leftow and Joseph Jedwab. Jedwab’s
insightful feedback greatly improved the whole of this chapter.
Leftow’s comments greatly helped me deal with issues in sect.
3. We await eagerly Jedwab’s important Oxford doctoral
dissertation on the whole issue. It should of course be added
that neither Leftow nor Jedwab would endorse the conclusions
I come to here.
4. I thank Joseph Jedwab for this way of spelling out the relevant
distinction between parts and properties. For a di erent
attempt that strikes me now as less clear and elegant, see Cross
forthcoming.
14. I am not sure whether Swinburne holds that all Christ’s human
beliefs are in fact inclinations to belief, or whether only the
false ones are. Swinburne introduces the distinction to deal
merely with the problem of contradictory beliefs, but ends up
arguing without quali cation that ‘the “beliefs” belonging to
the human perspective would be mere inclinations to belief’
(Swinburne 1994: 202-3). The true propositions contained in
the human belief-system would seem to be expressive of the
divine person’s world-view, and thus count as fully- edged
beliefs.
REFERENCES
EVANS, C. STEPHEN (1996). The Historical Christ and the Jesus of Faith:
The Incarnational Narrative as History. Oxford, Clarendon Press.
GANSSLE, GREGORY E., and WOODRUFF, DAVID M. (eds.) (2002). God and
Time: Essays on the Divine Nature. New York: Oxford University
Press.
HICK, JOHN (ed.) (1977). The Myth of God Incarnate. London: SCM.
TRENTON MERRICKS
I have a body. And it is the very same body that I had earlier today.
It is even the same body I had as a child. That is why, for example,
my foot now bears a scar from an injury I su ered as a toddler.
Again, the body I have now is numerically identical with—is one
and the same object as—the body I had as a child. To deny this
would imply, I think quite implausibly, that I literally lost one body
and then acquired another at some point or other between my
childhood and now.
Dead bodies often pass out of existence. For example, some dead
bodies decay completely; others are cremated; some are even eaten
by wild animals. But, given the doctrine of the resurrection, even
those bodies that have gone out of existence will one day rise—and
so will one day exist—again. Thus the doctrine of the resurrection
implies a ‘temporal gap’ in the career of many bodies.2
Suppose, once more, that the time machine sends you to the
future. You arrive in the future with a familiar tattoo on your leg.
That tattoo’s being on your leg was caused not only by a youthful
lapse of judgment, but also—and more importantly—by your having
that very tattoo on your leg before entering the time machine. This
implies that causation can occur across a temporal gap, since the
way your leg was before time travel causes it to be a certain way
after time travel. In fact, this seems to be just the sort of causation
that is allegedly necessary for bodily identity over time.
Now some might object that the time machine story just told is
absolutely impossible. But I do not see why we should agree with
them.10 More generally, and more to the point, I see no compelling
reason to conclude that there is any condition that is both necessary
for bodily identity over time and also cannot possibly be satis ed
across a temporal gap. On the other hand, the considerations raised
above do not show that there is no such condition. As far as those
considerations go, we should be agnostic about the existence of such
a condition.
The second step says that you are neither heavier than nor
lighter than your body; that is, your weight is the same as your
body’s weight. Moreover, you are not one shape, and your body
another; rather you and your body have the same shape. Nor are
you o in one corner of the room, while your body is to be found in
another; instead, you are located just where your body is located.
The third step says that there is only one human-shaped object
exactly and entirely located where you are exactly and entirely
located, and, more generally, only one object with all of the physical
properties had by you and had by your body. Once we have taken
these three steps, we must conclude that you are identical with your
body.
Look at it this way. Suppose you know that you are about to die.
And you hope that death is not the end. Add that you know that you
are one and the same thing as your body. Then your hope for life
after death should have a very clear focus. You should hope that
your body (i.e. you yourself) will one day live again. Your body’s
living again will not happen on its own, of course. It will take a
miracle, especially if your body passes out of existence by way of
(e.g.) cremation. But that miracle—and, more generally, God’s
raising every dead body—will not be merely some sort of spooky
sideshow. Instead, it will be your only shot at life after death.
Or suppose that a close friend has just died. Suppose that you
know for certain that your friend was identical with his or her body.
Then you have only one hope for seeing your friend again: the
resurrection. Your only hope is the hope that, someday, God will
raise the dead. Thus we see once more that our being identical with
our bodies makes the motivation for, and importance of, the
doctrine of the resurrection perfectly clear.
At that time Michael, the great prince, the protector of your people,
shall arise. There shall be a time of anguish, such as has never
occurred since nations rst came into existence. But at that time
your people shall be delivered, everyone whose name is found
written in the book. Many of those who sleep in the dust of the
earth shall awake, some to everlasting life, and some to shame and
everlasting contempt. (Dan. 12:1–2, NRSV)
Do not be astonished at this; for the hour is coming when all who
are in their graves will hear [the Son of Man’s] voice and will come
out—those who have done good, to the resurrection of life, and
those who have done evil, to the resurrection of condemnation.
For the Lord himself, with a cry of command, with the archangel’s
call and with the sound of God’s trumpet, will descend from heaven,
and the dead in Christ will rise…
Let us begin with what I suspect is the most common reason that
many Christians, and others, deny that a human person is one and
the same thing as his or her body. They deny this because they want
to make sense of life after death, life after the destruction of one’s
body. And they think that this can be done only if one is not the
body that will be destroyed, but instead something else, such as a
soul. But as should now be perfectly clear, this ‘reason’ is no good.
On the contrary, I argued above that we are identical with our
bodies precisely because this identity makes the best sense of
speci cally Christian claims surrounding life after death, even life
after the destruction of one’s body. (Our being identical with our
bodies is, I confess, entirely inconsistent with the pictures of life
after death found in, for example, pagan Greek philosophy and the
movie Ghost.)
When he opened the fth seal, I saw under the altar the souls of
those who had been slaughtered for the word of God and for the
testimony they had given; they cried out with a loud voice,
‘Sovereign Lord, holy and true, how long will it be before you judge
and avenge our blood on the inhabitants of the earth?’ They were
each given a white robe and told to rest a little longer… (Rev. 6:
9–11, NRSV)
But consider the following. I ask Saint Frideswide to pray for me,
to ask God to grant a certain request. God, being omniscient, knows
that I have asked her this. So suppose that God, after the
resurrection, will communicate my request to her. She will then ask
God to have granted my petition. God even now knows that she will
do this. And so he now grants my petition, on account of
Frideswide’s future intercession. And so it goes, in general, with
how the saints intercede for us.
NOTES
12. The Athanasian Creed tells us that, at Christ’s coming, ‘all men
shall rise again with their bodies’.
13. Our having physical properties does not imply that our only
properties are physical. For example, our having physical
properties is consistent with our having mental properties,
even if those mental properties are themselves in no way
physical. Thus our having physical properties is consistent
with ‘property dualism’ about the mental.
14. I am not saying that the human authors of Scripture, or those
who formulated the creeds, believed or meant to teach that we
are identical with our bodies. I am saying that they believed
and meant to teach that our bodies will be resurrected, that
this is intimately related to our hope for life after death, and
that dead people will rise again. Because I believe what they
taught, I conclude—for reasons given in this chapter—that we
are identical with our bodies.
15. I have just argued from the doctrine of the resurrection to the
claim that we are identical with our bodies. That claim implies
that we lack (substantial) souls. This is why I said, in the
preceding section, that the doctrine of the resurrection
provides a reason to deny that bodily identity across a
temporal gap is secured by having the same soul.
Those who deny that we are identical with our bodies might
say that they have no idea why the doctrine of the resurrection
is important, even though it is important. Perhaps this is a
reasonable thing for them to say. And they might add that
saying this is analogous to saying that they have no idea what
grounds bodily identity across a temporal gap, even though
(some might maintain) something must ground it. But I do not
think that the cases are appropriately analogous. As I argued
in the previous section, there is nothing remotely like a
genuinely live option that, if true, would deliver a full and
satisfying account of what grounds the identity of a
resurrection body with a body that was (e.g.) cremated. So an
appeal to ignorance here is unavoidable for believers in the
resurrection, at least for those who think there must be some
ground for bodily identity across a temporal gap. On the other
hand, there is (what I take to be) a genuinely live option that,
if true, would deliver a full and satisfying account of the
importance of the doctrine of the resurrection: namely, the
identity of a person with his or her body.
REFERENCES
PLANTINGA, ALVIN (1999). ‘On Heresy, Mind, and Truth’, Faith and
Philosophy 16: 182–93.
SMITH, JANE IDLEMAN, and HADDAD, YVONNE YAZBECK (2002). The Islamic
Understanding ofDeath and Resurrection. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
JERRY L. WALLS
With the prospects for happiness and misery so magni ed, the
meaning of our lives and the signi cance of our choices are both
elevated to dramatic proportions. Indeed, both heaven and hell have
stirred the imagination of western culture for centuries, inspiring
great literature as well as visual art. Moreover, heaven and hell have
played an undeniable role in the moral foundations of western
culture, providing direction as well as hard motivation in the form
of ultimate sanctions.
(4) Therefore, God must punish any sin that is not atoned for
with in nite punishment.
Among classical theologians who have defended hell on these
grounds are Augustine, Aquinas, Anselm, and Jonathan Edwards.
At the end of the day, for Pascal, neither belief nor unbelief is
simply a matter of evidence or recognition of certain facts. Belief
requires a heart that is rightly disposed, and unbelief exposes a
wicked heart. And if this is correct, then evidence alone can never
be compelling for genuine faith. The evidence can be compelling in
the more modest sense that it makes clear the disposition of our
hearts. However, neither evidence that is compelling in this sense
nor unbearable su ering can guarantee the sort of free response that
God desires from us. Evidence can never be compelling in the sense
that Talbott’s argument requires and unbearable su ering cannot
elicit the sort of repentance that is rationally motivated and morally
free.
OBJECTING TO HEAVEN
Obviously, the argument assumes that the saved would not only
be aware of the damned but would also empathize with their
miserable condition. Since the saved would be fully transformed and
perfected in love, they would surely have a deep love for all persons
and desire their salvation. So if any remain separated from God,
none could experience the perfect happiness that is supposed to
characterize heaven. Indeed, the argument can be extended to claim
that not even God himself could be fully happy if some are forever
lost.49 Although this argument is usually cast as an argument
against eternal hell, it can also be used against the doctrine of
heaven since it says in essence that heaven and eternal hell are
incompatible.
While it is no doubt true that many persons who have held and
promoted beliefs about heaven have been at least partially
motivated by the dubious sort of motivations cited by Wright and
Segal, there is more to the story, even as told by them. As Wright
notes, the idea of the afterlife in Judaism originally grew out of
bedrock convictions about the ultimate reality of God’s goodness
and justice. The treacherous injustice of this life poses an obvious
challenge to these convictions and they could be sustained only if
this life is not the last word.54 Now if the deepest roots of belief in
heaven are tied up with convictions about God’s moral nature, then
the hope of heaven at its best is motivated by our highest and best
aspirations for goodness and justice. This part of the story provides
resources to critique dubiously motivated belief in heaven where it
occurs as well as to challenge histories of the doctrine that unduly
emphasize such motivation.
NOTES
1. The Book of Heaven, ed. Carol and Philip Zaleski (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2000), 5.
10. Alfred J. Freddoso (ed.), The Existence and Nature of God (Notre
Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), 3. Although hell
has not been de ned with ‘orthodox’ precision in anything like
the way Christology has been de ned in the Councils of Nicea
and Chalcedon, the doctrine of eternal hell is nevertheless a
matter of broad consensus among orthodox Christians of all
the major traditions.
20. Eleonore Stump has also defended a variation of the view that
God in his love sustains the damned in existence. See ‘Dante’s
Hell, Aquinas’s Moral Theory and the Love of God, Canadian
Journal of Philosophy 16 (1986), 181–98.
26. See Walls, Hell, 83–105. Seymour also takes this view: see A
Theodicy of Hell, 167. See also Andrei A. Buckare and Allen
Plug, ‘Escaping Hell: Divine Motivation and the Problem of
Hell’, Religious Studies 41 (2005), 39–54.
27. John Hick, Evil and the God of Love (San Francisco: Harper &
Row, 1966), 343. Gordon Knight has recently argued that
‘open theists’, those theists who hold that God cannot have
infallible knowledge of our future free choices, should
embrace ‘contingent universalism’. See Gordon Knight,
‘Universalism for Open Theists’ Religious Studies 42 (2006),
213–23.
28. Hick, Evil and the God of Love, 343–4. If God is necessarily
good, and something is morally impossible, then it should be
metaphysically impossible as well, for God’s nature limits what
is metaphysically possible. For further criticism of Hick, see
Walls, Hell, 70–81.
31. Talbott lays out his biblical argument in Robin A. Parry and
Christopher Partridge (eds.), Universal Salvation? The Current
Debate (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2003), 15–52. This volume
also includes critiques of Talbott’s universalism by several
authors representing di erent disciplines, including
philosophy. Talbott’s biblical arguments are critiqued by I.
Howard Marshall and Thomas F. Johnson. The book also
includes Talbott’s replies to his critics.
39. Thomas Talbott, ‘On the Divine Nature and the Nature of
Divine Freedom’ Faith and Philosophy5 (1988), 13.
47. This section reiterates and summarizes some of the key points
in two papers in which I criticize Talbott’s views. For further
argument of these points, see my ‘A Hell of a Choice: Reply to
Talbott’ Religious Studies 40 (2004), 203–16; and ‘A Hell of a
Dilemma: Rejoinder to Talbott’, Religious Studies 40 (2004),
225–7.
50. In the article just cited, Reitan surveys and criticizes several of
these arguments. It is worth noting, incidentally, that this
problem is one that would not have bothered many classical
theologians. Indeed, the likes of Augustine and Aquinas argued
that contemplating the misery of the damned would provide a
contrast that would actually enhance the joy of the saved. See
D. P. Walker, The Decline of Hell (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1964), 29.
51. For Nietzsche’s own thoughts along this line, see The Birth of
Tragedy & The Genealogy of Morals, trans. Francis Gol ng (New
York: Anchor, 1956), 178–85.
52. J. Edward Wright, The Early History of Heaven (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2000), 202; see also 137, 157, 163, 177.
53. Alan Segal, Life After Death: A History of the Afterlife in Western
Religion (New York: Doubleday, 2004), 699; see also 11, 16,
68, 243, 292, 344.
54. Wright, The Early History of Heaven, 158, 191–2. See also Segal,
Life After Death, 271–2.
ALEXANDER R. PRUSS
1. INTRODUCTION
Thus one should take seriously the idea of Christ’s body and
blood being present in a non-metaphorical way, ‘really present’. The
doctrine of ‘real presence’ presents several questions. First, we may
wonder about the sense of ‘present’ here. While we have taken
‘presence’ as not metaphorical, there may still be multiple senses of
presence. Is Christ’s body and blood ‘spatially present’ in the same
sense in which the bricks of the church building are ‘spatially
present’? Or is there some other non-metaphorical way of being
present that is applicable? How can Christ’s body and blood be
simultaneously present in multiple, disconnected places? Is a part
here and a part there, or is the whole present in each place?
For brevity, I will usually speak of the body rather than the
blood. There is here yet another question that I shall not address,
which is whether the presence of the body brings along with it the
presence of the blood and vice versa. The Catholic tradition answers
this a rmatively, and in the 13th Session of the Council of Trent
adds that the soul and divinity are present along with the body. On
Aquinas’s view, the blood, soul, and divinity are present on account
of their union with the body which is eucharistically present where
the bread used to be (Summa Theologiae III q. 76 a. 1).
2. REAL PRESENCE
But if the parts of the bread become parts of Christ’s body, they
do not seem to become organically important parts. As far as we can
tell, they do not engage in any organic interaction with Christ’s
heavenly body. Thus on the Leibnizian account, what is present in
the Eucharist seems to be an insigni cant portion of Christ’s body. If
there is no organic interaction there, the part present seems to be
more like a hair than a heart. Moreover, it is a part that Christ could
easily do without, since moments earlier he did not have it, and
nonetheless had a fully complete, indeed glori ed, body.
Thus this kind of partial presence would not only not be doing
justice to the idea of a real presence, but would also not match the
devotional tradition’s focus on Christ’s self-giving to us in the
Eucharist—here one thinks of the common image in Christian art of
the pelican legendarily feeding its young with blood from her breast
—since his giving us his hair to eat would not seem to have the kind
of depth of self-giving that is ascribed to the Eucharist. Moreover, it
would appear that on the Leibnizian view, Christ should have said
‘This is a part of my body’ rather than ‘This is my body.’
There are, then, two things that the substance is really present
in: it is directly present within the dimensions D, and thereby
mediately present in P. The substance is then said by St Thomas to
be ‘substantially’ present in D and ‘locally’ present in P.
What we then have are the dimensions of bread that are directly
present on the altar as in a place, and then the body of Christ is
substantially present in these dimensions, in the way in which the
substance of bread had been present in them. The body of Christ,
however, is not present locally on the altar, whether directly or
indirectly. It is not present directly locally, because material
substances are only directly present in their dimensions—it is only
through the dimensions’ presence that they are present anywhere.
And the body of Christ is not indirectly present locally, because to
be indirectly present locally in P, a substance must have dimensions
that are directly locally present in P. But the dimensions in question
are not ones that Christ’s body has, though it is contained in them
‘substantially’.
Furthermore one might think that shape and size are not intrinsic
properties of an entity, but instead depend on the location of the
parts, with location being a relational property (this will be
discussed further in sect. 2.5). If one takes this view, then one will
not see locatedness as mediated by being within dimensions, and
Aquinas’s view will not be attractive. However, one can still take
one of the views of the next two sections.
This claim seems quite plausible, but is not clearly true. Observe
rst that a person might be wholly located in two buildings at once.
Thus, the Royal British Columbia Museum contains a wooden house
ceremonially belonging to the descendants of Chief
Kwakwabalasami, and someone within that house would be in two
buildings at once. Moreover, then the place where the person would
be would itself be in two houses. But if a place could be in two
buildings at once, it seems plausible that a place could be on two
altars at once. Of course that would require a special spatial
relationship between the two altars. Imagine, for instance, a large
altar whose surface seen from above was a wooden rectangle
surrounded by a larger stone surface. It might turn out that the
wooden rectangle had its own independent legs, and was originally
consecrated as a separate altar, and then became a part of a larger
altar without losing its initial consecration. Then something lying on
top of the wooden rectangle would by lying on two altars at once—
the larger one of stone and wood, and the smaller one just of wood.
But how would we argue that St Peter’s and the National Shrine
have no common place? The best way I can see—and one whose
failure will be illustrative of the failures of other ways—would be to
note that a straight line segment can be drawn between any pair of
points one of which is wholly in St Peter’s and the other wholly in
the National Shrine, and the line segment will have positive length.
This argument, however, presupposes the premise that when a line
segment of non-zero length can be drawn between point A in space
and point B in space, then A and B are distinct. This premise is
empirical, and we do not at present actually know if it is in general
true. For all we know, the space of the universe has a geometry such
that if you go far enough in any one direction you will come back to
where you started.
The same quotient space move could be done with more than
one wafer, as well as with the wafers and Christ’s body in heaven.
Christ’s body would come to be present on the altar, then, in the
sense that the points in the space just around the eucharistic host
would come to be neighbors of points in heaven. It would become
literally true that a little piece of heaven is on earth. The only thing
one needs to do to form the quotient space is to have a one-to-one
correspondence between each set of points where a wafer is before
consecration and the points in Christ’s heavenly body.
2.5. Bilocation
Since the whole is where all the parts are, we can then say that the
whole is in P.
A di culty with this de nition is an ambiguity in ‘all the parts’.
If we mean all the parts that exist at the given time t, then
multilocation is only possible when the object has the same parts in
all one’s locations. In particular, the kind of multilocation that is
involved in time travel will be ruled out, because the adult time
traveler who visits her teenage self has cells that the teenager does
not and vice versa. If, on the other hand, we mean all the parts that
are found in P, then it follows that we are trivially wholly located
wherever any of our parts is present, so that being wholly located
reduces to being present, which seems implausible.
This is all we need in the case of the Eucharist because there the
possibility that an entity may have more parts at one of its multiple
locations than at another may not come up. Rather, we can simply
say that each of the parts that Christ’s body now has is found in
each of the multiple locations of the Eucharist.
A more serious di culty with bilocation is the possibility of
di erences in intrinsic properties. If I am present in more than one
place at a time, I might be red all over as found in one place and
green all over as found in another, which would imply that I am
simultaneously red all over and green all over. One response,
defended by Koons 2005, is that the problem here is no bigger than
the problem of intrinsic change for an eternalist, i.e. for someone
who believes that the past and future are equally as real as the
present. The problem of change, raised by Lewis 1986: 204 is
generated by the fact that an entity might have contradictory
properties at di erent times, say, being round at one time and
square at another.
But in fact shape and size are not intrinsic properties. We learn
from Einstein that shape and size depend on reference frame, for
instance. We might also argue that the shape and size of an object
supervenes on the positions of its parts. If so, then we might take
the shape and size as constituted by facts about the positions of the
parts. But the position of an entity may well be relational, consisting
in the relation between the entity and a point in space on an
absolutist view of space, or the relation between the entity and
other entities on a relational view. (For other arguments for the
non-intrinsicness of shape, see Skow 2007.)
(See also McDaniel 2003.) If so, then it might be that the internal
shape and size is something intrinsic but the external one is not.
One might be suspicious of even the idea that the internal shape and
size is intrinsic (e.g. the arguments of Skow 2007 would still apply),
but even if we grant the intrinsicness, it is not clear that a problem
for multilocational accounts of real presence results.
For the main di culty is, presumably, that Christ is, let us
suppose, ve feet tall while the Eucharistic host is, let us suppose,
an inch in diameter, and there is a disparity of shape. However, we
can imagine a space where the inside of an area is in some sense
bigger than the outside, and whose internal geometry is di erent
from what one might expect from the outside. Imagine an in nite,
at two-dimensional space. Think of this as a rubber sheet. Draw a
small circle. Now keep the edges of the circle xed, but stretch the
rubber within the circle into a large bubble whose diameter is much
larger than that of the circle (for visualizing this, we stretch the
sheet into the third dimension; to avoid making use of an extra
dimension, we could simply modify the metric). The resulting space
is at, except for a circle that pinches o a large balloon. Then there
is a real sense in which the inside of the area is larger than the
outside: the outside is a small circle, but the diameter of the bubble
within is larger. Moreover, the geometry inside may be quite
di erent from what we expect from the outside.
3. REAL ABSENCE
4. CONCLUSIONS
NOTES
7. One worry is that ‘this’ gets its reference from the visible
accidents when these are attached to a substance. If there were
some third substance in view, then ‘This is my body’ might
seem to refer to that substance, which would be incorrect.
REFERENCES
NON-CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHICAL
THEOLOGY
CHAPTER 24
DANIEL H. FRANK
Among all the prescriptions and ordinances of the Mosaic law, there
is not a single one which says: You shall believe or not believe. They
all say: You shall do or not do. Faith is not commanded, for it accepts
no other command than those that come to it by way of conviction.
All the commandments of the divine law are addressed to man’s
will, to his power to act. In fact, the word in the original language
that is usually translated as faith [emunah] actually means, in most
cases, trust, con dence, and rm reliance on pledge and promise …
Commandments and prohibitions, reward and punishment are only
for actions, acts of commission and omission which are subject to a
man’s will … Hence, ancient Judaism has no symbolic books, no
articles of faith. No one has to swear to symbols or subscribe, by
oath, to certain articles of faith. Indeed, we have no conception at
all of what are called religious oaths; and according to the spirit of
true Judaism, we must hold them to be inadmissible.2
A MEDIEYAL PROLEGOMENON
If we turn back to the medieval period, when Jews and Judaism
were not vying for a spot at a (modern) secular table, we might
imagine we would see Judaism in an unapologetic mode, not intent
on (ex hypothesi) e acing dogmatic, credal commitments. With a
view to maintaining group loyalty, we might expect a certain
presumption of orthodoxy and credal commitment. The rst great
work of medieval Jewish philosophy, The Book of Doctrines and
Beliefs, written in the rst half of the tenth century in Baghdad by
Saadya Gaon, is a work of Jewish kalam (dialectical theology).3 It
presents in considerable detail discussions of a standard set of issues
such as creation of the world, the nature and unity of God, divine
justice, freedom and determinism, and divine reward and
punishment. In its own way this work is an apology, a defense of
traditional Judaism, but the defense is of a certain way of
understanding Judaism, namely as committed to a distinct set of
philosophical theses, noted above. Saadya’s project is manifestly not
a defense of (what Mendelssohn would call) ‘articles of faith’.
In sum, the fact that some laws are the product of reasonless
choice, enforced by logical necessity, does not compromise divine
wisdom. God is wise, and so is his law, even in those situations in
which he chooses, perforce, without preference. Given this,
Solomon’s traditional wisdom concerning grounds for the
commandments (ta‘amei ha-mitzvot) is con rmed: it rightly extends
to ‘the utility of a given commandment in a general way, not an
examination of the particulars’.20
Are there any substantive conclusions we can draw from this brief
excursus through the thoughts of some major Jewish philosophers?
One conclusion might be a healthy revision of the very notion of
philosophical theology. I think that the subject is generally
conceived to be a highly theoretical one, having little to do with
actions and living one’s life. The (philosophical) theologian is the
person who wonders about the nature of God, divine power and
knowledge, the creation (or eternity) of the world, and the
implications of this on divine freedom, etc. The list goes on and on,
and there can be no doubt that the medieval Jewish philosophers
from Saadya onwards address these issues. But perhaps what is
overlooked is how these ‘theoretical’ discussions appear to support
some rather practical, moral, and even political considerations. At
the very beginning of this chapter, we noted Mendelssohn’s claim
that the only commandments that Judaism knows are commands to
act and to refrain. He stresses as strongly as he can, and for the
apologetic reasons we noted, that Judaism has no ‘articles of faith’,
no commands to believe.
NOTES
6. Ibid. 30.
19. Ibid.3. 26. For a possible source for this latter point, see NE 5.
7 (1134b20–3).
20. Ibid.
21. For a full discussion of this point, see J. Stern, ‘The Idea of a
Hoq in Maimonides’ Explanation of the Law’, in S. Pines and Y.
Yovel (eds.), Maimonides and Philosophy (Dordrecht: Nijho ,
1986), 92–130.
OLIVER LEAMAN
PERIPATETICISM (FALSAFA)
MYSTICISM
ILLUMINATIONISM
ETHICS
POLITICS
THE SOUL
The nature of the soul, the thinking part of human beings, was a
particularly important issue from a religious point of view. Many
Peripatetic thinkers followed Aristotle in regarding the soul as the
form of a person, as the way in which we are organized and not
something distinct that is part of us. This implies that once the body
or matter dies, the soul or form of the matter no longer exists since
it then has nothing to inform. Yet Islam has a strong notion of an
afterlife, graphically described in the Qur’an and the traditional
sayings as a physical afterlife, and the soul and body would in some
sense be regarded as eternal in that afterlife. It might be suggested
that the Qur’anic view is largely allegorical, so that our actions in
this life have consequences that extend further than this life, and a
good way of communicating this to people who think that matter is
important is through talking about having an afterlife in the sense of
eternal souls. Other thinkers tended to use a Platonic account of the
soul as something eternal and immaterial, and this also seems to
contradict the Qur’anic account of the afterlife as a physical sort of
place, as heaven or hell or what lies in between. Many of the
Peripatetics (falasifa) argue that the religious language is physical
because for most people that is what is important in their lives. It is
a way of explaining to everyone why it is important for us to behave
well, whereas a more spiritual grasp of the links between this world
and the next one is achievable only by a few intellectuals or
spiritually advanced individuals, and should not be widely
broadcast.
LOGIC
One of the shocking implications that was derived from Ibn Rushd
in Christian Europe was the idea that religion and reason are
entirely separate areas of thought. A proposition may be true in one
and false in another, a view often attributed to Ibn Rushd. Although
he certainly did not argue in this way, he did suggest that there are
di erent routes to the truth, to the same truth, and these routes may
be quite distinct from each other. This is an important topic for the
falasifa as a whole, since for them many issues and ideas can be seen
from a variety of perspectives, each of which represents where the
individual is coming from, each of which links up with the truth,
and all of which are di erent. For example, al-Farabi points out that
the religious understanding of the prophet is that he is someone of
excellent moral character chosen by God to transmit a message.
From the philosophical point of view he is someone of equally
sound moral character whose intellect is in line with the active
intellect and so knows how to persuade an audience of a particular
point of view. By the active intellect is meant the highest level of
conceptual thought that is accessible by human beings. The
philosopher and the believer both listen to the same message, that
provided by the prophet, and analyze what they hear di erently,
but both are right. The philosopher understands the rational basis of
the prophetic message, while the ordinary believer is impressed
with its emotional power. Does this mean that the former has a
better grasp of the meaning of the message than the latter?
QUR’ANIC LOGIC
Another theoretical debate that swiftly arose was over the nature
of determinism and freedom. Are human beings free to act, or are
their actions determined by God? Both sorts of language are found
in the Qur’an and the remarks of the Prophet and his Companions,
but the nal position is a matter of debate. This is a good example
of a theological debate that quickly became philosophical, in that it
started by looking at scriptural passages and trying to understand
their implications, and ended up by exploring the rational
foundations of each position. The determinist can nd plenty of
Qur’anic passages that suggest that God makes everything happen,
even the fact whether we believe in him or otherwise. This implies,
though, that one cannot be held responsible for one’s actions, yet
the Qur’an goes into long and highly descriptive detail of the day of
judgment and the afterlife of reward and punishment. How can this
life be a realm of testing if God determines everything that happens?
Yet the idea that people have free will has di cult implications
also, in that it could be taken to suggest that they are in charge of
things rather than God.
There has been a long discussion in Islam about the signi cance of
following tradition or taqlid. Clearly any religion requires
interpretation, and there are some authorities that are likely to be
more reliable. They are the people to follow when it comes to
seeking an understanding of what the religion means and expects
one to do. In any area, it was argued, one should seek to follow the
expert, since if one knew what to do one would not need to ask an
expert in the rst place. But who is an expert? The Qur’an is full of
injunctions to its hearers and readers to consider, think, reason, and
that is presumably because Muslims are supposed to use their
rational faculties to work out what the text means and indeed what
everything means, insofar as they can. There are limits to what one
can work out oneself, however, and it is here that there is a need for
guidance.
Taqlid has an important role in that there are people who can
help one understand a text and its contemporary relevance if one is
unable to grasp this owing to a lack of knowledge of the whole book
and its context and other appropriate sources of information. It is
rational to follow authorities under such circumstances, and to do so
is not blind obedience; it is submitting oneself to the authority of
another when one has good grounds for doing so. Those good
grounds are established rationally.
Does the text really argue for the existence of God? Not very
seriously. God’s existence is taken to be an obvious and natural fact,
based on what we observe around us all the time, and nature, like
the verses of the Qur’an, is full of ‘signs (ayat) for people who
understand’ (2. 164). There is quite a bit of argument about why we
should believe in the existence of one God as opposed to many gods,
and why associating partners with God (shirk) is to be rejected
totally. There are also many arguments in the Book for resurrection,
a basic doctrine given the importance of rejecting materialism and
the belief that our deaths are followed by nothing more than the
collapse and decay of our bodies. These are based on the idea that
God can do anything, and on our experience of nature in which life
often follows death. The materialist who believes that all there is is
this life has no reason to believe in God and his message. There are
also many arguments for the prophethood of the Prophet himself,
and much of this clearly replicates the sort of to and fro of debate
that took place in Mecca and Medinah when Islam was becoming
established in the early years. The issue of who should succeed the
Prophet, the source of the Sunni/Shi‘i split, is of course discussed
widely.
The fact that reasons may explain but not determine subsequent
actions was not accepted by al-Ghazali, advocate though he was of
the use of logic in theology and of its incorporation as a natural part
of Islamic thought. Al-Ghazali criticized thinkers such as Miskawayh
(320–421/932–1030) for believing that God had reasons to establish
certain rituals and rules that t in with human nature. Miskawayh
suggests that many of the rites of Islam have the purpose of
strengthening the links between believers, so that religion uses
social norms to encourage and strengthen religious observance. Al-
Ghazali argues on the contrary that God institutes rules just because
that is what he wants to do; there is no necessity for him to align
himself with our social instincts, nor even to employ them. Where
al-Ghazali goes awry here is thinking that because God may have
had reasons for what he did, those reasons would make his actions
governed by them. He would be forced by the reasons to act in a
particular way. The Mu‘tazilites did in fact argue in this way that
God has to follow certain principles of morality in his behavior; he
has to have justice in mind when he acts. Al-Ghazali rejected that
theory, arguing plausibly that it is an error to think that God must
have a particular purpose in mind that we can understand when he
does something. But he went too far in suggesting that God could
have nothing in mind when he does something. For al-Ghazali, all
God wants to do in telling us how to act is demonstrate his power
and the necessity on our part to obey him. However, having reasons
for action only constrains us if they inevitably result in particular
actions, but God cannot be forced to act in this way, and nor can
we.
One might think that the case for God would be di erent here
than it is for us. We are nite and changing creatures with a partial
view of the world and ourselves. None of this is true of God; he is
perfect, in nite and understands everything. Yet for him also
reasons do not determine. There are many things he can do and
might wish to do given the same set of facts. Rationality and
bene cence do not inevitably lead to particular actions. When the
angels are told by God to bow down to Adam (2. 30–4) and they
complain saying that Adam and his descendants will wreck the
earth if they get power over it, the angels have a point. But God
replies that he understands this and will send human beings a guide.
The notion of a guide is important here. A guide guides, he indicates
the right direction and the appropriate ways to determine the right
direction. The guide does not force people to obey him nor even to
accept him. The guide brings a message, but messages get distorted
and twisted, or are just quite honestly misunderstood. God provides
general advice and instructions to his creation, but there is a great
deal of freedom for people to make their own decisions and take
their own risks. This explains the signi cant role of theology and
philosophy. The reasons they accept as signi cant in controlling
their actions do not point to a set of clear and distinct propositions,
since if they did there would be no variety of understandings of
religion, or even of Islam. Since the Qur’an tells us sometimes to
respect diversity in humanity and forbids us from compelling
religious allegiance, the idea that reasons are not followed
inevitably by particular actions and beliefs is presumably well
taken.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
AL- BAQILLANI, ABU BAKR MUHAMMAD, I‘jaz al-Qur’an. Beirut: Dar lhya’
al-’Ulum, 1994.
CRAGG, K., The Event of the Qur’an, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oneworld, 1994.
GWYNNE, R., Logic, Rhetoric, and Legal Reasoning in the Qur’an: God’s
Arguments. New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2004.
HAHN, L., et al.(eds.), The Philosophy of Seyyed Hossein Nasr. Chicago:
Open Court, 2001.
IZUTSU, T., God and Man in the Koran: Semantics of the Koranic
Weltanschauung. Tokyo: Keio Institute of Cultural and Linguistic
Studies, 1964.
JOMIER, J., The Great Themes of the Qur’an. London: SCM, 1997.
AL- JUWAYNI, Kitab al-irshad ila qawati al-adilla usul al-i‘tiqad, ed. M.
Musa and A. ‘Abd al-Hamid. Cairo, 1950.
2001.
——— Islamic Aesthetics: An Introduction. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2004.
PETERS, F.E. (ed.), The Arabs and Arabia on the Eve of Islam.
Brook eld: Ashgate, 1999.
JOHN H. BERTHRONG
PREAMBLE
The sun’s rays glint rst on the mountains to the west, then,
moments later, touch the thatched roofs of the temples and pit
dwellings that follow the curve of the Huan. The river, still in
shadow at the foot of the earthen cli , winds to the southeast
between clearings of sprouting millet, on its way to merge with the
powerful He. The year is the eleventh of Wu Ding’s reign, the season
spring, the day xinwei, eighth of the week.
7. 23: The Master said, ‘Tian has given life and nourished
excellence (de ) in me—what can Huan Tui do to me!’
11.12: Zilu asked how to serve the spirits [gui ] and the gods [shen
]. The Master replied, ‘Not yet being able to serve other people,
how would you be able to serve the spirits?’ Zilu said, ‘May I ask
about death?’ The Master replied, ‘Not yet understanding life, how
could you understand death?’ (Translations from Ames & Rosemont
1998: 85, 116, 144)
EISEGETICAL EXEGESIS
Contrariwise, the third quote, Lunyu 11. 12, is cited to prove that
Master Kong did not believe in the spirits and gods. However, such
an inference is not clear in the text. The most that can be drawn
suggestively from the quote is an agnostic view of how the spirits
and gods interact with human beings. Remembering that tian not
only gives us life but also nourishes de virtue, I interpret the
passage to mean that Kongzi is reminding his audience that
whatever role the spirits and gods play in the world, the proper
charge or supernal mandate tianming for a person was to
cultivate humane virtue ren . If a person persistently cultivates
virtue, then what is there to worry about in relationship to the
spirits, gods and even tian? As Herbert Fingarette (1972) so
elegantly observed, for Master Kong the secular is the sacred and
the axiology of ethical self-cultivation trumps any kind of bhakti
devotion to the spirits, gods, and tian. This does not mean that we
lack a natural or cultivated piety towards the spirits and gods, but
that our primary task is to learn how to serve our fellow human
beings in the way we would ourselves like to be treated in order to
create a ourishing, harmonious, and shining human society.
CONFUCIAN RELIGIOSITY
Master Meng makes two points. The rst is that he has insight
into words, and this means that he understood the role of
philosophical disputation about the true nature of the Dao. But
secondly, more than merely having insight into words, he had the
ability to cultivate his ood-like qi. His disciple is as perplexed by
what Mengzi means by this qi as we and countless Confucian
scholars have been over the centuries. Although to pro er some
‘obvious’ exegesis is the height of folly, it does appear that if one
can achieve this feat of the cultivation of the ood-like qi then the
person will be in tune with heaven and earth in manifest yi
rightness or righteous justice within the matrix of the Dao. In short,
such a person can achieve oneness with the very ow of the cosmos
in the highest degree. This truly is a teaching about self-cultivation
that becomes part of the Confucian religious quest. In fact, based on
Mengzi’s teachings, many of the great mystics of the Confucian
tradition have counted themselves as followers of Master Meng in
seeking to cultivate the ood-like qi.
The third of the great classical Confucians was Xunzi (c.310–238
BCE). Because Master Xun had the audacity to contradict Master
Meng concerning xing by declaring that human nature or
dispositions were odious and perverse, he was banished from the
inner circle of the ‘orthodox’ founders of the Confucian way.
However, it is wise to remember that this banishment was only
formalized in the Song dynasty; prior to the rise of Neo-
Confucianism Master Xun was considered one of the greatest of the
classical Confucians. Given the range of his works, from poetry,
ritual theory, ethics, military theory, and epistemology, he was by
far and away the most systematic and coherent of any of the early
Confucian masters.
17. 2b The constellations follow their revolutions; the sun and moon
alternately shine; the four seasons present themselves in succession;
the Yin and Yang enlarge and transform; and the wind and rain
spread out everywhere.…We do not perceive the process, but we
perceive the result—this indeed is why we call it ‘divine’.
17. 5 Heaven does not suspend the winter because men dislike cold
weather. Earth does not reduce its broad expanse because men
dislike long distances. The gentleman does not interrupt his pattern
of conduct because petty men rant and rail. Heaven possessed a
constant Way; Earth has an invariable size; the gentleman has
constancy of deportment.
THE ZHONGYONG
The second great epoch of the Confucian Way began in the late
Tang and gained momentum to in uence in the Northern Song
(960–1126 CE). It is important to remember that the contemporary
New Confucians of the third epoch are the direct descendants of the
great masters of the Tang, Song, Ming, and Qing dynasties. Many
western students of Confucianism have a marked preference for the
classical period even though the Song–Ming masters argued that
they were faithfully reviving and restoring the grand classical
Confucian tradition that had been partially eclipsed by the arrival of
the Buddhist dharma in China in all its resplendent Mahāyāna glory
and the ourishing of various indigenous Daoist sects.
Zhang Zai was one of the greatest of the Northern Song masters,
and with his strong a rmation of the role of qi vital energy as the
key concept of his philosophy, he was deeply appreciated by the
later Qing scholars because of this commitment to the dynamic,
concrete nature of the cosmos. Zhang is lauded for writing the
famous short essay the ‘Western Inscription’.6 Not only does the
‘Western Inscription’ capture the cosmic scope of Song cosmology,
axiology, and ethics, it also has an unmistakable religious sensibility
that has inspired the entire Confucian tradition.
The classical Confucian virtues are all recon rmed, but within a
spiritual vision of the cosmos that expands its sense of concern
consciousness from the immediate family and clan to the whole of
humanity and beyond to all the things or events of the world. Both
blessings and di culties are the methods by which the Dao
strengthens the sage and the worthy. If one is successful in this
spiritual, moral, and intellectual quest, then as Zhang says with such
eloquence, even ‘In death I will be at peace.’ If this is not an
evocation of a supernal religious sensibility, a meditation on how a
person ought to deport him or herself in the presence of the Dao,
the reader is deaf to the spiritual yearnings of the Northern Song
mind-heart.
Lunyu 15. 29 says, ‘The Master said, “Human beings can broaden
the Way—it is not the Way that broadens human beings”’
(Slingerland 2003: 185). It is this kind of insight that has always
separated the Confucian religious tradition from the great theistic
teachings of west and south Asia. Nonetheless, a sampling of
modern New Confucians such as Mou Zongsan and Tu Wei-ming
illustrates why Lunyu 15. 29 remains relevant to the current New
Confucian revival project. One can imagine many changes or
transformations of the Confucian Way in the future, but one cannot
imagine that Confucians will turn the saying around to a rm that it
is the Way that broadens human beings, even if Confucians are
concerned to discern how they should respond to the Way of
Heaven. It is precisely this note of immanent transcendence that
many western thinkers nd appealing as they struggle to overcome
the feeling that the western religious path has overemphasized the
nature of God as the wholly other, the completely transcendent One
of worship. If the Jesuits and early Protestants found the
Zhongyong’s thesis that heaven, earth, and humanity form a living
trinity to be heretical, then modern men and women nd this an
increasingly plausible notion about how to be spiritual in the world
that modern science reveals to us.
NOTES
Save for the names of authors and book titles, I have modi ed
all texts and translations to use the contemporary pinyin
Romanization system for consistency.
REFERENCES
AMES, ROGER T., and Rosemont, Henry, Jr. (1998). The Analects of
Confucius: A Philosophic Translation. New York: Ballantine.
PLAKS, ANDREW (trans.) (2003). Ta Hsüeh and Chung Yung (The Highest
Order of Cultivation and On the Practice of the Mean), trans. with
an introduction, Andrew Plaks. London: Penguin.
ZHU XImage
I (2002). Zhuzi quan shu
Image [The Collected Works of
Master Zhu], ed. Zhu Jieren, Yan Zuozhi, Liu Yongxiang. 27
vols. Shanghai: Shanghai gu ji chu ban she & Anhui jiao yu chu
ban she.
INDEX
Baconian inductivism 61
Baillie, John: The Idea of Revelation in Recent Thought 51 n5
Ban Gu 579
Barbour, Ian 74 n5
Barnes, Michael 420
Barr, James 49, 145–6
Barth, Karl: Church Dogmatics 441, 442–3
Barton, John: Reading the Old Testament 27 n5
Basil, St, of Caesarea 27 n3
Epistle 52 423
On the Holy Spirit 27, 67, 27 n3
Basinger, David 294
Bayes’ theorem 339–49
Bayle, Pierre 86–7
Bayne, Tim 467
beati c vision 91–3
Beaudoin, John 395 n9
belief
and evidence 503–4
and evil 332–3
Islam 563, 567
justi cation for 19–27
Maimonides and 546
systems of 469–70
and trust 26
see also logic; science: and religion
Benedict XVI, Pope 352
Bernstein, Mark 385
Berulle, Pierre de 80
Bible
Apocrypha: Acts of John 81
authority of 11–13, 21–2, 25, 45–6, 50
authorship 41–2, 47–9
and Christian tradition 12–19
and Creation 249–50, 252
and divine-human relationship 500
and divine revelation 11–13, 15, 18, 20–1, 35–6, 37–9, 43
Hebrew: book of Job 354
and history 35, 36–7
inconsistencies in 13–14
and inspiration 41–50
metaphor in 16
New Testament 12, 13, 14, 18, 39
Old Testament 12, 13–14, 16
and science 15
see also Scripture
bilocation, Eucharist 526–33
Bivalence, Principle of 164 n7, 219
Blount, Charles 85
Blount, Douglas K. 455–6
Boethius, Anicius Manlius Severinus 138–9, 147
Brower, Je 425 n22
Brümmer, Vincent 448 n19
Buddha 319, 320
Buddhism 75 n18, 585
Madhyamikas 87
Burrell, David 454
Byrne, Peter and Houlden, Leslie: Companion Encyclopedia of
Theology 79
facts
moral 309, 310–20
tensed 159–63
faith
Christianity 25–6, 35
Judaism 543
Fallen Humanity 438–9, 444–5
Falsafa see Peripateticism families 254, 256
Faraday, Michael 65
Fiddler on the Roof 277
Fingarette, Herbert 577
Flew, Anthony see MacIntyre, Alasdair and Flew, Anthony
Flint, Thomas 130, 142, 174–83, 234, 293
foreknowledge 133, 138–41, 148–9, 263–7, 270–3, 275, 277, 357–
8
forgiveness 435
Francis of Marchea 65
Frankfurt, Harry G. 178
Freddoso, Alfred 133, 140, 174–83, 494
freedom
of action 132, 222, 223, 233, 245, 263, 289–90, 567
in Islam 571
challenges to 499–502
of choice 121–2, 295–6, 356–8, 363, 365, 366–70
and divine foreknowledge 138–42, 218–19, 262–72, 274–6, 356–
8
and God see divine freedom and Hell 496, 499–502
libertarian 43, 141, 154, 180–1, 187, 248, 258, 263–70, 274–6,
496, 497, 501, 504
and non-human creatures 370
Free Process Defense 244
free will 68, 244–6, 362–5
Free Will Defense 222–3, 335
Free will theodicy see theodicy, free will
Freud, Sigmund 62
Friedman, Alexander 151
haecceity 136
Hájek, Alan 396 n26
Hall, David L. 584
happiness, eternal 234, 506–8
Hare, John 318
Hartshorne, Charles 202–3
Hasker, Willam 139–40, 279, 280
Haught, John 243, 244–6, 259 n3
Heaven: doctrine of 491–2, 506–8
Hebblethwaite, Brian 472 n3, 473 n13
Hebrews, Letter to the 33, 129, 202, 441, 464, 513
Hell 491–506
accounts of 499–502
defenses of 493–9
eternal 495, 502–6
and freedom 496, 499–502, 506–7
proportionality objection 495–9
separation conceptions of 498
Helm, Paul 37, 163, 220
hermeneutics 13–14
Hesse, Mary 70
Hick, John 368, 435
Evil and the God of Love 499
Hilbert, David 91
Himma, Kenneth 497–8
Hobbes, Thomas 314–16, 328 n24
Hodge, Charles 448 n17
Ho man, J. and Rosenkrantz, G. 139, 175
Holocaust 352
Holy Spirit 24, 26–7, 27 n3, 36–8, 40, 41–2, 45–6, 48–9
Holy Trinity see Trinity, the homoousion clause 404, 416
Hookway, Christopher 71
Houlden, Leslie see Byrne, Peter and Houlden, Leslie
Howard-Snyder, Daniel 368, 376
Hudson, Hud 487 n6, 536 n5
human body 255
human identity 478
human intellect 83
humanity
attributes of 463–4
fallen see Fallen Humanity
human nature 581–2, 587, 590
and morality 314, 315, 318
human perception 23, 71
human reason 87–8
humans
emotions 71
interconnections 254–7
human su ering 233, 337–8, 339, 340–2, 344, 346, 354, 393, 495
Hume, David 78, 343
Hunt, David 131–2
Hyperactive Agent Detection Device (HADD) 62
Kant, Immanuel 223, 224, 228, 308, 326, 329 n40, 547
Kaufman, Gordon 492, 493
Keightly, David N. 575
Kellenberger, James 90
Kellner, Menachem 546
Kennedy, John Fitzgerald 543
kenosis 465
Kepler, Johannes, Mysterium Cosmographicum 57
Kings, First book of 293
Kitcher, Philip 369
Knight, Gordon 510 n27
Knoblock, John 582
knowledge 132–3
accounts of 302 n26
de dicto 134
de praesenti 135–7, 162–3
de re 134, 162
de se 136, 162
divine 42–3, 91–5, 117–18, 121–2, 129–42, 159–63, 262–3,
274–5, 559
rst-person 135–7, 162
foreknowledge 133, 138–41, 148–9, 263–7, 270–3, 275, 277,
357–8
free 43, 141, 274–5
middle 42–3, 140–2, 149, 275–7, 301 n14
moral 318
natural 42, 141–2, 274–5
Kongzi see Confucius
Koons, Robert C. 526, 528
Kretzmann, Norman 135–6, 139, 151, 157–8
Kuhn, Thomas Samuel 65
Kvanvig, Jonathan 136, 160, 497, 498 604
Lamont, John: Divine Faith 25
Lang, Bernhard 492
language: and Islam 556–7, 558, 568
law
of nature 242, 246, 251–2
natural 314–17, 365–7
Judaism 548, 549, 550
Leftow, Brian 151, 158–61, 410–12, 461–2, 489 n16
legalism 31
Leibnitz, Gottfried Wilhelm 87–8, 99 n44, 353, 361–2, 516–7
Lewis, C. S. 6 n3, 235, 297, 496, 498, 503
Lewis, David 113, 360, 436–7, 528
libertarianism 43, 141, 154, 180–1, 187, 248, 258, 263–70, 274–6,
496, 497, 501, 504
life, eternal 507–8
liturgy 512
Locke, John 89, 543
logic: Islam 564–5, 566–8
logical empiricism 2–3
Lombard, Peter 169
Luke, Gospel according to 14, 167
Lunyu (Analects) 574, 576, 577
obedience 321
obligations, moral 317–18 ‘occasionalists’ 314
Ockham, William of 138, 140, 170
Old Testament see Bible: Old Testament
omnipotence see divine omnipotence
omnipresence see divine omnipresence
omniscience see divine omniscience
‘Open Theism’ movement (Openists) 76 n42, 139–40, 263, 264,
269–74, 281, 356–8, 510 n27
Oppy, Graham 176, 177–9, 195 n47
Origen of Alexandria 14, 15–16, 28 n11, 168, 361, 478
original sin 6 n3, 257, 437–40, 443–7
and imputation 437–8
traducianism 438, 440
Orr, James 43
orthodoxy 413
Eastern Orthodox 250
Otte, Richard 342
Otto, Rudolph 79, 82, 94
Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Religion 4–5, 79
rabbis 548–9
Rachels, James 311
Rahner, Karl 85, 92–3, 95
Ramanuja 578
rationality, religious 62–3, 67
realism
Augustinian 437–40
and regions 199
Rea, Michael 302 n19, 358
real absence: doctrine of 533–5
real presence: doctrine of 512–36
reason, human 87–8
Redeemed Humanity 441, 442, 443, 444–5
redemption 249–53, 256, 434
reductionism 69
reduplicative analysis 455
Reformed theological tradition 220
Régnon, Theodore de 424 n15
Reid, John: The Authority of the Scripture 52 n33
Reitan, Eric 506
relativism 31
Relativity Theory 251, 359 see also Einstein, Albert
reliabilism 23, 24
religion 591
erosion of 63–4
point of 570
and reason 565–6, 568
and science 54–73
religious rationality 62–3, 67
religious studies: schools 492–3
representationalism 443
Resurrection Day of see Day of Resurrection
resurrection, doctrine of 476–86
Revelation, book of 485
revelation see divine revelation
risk see God: and risk
ritualism 31
Romans, Letter to the 129, 246, 249, 255, 258, 444, 446, 447
Rosenkrantz, G. see Ho man, J. and Rosenkrantz, G.
Roughgarden, Joan 249
Rowe, William 81, 219–20, 222, 226, 341, 376, 381–2, 390
Russell, Robert 242