Texto Librodeleuzeandfascism1
Texto Librodeleuzeandfascism1
Texto Librodeleuzeandfascism1
As Michel Foucault has famously stated, ‘knowledge is not made for understanding; it is made for
cutting.’ In this spirit the Edkins–Vaughan-Williams Interventions series solicits cutting edge,
critical works that challenge mainstream understandings in international relations. It is the best
place to contribute post disciplinary works that think rather than merely recognize and affirm the
world recycled in IR’s traditional geopolitical imaginary. Michael J. Shapiro, University of
Hawai’i at Mãnoa, USA
Index
Contributors
Brad Evans is a Senior Lecturer in International Relations at the Global
Insecurities Center, the School of Sociology, Politics and International
Studies, the University of Bristol, UK. He has published extensively on the
Liberal bio-politics of security, contemporary war and political violence, the
politics of catastrophe, along with mediation's on post-liberal political
thought. Brad is the author of numerous books and edited volumes, most
recently including: Liberal Terror (Polity Press: 2013) and Resilient Life:
The Art of Living Dangerously (forthcoming with Julian Reid, Polity Press:
2014). He is the Founder and Director of the Histories of Violence project
(www.historiesofviolence.com) and a member of the Society for the Study
of Bio-political Futures.
Julian Reid is Professor of International Relations at the University of
Lapland, Finland. He taught previously at King's College London, Sussex
University, and SOAS (School of Oriental and African Studies), University
of London. He is the author of numerous studies of the liberal biopolitics of
war including The Liberal Way of War: Killing to Make Life Live (co-
authored with Michael Dillon) (New York and London: Routledge, 2009)
and The Biopolitics of the War on Terror: Life Struggles, Liberal Modernity,
and the Defence of Logistical Societies (Manchester and New York:
Manchester University Press, 2009, 2007 and 2006).
Leonie Ansems de Vries is Assistant Professor of International Relations
at the University of Nottingham Malaysia Campus. She holds a PhD from
the Department of War Studies at King's College London. Her doctoral
thesis draws upon insights from modern political theory, continental
philosophy (especially Deleuze and Foucault) to produce a novel account of
political life. At the heart of this research lies a concern with the notion of
political life understood as a question of ordering and disordering: the
management and disruption of conflicting claims regarding what life may
be and become politically. Her current research continues the exploration of
the relationship between politics and life from a multidisciplinary
perspective. A second research strand interrogates the relationship between
governance and resistance. Before joining the Malaysia Campus in 2011,
Leonie taught at the Department of Politics and International Relations,
QueenMary University of London.
Ruth Kitchen is a researcher at the University of Leeds. Her work
examines the relationships between twentieth- and twenty-first-century
French literature and visual culture, critical and cultural theory, and
historiography. She has published several articles on guilt in French
literature and film concerning the Nazi Occupation of France. Her
monograph, A Legacy of Shame — French Narratives of War and
Occupation, adapted from her thesis, will be published with Peter Lang in
2013.
Erin Manning holds a University Research Chair in Relational Art and
Philosophy in the Faculty of Fine Arts at Concordia University (Montreal,
Canada). She is also the director of the Sense Lab (www.senselab.ca), a
laboratory that explores the intersections between art practice and
philosophy through the matrix of the sensing body in movement. In her art
practice she works between painting, dance, fabric and sculpture
(www.erinmovement.com). Current iterations of her artwork explore
emergent collectivities through participatory textiles. Her project Stitching
Time was presented at the 2012 Sydney Biennale and The Knots of Time
will open the new Flax Museum in Kortrijk, Belgium, in 2014. Her
extensive publications address movement, art, experience and the political
through the prism of process philosophy, with recent work developing a
notion of autistic perception and the more-than human.
Todd May is a Professor of Philosophy at Clemson University. He is the
author of 10 books, including The Philosophy of Foucault, Gilles Deleuze,
The Political Thought of Jacques Ranciere, Our Practices, Our Selves, and
Death, and Friendship in An Age of Economics (2012). Todd's
contemporary philosophical writings regularly feature in The New York
Times ‘The Stone’ column.
Nicholas Michelsen was awarded his PhD by the Department of War
Studies, King's College London, where he is currently a Teaching Fellow.
He holds an MRes in War Studies and an MA in International Conflict
Studies from Kings College London, and a BA(Hons) in International
Relations and Philosophy from the University of Sussex.
Michael J. Shapiro is a Professor of Political Science at the University
of Hawai'i, Mãnoa. He has published extensively on areas of political
theory and international politics. Among his recent publications are Studies
in Trans-disciplinary Method: After the Aesthetic Turn (Routledge, 2012).
Geoffrey Whitehall is an Associate Professor of Political Science at
Acadia University, NS, Canada. He teaches courses in Contemporary
Political Theory, World Politics and Discourses of Cultures and Technology.
His research explores Sovereignty and Pre-emptive Governance and the
Aesthetics of International Politics. His publications have appeared in the
journals International Studies Perspectives, Theory and Event, Borderlands
and Millennium.
Introduction
Fascism in all its forms
Brad Evans and Julian Reid
DOI: 10.4324/9780203374702-1
References
Arendt, H. Eichmann in Jerusalem (London: Penguin, 2006)
Badiou, A. Saint Paul: The Foundation of Universalism (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2003)
Deleuze, G. Cinema 2: The Time-Image (London: Athlone Press,
1989)
Deleuze, G. Cinema 2: The Time-Image (London: Athlone Press,
2000)
Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism &
Schizophrenia (London: Athlone Press, 2000)
Dillon, M. and Reid, J. The Liberal Way of War: Killing to Make Life
Live (New York and London: Routledge, 2009)
Foucault, M. ‘Preface’ to Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, Anti-
Oedipus: Capitalism & Schizophrenia (London: Athlone Press, 2000)
Guattari, F. Chaosophy (New York: Semiotext, 1995)
Massumi, B. A User's Guide to Capitalism and Schizophrenia:
Deviations from Deleuze and Guattari (Cambridge, Mass. and
London: MIT Press, 1999)
Ravetto, K. The Unmaking of Fascist Aesthetics (Minneapolis and
London: University of Minnesota Press, 2001)
Reid, J. ‘Of Nomadic Unities: Gilles Deleuze on the Nature of
Sovereignty’ (Journal of International Relations and Development
Vol.13 No.4, 2010)
Reid, J.The Biopolitics of the War on Terror: Life Struggles, Liberal
Modernity and the Defence of Logistical Societies (Manchester and
New York: Manchester University Press, 2006).
1 Desire and ideology in fascism
Todd May
DOI: 10.4324/9780203374702-2
Reich is at his profoundest as a thinker when he refuses to accept ignorance or illusion on the part
of the masses as an explanation of fascism, and demands an explanation that will take their desire
into account, an explanation formulated in terms of desire: no, the masses were not innocent
dupes; at a certain point, under a certain set of conditions, they wanted fascism, and it is this
perversion of the desire of the masses that needs to be accounted for.
(Deleuze and Guattari 1977: 29)
It is the task of this paper to show that the above quote is exactly half right.
Fascism is a matter of desire. However, it is not only that; it is also a matter
of ignorance or illusion. In fact, it arises at the point at which desire and
ignorance and/or knowledge arise. In order to show this, we will contrast
Deleuze and Guattari's thought with that of a contemporary journalist who,
to my knowledge, has not been brought into productive discussion with
contemporary French thought. In What's the Matter with Kansas? Thomas
Frank argues that it is precisely a matter of ignorance or illusion (and for
Frank, specifically, ideology) that is operative in the dominance of
conservative thought in America's heartland. It is because the masses have
been duped into believing an ideology contrary to their interests that
Republicans have come to dominate that part of the country. As with
Deleuze and Guattari, this paper will argue that Franks is exactly half right.
In order to place these two halves into a proper whole, we will need to
appeal to a picture of desire and illusion that roots them in human practice.
It is through a conception of practice that we can recognize that, in a sense,
people can, under certain conditions, want fascism. This is true even though
people rarely tell themselves that it is fascism that they want. Again, it is
through a conception of practice that we can understand how people can be
duped into endorsing fascism, even when it is against their interest. The
conception of practice to be developed here will have affinities with the
thought of Michel Foucault. Although Foucault does not offer a theoretical
articulation of this conception, it can be said to be operative particularly in
his more genealogical work.
In order to approach these ideas, I will start with a short summary of
Deleuze and Guattari's treatment of desire and then of Franks's treatment of
illusion. The goal is simply to situate the key elements of these discussions
as a backdrop for the positive conception of practice to be developed here.
Then I will return to these elements in order to show their proper place in
that conception and, one hopes, to show the half-rightedness of each of
these treatments. My claim for the alternative conception will not come in
the form of an argument. I do not try to show that either Deleuze and
Guattari or Franks is half-mistaken. Rather, I seek to put in place a
conception of human practice that is compelling enough that the way I
situate desire and illusion will also seem compelling. That is to say, in
keeping with Deleuze's dictum in Dialogues, rather than arguing at length
against the reduction of fascism either to desire or to illusion, I will mostly
‘go on to something else’ (Deleuze and Parnet 1987: 1).
For Deleuze and Guattari, fascism, like much else in human commitment,
is not a matter of ignorance or mistaken reflection. This is in keeping
particularly with Deleuze's Nietzschean orientation toward human
consciousness: that it is secondary or even epiphenomenal. For Deleuze,
much of what makes us tick is unconscious. Consciousness comes
afterwards. The vast majority of human experience and motivation happens
outside our reflective awareness. ‘Underneath the self which acts are little
selves which contemplate and which render possible both the action and the
active subject. We speak of our “self” only in virtue of these thousands of
little witnesses which contemplate within us: it is always a third party who
says “me”’ (Deleuze 1994: 75).
This idea finds expression in Anti-Oedipus' central claim that ‘the social
field is immediately invested by desire, that it is the historically determined
product of desire, and that libido has no need of any mediation or
sublimation, any psychic operation … There is only desire and the social,
and nothing else’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1977: 29). We must be careful in
understanding this citation. It could appear to be more Rousseauian than it
is. If we take Deleuze and Guattari to mean that there is only desire on the
one hand and the social on the other, it would be only a short step to
thinking that the social is an evil that represses desire. This would align
their thought with Rousseau's idea (at least in some of his moods) that
organized society represses the natural goodness of human being.
However, this would be to forget the central idea of Anti-Oedipus: that
desire is productive. If there is only desire and the social, it is because
desire produces the social. Rather than, as with psychoanalytic theory,
desire being desire for something, desire directly creates its objects. We can
recognize here Deleuze's distinction between the virtual and the actual. The
actual is a product of the virtual. The virtual is a field of difference from
which all actuality arises. The actual, in turn, emerges from the virtual,
while still retaining the virtual within it. In the same way, desire produces
the social. Now it may be that the social produced by desire in turn
represses or transforms or distorts desire, as the authors argue Oedipus
does, but this does not mean that the social is exterior to desire, or that it
comes from something or somewhere else. As Deleuze insists throughout
his career, there is no transcendence, only immanence. Deleuze and Guattari
note in What is Philosophy?of all the illusions of philosophy, ‘First of all
there is the illusion of transcendence, which, perhaps, comes before all the
others’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1994: 49). To say that there is only desire and
the social, then, is to say that there is only desire and what it creates, which
includes the social.
On this view, if there is a problem of fascism, it is a problem of desire
rather than of illusion or ideology. ‘It is not a question of ideology. There is
an unconscious libidinal investment of the social field that coexists, but
does not necessarily coincide, with preconscious investments, or with what
preconscious investments “ought to be.” That is why, when subjects,
individuals, or groups act manifestly counter to their class interests … it is
not enough to say: they were fooled, the masses have been fooled’ (Deleuze
and Guattari 1977: 104). The picture Deleuze and Guattari are trying to
overcome here is a traditional Marxist one. On this picture, the reason the
masses do not immediately seek their own interests — which would
necessarily be revolutionary ones — is that they have been ideologically
deceived. They have been convinced that their interests are aligned with,
rather than contrary to, the interests of the ruling class. If this is right, the
political task would be to educate the masses, to get them to recognize their
true interests. Otherwise put, the first task of political struggle would be to
overcome the ideological blinders that have prevented the masses from
seeing their true interests.
The problem with this picture is, in Deleuze and Guattari's view, that it
sees things the wrong way around. It is not that we come to desire fascism
rather than revolution because we mistakenly believe that fascism is good
for us. Rather, it is because we become invested in fascism that we come to
believe in it. Desire as a form of unconscious creation and investment
comes first. In fact, from this perspective it does not even matter whether
we believe in fascism. We can be entirely cynical and believe in nothing at
all. Politics is not a matter of belief; it is a matter of what we desire. To ask
why it is that the masses form beliefs that are against their own interests is
to ask the wrong question; it is to ask a question at the wrong level. ‘We see
the most disadvantaged, the most excluded members of society invest with
passion the system that oppresses them, and where they always find an
interest in it, since it is here that they search for and measure it. Interest
always comes after’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1977: 346).
Even to ask why we desire fascism is to mistake the political project. The
goal instead, which is the project of schizoanalysis, is to recognize the
character of libidinal investments and then to see what can be done to make
those investments more revolutionary. ‘The first positive task consists in
discovering in a subject the nature, the formation, or functioning of his
desiring-machines, independent of any interpretations’ (Deleuze and
Guattari 1977: 322). The second task is ‘to reach the investments of
unconscious desire of the social field, insofar as they are differentiated from
the preconscious investments of interest, and insofar as they are not merely
capable of counteracting them, but also of coexisting with them’ (Deleuze
and Guattari 1977: 350). Rather than interpreting reality for the masses so
they that can come to see what is oppressing them, to recognize the fascism
which they have been duped into embracing, schizoanalysis aims to
discover the particular investments one makes into the social field and then
to counter them with other, more revolutionary, investments.
This, I would argue, is why Anti-Oedipus is written in the way that it is.
There has, of course, been much commentary on the style of the book: its
energy, its use of curse words, its slash-and-burn treatment of Lacan and
others. However, if we treat the style as something exterior to its message,
we miss the point of that style. If the political goal were one of convincing
people to believe otherwise than they do, then there might be something
juvenile about the writing, but that is not the political goal. Rather, it is to
get people's desire going in another direction. Anti-Oedipus seeks to realign
our desire more than our belief. It seeks to follow its own message that we
ask not what something means but how it works. That is why, when
Foucault claims in the preface to Anti-Oedipus that it is ‘a book of ethics’
(Deleuze and Guattari 1977: xiii), he is right on target. It is a book that
seeks to get us to live differently, not by convincing us of better ways to
live, but by offering desire (as well as philosophy and critical social
thought) another way to invest in the social field, which is to say another
way to create.
If, for Deleuze and Guattari, ‘the concept of ideology is an execrable
concept that hides the real problems’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1977: 344), for
Thomas Frank ideology or illusion is precisely the heart of the matter. In
What's the Matter with Kansas? How Conservatives Won the Heart of
America, Frank seeks to understand the Republican strategy from the Regan
years of the 1980s to the Bush years of the early 2000s (the book was
published in 2004, prior to the second term of the Bush administration), to
win the support particularly of middle America and, for Frank's purposes, of
Kansans. What puzzles him, which is not dissimilar to what puzzles
Deleuze and Guattari, is how people can be brought to support policies that
are directly opposed to their interests. Where Deleuze and Guattari undercut
the primacy of the concept interests, however, Franks seeks instead to
remain precisely on that terrain. His strategy is to show that by focusing on
certain cultural issues, the Republicans have been able to garner support for
their economic programs, which is really what motivates them:
The movement's basic premise is that culture outweighs economics as a matter of public concern
… Over the last three decades they have smashed the welfare state, reduced the tax burden on
corporations and the wealthy, and generally facilitated the country's return to a nineteenth-century
pattern of wealth distribution … The leaders of the backlash may talk Christ, but they walk
corporate.
(Frank 2004: 6)
References
The new fascism is not the politics and the economy of war. It is the global agreement on security,
on the maintenance of peace — just as terrifying as war. All our petty fears will be organized in
concert, all our petty anxieties will be harnessed to make micro-fascists of us; we will be called
upon to stifle every little thing, every suspicious face, every dissonant voice, in our streets, in our
neighborhoods, in our local theaters.
(Gilles Deleuze 2006: 138)
Appeals of fascism
The historic Nazi rally simulated in White Noise conveys an aspect of the
appeal of Hitler's party at the time it was assuming power. However,
although much of the party's mass appeal was orchestrated by its visual
displays (its public semiotics), it should also be noted that the party
developed its following at a time of national economic deprivation. In a
classic explanatory-oriented investigation of the rise of the Nazi party in
Germany, Rudolph Heberle describes the economic and related status crises
experienced by various social strata in Germany in the 1920s and 1930s and
surmises:
It should not be difficult to understand why, in such circumstances, a party led by fanatic patriots,
which denounced radically all existing parties, which claimed to be independent of any particular
economic interests, the only champion of the real people and the avant-garde of the awaking
nation, would exert immense attraction for the uprooted middle class elements, for politically
untrained youths, for political adventurers, and for counter-revolutionaries in general.
(Heberle 1945: 6)
Elaborating, Heberle writes, ‘When the terrible depression with its mass
unemployment cast its shadow on the people's minds, when masses of
young voters grew up who had never had a permanent job or any job at all,
the Nazi party offered at least activity, an outlet from the doldrums, and also
shelter, food, and uniforms, attractions which made it a bitter competitor of
the Communists in certain proletarian areas of the metropolitan cities …’
(Heberle 1945: 9).
Heberle conducts a data analysis to validate his economy-focused
explanatory model. Focusing on public opinion and party voting patterns of
diverse occupational groups in the rural, Schleswig-Holstein region of
Germany from 1918 to 1932, he shows how the National Socialists were
able to displace other radical parties, not only by playing on economic
issues (all the parties were doing that) but also by promoting mass
participation. However, there are hints of the other kind of appeal to which
DeLillo gestures and to which Heberle refers as well, an aesthetic appeal
that is evident in Heberle's remarks on uniforms and mass participation. The
appeal of the National Socialist's elaborate and colorful uniforms and
regalia was part of their aesthetic strategy. That strategy's effectiveness is
registered in a statement attributed to Walter Henisch, a press photographer
who served as Josef Goebbels's official war photographer. Henisch, a man
wedded to his photographic art and not to the Nazi ideology, is described by
his son Peter (in his novelistic biography of his father) as explaining the
attraction of the National Socialist party when they marched into Austria:
‘Compared to the Socialists and even more to the conservatives, the Nazi's
were remarkable. They did something for your senses, especially for your
eyes, and therefore for the camera’ (Henisch 1990: 50). What Walter
Henisch experiences is one small marker of a more pervasive aspect of the
appeal of fascist aesthetics, which shows up in popular culture texts,
especially films such as The Night Porter, The Damned, and Scorpio Rising
in the form of ‘the eroticization of Nazi regalia in certain gay cultures’
(Schnapp 1996: 236). Such contemporary aesthetic effects of Nazi or more
generally fascist aesthetics points to what Kriss Ravetto has observed as the
way ‘Fascism occupied the unique (if not contradictory) space of a
historical past and a political present’ (Ravetto 2001: 5).
Of course, as is well known, photography was only one dimension of the
Nazi media strategy. Goebbels was particularly struck with the capacity of
cinema to create mass appeal and was especially taken with Sergei
Eisenstein's cinematic celebration of the Russian revolution. While
Eisenstein rebuffed Goebbels after the latter wrote for advice about
propaganda films (Eisenstein 1988: 280), the very form of his cinematic art
was also recalcitrant to Goebbels's propaganda plans. As Jacques Rancière
points out in a gloss on the film-propaganda relation in Eisenstein's films,
Eisenstein's films cannot function as propaganda because ‘a propaganda
film must give us a sense of certainty about what we see, it must choose
between the documentary that presents what we see as a palpable reality or
the fiction that forwards it as a desirable end [and]… Eisenstein
systematically denies us this sense of certainty (Rancière 2006: 29).
While Rancière sees Eisenstein's films as recalcitrant to a fascist
aesthetic, he construes Brechtian theater as positively anti-fascist:
If Brecht remained as a kind of archetype of political art in the XXTH century, it was due not so
much to his enduring communist commitment as to the way he negotiated the relation between the
opposites, blending the scholastic forms of political teaching with the enjoyments of the musical
or the cabaret, having allegories of Nazi power discuss in verse about matters of cauliflowers, etc.
The main procedure of political or critical art consists in setting out the encounter and possibly the
clash of heterogeneous elements … to provoke a break in our perception, to disclose some secret
connection of things hidden behind the everyday reality.
(Rancière 2006: 30)
Counter-aesthetics: Syberberg
Although cinema was central to the fascist aestheticization of politics, it
also lends itself to a politics of aesthetics. While the aestheticization of
politics encourages ritual allegiance, a text that enjoins a politics of
aesthetics ‘suspends the ordinary coordinates of sensory experience and
reframes the network of relationships between spaces and times, subjects
and objects, the common and the singular’ (Rancière 2004: 65). Here I turn
first to Hans Jürgen Syberberg's Hitler: A Film from Germany (1977),
which resembles the anti-fascist aesthetic in DeLillo's White Noise as well
as comporting with a Brechtian anti-fascist aesthetic (part of Syberberg's
explicit intention). The aesthetic is Brechtian in the sense described by
Benjamin (already noted) in that its shock effect creates a ‘heightened
presence of mind’ and in the sense described by Rancière in that it creates
breaks in perception through its ‘clash of heterogeneous elements.’ Hitler is
a seven-hour film the primary heterogeneity of which combines Brechtian
and Wagnerian aesthetics to effect what Syberberg refers to as an ‘aesthetic
scandal: combining Brecht's doctrine of epic theater with Richard Wagner's
musical aesthetics, cinematically conjoining the epic system as anti-
Aristotelian cinema with the laws of a new myth’ (Syberberg 1982: 18).
The ‘scandal’ is heightened as well by Syberberg's combination of
cinematic genres, a mixing of ‘documentation with subjective interpretation
and imagination with historical fact’ (Mueller 1980: 60). In Susan Sontag's
well-wrought phrases, the film is a ‘medley of imaginary discourse’ with a
‘complex sound track … interspersed between and intermittently overlaid
on the speeches of actors,’ and with ‘a varying stock of emblematic props
and images’ (Sontag 1973: 143). Moreover, by focusing on minor
characters — for example Himmler's masseur Felix Kersten, and Hitler's
valet Karl-Wilhelm Kraus — the film encourages the viewer to discover
‘horror in the banal’ (Syberberg 1982: 13).
One of the film's major analytic assumptions, which Syberberg shares
with DeLillo, is that Hitler as an historical subject is fundamentally a
cinematic character. In DeLillo's case, that assumption is enacted in his
Running Dog, a novel the main drama of which is based on a search for
rumored pornographic film of Hitler, created during the last days of the war.
At the end of the novel, the film turns out to be something else. It shows
Hitler as an aesthetic figure, imitating Charlie Chaplin for a bunch of
children:
The figure shuffles toward the camera, his cane swinging. Behind him, in a corner of the screen,
one of the small girls looks on.
Briefly the main is flooded in light — the bleached and toneless effect of overexposure. With the
return of minimal detail and contrast, he is very close to the camera, and his lifeless eyes acquire a
trace of flame, the smallest luster. A professional effect. It's as though the glint originated in a
nearby catch light.
He produces an expression finally — a sweet epicene, guilty little smile, Charlie's smile, an
accurate reproduction …
Three quarter view. At first he seems to be speaking to the smallest of the children, a girl about
three years old. It is then evident he is only moving his lips — an allusion to silent movies. One of
the women can be seen smiling.
(DeLillo 1978: 236–37)
Second, while a primary narrative thread of the film is a story about the
dangers of drug use, the Fred/Arctor body is recalcitrant to the narrative.
Vincent Amiel's observations on the subversive cinematic body serves well
here. Amiel analyzes those films (e.g., those of Robert Bresson, Buster
Keaton and John Casavetes) in which what he calls ‘the cinematographic
body is no longer an object of film knowledge; rather it is a model of
knowledge via editing … [It is] simultaneously that which is filmed and
that which (re)organizes the film in the mind/body of the spectator …
[becoming the] source rather than the object of cinema’ (Game 2001: 50–
51).
While in what Amiel calls ‘classic cinema’ the moving bodies were
simply vehicles for a story, in his terms the tendency was to ‘abandon the
body's density for the exclusive profit of its functionality,’ so that it was
merely ‘at the service of narrative articulations,’ in much of contemporary
cinema ‘the idea is for the cinema to dis-organ-ize the body … by means of
revealing its fragmented nature, by extracting from it the yoke of unity and
consciousness, by giving it back the complexity of its own determinations’
(Amiel 1998: 7).
Certainly the protagonist in Scanner should be understood aesthetically,
even though he develops a psychosis. ‘Bruce’ (Arctor) discovers the blue
flowers that are the source of the drug Substance D. Inasmuch as the blue
flower is a symbol of German romanticism, the psychosis-inducing flower
is also an aesthetic icon. As such, it assists in recruiting the film into a
politics of aesthetics frame rather than moving it toward the simple policy
problem of how to treat a drug-induced psychosis. Moreover, chez
Benjamin, the blue flower motif suggests that the film evokes the
pervasiveness of illusion (what Benjamin referred to as phantasmagoria)
rather than psychic delusion (where illusion as phantasmagoria is Dick's
emphasis in the novel). The cinema version of Scanner is ideally suited to
such an aesthetic frame, especially because of the way it situates the viewer
vis-à-vis the couplet of reality versus illusion. As Benjamin suggests in his
run up to the blue flower imagery, ‘the shooting of a film … presents a
process in which it is impossible to assign to a spectator a viewpoint which
would exclude from the scene being enacted such extraneous accessories as
camera equipment, lighting, machinery crew, etc. … Its illusory nature is a
nature of the second degree, the result of editing.’ Benjamin adds, ‘The
equipment-free aspect of reality here has become the height of artifice, the
site of immediate reality has become the “blue flower” in the land of
technology’ (Benjamin 1968: 232).
In interpreting Benjamin's meaning here, Miriam Hansen insists that the
blue flower imagery helps Benjamin lend a political force to cinema-as-
form. For Benjamin, she writes, ‘… if film were to have a critical, [i.e. anti-
fascist] cognitive function, it had to disrupt that chain [the mythical chain of
mirrors] and assume the task of all politicized art and [quoting Susan Buck-
Morss] “not to duplicate the illusion as real, but to interpret reality as itself
illusion”’ (Hansen 1987: 204). The ‘metaphor of the blue flower — the
unattainable object of the romantic quest’, she adds, suggests the critical
role of cinema's ‘distortion of distortion.’ Most significantly, according to
Benjamin, the actor who is able to maintain her/his ‘humanity in the face of
the apparatus,’ frees the mass audience from myth as they ‘watch an actor
take revenge in their place …’ (Benjamin quoted in Hansen 1987: 205).
To elaborate the critical anti-fascist aesthetic insights of Benjamin and
others that Scanner delivers, we can consider the name of Dick's main
protagonist, Arctor, likely a reference to the subject-as-actor, and follow his
relationship to illusion. Arctor is under cover, acting an identity, performing
in effect for the scanners. Moreover, his persona is deployed on both sides
of the surveillance process; he is both a subject and object of surveillance
and is therefore performing for himself as well. The split in his focus of
observation is doubled by the way Substance D has created a split between
the hemispheres of his brain. These dual divisions encourage a model of
historically fraught subjectivity that is decidedly anti-fascist in more or less
the sense in which the Brechtian subject emerges from his theatrical
practice. In Brechtian theater, what is in front of the audience, as it is acted
out, is conveyed as something that might well be otherwise. The effect is a
dualism that points to the possibilities of multiplicity, a sense of not simply
what is being done ‘but what might just as well have not been done, what
might have been something else altogether, or simply have been omitted’
(Jameson 1998: 58). As a result, what is presented is a challenge to the
fascist desire to reign in contingency in order to establish historical
necessity.
As Kriss Ravetto (2001: 227) points out, ‘… hundreds of films have been
produced on the subject of fascism …’ However, I want to emphasize that
what makes a film anti-fascist is not necessarily a matter of the way it
explicitly addresses the historically bounded phenomena that produced a
Hitler and Mussolini. Jacques Rancière makes the point well in his
reference to the politics of the novel. For example, he suggests that Virginia
Woolf's novels are more connected with democratic history than Emile
Zola's, not because she wrote ‘good social novels but because her way of
working on the contraction or distention of temporalities, on their
contemporaneousness or their distance, or her way of situating events at a
more minute level, all of this establishes a grid that makes it possible to
think through the frames of political dissensuality more effectively than the
social epic's various forms’ (Rancière 2004: 65). Accordingly, one might
surmise that Dick's Man in the High Castle (1992), which explicitly
addressed an America that is organized around the victory of fascism
(Germany and Japan have won World War II as the novel begins), is his
most anti-fascist story. However, I want to suggest, in accord with
Rancière's point, that like his Scanner, Dick's Minority Report, especially in
its cinematic realization, delivers a more effective anti-fascist aesthetic.
The film version of Minority Report articulates well the Deleuzian
conception of micro fascism and goes beyond Scanner's anti-fascism
because it displays a coercive society-wide securitization rather than the
more focused assault on one of society's sub-cultures. That securitization is
effectively an imposition of a ‘peace’ that stifles all forms of dissonance.
Although the society represented is not explicitly fascist, as it is in Dick's
Man in the High Castle, it is nevertheless a society of totalizing control, run
by a precrime unit that arrests and incarcerates anyone who is interpreted as
planning a violent crime. The suborned interpreters are precogs, psychic
women who are connected to informational prostheses to form a person-
technology assemblage. With its form as well as its content, Steven
Spielberg's film version of the story provides the most notable
representation of a contemporary politics of surveillance, well captured in
Gilles Deleuze's conception of ‘societies of control.’ Whereas Foucault
conceived the disciplinary society, based on enclosures — the school, the
factory, the prison and so on — as historically supplanting the old societies
of sovereignty, Deleuze argues that the society of control has displaced the
disciplinary society. It is not a society of walls and containments but a
system of domination that works through modulations and coding
procedures: ‘In the control societies what are important are no longer
numbers and names but codes, a password instead of a watchword’
(Deleuze 1992: 5). They are codes that control movements from one
function and setting to another and the coding mechanisms are located in
dominant centers, centers of capitalism (global incorporations) but also
articulated in the control measures of the state.
Although capitalism is disproportionately connected to ‘societies of
control,’ there is also a micro fascism that is state-oriented. With respect to
this aspect, Deleuze and Guattari write, ‘The administration of a great
organized molar security has as its correlate a whole micro-management of
petty fears [amounting to] … a macropolitics of society by and for a
micropolitics of insecurity …’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 215–16).
Within this model of securitization, the social order has two opposing
modalities: machines of capture in which bodies and spaces are coded, and
lines of flight, which are the mechanisms and routes through which people
elude the machines of capture. In effect, the lines of flight constitute
micropolitical reactions to the mechanisms of capture to resist the society's
‘normalizing individualization’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 208–31).
Minority Report's enactment of a dynamic opposition between the
machines of capture and the micropolitics of escape takes place in
Washington, DC, in 2054, where the ‘precrime unit,’ which has aspirations
to become a national program, operates the policing mechanisms through
which persons identified as future criminals are arrested and incarcerated.
While the eventual escape and return to normal life of one of the precogs,
who has been held in a drugged state of suspended animation, is part of the
film's drama, the most significant body (the primary aesthetic subject) in the
film is that of John Anderton (played by Tom Cruise), who when the film
opens is the head arresting officer of the precrime unit. Anderton's moving
body, first as part of the mechanisms of capture and subsequently as a
fugitive from the unit he formerly led, drives the film's primary narrative.
At first he operates as a wholly suborned body, with his movements, for
example, gesturally drawing out the information on a future crime from his
unit's media technology screen but then, after he is set up and programmed
by the unit as a future criminal, as one moving to stymie the machine of
capture.
Ultimately, Anderton's exoneration involves a recovery of the precrime
unit's suppressed archive of minority reports (submitted by precogs who see
the future crime differently). As Philip Dick's version of the story puts it,
‘The existence of a majority logically implies a corresponding minority’
(Dick 2002: 45). In the film version, the minority reports have been
suppressed (because the head of the program, eager to have it implemented
nationally, has suppressed them in order to represent future criminal acts as
certainties rather than probabilities), and Anderton learns that his only hope
is to find the one in his case, if it exists. Ultimately, although the narrative
has a positive ending (John Anderton is exonerated, the head of the program
is discredited, and the precrime program is eliminated), the film's most
significant aspects are non-narrative, anti-fascist and micropolitical.
In the opening scenes, Anderton's body functions as a physical extension
of the precrime surveillance and arrest functions, filmed with Anderton's
body moving in a musically accompanied ballet that is in harmony with the
machinery of prediction; his movements at this stage are wholly modulated
and choreographed by the system. Specifically, his swinging arms are
shown pulling up the relevant images on a large screen, and subsequently
his moving body is shown closing in on the alleged perpetrator. Later, the
images of his body and its movements are subversive. As his body
challenges the totalizing precrime choreography, he evinces a counter-
movement to those of the system's machine of capture, and to do so he has
to modify his body to subvert the surveillance system — for example, by
having his eyes replaced to subvert the coding system, which reads eyeball
patterns.
As a result, Anderton is an exemplary Deleuzian fugitive: ‘Everybody
runs,’ he says when the police first try to apprehend him, and thereafter his
running requires him to move in ways that allow him to escape from the
coding apparatuses and exemplify Deleuze's suggestion that there are
always forms of flow that elude the capturing, binary organizations.
Notably, apart from Anderton's movements, which articulate Deleuzian
lines of flight by exploiting the gaps in the apparatuses of capture, the
subversiveness of his body is also a function of a film form that opposes the
body to the narrative. As is the case with the aesthetic subject in Scanner,
Bob Arctor, John Anderton's body performs as the kind of cinematic body
analyzed by Vincent Amiel, a cinematic body that is ‘dis-organ-ized’ and
thus resistant to the functionality of the film narrative (Amiel 1998: 7). As a
result, the film uses Anderton's body to realize the Deleuzian political
inspiration to resist the apparatuses of capture and thus works not simply
through its narrative drama but also through its imagery, as an exemplary
anti-fascist aesthetic.
References
Reich's warning
Gilles Deleuze's account of fascism owes considerable intellectual debt to
the work of Wilhelm Reich. Noting in particular how Reich discredited
orthodox wisdom, Deleuze wanted to question how conditions of servitude,
humiliation and slavery could actually be embraced given the right
conditions:
Reich is at his profoundest as a thinker when he refuses to accept ignorance or illusion on part of
the masses as a explanation of fascism, and demands an explanation that will take their desires
into account, an explanation formulated in terms of desire: no the masses were not innocent
dupes; at a certain point, under certain conditions, they wanted fascism, and it is this perversion of
desire of the masses that needs to be accounted for.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2003: 31)
This chapter will foreground these ‘wider political functions’. In doing so, it
will argue that any understanding of contemporary fascism needs to move
beyond the lure of ideological reification and towards understanding it
through the conditioning prism of what Foucault terms the dispositif of
security if it is to be combated in the twenty-first century.
Bio-political mediations
Deleuze's conception of fascism extends well beyond and yet appears prior
to the tyrannies of a totalitarian state. Bypassing sovereign temporalities, it
focuses instead upon those power formations that can appear in many
different localised forms whatever the political emblem. These include
‘rural fascism and city and neighbourhood fascism, youth fascism and war
veteran's fascism, fascism of the Left, and fascism of the Right, fascism of
the couple, family, school and office’ (Deleuze and Guattari 2002: 214).
This brings us to the fundamental distinction Deleuze draws between
fascism and the Total State: ‘Doubtless, fascism invented the concept of the
totalitarian state, but there is no reason to define fascism by a concept of its
own devising’ (Deleuze and Guattari 2002: 214). Whilst totalitarian
regimes are capable of oppressing populations, they result from the actions
of a relatively small number of individuals. Fascism, in contrast, works by
manipulating what appeals to the general population. It mobilises the
masses by drawing attention to political problems of the everyday: ‘what
makes fascism dangerous is its molecular or micro- political power, for it is
a mass movement: a cancerous body rather than a totalitarian organism …
Only micro-fascism provides an answer to the global question: Why does
desire desire its own oppression, how can it desire its own oppression?’
(Deleuze and Guattari 2002: 215). This localised focus is sig- nificant.
Since it is understood ‘the masses certainly do not passively submit to
power; nor do they “want” to be repressed, in a kind of masochistic
hysteria; nor are they tricked by ideological lure’, it is the masses’ active
investment in their own political decay that allows us to challenge all
attempts to give fascism ideological determinism.
Deleuze does not, however, seek to diminish the importance of macro-
specific fields of formation. His vocal admiration for Primo Levi
emphasises this point. Levi's personal testimonies not only explain in the
most intimate details the divisive nature of fascistic rule (even amongst the
Lager's captors); it was his sophisticated account of the economy behind
these relations which obliterated the absurd notion that the phenomena
should be consigned to the pages of history: ‘Nor is it in the extreme
conditions described by Primo Levi that we experience the shame of being
human. We experience it in insignificant conditions, before the meanness
and vulgarity of existence that haunts democracies, before the propagation
of these modes of existence and of thought-for-the-market, and before the
values, ideals, and opinions of our times’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1994: 107).
The argument here is straightforward. Localised or even psychic forms of
oppression only make sense once wider fields of political and social
formation are taken into account. Or to be more specific, since every regime
(dictatorial, monarchical, liberal) has become isomorphous to the politically
suffocating dictates of the world market; there is no reason to presuppose
that any political project is immune to the active production of determinable
inequalities.
So how does desire connect to the wider social field? Deleuze argues that
all desire is assembled. Desire does not exist in some isolated personal
vacuum. It is an integral part of the collective human condition. Desire
connects us to the social world, while the social world intercepts individuals
with its many complimentary and competing flows. Hence, for Deleuze,
‘there is no such thing as social production on the one hand, and a desiring
production that is mere fantasy on the other’ (Deleuze and Guattari 2003:
29). Social production is ‘purely and simply desiring production itself under
determinate conditions’. It is nonsense, therefore, to suggest that individuals
and society can be empirically separated. They are ‘strictly simultaneous
and consubstantial’ (Massumi 2002: 68). Importantly, however, since it is
the assemblage which ‘gives desire a fascistic determination’ (Deleuze and
Guattari 2002: 215), the problem, as Eugene Holland puts it, is to question
‘what exactly are the assemblages that produce the “thousand little
monomanias [and] self-evident truths … giving any and everybody the
mission of self-appointed judge, dispenser of justice, policeman,
neighbourhood SS man”’ (Holland 2008: 77–78, quoting Deleuze and
Guattari). This is supported by Ian Buchanan (2000), who notes that to
understand the relationship between the human and its world, one must take
into account both the individual desire to exploit determinate conditions,
along with the nature of those assemblages that articulate those desires to
the point of their effective normalisation. For it is only through this wider
strategic focus which connect localised forms of micro-physical desire with
macro-politicised forms of social organisation that the power over life can
be properly understood.
Deleuze famously re-orientated our understanding of social systems by
arguing that ‘lines of flight’ are primary. One implication of this is to
suggest that no social assemblage is ever completely totalising. Life is
always potentially greater than the sum of its assembled parts. This brings
us to an important distinction Foucault draws between the ‘milieu’ and the
‘dispositif’. For Foucault, the ‘milieu of life’ in its original scene is ‘the
space in which a series of uncertain events unfold’ (Foucault 2007:22). It is
a ‘problem of circulation’ that composes of unmediated natural flows (i.e.
weather systems), along with artificially constructed agglomerations (i.e.
populations). This space of flows in many senses correlates to what Deleuze
termed the ‘non-stratified’:
the interior presupposes a beginning and an end, an origin and a destination that can coincide and
incorporate everything. But when there are only environments and whatever lies between them,
when words and things are opened up without ever coinciding, there is a liberation of forces
which come from the outside and exist only in a mixed-up state of agitation, modification and
mutilation.
(Deleuze 1999: 72–73)
If the milieu refers to the open field of possibility, for Foucault, the
dispositif ‘works on the basis of this reality, by trying to use it as a support
and make it function in relation to each other’ (Foucault 2007: 47). It is all
about creating a ‘specific arrangement’ so that life can be made to live: ‘no
longer that of fixing and demarcating the territory, but of allowing
circulations to take place, of controlling them, sifting the good and the bad
… in such a way that the inherent dangers of this circulation are cancelled
out’ (Foucault 2007: 65). Tasked then with ‘modifying something in the
biological destiny of the species’ (Foucault 2007: 10), the dispositif
operates by, first, promoting what is ‘generally desirable’ to the population,
and second, seeking to eliminate what is uncertain in any given situation.
As Foucault explains:
By the term apparatus [dispositif] I mean a kind of formation, so to speak, that a given historical
moment has as its major function the response to urgency. The apparatus therefore has a dominant
strategic function … I said that the nature of an apparatus is essentially strategic, which means
that we are speaking about a certain manipulation of relations of forces, of a rational and concrete
intervention in the relation of forces, either so as to develop them in a particular direction, or to
block them, to stabilize them, and to utilize them. The apparatus is thus always inscribed into a
play of power … The apparatus is precisely this: a set of strategies of the relations of forces
supporting, and supported by, certain types of knowledge.
(Foucault 1980: 194–96)
Whilst Hayek equipped the free market with a sure moral purchase, it is
nevertheless possible to detect beneath the surface a shameful deceit.
Sovereignty for its part has always betrayed unification. As Schmitt (1996)
famously proclaimed, what makes the sovereign concept real is the ability
to declare upon the exception. It only functions by mapping out distinctions
between politically qualified and politically disqualified in a manner in
which the latter informs the former (Agamben 1995). Sovereignty's
technical mantra is therefore ‘inclusive-exclusion’. It relies upon marks of
absolute separation in order to define the realm's moral and political
registers. Indeed, it is only by pointing to the epiphenomenal that one's
place in the world begins to make any phenomenological sense. Without
‘them’ who are ‘we’? Without ‘externalities’ why the ‘internal’? Without
‘endangerment’ what need for the ‘sovereign’? Such markers have
undoubtedly dominated what it means to think politically. Moving through
the allegiant frames of Queen and Country, Fatherland, Motherland,
Homeland, Nation, and even onto the final great binary of ‘outright’
destruction made possible by the geo-strategic divisions of the Cold War,
sovereign unity has been inextricably bound to a regimes of power and
violence that are ‘marked out’ by clear lines of demarcation between
self/other, inside/outside, friend/enemy, citizen/soldier, and so forth. Its
unity at best bequeaths uneasy alliance, while at worst Total War.
Progressive unification in contrast is made real on account of its modes
of ‘incorporation’. While these modalities emanate from humanistic
sensibilities, they are nevertheless initially conceived in ‘quantitative’
terms. This enables relative comparisons. Indeed, what is progressive as a
matter of principle only finds meaningful expression once wagered against
the ‘regressive’. Since progressive notions of unity are therefore premised
upon ‘statistical’ qualities that sub-divide elements into various deviations
from the ‘standard’, progressive imaginaries consists of ‘unifying’ and
‘divisive’ tendencies which make judgements premised upon temporally
conceived stages of advancement or backwardness. That is not to suggest a
uniform teleology. Modern times are multiple times. Each can live on its
own sliding scale. While a progressive imaginary thus emanates from a
more/less incomplete account of life, the ‘identification’ of those of
‘inferior quality’ who are subject to remedy and demanding engagement
births the problem of race by means of the need for a sophisticated
taxonomical assay. This is the betrayal. Since these taxonomies have never
been simply tied to epidermal schematics and distinctions alone, race has
always been tied to the wider problem of societal progression/regression
that provides judgement on particular ‘ways of life’. The outcome of course
has been to invoke humanistic narratives in order to accentuate the most
acute and violent divisions amongst the human species.
Zygmunt Bauman's mastery of the Holocaust provides an important
complimentary here. As Bauman notes:
The unspoken terror permeating our collective memory of the Holocaust (and more than
contingently related to the overwhelming desire not to look the memory in its face) is the gnawing
suspicion that the Holocaust could be more than an aberration, more than a deviation from an
otherwise straight path of progress, more than a cancerous growth on the otherwise healthy body
of the civilised society; that, in short, the Holocaust was not an antithesis of modern civilisation
and everything (or so we like to think) it stands for.
(Bauman 1991: 7)
Fascistic exposure
Dangers require exposure to the fact. Manipulated desire also requires
exposure to the fact in order to force the body to act upon the present in
order to thwart certain possible outcomes. Invariably, the manner in which
desires are to be mobilised in the face of certain dangers largely depends
upon the political strategies recruiting insomuch as the nature of threat is
always rationality- specific. Every threat occasions a rational underpinning
which foregrounds its primary specificity in the collective political
imaginary. Liberal regimes for their part operate in a particularly novel way.
Unlike totalitarian systems which rely upon secrecy, liberalism brings
everything into the open. It continually exposes us to that which threatens
the fabric of the everyday. Even our own violent excesses are subject to the
same treatment. Since the sources of our anxieties do not therefore rest
upon the fear of the unknown, i.e. the advent of disappearance, fears are
generated through a communicative assault which overloads the senses by
heightening the stakes of all appearances. Indeed, since visual
representations of threat so integral to future imaginaries have become
globally networked — hence effectively rendering localised drama greater
affective power than ordinarily afforded — the visualization of all
dangerous encounters becomes the power of the image combined in its
affects. Everything in this visually internalised world is connectable — our
fears included.
We are reminded by Paul Virilio's (2007) two regimes of fear. Mapping
out the distinctions between totalitarian and liberal regimes, Virilio reveals
some disturbing connections. While the former invokes paranoia by
working in the shadows, the latter strikes at the same senses through
overexposure. The former, in other words, stifles reality through repression
and censorship, while the latter overloads the imaginary in a frenzied
assault so that we are anxiously synchronised yet blinded to the attempted
mastery of social space. The relationship to violence is particularly telling.
While the embodiment of totalitarian regimes is pre-figured in the
‘disappeared’ — those missing lives who offer no empirical verification of
the encounter — liberal violence is virtuously declared. It takes place as an
‘open event’. It actively shapes the world anew by ‘making the world safer’.
Importantly, for Virilio, these affective relations are never simply
articulated in a linear, top-down fashion. Like a networked system they
endlessly feed back: ‘the synchronisation of sensations that are likely to
affect our decisions’ (Virilio 2010: 6). While the problem of terror has
therefore become connectable with all manner of everyday threats,
liberalism produces a different regime of fear that replaces the neat tensions
of sovereign (dis)order with the paradox of a bio-political potentiality in
which life itself always registers to be greater than the sum of its epistemic
parts. This will have a profound impact upon both the spatial and the
subject account of living systems.
Once notions of space are fully enclosed, nothing is epiphenomenal to
the order of things. What terrifies actually emerges from within the afflicted
com- munity. It is integral to the modalities which sustain life. It is therefore
no coincidence to find that contemporary accounts of terror demand
environmental frames of reference (Sloterdijk 2009). Within a global
imaginary of threat, we fear what we actually produce. That is to say, since
what endangers arises from within our living systems, what threatens is
integral to that existence (Virilio 2010). Not only does this imply that terror
is necessarily indiscriminate. It is also indiscriminable and indistinguishable
from the general environment (Massumi 2009). It precludes any prior
elimination of the fact on the basis that its sheer possibility inaugurates its
simulated occurrence. No longer then a conventionally singular problem,
contemporary terrors register in the multiple. Anything can become the
material source of our physical undoing. With sequential notions of
catastrophe as such firmly displaced by an unending continuum of endemic
crises, selective auto-immunity is replaced by the demands for an auto-
responsive logic that strategically connects all things liveable. Since this
invariably lends itself to pre-emptive forms of governance in which all
manner of threats blur into one strategic framework for counter-affection,
the political is effectively overwritten as the normalisation of threat
foregrounds an account of life already assumed to be settled.
Faced with these conditions, geo-strategic tensions appear to be mere
aberrations. Arcane remnants of an outdated past! Not only does this mean
that our sense of political community transcends traditional state-centric
demarcations, but enmity itself is radically transformed. As Michael Dillon
and Julian Reid note, ‘Here, there is no Schmittean existential enemy
defined, in advance or by what Schmitt calls the miracle of decision, by its
radical otherness … instead, only a continuously open and changing field of
formation and intervention: the very continuous and contingent emergency
of emergence of life as being-in-formation; becoming-dangerous’ (Dillon
and Reid 2009: 44). This again is altogether Kantian. While Kant proposed
a life of infinite potentiality, life in the process appeared infinitely
problematic. The Kantian subject there- fore not only finds its proper
expression in our complex, adaptive and emergent times, but the
paradoxical nature of its potentiality has redefined the security terrain so
that indisrimination becomes the default setting. This is perhaps what
Deleuze had in mind when he previously argued that a ‘global agreement on
security’ was ‘just as terrifying as war’, for when our very life processes
become the source of our bio-political concerns, what Kenneth Galbreith
once termed the ‘contented society’ is displaced by an Anxious Mass’ who
fear the infinitely dangerous: All our petty fears will be organized in
concert, all our petty anxieties will be harnessed to make micro-fascists of
us; we will be called upon to stifle every little thing, every suspicious face,
every dissonant voice.’
Whilst it is common to suggest that this dismantling of traditional
sovereign allegiance has resulted in a crisis of subjectivity — to say that the
subject is in crisis misses the point. Liberal subjectivity is made real on
account of its ability to live through the ongoing emergency of its own
emergence. Eschewing fixed modes of being, it is forever in the making.
The liberal subject is therefore the subject of crises (Evans 2012). It lives
and breathes through the continual disruption to its own static modes of
recovery. None of this is incidental. It is central to paranoiac underpinnings
of contemporary forms of fascism. While security has become the main
criteria of political legitimacy (Agamben 2001), still we hold onto the belief
that subjects of crises are desirable. Freed from the boundary-drawing
constraints of the past, it is the risk- embracing subject who is enriched
beyond their forbear's wildest dreams. This reveals the fateful paradox of
our times. Encoded with an altogether more powerful bodily trope,
contemporary liberal subjectivity is assumed to be exponentially more
powerful and dangerous because of it. It, too, registers the same dynamic,
decentralised and recombinant presumptions which give risk societies their
very meaning. If its allegiance, then, can no longer be taken for granted,
neither can its actions be anticipated with absolute precision. It, too,
operates beyond the epistemic pale. While planetary life is therefore seen to
be the proper embodiment of liberated political existence, life's emergent
globality renders it globally dangerous unto itself because of this
potentiality. We must in short learn to embrace and yet fear what we have
become.
Life as bio-technology
Late liberalism shares certain features with Deleuzian ontology. Like
Deleuze, it eschews fixed notions of being. Undermining traditional forms
of sovereign allegiance, it seeks to create political communities anew. Like
Deleuze, it also warns against the potential for political endangerment to
reside in the most localised of levels. The post-Industrial individual's
capacity to inflict a micro-apocalyptic attack is the case point. However,
this is where the similarities end. Not only does Deleuze's preference for the
micro-political stand in marked contrast to the universal orientations of
liberal advocates, but Deleuze's allegiance to the affirmation of difference
puts him in direct conflict with the liberal tendency to see the political as a
problem to be solved. Hence, whilst Deleuze puts forward a concept of the
political that is predicated upon one's affirmative becoming — thereby side-
stepping dialectical notions of enmity (Evans 2010a) — liberalism seeks to
‘control-becoming’ in order to manufacture consent by over-coding the
flows of life. If Deleuze, therefore, can be said to have a distinct ‘politics of
the event’ that is open to a future-anterior, the liberal problematic of
security takes this anteriority to be its point of departure so that all possible
events (which if true to the creative philosophical understanding of the term
‘event’ necessarily has an inherent political element of becoming-different
at its point of emergence) can be inserted into the strategic calculus of the
security dispositif.
Here we arrive at the problem of ‘life as technology’. This problematic
has a considerable genealogy in the continental tradition. Beginning with
Nietzsche, it would subsequently resonate throughout the critical works of
Max Weber, Martin Heidegger and Hannah Arendt, to name a few. While
Heidegger in particular is widely regarded to be the most influential theorist
of technology, it was in fact Carl Schmitt who offered a purposeful critique
that was fully aware of the political, cultural and philosophical stakes
(McCormick 1997). Schmitt's contribution is significant for a number of
reasons. In particular, for our concerns, it was Schmitt who: first,
understood how technologically driven forms of oppression are latent
within liberal regimes of power; second, related liberal oppression to the
problem of the securitisation of life so that the political gets infiltrated by
technologised vision of being; third, understood that technology referred to
an entire ontological framework through which notions of political
authentication take place; fourth, appreciated how technological processes
of authentication are of an entirely different nomos to that of law, so that
juridical safeguards tell us nothing and offer no protections from those
technologies that fixate on the qualitative and the particular; fifth, paved the
way for an understanding of technology that moves beyond mere scientism,
so that the bio-affective dimensions to political manipulations are
appreciated; and sixth, set out a framework so that juridical ‘states of
exception’ appear markedly different from economising ‘states of
emergency’ that denote a more normal (though no less oppressive) state of
political affairs.
Despite Schmitt's revival in the post-9/11 moment, very few have sought
to resurrect these particular concerns. Instead, his turn in fortunes in part
emanates from liberal engagements that have sought to deploy Schmitt
against himself in order to provide liberals with a way of distancing
themselves from the perceived geo-strategic excesses of the global war on
terror. With exceptionality therefore forming the basis on which a truly
internationalist order of things is said to depend, Schmitt has been
summoned to reveal the truth of a world in which power operates beyond
the law. Leaving aside the fact that these accounts categorically fail to see
liberalism as a contemporary regime of power, not only do they maintain
the ‘friend/enemy’ decision in order to draw out their own ‘concept of the
political’ (hence openly adopting Schmitt's methodology as they attempt to
criticise him), but by pursuing some pure theory of the exception that does
not grasp the ongoing exceptionality of every single law-making process
(i.e. every law is made in response to some perceived exceptional moment
of crises to prevailing order), there is a complete failure to deal with his
wider corpus of which exceptional politics is merely a temporal ordering
principle. Hence, while these attempts invariably fall into the precise
dialectical trap that Schmitt set (so that enmity is subsequently tied to a
vision of (in)humanity complete), no attempt whatsoever is made to deal
with the links between Kantian positivism and technological determinism
which he believed to be the basis of liberal oppression.
Despite our concerns with Schmitt, there is an evident danger here. Like
Heidegger, we cannot get away from the fact that his personal intellectual
journey proved to be politically disastrous. His personal affinities with
Nazism, in particular, make it extremely difficult to engage his ideas
especially in the context of fascism without invoking certain moral outrage.
One possible way of navigating through these troubled waters is to expose
the fateful paradox of his particular thought process. While Schmitt sought
to rework the ideas of Hobbes in order to antidote liberal formalism with
the myth of National Social- ism, he actually ended up supporting a regime
that became the master of the types of technologisation against which his
work was so keen to warn. This was certainly anticipated by Walter
Benjamin. Warning against the Schmittean ‘myth of the nation’ which was
presented to be the antidote to the liberal age of technology, fascism as
Benjamin explained was nevertheless consummate to the aestheticisation of
political forms of domination to ideal mythical forms more violent than
traditional forms of rule long since overcome:
The logical result of Fascism is the introduction of aesthetics into political life. The violation of
the masses, whom Fascism, with its Fuhrer cult, forces to its knees, has its counterpart in the
violence of an apparatus which is pressed into the production of ritual values … All efforts to
render politics aesthetic culminate in one thing: war … ‘Fiat ars — pereat mundus’ says Fascism,
and … expects war to supply the artistic gratification of a sense of perception that has been
changed by technology.
(Benjamin 1968: 241)
Notes
References
Notes
References
Agamben, G. Homo sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life (Stanford,
Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1998)
Arendt, H. The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Schocken
Books, 1951)
Césaire, A. Discourse on Colonialism (New York: Monthly Review
Press, 1972)
Clausewitz, C. On war (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1982)
Comité Invisible. The Coming Insurrection (Cambridge, Mass.:
Semiotext(e), 2009)
De Landa, M. War in the Age of Intelligent Machines (New York: Zone
Books, 1991)
Deleuze, G. Cinema 2 (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1989)
Deleuze, G.‘Postscript on the Societies of Control’ (October Vol. 59,
Winter 1992: 3—7)
Deleuze, G.Negotiations, 1972–1990 (New York: Columbia University
Press, 1995)
Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. Anti-oedipus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983)
Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F.Nomadology: The War Machine (New
York, NY: Semiotext(e), 1986)
Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F.A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987)
Der Derian, J. Virtuous War: Mapping the Military-industrial-media-
entertainment Network (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 2001)
Duffield, M. Development, Security and Unending War: Governing the
World of Peoples (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007)
Foucault, M. The History of Sexuality (New York: Pantheon Books,
1978)
Galloway, A.R. Protocol: How Control Exists After Decentralization
(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2004)
Hayles, K.N. My Mother was a Computer: Digital Subjects and
Literary Texts (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005)
Heidegger, M. ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, in Basic
Writings (New York: Harper Collins, 1977)
Jomini, H. The Art of War (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press,
1972)
Mamdani, M. When Victims Become Killers: Colonialism, Nativism,
and the Genocide in Rwanda (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 2001)
Mamdani, M.Saviors and Survivors: Darfur, Politics and theWar on
Terror (New York: Doubleday, 2009)
Massumi, B. ‘Potential Politics and the Primacy of Preemption’
(Theory & Event, Vol.10, No.2, 2007)
Nandy, A. Exiled at Home: Comprising, at the Edge of Psychology, the
Intimate Enemy, Creating a Nationality (Delhi: Oxford University
Press, 1998)
Pogge, T.W. World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan
Responsibilities and Reforms (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2008)
Rancière, J. Aesthetics and its Discontents (Cambridge: Polity Press,
2009)
Rasmussen, M.V. The Risk Society at War: Terror, Technology and
Strategy in the Twenty-first Century (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2006)
Reid, J. The Biopolitics of the War on Terror: Life Struggles, Liberal
Modernity, and the Defence of Logistical Societies (Manchester:
Manchester University Press, 2006)
Schmitt, C. The Concept of the Political (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1996)
Schmitt, C.Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of
Sovereignty (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1985)
Singer, P. Wired for War (New York: Penguin Press, 2009)
Stannard, D.E. American Holocaust: Columbus and the Conquest of
the New World (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992)
Virilio, P. Pure War: Twenty Five Years Later (Los Angeles, CA:
Semiotext(e), 2008)
Whitehall, G. ‘The Aesthetic Emergency of the Avian Flu Affect’, in
FrancoisDebrix and MarkLacy (ed.) Geopolitics of American
Insecurity: Terror, Power, and Foreign Policy (New York: Routledge,
2009)
Whitehall, G.‘Preemptive Sovereignty and Avian States of
Emergency’ (Theory and Event Vol.13, No.2, 2010)
5 A people of seers
The political aesthetics of post-war
cinema revisited
Julian Reid
DOI: 10.4324/9780203374702-6
Deleuze's Bergsonism
Deleuze's account of the ‘cinema of the seer’ can only be understood as an
extension of Henri Bergson's account of the politics of perception. Bergson
argued that the failure to perceive that which is most real of the world is a
constitutive practice in the everyday business of being human (Bergson
1991). In order to make use of the world we literally have to practice
evading the reality of the world; distorting and reducing it to perceptions
that are unreal but which enable our smooth functioning in the world.
Within the political register of experience this involves us, crucially, in
distorting the reality of the oppression and deprivation to which we are
subject in the world as well as the oppression and deprivation of others on
which our own lives are predicated, perceiving the world such that our
identities go undisturbed. While we may sense oppression and deprivation
on a daily basis, our intellect intervenes within the course of experience to
organize our perceptions such that we tolerate what would otherwise seem
intolerable. In spite of this fundamentally human quality of illusion it
remains conceivable, Bergson argued, for us to develop aesthetic practices
with which to unmake our own illusions and ‘recover contact with the real’
(ibid.: 185). Such practices may well serve to harm us, making us sick with
the reality of our own existence, but they will nevertheless bring us closer
to those real conditions which Bergson believed to exist at the source of
experience. Thus might we, if we choose to follow Bergson, believe in the
possibility of developing aesthetic practices to relieve ourselves of the
‘necessary poverty of our conscious perception’ (ibid.: 38) to see the real
poverty and oppressions of a world which otherwise passes us by.
Bergson himself deplored cinema, arguing that it merely recuperates the
mechanisms of the ordinary forms of perception on which the sensori-motor
systems of humans depend for efficient action (Bergson 1928: 322–23).
Deleuze's claims as to the potential of cinema to increase our capacity for
(in)sight only would have served to rile him, but the political potential of
the arts to enable societies to see beneath the conditions of their own
illusions was a phenomenon that he held dear. He argued that the processes
by which the limits of our political sensibilities are redrawn are akin to the
process by which artists transform public perceptions with creative works
(Deleuze 2005: 976). This modern power of art is akin, he also argued, to
the ancient powers of seers and prophets in guiding communities (ibid.:
978–79). The celebration of the power of the seer is not, of course,
particular to philosophy or cinema. The Greek tragedians and poets
celebrated the power of the seer while, in a similar fashion to modern
cinema, deploying him or her to warn against the dangers of sensori-
motorized action, the classic example being the seer Tiresias who in order
to guide Homer's Odysseus home has to intervene and rearrange his senses
so that he does not fall victim to the same fate as his unseeing crew
(Barnouw 2004: 11); who, when deployed by Sophocles, resists his
conscription to the city of Thebes on account of the unseen corruption of its
king Oedipus (Gooding 2003). Nor is the dramaturgy of the disruption of
the sensori-motor system distinct to cinema. It is the condition of
Shakespeare's Hamlet, who faced with the rotten state of Denmark
discovers that ‘time is out of joint.’ Nevertheless, Deleuze argues that
modern cinema embodies Bergson's commitment to a politics of perception
to new effect. In arguing his case he provided a wide variety of examples
across a range of different genres, too vast to detail in total here, and some
of which, as I will explain, are less sustainable than others.
‘The dumbest thing I ever heard.’ Seers are never portrayed simply in their
fugitive condition of perceiving the intolerable, but always in relation with
their schmucks. Doing so allows post-war cinema to invert the master-
discourse of ‘the people’ that distinguished classical political cinema. In
Taxi Driver this is most overt in the scenes where Travis confronts the
cretineity not just of his work colleagues but of the state apparatus more
directly. This confrontation is sketched in a variety of encounters. One in
his cab with the Democratic party's presidential candidate Charles Palantine
(whose campaign slogan is ‘We are the People’), but more poignantly with
Palantine's campaign manager Betsy, who in spite of the gulf in social class
separating them, he seduces. In an exchange over coffee Betsy tells Travis
how he reminds her of the Kris Kristofferson lyric, ‘He's a prophet and a
pusher. Partly truth, partly fiction. A walking contradiction.’ However,
when on their first date Travis takes Betsy to a porn cinema she is horrified
by the orgy of sensori-motorized actions that appear in close-up on the
screen. Unable to relate to Travis's motives (for whom porn symbolizes the
debasement of the sensori-motor mechanism), she rejects him. Like the
arch-cretin of Thebes, Oedipus at the crossroads, the state apparatus of post-
Vietnam America cannot bear the intolerable truths relayed to it by its seers.
Thus did cretineity in post-war cinema become not only the site of
something intolerable, but the distinguishing feature of the state apparatus
itself, and consequently that which must also be destroyed.
Conclusion
Deleuze's account of the modernity of cinema, including the distinctiveness
of its politics, can only be understood in the context of his broader political
thought and project. In the years since his death, his works have become
associated with the political ideal of a stateless world, of a human-social
assemblage which is utterly self-organizational, and which makes no
recourse to unanimity in the advance of political struggles. Certainly
Deleuze rejected the kinds of false unanimity on which the classical
political ideal of ‘the people’ was founded. When it came, however, to
confronting the political problems of his time he was insistent that a
political theory and practice of the present required a new typology on
which to advance its struggles. Substantial forms of political change, the
vast historical cleavages and upheavals which his works were concerned
with theorizing, were underwritten by collective projects. Deterritorialized
multitudes are not enough (Reid 2010). The main question that motivated
him, then, was that of how, in the establishment of particular regimes of
power did new counter-strategic collectivities emerge? How, in turn, did
such collectivities ‘embark on another kind of adventure, display another
kind of unity, a nomadic unity, and engage in a nomadic war-machine’
(Deleuze 2002: 259)? This was not merely an historical point for Deleuze.
He thought it as pertinent for the present as in the past. ‘The revolutionary
problem today,’ he argued, ‘is to find some unity in our various struggles
without falling back on the despotic and bureaucratic organization of the
party or State apparatus: we want a war-machine that would not recreate a
State apparatus, a nomadic unity… that would not recreate a despotic
internal unity’ (ibid.: 260).
Deleuze's arguments as to the importance of the cinema of the seer, its
new race of characters and its power to perceive the intolerable are all
highly indicative in this regard. These are characters who while bereft of a
political project to contribute to are nevertheless constitutive of a new kind
of political imaginary. Characters in which another kind of people can be
seen in its emergent properties: a people of seers. The cinema that Deleuze
describes posits the existence of this people in the condition of its
emergence. However, to see and extrapolate this we ourselves have to think
outside of Deleuze's own treatment of this cinema, especially the taxonomic
system through which he differentiates between Western and non-Western
cinemas, and his conception of political versus non-political cinema.
Moreover, we have to grasp this people of seers, its political practices of
seeing the intolerable, and the intolerant subjectivity on which it is founded
not simply in a deeply antagonistic relation with its cretinous Other. What
distinguishes the political function of the cinema of the seer is its depiction
of the antagonistic process by which cretins become seers, recognizing the
conditions that prevent them from being able to see, aswell as showing
would-be seers their own cretineity. The becoming conscious not only of
the intolerability of present conditions but dramaturgy of the call to destroy
it through novel alliances between the full range of different subjective
types is fundamental to the political function that this cinema performs.
References
The scene returns three times. In hues of amber and grey-black, three ani-
mated1 figures emerge from the sea. We see the first figure from behind, a
standing naked male body holding a gun, walking out of the water toward
an amber-grey shelled-out cityscape. Two more figures lie on their backs in
the water. Then the face, a face that will haunt us with its detached
familiarity, fills the screen, looking off slightly to the right.
A body framed by water, rippling black-amber, rises, shells brightening
the amber-hued night sky. The image pulls back, the cityscape now framed
by two feet peaking out of the water. Then we are close once more, facing
the rising bodies, accompanying them as they walk out of the sea toward
the city.
Two bodies, and finally a third, have now made their way out of the
water. Bombs fall on the scene of destruction but we don't hear them, the
audio-scape carried by the music that will haunt this scene, and with it, the
film, from beginning to end. In amber light we watch the bodies dress.
Then, the tone shifting from amber to grey, we accompany their climb into
the city, where, still fastening their clothing, they weave into the streets,
streets with posters of Bashir's face, streets full of mute, anguished women,
women whose voices we won't hear until the very last scene. Then, as the
camera turns, turning its back on the women, we are faced, again and once
more, with the face, a full-screen close-up of the soldier's impassive face.2
Twice more we will see the stark amber sky and the soldiers dressing, but
never again will we see this scene from beginning to end. Yet as we watch
it, we will feel as though it repeats itself frame for frame: every time we
will once more have the experience of following the soldiers walking up the
stairs into the city, under the posters of Bashir, into the crowds of mourning
women, a repetition framed, always, by the face.
The repeated scene of the bodies rising out of the water begins as a
promise: it looks like a flashback. As with all flashbacks, we are lulled into
the feeling that there will be a dénouement, that the scene will grow into its
content, rather than withdraw again and again into the expressionless face.
Coming as it does soon after the first scene — the dreamscape of amber-
grey-black dogs barking, of violence on the cusp of playing itself out, the
city caught in a web of fear — we assume that this scene of bodies
emerging from water will hold the key to the missing facts that memory
holds at bay. We are almost certain the scene will provide the clues to the
Sabra and Shatila massacre, that the rising bodies moving into the amber-
grey night of war will let us know how the repressed returns.3
However, the repressed does not return.4 We are witnesses not to the
victims of truths now uncovered, but to sheets of experience exposing at
once the singular horror of the Sabra and Shatila massacre and the
impossibility of containing it within an explanatory narrative. What returns
is not the past but the future, the ineffable more-than. Toward this future is
the figure of the face, the face we can never fall into, the face that resists
affective recognition, the face that leads us incessantly across, onto the
surface of an imagescape that folds, twists, undoes and recreates itself at the
complex intersection where life-living comes to expression.
Despite how haunted we are by the face and its reappearance especially
when we realize that it is the face of Ari Folman, the soldier/filmmaker/
memory-driver of the film the face never sticks. The face does not produce
the interiority for the film, does not become the centre as the affective
image around which the narration turns. It appears and disappears,
remaining flat, an impersonal surface that marks the passage from now to
now, from singularity to singularity, in a deferred rhythm without pre-
conceived connection, without attachment to time-as-such, without
territorializing on a ‘personal’ body. The face resists catharsis.5
Yet at first we cannot know this, and so we are almost certain the scene
of the rising bodies will provide the clues to the Sabra and Shatila massacre,
that the face staring into the amber-grey night of war will let us know how
the repressed returns. What we find instead is that we are witnesses to what
Deleuze calls ‘the power of the false,’ that which ‘replaces and supersedes
the form of the true, because it poses the simultaneity of incompossible
presents, or the coexistence of not-necessarily true pasts’ (Deleuze 1989:
131). The many-ness of expressibility in all of its entangled unfoldings is
what is at stake here. This is why, despite appearances to the contrary, it is
soon revealed that this is not a film ‘about’ the Sabra and Shatila massacre,
not a film that attempts to ‘return’ to the past to resolve the massacre's
fascistic unfolding. It is a film, rather, that surfaces the complexity of time
to make felt what cannot be straightforwardly resolved, a film that asks
experience in the making to encounter its own uneasiness, its own
ineffability in the face of the incompossibility of truth.
Figure 6.1
Waltz with Bashir (Ari Folman, 2008) is an animated film about living
memory, about life's opening onto memory as forgetting, about the
impossibility of memory's causal narration, about the ineffability of
violence's containment within the frame. It is a drama of amber and grey-
black that leaks onto all memory-surfaces, until it ends, finally, on the blues
and grays of archival documentation with one startling image of orange, a
dead girl's body on the sandy road of the Sabra and Shatila refugee camp.
Waltz with Bashir is a film replete with singularities that do not add up, that
cross over into sheets of experience that cannot ever manage to tell the
whole story, once and for all, the story of how memory and war coincide.
The face
Waltz with Bashir is about how the virtual plane — what Deleuze calls the
metaphysical surface6 — of the film brings life back not as a human face,
not as a past converted into a present, but as a movement across. By
presenting the face in its withdrawing from the imagescape, Waltz with
Bashir creates a tight circuit between what presents itself and what remains
virtual, returning us to the image's own movement, to the affective tonality
of the imagescape's haunting amber-black-grey, thus creating an opening for
what Deleuze calls a life, the barely active stirrings of life at the limit. To
bring a life to the fore, the human face must remain deterritorialized,
collective: when territorialized on a ‘personal’ body of the individual, the
face too strongly proposes a territory, an interiority. In Waltz with Bashir,
the face that returns, the impassive face of the soldier/filmmaker, is felt as
the surface of its own collectively transient becoming. It does not
overcome. It is a life, affective resonance in the intensive passage between
surfaces of experience. A life, Deleuze reminds us, happens not through
transcendence, but on the transcendental field itself. ‘Whenever immanence
is attributed to subject and object, which themselves fall outside the plane
[of immanence], the subject being taken as universal, and the object as any
object whatsoever, we witness a denaturing of the transcendental … And
we witness a distortion of immanence, which is now contained in the
transcendent’ (Deleuze 2007: 389). A life is immanence felt in the stirrings
of actualization. Force of potential, force of life.
The characters in Waltz with Bashir are faces, but faces as flat surfaces,
as markers for the force of fabulation, a telling poised at the limit of
articulation, a telling, as one character explains, of a past ‘not in my
system.’ Fabulation is about the event, the event of time: fabulation is not
the telling of a narrative in the form of the ‘what was’ (the transcendent) but
the expression of ‘the act of legending.’ This act creates not a truth but an
opening onto the aberrant movement of time where the surface of the film
itself begins to ‘fiction,’ to ‘legend’ or fabulate, where the character (the
surface) begins to ‘fabulate without ever being fictional’ and where the
filmmaker cannot but ‘“intercede himself” from the real characters who
wholly replace his own fiction through their own fabulations’ (Deleuze
1991: 150, translation modified). What emerges via the face in Waltz with
Bashir are stories fabulating themselves, creating themselves in the merging
of events that do not constitute a clear continuity, events replete with
fantasy and dream, reconstruction and confusion.7 ‘Do you recognize this
picture,’ the filmmaker asks, ‘no’ the impassive face responds; ‘was I
always there?’ he asks another, ‘yes.’ The impassivity of the faces of the
characters as they relay their selective memories tinged with forgetting
invites a moving-across into the texture of memory itself. The telling does
not sink into the myth of an attainable past. It moves through events in the
making, creating a collective surface for the telling. In the fabulation that
ensues, the face resists empathy at any personal, individual level. For the
face here is not the locus of human expression, but the metaphysical surface
through which events pass; the movement of the events of the film bubble
at its impassive surface inviting us to move across into the collective event
that is the imagescape itself. We cannot get inside the faces, so we move
across their surfaces into the texture of the becoming-image, the becoming-
image of a forgetting that is all but a past uncovered. Shards of meaning
coincide, but no ultimate meaning is revealed. Waltz with Bashir is a web of
futures in the making more than a depth of remembrance, once and for all.
What we see is not the past bubbling to the surface, but life itself active in
the immanence of the future-arising, a life on the verge of appearance at the
very intersection where immanence transcends itself and merges with the
actuality of the ineffable.
A life is how the drama of the political expresses itself in Waltz with
Bashir. It is Nietzsche's ‘was that life? Well then once more’8 and
Massumi's bare activity.9 It is the force of agitation that pushes the virtual
to the limit, the dark precursor that propels the doubling of transcendence
and immanence into the pure experience10 of the now. It is the activity of
the metaphysical surface and, as such, it is the force of expression of the
transcendental field.
The concept of the transcendental field radically challenges standard
notions of transcendence. Where transcendence relies on the already-
existent platform of spacetimes of experience in order to overcome them,
the transcendental field is a pre-individual topological surface that spurs
aberrant movements out of which spacetimes are created anew, aberrant
because there can never be a pre-imposed path for how life can and will
emerge.11
A transcendental field can never be known as such; however, it can be
felt through the singular series — the lives — that bring it momentarily into
appearance: ‘Singularities are the real transcendent events, and Ferlinghetti
calls them “the fourth person singular” … Only when the world, teaming
with anonymous and nomadic, impersonal and pre-individual singularities,
opens up, do we tread at last on the field of the transcendental’ (Deleuze
1990: 103).
Waltz with Bashir's relentless imagescape of amber-grey-black steers us
into an uneasy realm. It does not give us anything to hold onto and yet it
pushes us across. It forces us to think, as Deleuze would say, pushing
thought to the beyond where it is no longer about content, but about the
creation of movements of thought. Thought in its bare activity, thought at
the cusp where it merges with feeling.
Forcing thought to its limit where the thinking and the feeling are one,
Waltz with Bashir activates a protopolitics that merges, uncertainly, with the
politics the film can never get beyond, pushing the political to its limit, a
limit from which it returns — if it returns — as the dramatic image of its
own bare activity, broken into shards of light, amber-grey. There is no face
to latch onto, no expression with which to empathize and so we keep
moving. Waltz with Bashir proposes more than it provides, offering
affective tonality before content, providing color and force-form before it
gives us a figure, a body as such. Waltz with Bashir thus propels us across
the infrahuman topological surface of the image, forcing us to think not
simply what but how — what surfaces is also how it surfaces.
What — as allied to Being — is the question of transcendence, the
question of interiority and depth, while how — as allied to process, or
becoming — is the question of the transcendental field. There are no
questions that cannot be dangerous in their own right, that are protected
from returning to habits of thought, but there are few starting points as
lethal as the totalitarianism of Being: I is a habit, and where it leads is
toward the supremacy of the human.12 Being and the human cannot be
disengaged, and with the human at the center, the frame is already in place
for the eclipsing of the complexity of other ecologies, of other surfaces of
experience. Foregrounding instead the metaphysical surface as the how of
experience in the making opens the way for a different proposition. For how
does not delimit a field according to preexisting parameters: it opens it to its
outside, to the outside as it curves back in on the topological surface that
never quite contains it. How brings us back to the protopolitical and the
dark precursor which is its movement of thought, to politics at the very cusp
of its appearance, at the bare edge of its agitation. How does not guarantee
against the return of fascism or the microfascist tendencies the political can
and does call forth. However, it at least offers an opening onto the potential
of a forking, onto a life welling at the winding surface that is the singular
limit between now and now.13
The ineffable
To the physics of surfaces a metaphysical surface necessarily corresponds.
Metaphysical surface (transcendental field) is the name that will be given to
the frontier established, on the one hand, between bodies taken together as a
whole and inside the limits which envelop them, and on the other,
propositions in general. This frontier implies, as we shall see, certain
properties of sound in relation to the surface, making possible thereby a
distinct distribution of language and bodies, or of the corporeal depth and
the sonorous continuum. In all these respects, the surface is the
transcendental field itself, and the locus of sense and expression (Deleuze
1990: 125).
The transcendental field filters into experience as the virtual agitation of
life welling. It is not yet delineated into subject or object: it moves
intensively across, preindividually, aberrantly creating remarkable points
that emerge, eventually, as the subjects and objects of the next now. It
resonates with these singular events of becoming, propelling series into
actualities that carry with them the germ of its intensive surface.
The transcendental field in Waltz with Bashir expresses itself as the
emergent surface that is the repeated and varied contrast of amber-grey-
black. This contrast is felt as a field of resonance where color becomes
sonorous continuum — its surface the rhythm for the seeing-hearing of a
life coursing through. While the amber-grey-black returns, always, in
moments of recollection, it is not the content of the scenes that feeds
forward from the transcendental field but the quality, the rhythm, the
resonance, of the imagescape itself. The imagescape pulses through,
pushing forward and across, moving us with it, resonating with the unseen,
the ineffable. For the image resonates with the forgetting at the heart of
memory, the forgetting at whose limit life begins to bubble to the surface.
Never conscious of itself, the transcendental field is the qualitative
duration of the without-me of relation, of life-living. Radically empirical, it
emerges, barely, at the interval of feeling and felt. When we feel it, what we
feel is the cut of the interval, the between of its singular appearance here
and now. In Waltz with Bashir we feel this quality of the active interstice in
the intensive surfacing of amber-grey-black, we feel it in the resonant field
created by the contrast of the bright and the dull, we feel it as the
intersection where the impossibility of strategically coupling then and now
expresses itself. Throughout Waltz with Bashir, we are never really out of
this interval for we never rest in the amber-grey-black. Its stark contrast
moves us each time anew, reminding us that the past cannot be doubled
onto the present, that what emerges appears in the multiple now of life in
the making, of life fabulating.
Sheets of the present move at various rhythms, creating different
sonorous continuums and affective tonalities, and with them come different
resonant fields. Take the scene between the filmmaker14 and Ori, the friend-
therapist. In stark departure from the grey-amber-black tones of the earlier
scenes of the film, this scene, in which Ori describes a memory experiment,
is in greens and pinks. The experiment is as follows: people are shown
pictures from their childhood. They figure as children in these pictures and
the events are real — they actually happened. Then, the experimenters give
them a false image. This image still has them as the protagonist but the
environment is invented. They were never really there. As Ori relates the
experiment to the filmmaker, the scene shifts to a child in an amusement
park, the child like a cut-out in a field of clowns and Ferris wheels, all this
in bright candy colors. This is one such ‘not really real’ image: the
amusement park is not one the child ever actually visited. Eighty percent of
the people who take this experiment, Ori explains, claim really to have been
there when they see themselves in the picture. The remaining twenty
percent — those who are unsure of whether they were really there — are
invited to go home and think about it. When they return, and upon seeing
the picture of ‘themselves’ in the amusement park once again, they
‘remember’ the amusement park. As Ori says, ‘memory is dynamic, it's
alive.’
This scene briefly takes us ‘out’ of the story of war. An aside on memory,
it feels like a film within the film. We relax in the assumption that we are
pausing outside the atrocities of war while we are being taught a lesson
about the slippery quality of memory so that when we return to the ‘real’
film, we will expect less from the ‘truth’ of recollection. However, just
when we are certain that this is simply an academic exercise into the
inevitability of memory's failures, and that this scene is cast apart from the
real events of the film, the scene itself begins to fabulate: a washed-out
version of the amusement park scene briefly becomes the backdrop to Ori
and the filmmaker's con-versation, the Ferris wheel and the clown
appearing out the window behind the filmmaker's back. The amusement
park has made its way onto the surface of the now, into the story of how
war and memory can never strictly coincide. Memory has already begun
working its sly tricks. The force of fabulation has once more infiltrated the
transcendental field of the film.
This short, washed-out amusement park scene haunts the film. We see it,
but they don't — the filmmaker and Ori continue to speak about memory as
though nothing had happened, as though their discussion hadn't already
changed the imagescape's course. The appearance of the amusement park
behind the filmmaker's shoulder cuts into the past/future circuit he is
working so desperately to unravel, bringing a new surface to a complex
topological field of recollections of the forgotten past and dreams of the
unimagined future. Then, a few seconds later, the semblance of the
amusement park gives way once more to the dreary backdrop of an outside
garden, things back ‘as they should be.’ Yet this instance of memory's
intrusion into the future-present will continue to resonate at the edges of the
film's metaphysical surface. Like the dogs of the first amber-grey-black
scene, it never returns as such. Never again do we even see its colors — the
bright pinks and greens of the clowns and the balloons. Nonetheless, this
scene has altered the field, multiplying time's supposed linearity. ‘[T]here is
no other crime than time itself,’ writes Deleuze (1989: 37). The amusement
park image marks time/memory as aberrant movement. ‘What aber-rant
movement reveals is time as everything, as ‘infinite opening,’ as anteriority
over all normal movement … ’ (Deleuze 1989: 37).
Figure 6.2
The transcendental field does not transcend time. It fields time's creation
in the event. To transcend time would be to posit linear time in order to
redraw time's passage as an inside and outside of experience that moves
seamlessly from past to present to future. This would assume an
omnipresent (human) body, documenting, remembering, orchestrating,
witnessing. This is transcendence, operative always on the molar stratum of
experience where life appears as predefined. The metaphysical surface, on
the other hand, has no preconstituted spacetime. It has virtual circuits,
impossible flows, ineffable becomings, washouts, active always on the
molecular stratum where life is still in the making. Events as they come to
expression merge with this metaphysical surface in infinitely dynamic
ways. Dynamic events are full of holes, or better, of folds. They propel
subjects and objects into the world, but they are not presupposed by them.
Actively emergent from the transcendental field of experience, events do
not create form once and for all, they create openings for the force of a
taking-form. This is memory: the dynamic force of life-living in the uneasy
forming.
Transcendence builds memory from without, feeding the past ‘fully-
formed’ into the container of the present. To transcend spacetime is to move
outside spacetime to force a mode of life on living. Transcendence cleaves
morally, separating fields of experience into representations of good and
evil. It is a back-gridding procedure that creates a totality, a totalitarian,
tautological experience.15 The transcendental field, by contrast, has no
direction except toward the event, and no form in itself — it folds into the
event forming.
Desiring surfaces
Let's return to the first scene of the film. The only dream in the film, this
first scene is strangely disconnected from every other event, and yet its
surface quality imbues all future imagescapes. This scene creates the mood
of the film, its contrast, color and affective tone. For two minutes we move
to the threatening rhythm of twenty-six dogs, their growls and panting in
tandem with the synthesized sound of drums mixed with aggressive
barking, the image finally centering on an amber sky, a grey building, a
lone, distant face at a window looking out onto the street.16 Moving
alongside the dogs, our gait is one of horizontality, a threatening movement
across, relentless, from now to now to now.17 Never is there a clear sense of
the status of this now. The now is always moving. The movement is before,
behind and across and we move with it, horizontalizing the topological
surface of pure experience. The dogs surround us on this hor-izontalizing
plane even as we move with them, following them in their fight to the
death. In this terrifying moving surround, we see amber eyes as place-
holders of certain versions of events; we experience the mobilization of
discrete singularities, and yet nothing stays still as we at once participate in
and fear the mobile surface, the abstract surface of the amber-grey-black
that continuously moves across.18
As the opening scene gives way to future amber-grey-black scenes of
memory and forgetting, we become somewhat distanced from the horror of
the dogs, but the dogs have set the tone and we cannot but feel that, in the
end, there is no distance, no break in the movement across, only the
semblance of a strange, detached calm.19
This uneasy movement between surfacings, topological and horizontal,
between affective tonalities, lull and anguish, between calm and agitation,
terror and beauty, is active, always, in the contrast, amber-grey-black. The
amber-grey-black is a backdrop that is never strictly a background, forcing
the viewer into a continued seeing-feeling across strata: we are drawn into a
backgrounding-foregrounding resonance, we are lulled by the warmth of
the amber, but cannot tear ourselves away from the nightmare of the inky
black, the threatening night sky, the destroyed world of grey asphalt. So
with each return of the amber-grey-black, a version of the dogs return, their
eyes amber, their fur grey, the sky amber, the streets grey, their sound
amber-grey-black, the sonorous continuum resonant on the mobile surface
of the imagescape.
The amber-grey-black is the fourth person singular, as Ferlinghetti calls
it. It is the desiring machine that moves us across the surface of the image,
not so much feeding the narrative as fuelling the intensive absence of a
linear reminiscence. It promises no mimicry of itself, no representation, no
absolute recognition, no ultimate tying of loose ends. It keeps us poised at
the limit, that edge where terror haunts the image. This edge is never
transcended. It remains the affective tonality of what cannot be expressed:
the transcendental field of a micropolitics in the making.
Figure 6.3
Becoming-body
Intensity of feeling in Waltz with Bashir emerges on the volumetric surface
of the becoming-body, the sensing body in movement, of the film itself.
This becoming-body resists the quintessential sensitive surface by refusing
to territorialize on the human face, except, perhaps, at the last scene, where
the animation gives way to documentary footage. In this amodal field of
experience, the becoming-body as surface is its own intensive multiple
movement across. It resists moving into a body, a personalized human body.
It remains instead a biogram on the transcendental field's topological
surface.
That the film moves between bodies in becoming, shaping the emergence
of a life not as body but as biogram,28 does not suggest that it disregards the
body. Quite the contrary. The biogram of the film makes Waltz with Bashir
all about the body, all about the intensity of life welling. What Waltz with
Bashir resists is the subjectification of this body, the stultification of this
personal experience as mapped through the recognition of the face as the
quintessential affective image. At the limit of the now of events diverging
where sense and memory coincide in an active forgetting, the becoming-
body is an attractor for the creation of nodes of resonance, of sonorous
continuums where a face has not yet congealed. This is why the face in
Waltz with Bashir eludes us. It is not yet fully formed. Until the last scene.
The biogram of Waltz with Bashir is a moving of preindividual life across
the folds of the surface of experience in the making. The becoming-body as
biogram plays at the interstice of individuation and singularity, trembling on
the resonant circuit of the virtual/actual now of pure experience, appearing
as a tonal difference that pushes the narrative along: the body not as content
but as crystal of potential. The biogram constitutes not a unique body, but a
body-emergent across series, the force of life that can never return to the
body as One. Force of life: where life is not yet individual or person but
collective individuation. Here, where the actual and the virtual coincide in a
tight circuit, there is no morality, there is only life-living, a life. Morality
belongs to the discourse of individualized politics where perpetrators and
victims are identified not as bodies in the making, but as fully formed nodes
of a politics already constituted, a politics that transcends the now of
experience.
Bare activity is the term Brian Massumi gives to the politics-in-germ of
the becoming-body. Politics-in-germ bubbles on the pre-individual level as
the singularly felt edging into life-living of the body-becoming. Bare
activity is not biopower. It is the biogrammatic tendency of an edging into
bodyness, of the surface welling into a singularity across series.
‘Biopower's “field of application” according to Foucault is a territory,
grasped from the angle of its actually providing liveable conditions for an
existing biological being. [Bare activity] operates on a proto-territory tensed
with a compelling excess of potential which renders it strictly unliveable.’29
On the edge of the livable: a life.
A life percolates. Unlike some of Waltz with Bashir's critics, we must not
mistake ‘a life’ with the life of the filmmaker, overlaying it with Ari
Folman or with a generalized version of the Israeli or the Palestinian body.
This is not what churns at the edges of the film. A life is the bare activity of
the surface folding, of the background foregrounding. A life pushes through
the plane of immanence, always on the verge of appearing, making itself
felt, but never ‘as such.’ Beyond good and evil. Protopolitical,
preindividual, a life shapes the sensing surface. We are caught by it, but
only peripherally, for it has always already moved beyond in a welling of a
new proto-territory. It is activation on the edge ‘at [the] intensive limit of
life’ (Massumi 2009). It is the waltz in Waltzing with Bashir.
The waltz: two men crouched on the edge of a road in a grey, shelled
cityscape fight over a gun in the midst of heavy artillery. Imminent danger
all around: soldiers shoot wildly, their anguish palpable. The sky is amber
against the grey of the buildings and the dusty asphalt. We see fire in the
distance. The soldier rises, the gun he has now managed to get a hold of at
his side. We watch, tense, as the soldier moves into the suicidal path of
bombs and bullets. The sound of a Chopin waltz playing in the background
intensifies. The soldier begins to cross the street to the rhythm of the music
in a three-step, all the while firing the gun into the air. Five seconds, ten
seconds, the image focused on his feet, one-two-three, one-two-three, the
bullet casings falling around him as he continues to shoot into the sky. We
hear a gunshot whizzing by but the soldier's seemingly invincible body is
the only one the image cares about, the ima-gescape dancing with him
amidst the gun-flame amber in the grey-light surround. As the waltz gains
in speed, the casings continue to pollute the earth around him and the image
turns and turns, waltzing with the soldier as the sky darkens, its amber
shadows intensifying in step with the image's focus in on the soldier's tight
circle, one-two-three, one-two-three. Twenty seconds.
Then the voice-over returns to address what is happening, but similarly to
the earlier music videos, this scene cannot be explained, cannot be
comprehended. So our attention remains focused on the soldier's movement,
his becoming-body dancing, a life quivering to the surface.
As the soldier's dance comes to an end, the image is taken over by the
larger-than-life poster of Bashir's face, gazing off-screen, pock-marked with
bullet holes. We sense a shift: from the micropolitics of the waltz to the
macropolitics of everything Bashir represents as the recently elected
president, as the murdered Phalangist leader, as the dark precursor to a war
already in the making. Bashir's face, larger than life, takes over the screen
until we are looking straight at him, another face that eludes us, that will not
look at us, but this is less an impassive face than a face uninterested in us:
Bashir's gaze is turned away, turned to the prelude, perhaps, of the Sabra
and Shatila massacre, a massacre we will neither fully see, nor directly
connect to, nor ever fully comprehend. Sixteen seconds with Bashir's face
looking away, a non-merging with its extensive surface, the macropolitical
surface of the Lebanon war.
What is the status of Bashir's face, filling the screen? How does this face
that refuses to face us coincide with the incessant return of the impassive
face that looks straight at us? What kind of circuit does Bashir's face
superimposed on the anguished waltz of the mad soldier create?
Bashir's face is not unexpressive, but nor is it engaged. It looks off into a
distance that cannot be fathomed — we cannot see what he sees. Here is a
proposition: Bashir's face creates the initial delimitation of a territory.30
This territory is where the massacre will take place: it is a specific place
with a date and a history and an aftermath. Bashir gazes toward the
macropolitical, his gaze directed toward the transcendent unity which is the
state, the unity from which he derives the power to make decisions such as
who is included and excluded from the realm of the political. Yet his face is
not there — it is here, here in the dance, here in the vertigo where the macro
and the micro coincide, where the affective tonality of a life coursing
through this life makes itself felt.
Bashir's face marks the passage from the abstract plane of experience
where memory and war collide without coinciding (the soldier's face) to the
plane of organization where war proliferates as the actual violence of
destruction. The soldier and Bashir's face: an uneasy pairing of bare activity
and representation dancing at the limits where the micro and the macro
coincide, at the dangerous limit where the micropolitical potentially
territorializes into fascisms in the making.31 For ‘[f]ascism is inseparable
from a proliferation of molecular forces in interaction, which skip from
point to point … There is fascism when a war machine is installed in each
hole, in every niche’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 214).32
Waltz with Bashir gives life to the bare activity of the political bubbling
to the surface of the transcendental field at the same time that it warns that
surfaces are not purveyors of moral truths. In the immensity of Bashir's face
filling the screen and dwarfing the soldier, we sense that protopolitics are
always potentially fascist politics, and yet we also feel the uncanny surplus
of the waltz's movement undermining the straightforward narrative of
political predetermination. From the waltz to Bashir, from the soldier's face
lost in the reverie of his mad movement to the calm certainty of Bashir's
distant gaze, a political drama is set forth that creates a tight circuit of
molecular potentials and micropolitical captures.
As Ari Folman was creating Waltz with Bashir, microfascisms were
playing themselves out in different ways across political constituencies, as
they have a tendency to wherever there is a transcendent capture, be it
liberal or neo-liberal, conservative or neo-conservative. At the liberal edge
of the spectrum ‘we’ insist on a politics of recognition based on a
benevolent responsibility for the other that builds on dichotomies of
inclusion/exclusion, perpetrator/victim, and reifies the human in the name
of race, identity, gender. Not necessarily fascism, but certainly a tending
toward fascism in the name of a universal figure of the human. As Guattari
underscores, the universal as a tendency activates forms of microfascism in
the name of desire to have the final word on the moral and the immoral,
right and wrong, and this tending toward universalizing is with us, always.
‘Fascism happened and it never ceases happening. It travels through the
finest weaves; it is in constant evolution. It seems to come from the outside,
but it finds its energy in the heart of each of our desires’ (Guattari 1977: 62,
my translation). Fascisms are war machines that fill the holes and gaps of
potential, sedimenting the open topological surface of the transcendental
field. Fascisms are a strange interplay of rigidity and suppleness -rigid
disciplinings that reek of totalitarianism, supple choreographies of surface
cells in the making. Waltz with Bashir does not protect us from the micro-
fascist edges of politics. Indeed, it takes us again and again to their limit.
What Waltz with Bashir does is refuse to know in advance how the
consequences of the undeniable horror of the massacre play out, and where
the ongoing fascisms of politics in the making are located. In so doing, it
makes felt how fascisms never reign simply on the macropolitical surface of
experience — they crawl between, across strata of experience, resurging in
forms and forces less obvious than those in the macropolitical realm but no
less insidious.
This is what Waltz with Bashir does: it complexifies the stakes by
resisting the settling of fascism within one or another of the camps; it resists
personalizing the political. Go back to the waltz scene, the scene of bullets
flying and a soldier dancing, and see once more how the impassive face of
Bashir is superimposed onto the agitations of a life. Note how, by
superimposing Bashir's face, enormous and compelling, onto the backdrop
of a mad dance of a soldier's undoing, Waltz with Bashir activates and
makes felt the originary difference at the heart of all dephasings. How it
makes felt that there is much more at stake than simply one surface of
experience. How it makes felt that what surfaces is also how it surfaces.
Moving through them, we find ourselves beside their anguish, our pace
now a little in advance of their movements. We dread what we are about to
see. For in the distance we see him, facing them, the soldier-filmmaker, his
face filling the screen, his previously impassive face slowly falling apart.
As we approach, as the face beckons larger and larger, we see that the face
is no longer pure surface: it is leaking, breathing, chest heaving up and
down, mouth slightly open, eyes roving. We feel the face's breakdown, the
loss of its contours, and through this intensive folding we feel the whole
metaphysical surface of the film folding into expression. However, it is not
expression of content: we do not see what he sees, our backs still to the
women. What he sees: the ineffable, the ungraspable, the horror.
Then we do see. We see with our own eyes. We see the wailing
Palestinian women through the documentary footage taken in 1982. One
Palestinian woman's face fills the screen, growing larger than life, larger
even than the space of the frame. Then the face moves away from us, into
the devastation of the massacre. Now another face looks straight at us,
screaming, wailing into the eye of the camera in a language so many will
never fully comprehend. In a rush we feel everything, we feel the amplitude
of the transcendental surface now active on the surface of life, this life: we
feel the terror, the empathy, the guilt, the shame, the horror. Yet we feel it
not solely in their name, but in the fullness of our taking part; we feel it as
our own movement across the surface of the ineffability of experience. This
shift from animation to documentary footage shakes our relation to the
image. We feel-see the horror.
In two minutes, the metaphysical surface of the film has completely
shifted. Everything has come undone, but this is not the film's first undoing.
The series of undoings that occur throughout the film keep the circuit tight
between affect and emotion, holding us to the now of experience in the
making. These undoings are what keep us from taking the stance of the
dispassionate observer, that keep us from falling into our selves. We watch-
with, we feel-with the terror of a life fleeting, consumed, subsumed by the
horrors of war. So we become responsible before the event, in the face of it,
in its incessant coming-to-act, as Deleuze would say. For what Waltz with
Bashir has instantiated with its roving imagescape and its relentless
sonorous continuum is emphatically not a responsibility for the event, as
though the event could be captured and cir-cumscribed.33 This is not to say
that the coupling with fascisms in the making is not always there, at the
ready, as are the risks of becoming responsible for, of taking a
universalizing stance from beyond the event of a life's unfolding. The
specter of the boy with his hands raised, the recall of Warsaw, looms large.
A rigid segmentarity. However, still the film resists, I believe, and it is this
resistance that is most haunting.
Figure 6.5
The documentary footage barely lasts one minute, its blues and grays
pausing in the end on an image of orange, a dead girl's body, before we are
taken back to black screen of the animated film, back to amber credits, back
to the Schubert that has returned more than once, differently each time,
activating the sonorous continuum of our experience in the watching.
Before the credits, though, the screen remains black, a blackness that lasts
an eternity of twelve seconds. We do not know where we stand.34 The
ground trembles with the responsibility before life. We cannot comprehend
the imagescape. It washes over us, black, a surface alive with the haunting
sonorous continuum of a horror uncharted, a surfacing that now gives time
for the re-creation of a circuiting back to each and every amber-grey-black
image of the film. We are back, rising out of the water, walking into a city
at dawn, terrified and deadened by the difference of repetition. We are back,
rising out of the water, dressing on the edge of the sea, holding our hands
up in the nightmare of Warsaw, lost in an image that refuses to situate us.
So Waltz with Bashir resists the resolve of a dogmatic political stance,
leaving us instead at the very heart of the drama of the political barely
active.
‘Everything changes when the dynamisms are posited no longer as
schemata of concepts but as dramas of ideas’ (Deleuze 1994: 218). How? is
the dramatic question. In its departure from the transcendental what?, the
differential how? is with what Waltz with Bashir is concerned. How: how to
conceive of relations of force over and above a power structure that puts the
individual at the center?
Relations of force are relations in their incipiency. They are tendencies in
the making. Their will to power is a fight to the death between the
metaphysical surface and transcendence. Transcendence often wins,
because in the end it is easier to give up on the amber-grey of the face-as-
surface, to turn away from the ineffable, to make the individual the starting
and the end point, to background the uncertainty of relations still in-
forming, to place blame, to live in resentment, to be a victim, to be guilty, to
be innocent.35 Yet to make the personal political — to opt for transcendence
— is radically to underestimate the power of fascism and its unique ability
to morph into folds of experience as yet unthought.
There is no question: responsibility must be taken, consequences must be
faced. The macropolitical cannot be ignored. However, the edge, the
differential, where the molar and the molecular meet is equally vital. For it
is here, where the bare-active forces of the political agitate beyond the
realm of the personal or the individual, that difference is felt at its most
acute.
Waltz with Bashir is a political drama the strength of which is that it plays
itself out at the uneasy intersection of a life effervescing and politics'
potential reterritorialization on the face of fascism.36 Waltz with Bashir
refutes an easy solution. There is no promise here, nor even the certainty
that it isn't fascism that rears its ugly head as the film comes to a close. Yet
it is also here, it seems to me, in the uncertainty, that the potential looms for
something yet to come that has not yet found its name, its face: a politics in
the making.
In providing us with the opportunity to think about the how of proto-
politics, Waltz with Bashir calls forth the future, but not a ready-made one;
an uncertain one. In doing so, it resists territory's refrain, creating the
opportunity for an ongoing conversation across surfaces of war and
violence, an ongoing conversation not only about past wars or ongoing
massacres, not only about the ineffability of the Israeli-Palestinian conflict
and its micro- and macro-fascist tendencies, but also about the danger of
‘new forms of microfascisms: the simmering of familialism, at school, in
racism, in ghettos of all kinds’ (Guattari 1977: 62, my translation).
Waltz with Bashir does this by taking a protopolitical stance: we must be
wary of identifying too strongly with the face, for the face is a dangerous
proposition — either we recognize it as our own, or we turn away from it in
horror.37 The face must remain a topological surface equal to all other
surfacings: it must not territorialize too quickly onto an identity, onto an
individual, onto the Jew or the Palestinian. Because if it does, we will have
positioned ourselves in advance, and we will already have succumbed to the
most potentially racist of subject-object positions.
Beyond the face is where the politics of the more-than can begin, but we
must walk the tightrope carefully, remembering all the while, as Deleuze
and Guattari remind us, that there are no micropolitical experiments
impervious to capture by macropolitical tendencies and vice versa:
‘everything is political, but every politics is simultaneously a macropolitics
and a micropolitics’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 213).
Beyond the human
On the dangers of macropolitical capture, we can learn, perhaps, from the
troubling about-turn of Emmanuel Levinas, whose ethical philosophy is
con-structed on the ineffability of the face, but for whom, as a Zionist Jew,
the face of the Palestinian was, in the end, too much to face.
Levinas's ethical philosophy is constructed around the concept of the
face-to-face encounter where ‘the face is present in its refusal to be
contained’ (Levinas 1961: 194). His ethics underscore the idea that the face
cannot be comprehended or encompassed and he is clear that the face must
not be thought as ‘content’ — that it ultimately cannot be grasped or
touched as such. The face is always the face of the Other, it is that which
underscores ‘the incomprehensible nature of the presence of the Other’ as
the first revelation of the absolute difference of the other, a relation that is
‘maintained without violence, in peace with this absolute alterity’ (Levinas
1961: 195, 197).
So far, the face as Levinas conceptualizes it is very reminiscent of the
face in Waltz with Bashir. It refuses to be contained and operates as the
topological surface of difference. Where Waltz with Bashir significantly
diverges from Levinas is in its emphasis on the infrahuman and on the
question of the response/ responsibility. In Levinas, the absolute alterity of
the face, that ‘puts me in a relation with being,’ calls forth a need for a
response, and there is no question that this is a response directed at another
human (Levinas 1961: 212). Relations abound and encounters multiply in
Waltz with Bashir, but these encounters are between abstract surfaces —
face color, face sound, face dance, each of them operational in the tight
circuit where the virtual and the actual coincide and differential relations
play themselves out. Were Waltz with Bashir to demand ‘a response,’ a
human-to-human encounter before all else, it would risk falling right back
into the transcendence of political pre-positionings. In order to create an
opening onto the drama of the political where relations of force are what is
at stake, and not individual power, Waltz with Bashir must do everything to
avoid making the pre-composed, pre-narrated body of the human the center
of life-living.
This is the topic of the conversation that takes place between Levinas,
Alain Finkielkraut and Shlomo Malka in the aftermath of the Sabra and
Shatila massacre. The discussion begins with the question of response and
responsibility, underscoring, as far as I am concerned, the dangers of an
ethical philosophy that humanizes experience and seeks to comprehend it in
a gesture of recognition of its humanity.
Shlomo Malka begins the conversation by quoting a talk of Alain
Finkielk-raut's where Finkielkraut says, ‘We are all split between a feeling
of innocence and a feeling of responsibility, both of which are anchored in
our traditions and our ordeals. I do not yet know which of the two,
innocence or responsibility, we will choose as Jews. But I believe that our
decision will determine the meaning that we give to the ordeal of genocide’
(Malka 1989: 290).
Taking this quote as a starting point, Malka asks: ‘Levinas, you are the
philosopher of the “other.” Isn't history, isn't politics the very site of the
encounter with the “other,” and for the Israeli, isn't the “other” above all the
Palestinian?’ Levinas responds: ‘Prior to any act, I am concerned with the
Other, and I can never be absolved from this responsibility’ (Malka 1989:
290). Continuing on the subject of responsibility toward ‘those “who have
done nothing”,’ and focusing on the concept of an ‘original responsibility of
man for the other person,’ Levinas underscores the fact that ‘my self… is
never absolved from responsibility toward the Other’ (ibid.: 290–91).
This statement of Levinas turns the stakes of the discussion toward the
specific question of the Jew and the Palestinian and the responsibility of
Zionism in the face of the Sabra and Shatila massacre. Is it a responsibility
for or a responsibility before? Can there be any question of innocence?
Levinas responds: ‘in alterity we can find an enemy, or at least then we are
faced with the problem of knowing who is right and who is wrong, who is
just and who is unjust. There are people who are wrong’ (Malka 1989: 294).
From the thinker for whom responsibility is always the question of the
response elicited by the face of the other yet who claimed that the face must
always remain without content, do we not experience here the stark
reterritorialization on the face against which Deleuze and Guattari warn in
their work on faciality?38 Isn't the question of responsibility once again a
question of whose face? Is it not the face of the other that we now see as
wrong?
This is precisely what Waltz with Bashir resists: nowhere in the film is
there a reterritorialization on the face of the other. By the time the
Palestinian women's faces appear, it can no longer be a question of territory,
the surfaces far too intermeshed. Waltz with Bashir thus resists the two
tendencies at play here in the bringing together of ethics and politics: the
staging of the politico-ethical solely in the body of the human and its
responsibility for the other it faces. Responsibility for reeks of benevolence,
a dangerous kind of liberal humanist ‘generosity’ that maintains the other as
either victim or perpetrator, keeping the strata rigid. Being responsible
before is a different proposition. To be responsible before is to engage at the
non-human limit of the barely active where a life is restlessly agitating. On
the cusp where the surfaces of life-living resonate, on the sonorous
continuum of the ineffable, responsibility before means that we cannot
already have positioned ourselves, that we are indeed, as Deleuze suggests,
sorcerers creating life, and more life.39
To create more life is to produce difference. It is to resituate memory in
the act of the telling that opens life-living to the pure experience of the
welling now. ‘Recollection introduces difference into the present in the
sense that recollection constitutes, each subsequent moment, something
new’ (Deleuze 2004: 45, translation modified). The drama of politics at the
heart of Waltz with Bashir is the recursive now, the terrible now of the
tense, war-infested street where the soldier erupts from his war-self into a
dance, the eerie now of the love-boat's dance exploding into blood-red
ocean, the strangely quiescent now of Bach dancing in the forest. This
drama of time, in time, is not theatrical. Waltz with Bashir does not
represent war, or memory, or suffering. It does not express it on a stage that
is separate from its happening. It lives it, on the very edge of life where life
takes on the resonant political drama of a life.
Notes
Introduction
Fascism, Deleuze and Guattari suggest, implies a molecular regime distinct
from molar segments: not the rigidity of state molarity but both the
suppleness and the dangers of the line of flight. In their conceptualisation of
social and political relations as a play of lines in dynamic interaction, lines
crisscross and clash as well as mix and merge; lines create and connect,
abort and destroy; lines function to capture, demarcate, defend and uphold a
territorial domain of limits and bounds, order and organisation; and lines
challenge, undermine, perturb and destroy domains or order(ing)s of
organisation and organisations of order(ing). If power and resistance,
creation and destruction, operate on the same line(s), then the problem is
not so much that forms of resistance come to resemble the regimes of power
they seek to counter, but rather that the gravest dangers lie in the capacity of
a single line to turn any direction. The same line(s) constitute the milieux of
strategies of both power and resistance hence neither their course nor their
outcome can be predicted in advance. Besides, the movement that holds out
the greatest promise of creative becoming — of modes of movement and
relationality affirmative of life — also poses the gravest danger of ending in
death and destruction. The political problematique that emerges with
Deleuze and Guattari's conceptualisation of lines is accordingly this: if what
holds the most promising creative potential also carries the most serious
danger of destruction, and if the course of movement can be neither
controlled nor predicted, then how to produce a politics of affirmative
becoming without either getting bogged down in a regime of molar fascism
or falling foul to a fascistic logic of destruction?
In his Preface to Deleuze and Guattari's Anti-Oedipus, Michel Foucault
describes this text as a book of ethics that responds to the major enemy of
fascism. Being ‘anti-oedipal’, Foucault writes, ‘has become a life style, a
way of thinking and living’ to rid our speech, acts, hearts and pleasures of
fascism. ‘Anti-Oedipus is an Introduction to the Non-Fascist Life’ (Foucault
2004). It could be said that Deleuze and Guattari continue this project in the
second volume of Capitalism and Schizophrenia, A Thousand Plateaus, in
which they take up, pursue and perturb a Spinozan ethics to create a style of
politics/life free from fascism. Yet this work also indicates that the danger
of fascism looms incessantly and its force destroys irrevocably. Everything
happens on the same lines: the line of ‘destruction pure and simple’ at once
is/becomes a line of transversal connection creative of affirmative
difference.
Deleuze in turn finds an articulation of the problem of fascism in
Foucault's writings. In Foucault, he writes that the question of resistance to
power is (for Foucault) that of how to ‘cross the line’: how to create
transversal lines of resistance rather than integral lines of power? What
troubled Foucault is that transversal relations of resistance continue to
become restratified and encounter or even construct knots of power. If we
must attain a life that is the power of the outside, what tells us that this
outside is not a terrifying void and that this life, which seems to put up a
resistance, is not just the simple distribution within the void of ‘slow, partial
and progressive’ deaths? (Deleuze 2006).
Put differently, the question is how to avoid warding off one form of
fascism (macro-fascism) by getting bogged down in another form of
fascism (microfascism) or, as Deleuze and Guattari put it, ‘[w]hy does
desire desire its own repression, how can it desire its own repression?’
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 236–37). Only micro-fascism, they reply in A
Thousand Plateaus, provides an answer to this global question: it is because
everything happens on lines inextricably entangled and crossing over into
one another:
It is not that these lines are pre-existent; they are traced out, they are formed, immanent to each
other, mixed up in each other, at the same time as the assemblage of desire is formed, with its
machines tangled up and its planes intersecting. We don’t know in advance which one will
function as a line of gradient, or in what form it will be barred.
(Deleuze and Parnet 2006: 100)
It has become apparent that the line of flight, whilst simple and abstract, at
once constitutes the most complex and tortuous — and accordingly most
dangerous — line (Deleuze and Parnet 2006: 94). Moreover, ‘[i]n a
multilinear system, everything happens at once’ — in one move, the line
breaks free of points, coordinates and localisable connections (Deleuze and
Guattari 2004: 328, 322) — with the implication that ‘[n]o one can say
where the line of flight will pass’ (Deleuze and Parnet 2006: 276). Does it
remain consistent; does it get bogged down or arrested into another line;
does it turn abolitionary? One cannot predict in advance what may happen
on the line. Each type of line has modes of movement and organisation —
of ordering) and disordering) — specific to it, which can nevertheless be
evaluated only in relation and in play with the other lines. Each type of line
accordingly carries its own dangers.
Resort to the seeming predictability of segmentised categories on the
molar line (‘a rigidity which reassures us’) will not suffice to avoid the
dangers and insecurities intrinsic to the tortuosity of the line of flight. The
rigidity of segmentised categorisations such as the reduction of life's vital
and creative complexity to dualistic choices, and the (fascistic) politics to
which this may lead, is specific to the macro-fascism that occurs on the line
of molar segmentarity. It turns us into ‘creatures which are most fearful, but
also most pitiless and bitter’. These excesses give impetus to and render of
great pertinence resistance against molar regimes of power. At the same
time, however, it will not suffice simply to blow up the molar line in a
movement of deterritorialisation or flight. ‘Even if we had the power to
blow it up,’ Deleuze and Parnet ask, ‘could we succeed in doing so without
destroying ourselves, since it is so much part of the conditions of life,
including our organism and our very reason?’ Resisting macro-fascisms
must be an effort of long labour and immense prudence — an effort not
simply to explode, but to manipulate, soften, divert and undermine the
molar line — directed at prevailing forms of order(ing) and organisation
both in the form of the state or order of governance and in the form of the
organisms that we are ourselves.
The line of supple segmentarity not only carries the dangers of the molar
line in miniaturised form but also holds its own. Referred to by Deleuze and
Guattari as the ‘black hole phenomenon’, this form of micro-fascism sees
one passing thresholds of deterritorialisation too quickly, without taking
sufficient precautions; one constructs a black hole, ‘with a self-assurance
about his own case, his role and his mission…: the Stalins of little groups,
local law-givers, micro-fascisms of gangs’ (Deleuze and Parnet 2006: 104).
Finally, lines of flight, in addition to the macro-fascistic dangers of the first
line and the micro-fascisms of the second, also have the most dangerous
potential of turning into lines of abolition — of destruction of oneself and
of others. The examples cited by Deleuze and Guattari/Parnet suggest that
lines of flight are more prone to end in suicidal destruction than to produce
life-affirmative movements of becoming. To the question why their
examples are all of lines of flight turning out badly, Deleuze and
Guattari/Parnet reply that it is precisely because they are real and not
imaginary — i.e. not due to the intervention of other lines but on their own
account; on account of the abolitionary force intrinsic and specific to them:
‘Kleist and his suicide pact, Hölderin and his madness, Fitzgerald and his
destruction, Virginia Woolf and her disappearance’ (Deleuze and Parnet
2006: 105).
The three types of lines, albeit distinct in their modes of movement and
organisation — and hence in the dangers intrinsic to each — are entangled
in a complex play of movements/relations, in which lines clash and merge,
fracture and mix, produce and destroy and turn into one another. According
to Deleuze and Guattari/Parnet, it is this complexity, relationality and
mobility that explains why resistance against the stifling power of macro-
fascistic forces is often productive of yet more and different fascisms (in
molecular form). It is as a function of the deep entanglement of lines in play
— and hence of modes of being and becoming — that desire desires its own
repression. The problem of fascism accordingly becomes a complex play
ungraspable and irresolvable through dualistic oppositions such as fascism
versus non-fascism or macro-fascism versus micro-fascism.
An answer to the question why desire desires its own repression is
therefore to be found in the entanglement of lines or of modes of being and
becoming: because everything happens on the same lines, which are
inextricably caught up in one another and continuously clashing and
turning into one another. Due to the complexity, relationality and mobility
of this play, one cannot predict in advance what will happen on the line(s).
One cannot know beforehand where or how a line(-play) will run, turn, mix,
clash, abort, create, destroy, become, etc. Here arises the political paradox.
How to construct a politics when the greatest promise at once constitutes
the most perilous danger, and when one cannot know in advance how things
will (continue to) turn?
The introduction of the concept of the milieu will serve to shed more
light on this political problematique of lines in play. Albeit not articulated in
those terms by Deleuze and Guattari /Parnet, the play can be described
usefully in terms of milieux. Put succinctly, the molar line of rigid
segmentarity establishes a territorial order (the milieu as territorial
environment), whilst the line of supple segmentarity (the milieu as a
medium of action) swings between this order and the line of flight (the
milieu as movement in-between (au milieu)). Articulated thus, the play of
lines expresses the political paradox qua fascism: the line of flight is both
most creative and most dangerous, and hence not salvatory in itself,
whereas molar segmentarity constitutes both a requirement and the
impossibility of the becoming of the line of flight. This problem equally
confronts regimes of governance and forces of resistance. How to govern or
resist if lines continue to cross over into one another, and if the outcome
cannot be predicted in advance? How to govern or resist if the chances are
rife that one may end up in a black hole or on a line of destruction?
If everything happens on the same line(s), the distinction to be drawn is
not between lines of governance as opposed to lines of resistance. Rather,
attention must be paid to the movements and forces at play in particular
milieux. For example, how do lines and milieux produce, create, delineate
and adjudicate in the different orders of governance identified by Foucault
— sovereignty, discipline and security? Deleuzean onto-political
productions of lines and milieux run the risk of disregarding the evolution
of forms of (liberal) rule and the specificity of the ways in which the lines
play out in different regimes of power. Foucault's dispositif de sécurité
serves to ground and contextualise the plays of lines. It also raises the
question of what marks out the contemporary order, specifically in relation
to the entry of complexity in the domains of life and politics: how to govern
if life is emergent, continuously becoming beyond the bounds of its own
being?
The dynamic proposition, too, stresses that ‘[y]ou will not define a body (or
a mind) by its form, nor by its organs or functions, and neither will you
define it as a substance or a subject’. Rather than subjects, bodies are
capacities for affecting and being affected (Deleuze 1988: 123–24). The
question, accordingly, is ‘of what is a body capable?’ The problem is that
one cannot know this in advance because life is becoming.
Understood through Deleuze's Spinoza a body never stands on its own; it
is not an entity with certain properties, an internal organisation and external
boundaries that distinguish it from other entities and the environment.
Rather a body is defined by its modes of relationality; by the kinds of
connections that are established and the modes of engagement of which
these movements are productive. It is a question of what a body can do —
of its relations of movement and rest as well as its powers to affect and be
affected, which is to say that what a body can do is not fixed or determined
but a matter of becoming(s).3
Of relevance in conceptualising bodies are therefore not organs,
functions, species or genus. In a lecture on Spinoza Deleuze asserts that:
[i]f you consider beasts, Spinoza will be firm in telling us what counts among animals is not at all
the genera or species; genera and species are absolutely confused notions, abstract ideas. What
counts is the question, of what is a body capable? And thereby he sets out one of the most
fundamental questions in his whole philosophy… by saying that we don’t even know what a body
is capable of… a body must be defined by the ensemble of relations which compose it.4
Significant for Deleuze is the question of the powers of the body that
pertain to it. Most important is to know which encounters agree with one's
body; and most beautiful ‘is to live on the edges’, at the (joyful) limit of
one's powers to be affected. Because this limit differs for each body —
‘What counts is what your power is for you’ — no formula can be specified
that is good for each and every body. Moreover, a body being defined in
terms of relations of movement and rest and powers to affect and be
affected, degrees and limits of power continuously change. Deleuze thus
accords to Spinoza an ethics of becoming.
Spinoza becomes the thinker who poses the question of what a body can
do in terms of movement/rest and powers to affect/be affected. Hence, what
a body can do is a matter of its relationality. Defining the body thus, the
political problematique re-emerges:
We know nothing about a body until we know what it can do, in other words, what its affects are,
how they can or cannot enter into composition with other affects, with the affects of another body.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 284)
Notes
References
Ansell Pearson, K. Germinal Life. The Difference and Repetition of
Deleuze (Oxford and New York: Routledge, 1999)
Bergson, H. Creative Evolution (New York: Cosimo, 2005)
Bergson, H.Matter and Memory (New York: Zone Books, 1991)
Deleuze, G. ‘What Children Say’, in Essays Critical and Clinical,
trans. Daniel W.Smith and Michael A.Greco (London and New York:
Verso, 1998)
Deleuze, G.‘Spinoza, 24/01/1978’, Les Cours the Gilles Deleuze,
www.webdeleuze.com (accessed 10 June 2010).
Deleuze, G. Bergsonism (New York: Zone Books, 1991)
Deleuze, G.Cinema I, The Movement-Image (London: The Athlone
Press, 1986)
Deleuze, G.Foucault (London and New York: Continuum, 2006)
Deleuze, G. Negotiations: 1972–1990 (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1995)
Deleuze, G. Spinoza: Practical Philosophy (San Francisco: City Lights
Books, 1988)
Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. A Thousand Plateaus. Capitalism and
Schizophrenia (London and New York: Continuum, 2004)
Deleuze, G. and Parnet, C. Dialogues II (London and New York:
Continuum, 2006)
Deuber-Mankowsky, A. ‘Nothing is Political, Everything Can Be
Politicized: On the Concept of the Political in Michel Foucault and
Carl Schmitt’ (Telos No.142, Spring 2008, 135–161)
Dillon, M. and Lobo-Guerrero, L. ‘The Biopolitical Imaginary of
Species-being’ (Theory, Culture & Society Vol.26, No.1, 2009)
Dillon, M. and Reid, J. The Liberal Way of War. Killing to Make Life
Live (London and New York: Routledge, 2009)
Foucault, M. Power/Knowledge. Selected Interviews and Other
Writings, 1972–77 (New York: Pantheon, 1980)
Foucault, M.‘The Subject and Power’, in James D.Faubion (ed.)
Power, The Essential Works of Michel Foucault 1954–1984, Volume 3
(London: Penguin, 2002)
Foucault, M. ‘Preface’, in GillesDeleuze and FélixGuattari, Anti-
Oedipus. Capitalism and Schizophrenia (London and New York:
Continuum, 2004)
Foucault, M. Security, Territory, Population, Lectures at the Collège de
France, 1977–78 (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007)
Grosz, Elizabeth A. The Nick of Time: Politics, Evolution and the
Untimely (London and Durham: Duke University Press, 2004)
Guerlac, S. Thinking in Time. An Introduction to Henri Bergson (Ithaca
and London: Cornell University Press, 2006)
Marks, J. ‘Introduction’, in Deleuze and Science, special issue
(Paragraph, A Journal of Modern Critical Theory, Vol.29, No.2, 2006)
Massumi, B. ‘Notes on the Translation and Acknowledgements’, in
GillesDeleuze and FelixGuattari, A Thousand Plateaus. Capitalism
and Schizophrenia (London and New York: Continuum, 2004)
8 Fascist lines of the tokkōtai
Nicholas Michelsen
DOI: 10.4324/9780203374702-9
Introduction
In fascism the State is far less totalitarian than it is suicidal.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 254)
The third line of fascism (its ‘suicidal line of flight’) completes the schema
developed in A Thousand Plateaus. Deleuze and Guattari argue that in
relation to the third fascist line ‘the dangers of all the other lines pale by
comparison’. Furthermore, they are clear that whilst the third line emerges
from the supple yet nonetheless territorial (i.e. paranoiac) segmentations of
microfascist molecularity, its dynamics are deterritorialising or
schizophrenic. For Deleuze and Guattari, the Nazi fascist event entailed a
suicidally schizophrenic ‘war-machine taking over the state’ (Deleuze and
Guattari 2004b: 254).
Deleuze and Guattari explicitly bind this element of their account into the
hypothetical framework developed in the Treatise on Nomadology, in which
paranoiac ‘state apparatus’ is distinguished from essentially schizophrenic
‘warmachines’ (Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 253). In the Nomadology, a
state apparatus is identified as determined by an ‘abstract machine of
overcoding’. State orders, they argue, are fundamentally based on a regime
of interiorisation, hinging on the two-headed disciplinarity of policing and
taxation that allows a territory to be organised and dominated. States striate
space, so as to code and over-code desiring flows to serve a despotic
function. The state is an abstract machine for molar and molecular striation.
War-machines, on the other hand, are determined by an ‘abstract machine
of mutation’. This abstract machine is qualitatively and ‘quantifiably’
different in function to the machine of paranoiac overcoding,
deterritorialising desiring flows rather than reterritorialising them (Deleuze
and Guattari 2004b: 564). ‘The war-machine’ is the diagram of any and
every function which actualises an abstract machine of mutation. Any
assemblage which emits lines of flight, ‘quanta of deterritorialisation’ or
‘mutant flows’, whether social, cultural, aesthetic, political or/and
economic, is understood by Deleuze and Guattari as having built a war-
machine to do so (Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 253).
War machines, as they define them, set up a ‘smooth space’ within which
(social, economic, sexual, artistic) flows can circulate and spring up at any
point. This is why they are intrinsically linked to creativity or productivity
for Deleuze and Guattari (always a function of deterritorialisation). The
fundamental function of the war-machine is to construct and occupy smooth
space for unconstrained flux. Deleuze and Guattari ascribe the ‘invention’
of the war-machine to nomadic, pre- or non-territorial social systems. This
must not be taken to imply that war-machines are solely built by pre-
modern nomadic societies.When any practice is productive of new flows it
has necessarily built a smooth space, and thus employs a war-machine;
there are purely aesthetic warmachines such aswriting andmusic.War
machinesmaximise fluxion by allowing a form to occupy geography
(whether physical, intellectual, artistic, or social) without building an
interiorised (striated molar-molecular) territory upon it.
Actual war, as an exercise of force, appears in this hypothetical
discussion as the means by which nomadic orders build and defend smooth
spaces against territorial state apparatus. War is what war-machines engage
in when faced by the interiorising (reterritorialising) praxis of a state
apparatus. War, as such, is originally an anti-state function. By extension,
war is understood as only the ‘supplement’ of the war-machine, rather than
its originary purpose or fundamental essence. War is directed at the
paranoiac barriers to nomadic fluxion, and originally serves no other
purpose than to allow a war-machine to build and occupy smooth space.
War machines are only given war as their exclusive object by states. State
apparatus seeks to harness the capacity to wage war to aid in the
construction of territoriality. Consequentially they seek to capture, under
their system of interiorisation, the war-machine. In doing so, they over-code
that war-machine with its supplemental destructive function (as in
Clausewitz's dictum, making war serve as a means to state ends). When a
state apparatus co-opts awar-machine it short-circuits it, ‘divest[ing] the
war-machine of its power of metamorphosis’, and ‘substitute[ing]
destruction for mutation’ (Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 253).
Once affected, this capture of awar-machine by the state apparatus is
instantly vulnerable to a counter-coup due to a ‘catastrophic charge’
released (Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 253). Once a war-machine is given
war as its sole objective it can all too easily, Deleuze and Guattari argue, set
off on a line that is so absolute in its focus that the state in question is no
longer able to determine and code its directionality. Harnessing war ‘as a
means to a state end’ always entails the (supplemental) risk of becoming a
total or pure war. In pure or total war the warmachine's power of
metamorphosis returns as a perverse monstrosity; an overwhelming urge to
radical abolition of self and others which co-opts the state and sets it upon
an apocalyptically suicidal trajectory: the unlimited essence of war (as an
act of force) that Clausewitz identified is now given free rein (Reid 2006:
294).
When Deleuze asks, ‘why is the [creative] line of flight a war one risks
coming back from defeated, destroyed, after having destroyed everything
one could’, he is not using war simply as a ‘metaphor’ (Deleuze 2002: 140–
41). Rather Deleuze and Guattari argue that a suicidal pure war is a danger
integral to any deterritorialisation. Whilst we must deterritorialise or
smooth space to create (and thus build war-machines), that movement, at its
logical limit, potentially results in the suicidal dissolution of self (which
reflects the surrender of the war-machine to its anti-productive supplement):
‘War is like the fall or failure of mutation, the only object left for the war-
machine after it has lost its power to change’ (Deleuze and Guattari 2004b:
253). Suicide is the supplement that may be built on any line of flight given
the correct (unlimited) conditions, such as, but not limited to, the short-
circuiting of a warmachine by a state apparatus.
Just as molarity carries with it the risk of instituting state-totalitarian or
despotic social arrangements and molecularity carries with it the risk of
forming little black holes of microfascist certainty, all lines of flight open to
suicidal excess (Deleuze 2002: 140–41). This is a crucial point, clarifying
that both paranoiac and schizophrenic processes have integral risks or
dangers. At the state level the danger on the third line manifests in the
catastrophic charge released when a state apparatus is captured by its war-
machine and set to pure war, but Deleuze and Guattari develop, in A
Thousand Plateaus, numerous examples of the integral association between
art's attempts to build smooth space and the tragic ends to which artists are
often inexorably drawn (Deleuze 2002: 61; Deleuze and Guattari 2004b:
208, 220, 227, 330). Their point is not that warmachines are suicidal rather
than productive, but that the productivity of warmachines (in building and
occupying smooth space) carries with it a suicidal danger that resides on all
lines of flight (just as a ‘totalitarian danger’ resides on all molar lines and a
‘microfascist danger’ resides on all molecular lines).
All lines of flight or deterritorialisation conceal suicide as ‘a danger
which is proper to them’, and this danger manifests itself in a variety of
ways (Deleuze 2002: 140–41).1 For Deleuze and Guattari there are suicidal
lines of flight in political assemblages which are not fascist (at the level of
the individual, aesthetic and evolutionary/organic as well as social). The
broader significance of this argument for Deleuze and Guattari's general
thesis on politics and creativity/deterritorialisation in A Thousand Plateaus
cannot be sufficiently engaged here; constraints on space insist that the
argument remain tightly focused on the sustainability of their theory of
fascism. Nonetheless, there is no doubt that it is the broader political
consequences of Deleuze and Guattari's claim that schizophrenia has an
integral danger which have called up such widespread antipathy to the idea
of a third fascist line, as the following section will outline.
Regarding fascism, Deleuze and Guattari's point seems clear: beyond
assembling the dangers on the molar and the molecular into a resonating
paranoiac machine, Nazism built a line of flight into suicidal pure war.
Fascism as a general category, for Deleuze and Guattari, is defined by the
realisation of the dangers on all three lines of the political real — molar,
molecular and flight. What gives fascism its difference (from
totalitarianism) is the third line, which ensures that it always establishes
suicidal states.
Fascist suicide
Long live death!
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 254)
Deleuze and Guattari are clear that what they refer to in this passage is
more than simply the work of an over-coding totalitarian ideology.2 Rather,
the war-machine that was established within the resonating microfascist
segmentarity of German society carried within it an unlimited potentiality
which was only to be fully released with the onset of total war but clearly
pre-existed it. That frenzied line of flight manifested in a suicidalism both at
the political and ‘at the economic level, where arms expansion replaces
growth in consumption and where investment veers from the means of
production towards the means of pure destruction’ (Deleuze and Guattari
2004b: 254). The ‘paradox’ of fascism is that it was defined, from the start,
not by its totalitarianism, but by a ‘reversion of the line of flight into a line
of destruction’ that always animated its foundational molecular
segmentarity (Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 253, 255).
To contain its mutant flows, the Nazi regime had sought to stabilise its
warmachine within the resonant void of the totalitarian state, trapping a
mutation machine within a militaristic narrative of national rebirth. By
attempting to harness this schizo-function to a paranoiac order, a short-
circuited or cancerous line of flight is set up (militarised re-birth as a
corruption of the mutational impetus). By the 1940s, following this line, the
Nazi state had been entirely set to total war, now explicitly pursuing the
radical politics of abolition which proceeds from the paranoiac attempt to
over-code the war-machine with its anti-productive supplement.
By short-circuiting a line of flight through a molecular segmentarity and
a molar centrality, Nazism built a fully ‘suicidal-state’. Hitler's telegram 71,
which declaimed ‘If the war is lost, may the nation perish’, was the ‘normal
outcome’ of this particular assemblage of the lines. Turned to total war, the
Nazi state apparatus became little more than an appendage of its suicidal
war-machine (Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 253).
Paul Virilio's analysis strikes us as entirely correct in defining fascism not by the notion of the
totalitarian state but by the notion of the suicidal state: so-called total war seems less a state
undertaking than an undertaking of a war-machine that appropriates the State and channels into it
a flow of absolute war whose only possible outcome is the suicide of the state itself… It was this
reversion of the line of flight into a line of destruction that already animated the molecular focuses
of fascism, and made them interact in a war-machine instead of resonating in a state apparatus. A
war-machine that no longer had anything but war as its object and would rather annihilate its own
servants than stop the destruction. All the dangers of the other lines pale by comparison.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 255)
Conclusion
We cannot say that one of these three lines is bad and another good, by nature and necessarily.
The study of the dangers of each line is the object of pragmatics or schizoanalysis, to the extent
that it undertakes not to represent, interpret, or symbolize, but only to draw maps, marking their
mixture as well as their distinctions.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004b: 250)
It should be clear from this chapter that mobilising Deleuze and Guattari's
‘theory of fascism’ need not be reduced to searching out events that directly
repeat the Nazi rise to power. Rather, their cartographical schema enjoins us
to map fascisms in terms of their contingent assemblage of the danger of all
three lines of the political: molar, molecular and flight.
Holland argues that the rise of the Bush regime demonstrates that a late-
modern capitalist post-fascist regime can collapse or regress into fascism-
proper: ‘Postfascism can in certain circumstances give way to a resurgence
of something like old-fashioned fascism’ (Holland 2008: 94). This
argument is put to the service of a partisan politics, whereby Holland
contrasts the ‘old-fashioned fascism’ of the Bush Republicans with the
‘post-fascist’ biopolitics of the Clinton Democrats. Indeed, he argues that
the palingenic scapegoating of the Bush regime renders the subtler
disciplinarity of post-fascism relatively preferable.
To some extent Holland is surely right to direct our attention to the
paranoiac power of the religious-conservative resonance machine in the
United States. Such totalitarian-religious political assemblages may
conjugate their molar and molecular lines to build machines that seem to
approach the status of fascist phenomena (as in Iran, for example), but to
reduce, as Holland does, the third fascist line in Deleuze and Guattari's
schema to a contingency of Nazism is to miss a crucial dimension of their
political cartography of fascism as entailing both reterritorialisations and
deterritorialisations. This has determinant significance if we are to extend
their theory of fascism whilst remaining faithful to their brief comments in
A Thousand Plateaus about the ‘post-fascist’ assemblage of contemporary
politics.
Having disaggregated the suicidal line from the peculiarities of the Nazi
fascist event by outlining its corresponding function in the Meiji fascist
event, we must now set out to chart its evolutionary trajectory into the
present day. Deleuze and Guattari directly followed their analysis of
fascism with an account of the historical mutations which took place on its
third line (pure war) after the end of the Second World War. They are
explicit that fascist ‘suicidal states’ were ‘the child precursors’ of a global
politics of post-fascist suicide that renders such territorial formations
increasingly obsolete, initially, but not necessarily conclusively, through the
terrifying pure-peace of nuclear deterrence. For Deleuze and Guattari, state
fascism cannot simply be recapitulated because the suicidal line of flight
serves new functions within the global assemblage. Deleuze and Guattari
argued, following Virilio, that the bipolar war-machine of nuclear
deterrence set up a suicidal global regime of ‘pure-peace’ that categorically
displaces the suicidal national politics of fascistic ‘total-war’ (Deleuze and
Guattari 2004b: 465, 516).
The terrifying cold peace of deterrence has now passed, but this certainly
does not mean that the third line has disappeared from contemporary
politics. It is rather conjugated anew. Deleuze and Guattari's statement that
latecapitalist global order is ‘post-fascist’ is explicitly not positing the rise
of a non-fascist order. Rather fascism continues directly into the post-fascist
assemblage by way of global innovations of the suicidal line of flight. The
fascist line of flight (as total war) mutates, via the Cold War, into what
suggestively they term a ‘new conception of security as materialised war, as
organised insecurity or molecularized, distributed, programmed
catastrophe’, under which ‘the enemy’ is now defined precisely by its lack
of specificity, as a register of disorder per se (Deleuze and Guattari 2004b:
516). Holland is ill-advised to search for the legacy of fascism only in its
national repetition. He may well find here the echoes of the first two lines
resonating, but they do so today within the framework of a global war-
machine that has transformed state apparatus into cogs of its global bio-
security mechanism (see Hardt and Negri 2000; Dillon and Reid 2009).
Any contemporary fascism must be mapped in its relationship to this
problematic.
This chapter has limited itself to elucidating and provisionally confirming
the utility of Deleuze and Guattari's cartography of three fascist lines. By
affirming the validity of the schema in its original format, against critiques
such as Holland's (2008), it has re-opened the space for us to chart
contemporary fascist re-assemblages of the three lines in Deleuze and
Guattari's cartographic schema. Under the contemporary global regime of
catastrophic bio-insecurity, territorial conjugations of the molar and
molecular (in America and elsewhere) must be reinterpreted as moving
parts in a global war-machine that overdetermines them. If we wish to think
about ‘fascism today’ with Deleuze and Guattari we cannot neglect its
fundamental relationship to the protean global politics of suicide at work in
this ‘Anthropocene era’ (Zizek 2010: 189).Without doubt, broader
questions concerning the relationship between politics and suicide in the
work of Deleuze and Guattari call for further critical elaboration, but if we
are to mobilise their cartography in search of fascisms today the third
suicidal line cannot be neglected.
Notes
References
For Deleuze, this shift has the effect of liberating cinematic aesthetics.
However, this change in post-war aesthetics also mirrors a post-Fascist
problem of ‘agent-less’ violence and lack of affect. In A Thousand
Plateaus, Deleuze and Guattari assert that the potential towards fascism in
the form of microfascisms can spring up indiscriminately regardless of
religion, cultural background or nationality.3 for France, the fascist violence
experienced as a result of the German Occupation during the Second World
War had a lasting cultural effect leaving traces in both thought and
aesthetics. These memories returned powerfully during France's war in
Algeria, when France, a nation formerly subjugated to German fascism,
became the brutal suppressor of Algerian liberty. In April 1961 De Gaulle
invoked Article 16 to declare a state of emergency in response to the
increasingly aggravated outbreaks of violence caused by opposition to the
war (Agamben 2005: 14). In his theory of multidirectional cultural
discourses of aesthetics, Michael Rothberg writes that the use of torture in
Algeria re-awoke memories and echoes of the acts of inhumanity
committed by the Germans during the Occupation among former members
of the Resistance and, perhaps more surprisingly, state officials:
in submitting his resignation in 1957, the secretary general of the police in Algiers, Paul Teitgen, a
former deportee, wrote that he recognized in Algeria ‘profound traces … of the torture that
fourteen years ago I personally suffered in the basements of the Gestapo in Nancy’.
(Rothberg 2009: 193)
Fear
Deleuze and Guattari write that the first danger of fascism is fear: fear of
the loss of security or stability (Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 250). Fear
becomes visible in both films through the existence of a perceived threat to
security and the culture of suspicion and surveillance that sparks further
fear in turn. The corrosive cycle of fear and surveillance is endemic to and a
product of fascist ideology. It feeds the steadily growing sense of strained
anxiety that personal, social and state security is somehow being eroded.
Deleuze and Guattari cite Daniel Guérin who claims that Hitler was able to
seize power because the micro-organizations created by his followers
presented him with ‘an unequalled, irreplaceable ability to penetrate every
cell of society’ (Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 236). This claim conversely
brings alongside the notion of the ever-watchful eye of the authoritarian
state, famously theorized by Foucault in the Panopticon, with the idea that
somebody may be watching not to enforce the law but to infringe it. In
Cinema 2, Deleuze observes that the difference between pre- and post-war
cinema is the ‘rise of situations to which one can no longer react’. This
leads to the seer, voyant, replacing the agent, actant (Deleuze 1989: 272). In
The Raven, the scene in which Dr Germain, the town newcomer and main
protagonist, receives his first letter is shot through the keyhole from the
perspective of Rolande, a snooping teenage girl. Effectively, the spying
camera eye captures and enables a sliding axis of active and passive witness
that creates the atmosphere of secrecy and surveillance, which permeates
the action. The letters of denunciation issue from a mysterious figure, The
Raven, who is at once considered an outsider to the community and yet
holds detailed insider knowledge of seemingly everyone's affairs. It
transpires that all of the letters contain at least a grain of truth. The fear
created by this unnameable insider ‘other’ creates guilt and secrecy and
closes down communication, generating further suspicion. Vorzet, the
flamboyant psychiatrist and husband of Laura, the woman with whom the
letters accuse the protagonist, town newcomer Doctor Germain, of having
an affair, advises Germain not to trust anyone. Not only does the oppressive
silence of the population communicate suspicion, but it also suggests there
are unspoken secrets to hide. In the letters, The Raven claims that he is
purging society of its moral debauchery. However, the effect of the poison-
pen revelations is progressively to unravel the social fabric of rural St
Robin by revealing that a vast swath of its inhabitants from the highest to
the lowest echelons of society are involved in socially, ethically, politically
and legally compromising activities. Although The Raven is a self-
appointed champion of moral virtue, he is acting outside the jurisdiction of
the law. He is perceived therefore as an insider-other, a rogue element,
which has penetrated the town's defences and must be flushed out.
Hidden opens with a static shot of the rue d'Iris looking towards a classic
Parisian apartment building in the tranquil and affluent thirteenth district of
the city. The rumble of distant traffic and early morning birdsong are
broken only by the occasional cyclist, pedestrian, or passing car. However,
as the minutes pass the stasis and banality of this scene becomes
increasingly unsettling. French cultural critic Libby Saxton observes: ‘we
wonder who else, besides us, might be looking, and why’ (Saxton 2007: 7).
Our belief that we are watching the opening scene of the film is shattered
by the discovery that we, like Georges and Anne, the film's protagonists, are
watching a filmed recording of the outside of their apartment. The blurring
of film and reality is achieved by Haneke's election to shoot the film on
high-definition video making the tapes indistinct from real cinematic time.
This ‘framing’ technique continues throughout the film. The seamless
splicing of surveillance video footage into the film causes the viewer to
begin to mistrust and interrogate the image. As in The Raven, there is a
disturbing instability and lack of security conveyed by the uncertain
temporal and spatial positioning of both protagonists and viewers. In
Hidden this feeds a sense of growing paranoia about who is watching and
who is being watched. The viewer is placed on the inside, and becomes
conscious that he or she is not only subject but also an object of the gaze.
The camera eye rigidly limits the field of vision, forbidding off-screen sight
and increasing the sense of impossibility of escape from the controlling eye
and delimiting the possibility of accessing the ‘bigger picture’ to
contextualize the meaning of minutiae. The camera's oppressive gaze
composes an incomplete picture that is both suspicious and disconcerting.
In agreement with Saxton's reference to the ‘out-of-field’ vision in Caché,5
French cultural critic Max Silverman adds that the image is only readable
through a reconnection with the ‘hors-champ’:
Those who have acquired a way of reading the image will realise that far from the ending
withholding its hidden secret, it actually makes it readable, not in the sense of solving the
whodunit (that is neither here nor there), but in terms of the transformation of the image from a
screen to a Benjaminian constellation composed of complex interconnections between the visible
and the ‘hors champ’ and between present and past.
(Silverman 2010: 63)
Clarity
The movement of clarity is the second vector of fascism. Deleuze and
Guattari observe that through vision and sounds we begin to perceive
spaces or holes permeating structures that previously appeared solid:
That is precisely what clarity is: the distinctions that appear in what used to seem full, the holes in
what used to be compact; and conversely, where just before we saw end points of clear-cut
segments, now there are indistinct fringes, encroachments, overlappings, migrations, acts of
segmentation that no longer coincide with the rigid segmentarity. Everything now appears supple,
with holes in fullness, nebulas in forms and flutter in lines. Everything has the clarity of a
microscope. We think we have understood everything, and draw conclusions.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 251)
With clarity comes the realization that there are breaches in personal and
societal structures results in the deterioration of shared common values and
sense of community. The loss of belief in the transparency and integrity of
the law translates into the breakdown of law and objective morality. We are
both agents and objects enmeshed in and directed by quantum flows. In his
theory of the effects and management of violence in ancient societies, the
French cultural anthropologist, René Girard, uses the term ‘sacrificial crisis’
to signal a period of chaos, violence and revenge brought about by a lack of
difference between the ‘pure’ and the ‘impure’, or ‘good’ and ‘evil’. As
these spaces or holes erase the distinctions between individuals, mediation
fails. There is no one to act as mediator. This heralds the onset of
Agamben's ‘state of exception’. Agamben asserts that the situation of
‘iustitium’ in Roman law is aligned with the ‘state of exception’ or
emergency.
a citizen who acts during iustitium neither executes nor transgresses a law but inexecutes
[insegue] it. His actions, in this sense, are mere facts, the appraisal of which, once the iustitium is
expired, will depend on the circumstances. But as long as the iustitium lasts, they will be
absolutely undecidable, and the definition of their nature — whether executive or transgressive,
and, in the extreme case, whether human or bestial, or divine — will lie beyond the sphere of the
law.
(Agamben 2005: 50)
The result of the loss of the sovereign results in ‘charivari’, the suspension
of normal legal and social structures and hierarchies that accompanies
upheavals in political or social order. This is sometimes celebrated by
publicly performed parodies of law and justice. This moment brings about
the blurring of all differences already observed by Deleuze and Guattari and
Girard. In The Raven, law and order is effectively erased by the growing
frenzy for denunciation as no one is shown to be above suspicion. The
town's authority figures and care givers are slandered. The mayor is accused
of corruption and the chief doctor of the hospital and the hospital nurse are
accused of malpractice. The post office is inundated with letters addressed
in Raven-style handwriting, leading a post room worker to comment that
‘everyone is at it’. In Hidden, although initially portrayed as victimized
subject of surveillance, Georges, quickly becomes a suspect. His dismissal
of the first tape as a teenage prank, his refusal of Anne's suggestion that
they call the police, and later, the muted intimation that he may know the
provenance of the tapes and the violent child-like pictures that accompany
them suggest that he is hiding something. Similarly, other characters, Anne,
Pierrot, Majid and Majid's son, flatly deny accusations made against them
but also refuse to answer probing questions or to provide evidence to the
contrary. In The Raven and Hidden cracks appear in familial and social
units. Isolation reigns. The ‘clarity’ created by the blurring of differences is
a challenge to the established ethical order. The characters' motivations and
integrity come under scrutiny, intensifying the discourse surrounding
belonging and ‘otherness’ as it becomes increasingly unclear who is on the
inside ‘in the know’, and who remains outside ‘in the dark’. The permeation
and fluidity of these boundaries unleashes a sense of unbounded threat and
terror and engenders violence. In Deleuze and Guattari's depiction of
‘clarity’ chaos reigns and anyone can be a policeman or an SS.
Instead of the great paranoid fear, we are trapped in a thousand little monomanias, self-evident
truth and clarities that gush from very black hole and no longer form a system but are only rumble
and buzz, blinding light giving any and everybody the mission of self-appointed judge, dispenser
of justice, policeman, neighborhood SS man. We have overcome fear, we have sailed from the
shores of security, only to enter a system that is no less concentricized, no less organized: the
system of petty insecurities that leads everyone to their own black hole in which to turn
dangerous, possessing a clarity on their situation, role, and mission even more disturbing than the
certitudes of the first line.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 251)
Clarity, as a fascist line of flight, can therefore be seen to permeate the fixed
social boundaries of home, work and the ‘outside’. The eradication of
difference uproots former solidarities and undermines social and legal
infrastructures challenging their ethical precepts and asserting the need for
radical action through the personal dispensation of justice. Paxton observes
that fascism seeks to eradicate all borders between the public and the
private (Paxton 2004). In Hidden, the borders between personal and private
spaces are persistently transgressed. After Georges tracks down and
threatens Majid and his unnamed son in their home, Majid's son intercepts
Georges at his workplace and confronts him about his harassment of their
family. Later, when Pierrot, Georges's son disappears, Georges leads the
police to Majid's flat in Romainville, where the police roughly apprehend
Majid and his son. French cultural critic, Jefferson Kline observes:
Haneke seems to bring the film's fictional events into interpretative arrangement not only with the
long tradition of the Franco-Arab conflict, but also with the current dynamics of the ‘war on
terror’.
(Kline 2010: 588)
The analogy of contagion used in both films is suggestive of the germinant
potential of microfascisms to permeate all strata and perceived ‘boundaries’
of society. Contagion appears in the form of information. In The Raven, the
‘information’ contained in the letters literally ‘informs on’ other members
of the community and instigates further acts of community-orchestrated
‘agent-less’ violence. Vorzet plots the town's frenzy for denunciation on a
chart likening the spikes and falls in letter sending to the temperature of a
feverish patient. In Hidden, ‘information’ takes the form of visual media —
the videotapes, cinema and television — during Georges and Anne's
anxious discussion about their son Pierrot's failure to return home, the
television news, in the background, flashes images into the family home of
the war in Iraq, torture in Abu Ghraib and the Asian bird flu epidemic. The
television screen is framed by the ceiling-to-floor bookshelves that decorate
the dining room, mirroring the set of the literary TV show that Georges
presents. It is in the report on the threat of a global bird flu pandemic that
the word caché (hidden), the film's title, is blurted into the couple's dining
room. Here fascist lines of flight permeate the ‘inside-outside’ boundaries
of the family's social, cultural and personal space spreading contagion or
virus. As Deleuze and Guattari point out, ‘What makes fascism dangerous
is its molecular or micropolitical power, for it is a mass movement: a
cancerous body rather than a totalitarian organism’ (Deleuze and Guattari
2004: 236). This plague-like power of fascism is vividly evoked by the last
lines of Albert Camus's The Plague, where Dr Rieux observes the town's
people's jubilation that the plague, widely considered to stand as an allegory
for Nazi oppression, has ended. Rieux observes that the plague can never be
truly expelled but instead lies dormant within the fabric of society.6 The
cultural implications of Western microfascist complicity in the occupation
of Iraq, acts of torture carried out by American soldiers and the endemic
nature of a potential global pandemic resonate powerfully with Georges and
Anne's feeling of fearful impotence at their son's potential abduction by
their stalker. However, in both films the superfluity of information in text
and image suggests not only the impossibility of holing up the spaces and
fluidity of the structures underpinning individual and societal relations by
revealing that the perceived dividing lines between the inner worlds and the
world outside are organic and permeable, but also reveals the emptiness of
the information that informs us of this. In Cinema 2, Deleuze observes that
the ‘nullity of information must be overturned in order to defeat Hitler’
(Deleuze 1989: 269). ‘Information’ in neither film is in fact the creator of
chaos but rather a conduit that reveals the porous and open boundaries
within individual, social and cultural identities and societal structures.
However, the becoming viral of information releases its potential as object
and vehicle of fascist violence.
Power
‘Power’, the third danger identified by Deleuze and Guattari, relates to the
questions of agency, complicity and impotence. Deleuze and Guattari
observe that power and impotence are alternating currents that run between
and connect the poles of power.
Every man of power jumps from one line to the other alternating between a petty and
grandiloquent style, drugstore demagoguery and the imperialism of the high-ranking government
man. But this whole chain and web of power is immersed in a world of mutant flows that eludes
them. It is precisely its impotence that makes power so dangerous.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 252)
In the films, the notion of power is related to both personal and cultural
history. Past power dynamics determine present behaviours and choices.
This bears loaded implications for the future. In The Raven, rather than
revealing the secret ‘true morality’ of the heavily stereotyped characters,
Clouzot fills in the caricatures bringing them to life. It transpires that
Germain, the morally conservative scientist, is concealing his former
identity as a famous brain surgeon, following the tragic and traumatic death
of both his wife and first child in childbirth. As a result, he demonstrates
immense difficulty in forming emotional attachments, declaring at one point
that he has ‘neither friends nor enemies’. It turns out that Denise, the
vampish femme fatale, has conducted numerous love affairs in an attempt to
allay feelings of ugliness and bitterness about her ugly, deformed clubfoot,
which is the result of a childhood accident. Marie Corbin, the spinster
nurse, who is initially suspicious of Germain's intentions towards her sister
Laura and of Laura's responsiveness to his advances, is revealed to harbour
real feelings of jealousy towards her sister, who has married Vorzet, Marie's
former fiancé. The characters' present actions are therefore determined by
their pasts. These histories are concealed, however, because their revelation
could potentially sow seeds of suspicion about whether the motivating force
behind the malicious letter writing may be the settling of old scores. The
characters are rendered impotent and mute by past events over which they
have no power. It is notable that the film's frame of reference extends
beyond the screen to Occupied France, where the political choices of the
film's audience were also being stifled and suppressed by Raven-like Nazi
control. The film is further steeped in questions about complicity and power
as Henri-Georges Clouzot, the director, was working for Continental Films,
an allegedly French company, which employed French actors and directors
and produced French-language films, but was in fact financially supported
by Goebbels's propaganda ministry.7 At the time of the film's release,
despite being a huge success with audiences, The Raven was criticized by
Vichy, the Resistance and the Germans.
This was not a picture of healthy provincial life as Vichy conceived it, and it is not surprising that
the film was criticized by the Vichy press for traducing all the icons of the National Revolution.
Nor was the film ever released in Germany: it was judged to be morbid, and the authorities could
not approve a film that implicitly criticized delation. But criticisms in the Resistance press were
no less strident: it vilified the film for portraying such a debased image of France.
(Jackson 2001: 325)8
In both films, the desire for totalitarian-type oppression is borne out of the
inextricable complicity of discovering oneself as an historical cog in the
machine. Thus the dream of absolute disempowerment, which desires the
negation of responsibility, emerges with the awareness of the potential
revolutionary power of one's acts. The characters experience feelings of
impotence and victimization as they become further enmeshed in the
politics of power through acts of fascist violence. Here, we see the organic
evolution of the fascist power dialectic. The suppression of the past and the
violent mobilization of powerlessness as justification for current actions is
evidence of this tendency. This vector makes victims into perpetrators and
vice versa. Alonso illustrates the way in which the claim to collective
victimhood promotes and excuses acts of violence in programs like
Lebensraum, the manifest destiny, la mission civilisatrice, the Full
Spectrum Dominance of the American neoconservative PNAC (Plan for a
New American Century), Greater Serbia, Eretz Israel, to cite a few
examples, ‘sufferings real or perceived, have more power than joy to
compact individuals into social blocks, on the one side, and to the
comparative advantage of negative emotions on the other’, thus ‘the group
provides a context that renders aggressive behaviour socially acceptable and
normatively appropriate’ (Alonso 2011: 15). In both films, characters
attempt to renegotiate and seize power by reterritorializing fascist lines of
flight through the persecution of scapegoats. In The Raven, realizing that
they are failing in flushing out the letter writer, the town's people begin to
pursue instead the main targets of The Raven's allegations. Thus nurse
Marie Corbin is sacked and pursued from the hospital to her ransacked
house by a jeering, violent mob, at which point she is apprehended and
imprisoned. Similarly, the town council try to oust Dr Germain by
attempting to trick him into performing an illegal abortion, a crime of which
the letters accuse him. Finally, in an act of vengeance, the mother of a
cancer patient who committed suicide after receiving a letter confirming his
condition was terminal, murders Vorzet believing him to be The Raven. In
Hidden, Georges determines that Majid is the source of the videotapes and
pictures and embarks on a campaign of terror by tracking down and
threatening both him and his son. Saxton observes:
Ironically it is in the course of attempting to establish his innocence that Georges inadvertently
reveals his guilt, and begins to merit punishment. The videotapes start to catch him out, capturing
his contemptuous treatment of Majid and exposing his denials and protestations of ignorance as
half-truths or, on occasion, barefaced lies. At stake here are not the falsehoods of a selfish six-
year-old but an adult's refusal to confront and acknowledge responsibility for the consequences of
his past actions.
(Saxton 2007: 10)
They recall the Nazi announcement that the Socialist movement would
bring wedding bells and death to Germany. The lines of flight that mobilize
microfascisms are simultaneously the stirrers of mass movements and
revolution. Elsewhere Deleuze and Guattari describe the transformational
movement of a line of flight as a war machine. Only when the line turns to
war as end does it take on a fascist nihilism thus losing all creative power
and becoming bent purely on destruction.
war is like the fall or failure of mutation, the only object left for the war machine after it has lost
its power to change. War, it must be said, is only the abominable residue of the war machine,
either after it has allowed itself to be appropriated by the State apparatus, or even worse, has
constructed itself a State apparatus capable only of destruction. When this happens, the war
machine no longer draws mutant line of flight, but a pure, cold line of abolition.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 253)
A permanent state of war is therefore both the end and necessary condition
of fascism. Deleuze and Guattari observe the desolation and desperation
generated by fascist movements: ‘They themselves emanate a strange
despair, like an odor of death and immolation, a state of war from which
one returns broken’ (Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 252).
This theme of destructive violence is borne out in The Raven by the
earlier-mentioned suicide of one of the hospital patients after a letter from
The Raven informs him that he has terminal cancer. This act bears the
hallmark of despair and impotent resignation and submission to a greater
force. In Hidden, Georges reacts to the horror of witnessing Majid slit his
own throat by seeking out the dark, escapist sanctuary of the cinema. The
security of filmic fiction literally screens Georges from reality. It satisfies a
conservative orthodoxy providing a distance from the question of Georges's
agency and complicity in Majid's death. However, Hidden does not provide
such a distance. Cinema and digital culture are shown here to act against
Deleuze's reading of Artaud. The unthinkingness of the characters'
engagements with these media breeds affect-less microfascist tendencies.
Once at home, Georges takes sleeping tablets, cachets, a further homonym
of the film's title, in an attempt to distance consciousness of reality and
conscience. Majid's suicide is shocking not only because the graphic throat-
slitting scene is totally unanticipated but also because of the violence that
emanates from this act. Previously we described Majid as a scapegoat, a
victim of an iustitium, a state of exception that has wreaked chaos in
Georges's world or a surrogate victim, to use Giraud's phrase, of Georges's
microfascist tendencies. Yet, there is a further level to this act. Majid's
suicide is borne out of desperation at the violent persecution to which
Georges has subjected him as a cultural outsider both during their childhood
and now again in their adult lives. In this sense, the nihilism that emanates
from Majid's act aims at forcing Georges to face the consequences of his
own campaign of terror through further horror. Majid's suicide plots a
microfascist trajectory as it allows him to seize agency reterritorializing the
microfascism demonstrated by Georges's acts by transforming it into his
own deterritorializing fascist line. This movement coincides with Deleuze
and Guattari's observation that, ‘Suicide is presented not as a punishment
but as the crowning glory of the death of others’ (Deleuze and Guattari
2004: 254). It is pertinent to this argument that the viewer is also forced to
witness the act of suicide as Majid gives no intimation of his intentions,
thus there is no ‘look away now’ prelude to the act. As a consequence, like
Georges, the audience is also forced into a shocked complicit collusion in
Majid's suffering and death. In The Raven, the slitting of Vorzet's throat by
the mother of the suicide victim in vengeance for her son's suicide must also
be considered a fascist line of flight. While this act ends the film and Dr
Germain declares that it solves the mystery, in fact it leaves a number of
questions unanswered. Earlier in the film, Vorzet points out that it is highly
unlikely that the 850 letters received during the two-month spate of
denunciation were the work of just one person. Both Denise and Laura
separately admit to writing letters and, at the height of the letter-writing
frenzy, a post office worker observes that ‘everyone is at it’. Although
Vorzet dies at his desk writing a Raven-style letter declaring that the town's
curse has been lifted, rather than an end to violence, I would suggest that
this act symbolizes a mutation of the vector of microfascist violence. It
perpetuates the cycle of violence by jumping the strain spiralling and
transforming victim into perpetrator. It thus bears a latent, threatening
legacy for the future. The Raven concludes with an over-the-shoulder shot
of Dr Germain looking out from the window over Vorzet's desk, where the
psychiatrist lies in a pool of blood, watching the suspected killer, the mother
of the cancer patient, make her way down the sunny street. This open
ending suggests a kind of ‘going underground’, which is, as we have
observed, a germinant trait of microfascisms.
Fascist lines foster new violence and seed new microfascisms. Slavoj
Zizek postures that the war on terror is not perhaps after all targeted at
terrorists but at tacitly reterritorializing and consolidating the precepts of
Western democracy and identity among Westerners by inflecting the rise of
the anti-globalist movement with fears over security and power (Zizek
2004). Perhaps this is not even a distraction. By indulging in the bloody
horror and the full and raw exposure of the Western masses to the
‘deterritorializing’ dissension and instability of the Middle East, the war on
terror and now the Arab Spring make us treasure our own increasingly
restricted freedoms and accept as a necessity the tightening control of their
borders. In this vein, it is interesting to reflect on how the subversive and
persistent deterritorializations and microfascisms of Occupied France
implicitly illustrated in The Raven return in a different guise relating to the
colonial and post-colonial debates of the 1960s and as part of a twenty-first-
century discourse on cultural integration and Arab-Islamist terrorism in
Hidden. This evolution of microfascisms resonates against the
reterritorializations of French politico-cultural history by French historians
such as Robert Aron (1958). However, the cultural inheritance of fascist
complicities is clearly not limited to France alone. Paxton affirms that
fascism exists within all democratic countries.
‘Giving up free institutions,’ especially the freedoms of unpopular groups, is recurrently attractive
to citizens of Western democracies, including some Americans. We know from tracing its path
that fascism does not require a spectacular ‘march’ on some capital to take root; seemingly
anodyne decisions to tolerate lawless treatment of national ‘enemies’ is enough.
(Paxton 2004: 220)
Hidden also provides insight into and critical commentary of other national
histories and cultural memories beyond France, as Silverman observes:
Haneke has argued that Caché works just as effectively as an indictment of other cultural
heritages: ‘I don't want my film to be seen as specifically about a French problem. It seems to me
that, in every country, there are dark corners — dark stains where questions of collective guilt
become important. I'm sure in the United States there are other parallel examples of dark stains on
the collective unconscious.’
(Silverman 2010: 63, note 4)
Haneke's 2010 film The White Ribbon implicitly explores the reasons
behind the rise of Nazism in Germany though the lens of a series of violent
events in a small village at the eve of the First World War that appear to
have been orchestrated by the local children. Similarly, Haneke observes
that this film is not simply an indictment of Germany's past but also serves
as an allegory for harrowing and shameful events and periods in other
countries' pasts (Cinefilms 2010).
So far, in this analysis of Deleuze and Guattari's four dangers of fascism
we have followed lines that lead to destruction. In concluding, I would like
to consider the potential for creative and revolutionary lines of flight within
the fascist discourse of The Raven and Hidden. Children appear in the final
scenes of both films. In The Raven, the mother of the suicide victim passes
children playing as she walks down the street and away from the murder
scene. French cultural critic Chris Lloyd proffers that these children convey
a sense of hopefulness for the future (Lloyd 2007: 52). Hidden ends with a
seemingly innocuous long shot of the steps of (Georges's son) Pierrot's high
school. However, careful viewing reveals Pierrot sitting on the steps in
conversation with Majid's son. There has been no previous intimation that
the boys know each other. The ambiguity of this scene is much debated. I
would suggest that both film endings could augur positively or negatively
for the future. However what is interesting about the ending of both films is
the subtle interjection of chance into narratives that appear cripplingly over-
determined by microfascist lines. In The Raven, the children in the street are
playing dice. In Hidden, the boys are sitting on the steps of the Stéphane
Mallarmé high school. Both references bring to mind Mallarmé's influential
experimental poem A Throw of the Dice Never Eliminates Chance. In
Difference and Repetition, Deleuze alludes to this poem when he describes
how the divine game of chance (re)opens the possibility of freedom:
First, there is no pre-existent rule, since the game includes its own rules. As a result, every time,
the whole of chance is affirmed in a necessarily winning throw. Nothing is exempt from the game:
consequences are not subtracted from chance by connecting them with a hypothetical necessity
which would tie them to a determinate fragment; on the contrary, they are adequate to the whole
of chance, which retains and subdivides all possible consequences … This is the point at which
the ultimate origin is overturned into an absence of origin (in the always displaced circle of the
eternal return). An aleatory point is displaced through all the points on the dice, as though one
time for all times. These different throws which invent their own rules and compose the unique
throw with multiple forms and within the eternal return are so many imperative questions
subtended by a single response which leaves them open and never closes them.
(Deleuze 2001: 353–54)
The revolutionary dice roll describes the trajectory of a war machine and
line of flight that is creative rather than nihilistic. Badiou describes this
movement as ‘an ethic of truths’ using the illustration of cultural
renaissance.13 The films reveal how past fascist and microfascist complicity
contrives to shame and terrorize us, engraining fascist violence deeper into
our cultural inheritance. This either silences our voices making us
‘outsiders’ or the ‘guilty’ scapegoats of contemporary political discourse, or
we in turn become ‘insiders’ the new terrorists of nihilism. The aesthetics of
microfascism revealed in The Raven and Hidden engender distrust, discord,
disempowerment and destruction foreclosing hope.14 Yet, as Deleuze and
Guattari point out, microfascisms originate from transformative lines of
creative resistance and revolution. Their trajectory is not pre-determined.
The films remind us that the violence of the past cannot be undone or
erased. However, resistance to fascism means the refusal of subjugation to
or seduction by fascist power. In the final scenes of The Raven, Dr Germain
and Denise recognize and celebrate the transformational power of new love;
where both had previously considered their outlooks doomed and hopeless,
they now look forward to becoming parents and a new life together. In
Hidden, the implied friendship between the sons of Georges and Majid
suggests a transformation of the former colonial and cultural divide. By
presenting viewers with the legacy of the agent-less spiral of microfascist
violence, the films warn of the vectors of past and indeed future
microfascist trajectories within historical and contemporary political
discourse. However, they also communicate the potential for a new throw of
the dice to make an affirmative break with the past and realize the hope of
fostering future freedoms.
Notes
References
Galbreith, Kenneth 57
Galloway, Alexander 72
genocide 53, 64, 119, 185 ; see also the Holocaust
Girard, René 178, 179; ‘surrogate victim’ 185, 188
global triage 9, 68–73, 75–6; contemporary fascism 69; definition 69;
human desire 73–4; pre-emption 69–70, 72, 75; technology 69, 70–2,
75
globality/globalization 11, 54, 58; global agreement on security 27, 43,
57, 171; global imaginary of threat 54, 56; global politics of post-
fascist suicide 170, 171; global war 4, 54, 59, 69; global war machine
171
Godard, Jean-Luc: Contempt 28, 35
governance 70, 140 ; biopolitical governance 128, 141; ‘emergency
governance’ 11, 141, 142, 143, 146; Foucault, Michel 133–4, 137;
liberal governance 138, 140–2; liberal way of rule and war 141–2;
milieu 136; milieu of security 140; normative governance 20–1;
norms/fascism relation 22; politics of lines 128, 130, 132, 133; security
dispositif 137–8; security governance 54, 55; see also lines of flight;
milieu;; politics of lines
Guattari, Felix 1; Nomadology 65–6, 155, 167; What is Philosophy?
15; see also Anti-Oedipus; politics of lines; A Thousand Plateaus
Guérin, Daniel 176
identity 31; collective identity 78, 79, 81, 86; fascism 18, 19, 25, 158;
fascist aesthetic 31; Japan 165
ideology 1, 2, 13, 16–19; ideology/illusion distinction 18;
ideology/practice relation 23–5; Marxism 8, 15, 16; wedge issues 17–
18
illusion, ignorance 13, 14, 18, 19, 23, 36, 42, 81, 138
immanence 106, 111, 123, 131, 134, 144 ; immanence/transcendence
relation 14–15, 98–9; see also transcendence
imperialism 64, 65
international law 76
interventionism 50, 54; humanitarian intervention 64, 69
Italy 86; Arezzo 31; Mussolini, Benito 1, 19, 31, 37, 42, 187
Machiavelli, Niccolò 68
machine: abstract machine 34, 74, 150, 155 ; abstract machine of
mutation 155, 158, 165, 168; desiring machine 2, 15, 74, 104–105,
124, 151, 154; killing machine 69, 76, 193; see also war machine
macropolitics 44, 113, 118, 129 ; macro-fascism 127, 132;
macropolitics/micropolitics distinction 129; molar line 129, 130, 132,
133, 148, 150–5, 157, 164, 165; politics of lines 129, 131;
totalitarianism 150, 157; see also micropolitics; politics
Malka, Shlomo 118–19
Mallarmé, Stéphane 190
Mamdani, Mahmood 64
Manning, Erin 10, 96–125
Marxism 8, 15, 16
mass 47, 61, 72, 78 ; fascism as mass movement 13, 29, 42, 44, 52, 72,
75, 151, 159, 181; fascist aesthetics 28–9, 30; fear 57; violence 184–5;
see also ‘the people’
Massumi, Brian 2, 70, 122, 134–5; bare activity 99, 111, 113, 124
May, Todd 8, 13–26
Michelsen, Nicholas 11, 148–72
micro-fascism 2, 57, 127, 152, 153–4, 191, 192, 193 ; ‘black hole
phenomenon’ 132, 152, 157, 192; Deleuze, Gilles 27, 31, 34, 37, 38,
122; France 12, 173, 180, 189; germinant trait of 174, 180, 189, 191;
micro-paranoia 152; Nazism 148, 151–2, 153–4, 158–9; A Thousand
Plateaus 174, 181, 184; see also fascism in everyday life;
micropolitics
micropolitics 44, 113, 118, 128, 129, 131, 181 ; micro-politics of
insecurity 38, 39, 53; molecular line 129–30, 131, 148, 150–5, 159,
165–6, 169; politics of lines 127, 132; Waltz with Bashir 10, 105, 112,
113; see also macropolitics; micro-fascism;; politics
milieu 11, 126, 127, 128, 133, 134, 138 ; Bergson, Henri 138; concept
133, 135; Deleuze-Guattari/Foucault's distinction of the term 137–8;
Foucault, Michel 135–7; French/English distinction of the term 134–5;
governance 136, 140; milieu of security 136–7, 139, 140; security
dispositif 136, 137, 139; A Thousand Plateaus 134; see also lines of
flight; politics of lines
the military 55; boundaries collapse 54, 71, 72; Japan 165–6;
(aesthetic militarism 166, 167, 169); military coup 152, 158
minority 38–9, 42–3, 80, 121
Mishima, Yukio 87
modernity 2, 4, 46, 52; bio-politics 53; ‘emergency of emergence’
141–2; fascist character of liberal modernity 3, 4, 6, 53; fear 54–5; the
Holocaust 52–3
Morris, Ivan 168
movement: Bergson, Henri 138–9; logic of 9, 65, 66; movements of
flight 130–1; Nomadology 65–6; politics of lines 126, 127, 129–30,
133, 134, 139–40; unpredictability 126, 127, 142; war 65–6, 67, 155–6
Mussolini, Benito 1, 19, 31, 37, 42, 187
Nandy, Ashis 73
National Socialism: mass appeal 29, 159 ; suicidal line of flight 148,
150, 151, 159, 169, 171; see also Nazism
Nazism 3, 6, 49–50, 59, 148, 159 ; aesthetic strategy 29–30; cinema
30, 72; France 12, 173, 174, 175, 182, 189, 191, 192, 193;
Germany/Japan fascist-suicide-state distinction 169; Goebbels, Josef
28, 29, 30, 182, 192; microfascism 148, 151–2, 153–4, 158–9; molar
line 148, 150–1; molecular line 148, 150–1; national palingenesis 153,
159, 160, 162, 163, 169; paranoia 160–1, 162; rise of 29, 151, 158–9;
schizophrenia 160, 162; suicidal line of flight 148, 158–9; ‘suicidal-
state’ 160–3, 171; Third Reich 33, 49, 151; total war 157, 159–60,
161, 162; totalitarianism 148, 150, 153, 158, 162; war machine 157,
159, 160, 169; see also fascism; Hitler, Adolf;; suicide
Nietzsche, Friedrich 14, 46, 58, 99, 108
nihilism 8, 109, 187, 193
nuclear weapon 124, 168; nuclear deterrence 170
paranoia 5, 88, 163, 169, 177, 185; fascism 57, 149–50, 152–3, 154–5;
micro-paranoia 152; Nazism 160–1, 162; paranoia/schizophrenia
dualism 149, 155, 157, 158; paranoiac body 5, 6; paranoid security
mentality 27; politics of paranoia 153, 157; reterritorialisation 149; A
Thousand Plateaus 153; totalitarianism 56, 153, 154–5
Parnet, Claire 127, 128, 129, 131, 143, 146; suicidal line of flight 134,
171
Paxton, Robert 175, 180, 187, 189, 192
peace: anti-fascist aesthetics 27, 31, 37, 40 ; capitalisation of 9, 43, 50;
liberal fascism 9, 43, 50; maintenance of 8, 27, 31, 37, 40; pure-peace
170; war/peace relation 9, 43, 46, 54, 68; see also security
‘the people’ 86, 93, 121 ; from classical to modern cinema 79–81;
‘people of seers’ 9, 85, 86, 94; ‘people to come’ 79, 86–7, 90–1;
unanimity of 7, 78, 79, 81, 93; see also mass
Perrault, Pierre 121
photography 29, 30, 122
political psychology 39–40
politics 5, 129 ; aestheticization of politics 31, 32, 36, 37, 40, 59–60,
124; Bergson's politics of perception 81–2; concept of the political 58;
fascism 1, 2, 3–4, 6; global politics of post-fascist suicide 170, 171;
modern political cinema 78, 84–6, 91, 93; molar/molecular dimensions
153; political theatre 85, 92; political theology 60; politics of the novel
37; politics of paranoia 153, 157; politics of technology 60–1; Waltz
with Bashir 99, 100, 114–18, 120 (protopolitics 100, 106, 110, 113,
117); see also biopolitics; cinema and political aesthetics;;
macropolitics;; micropolitics;; politics of lines
politics of lines 10–11, 126–47, 148, 149–71 ; fascism 11, 126, 127,
132, 133, 157, 162; governance 128, 130, 132, 133; lines of creation
126, 127, 130; lines of destruction 126, 127; macro-fascism 127, 132;
macropolitics 129, 131; micro-fascism 127, 132; micropolitics 129,
131; molar line 129, 130, 132, 133, 148, 150–5, 157, 164, 165;
molecular line 129–30, 131, 148, 150–5, 159, 165–6, 169; movement
126, 127, 129–30, 133, 134, 139–40; political problematique 126, 127,
128, 133; security dispositif 128, 134, 135–6, 139; segmentarity 129–
30, 132, 133; Spinozan ethico-politics of bodies 11, 126, 128, 143–5;
suicidal line 11, 132–3, 134, 146, 148, 155–7, 158–9, 161–2, 166–9,
171; A Thousand Plateaus 126–7, 128–9, 134, 148; three lines schema
126, 127, 128–34, 148, 149–71; uncertainty 128, 133, 139;
unpredictability 126, 127, 137; see also governance; lines of flight;;
milieu;; movement
power 181–6; bio-politics 47; fascism and desire of 1, 4, 19; fascism as
system of power relations 1, 2, 3, 5, 187; knowledge/power relation
22; ‘the power of the false’ 10, 97–8, 121; liberal power relations 4;
resistance to 47, 127, 145
practice 13–14, 20–6; definition 20, 22; desire/practice relation 23–4,
25–6; fascist practices 8, 21–2, 24–6; Foucault, Michel 13, 22;
ideology/practice relation 23–5; knowledge 22–3, 24; normative
governance 20–1; norms/fascism relation 22; religious and economic
practices 24–5; social nature of 21; volitional and epistemic elements
20, 23–6
pre-emption 9; global triage 69–70, 72, 75; legitimacy 69–70;
operating system 70
propaganda: National Socialism 171; propaganda film 30, 182, 192,
193
Protevi, John 149, 150, 158
psychoanalysis 21–2, 46
Sabra and Shatila massacre 97, 112, 114–15, 120, 123; Sharon, Ariel
125; see also Waltz with Bashir
Sartre, Jean-Paul 183
Saxton, Libby 177, 183, 185, 192
schizophrenia 157, 158, 160; deterritorialisation 149, 155; Nazism
160, 162; paranoia/schizophrenia dualism 149, 155, 157, 158;
schizoanalysis 15, 158, 169; schizophrenic war machine 155, 159, 160
Schmitt, Carl 51, 57, 187; political theology 60; technology 58–9, 60
Schrader, Paul 87, 91
Scorsese, Martin 89; Taxi Driver 83, 86, 87, 89–90, 91, 92
security 134 ; anti-fascist aesthetics 27, 35, 37, 38; biopolitics 47–8,
53; development/security relation 54; fascism 6, 10, 27, 53, 171;
global agreement on security 27, 43, 57, 171; insecuritisation
imperative 53–5, 171; liberal fascism 48, 53–5, 57, 58; micro-politics
of insecurity 38, 39, 53; milieu of security 136–7, 139, 140; paranoid
security mentality 27; securitization 9, 35, 37, 38, 43, 46, 47, 74;
security dispositif 46, 58, 128, 134, 135–6, 137–8, 139; security
governance 54, 55; society of control 38, 71, 73; suicidal line 170–1;
United Kingdom 61; war/security relationship 46; see also peace;
social order
the seer 9–10, 81, 82–8, 91–4; ‘people of seers’ 9, 85, 86, 94;
resistance of the seer 10, 88, 90; seeing the intolerable 82, 83, 86, 88,
90, 91, 94; seer/agent replacement 176, 178, 183; witness 178, 183–4,
188; see also Cinema
Sellars, Wilfrid 22
Shakespeare, William 82
Shapiro, Michael J. 8, 27–41; cinematic heterotopia 8
Silverman, Max 175, 177, 189–90
Sloterdijk, Peter 91
social issues 45 ; desiring production 44–5, 74; fascism as socially
invested 42; social order 38, 40, 43, 49, 158, 179 (Japan 164, 166);
society of control 38, 71–2, 73; see also security
socialism 50, 51
Sontag, Susan 28, 32, 33
Spielberg, Steven 38–9
Spinoza, Baruch 11, 61, 126, 128, 143–5state 50, 148; Nazism and
‘suicidal-state’ 160–3, 171; sovereignty 48–9, 51, 53, 54, 57, 58, 133,
135; state apparatus 83, 93, 155–7, 160, 162, 164, 166–9, 187; suicide
148, 155–7 (‘suicidal-state’ 148, 149, 157, 160–3, 166, 168–9, 171);
war 65 (war as anti-state function 156); war machine 93, 155–7, 160,
162, 187; see also totalitarianism
suicide 11, 91, 92, 148–72, 188 ; concealment 157; deterritorialization
11, 148, 149, 155–7, 160–1, 162, 165, 188; fascism 148, 157–63;
fascist aesthetics 10, 165–6, 167, 168–9; (aesthetic militarism 166,
167, 169; aestheticization of death 165–6, 167); Festen 91, 92; global
politics of postfascist suicide 170, 171; Hidden 188, 189; post-fascism
11, 170; The Raven 188–9; state 148, 155–7; (‘suicidalstate’ 148, 149,
157, 160–3, 166, 168–9, 171); suicidal line 11, 132–3, 134, 146, 148,
155–7, 158–9, 161–2, 166–9, 171, 187; suicidalism 148–9, 159, 162; A
Thousand Plateaus 11, 148, 155–9, 170, 187–90; three lines schema
148, 149–71; total war 156, 157, 158, 160, 167, 170;
totalitarianism/fascism distinction 148–9, 152–3, 157; war machine
155–7, 159, 160, 162, 165, 171, 187; World War II 149, 163, 164; see
also Holland, Eugene; Japan;; lines of flight;; National Socialism;;
Nazism;; paranoia;; schizophrenia;; Virilio, Paul
Sun Tzu 68
surveillance 34–5, 36, 38, 39, 176, 183; Hidden 177 (surveillance
footage 177, 179, 180, 182, 185, 191); The Raven 176, 177, 179, 182;
A Scanner Darkly 34–5, 36
Syberberg, Hans Jürgen 8, 32–4, 40; aesthetic scandal 32; Hitler: A
Film from Germany 32–3
technology: bio-political fascism 60; global triage 69, 70–2, 75; life as
bio-technology 58–61; politics of technology 60–1
territory 46, 87, 98, 112, 124; deterritorialisation 11, 98, 124, 129, 130,
131, 132, 134, 189 (suicidal line 11, 148, 149, 155–7, 160–1, 162,
165); lines of flight 130, 131, 134; reterritorialisation 117, 119, 131,
134, 187; territorialisation 130, 134
terrorism 4–5, 54–5, 69, 189
theatre 31, 83–4; Brecht, Bertolt 30, 32, 37; political theatre 85, 92
A Thousand Plateaus 11, 125, 148, 150, 153, 170, 173; becoming 139–
40; desire 184; four ‘dangers’ of fascism 173, 190 (clarity 178–81; fear
38, 176–8; lines of flight 187–91; power 181–6); micro-fascism 174,
181, 184; milieu 134; Nazism 148, 150; paranoia 153; suicidal line of
flight 11, 148, 155–9, 170, 187–90; surveillance 176; see also Deleuze,
Gilles; Guattari, Felix; Hidden; lines of flight; politics of lines; The
Raven
Thucydides 68
time 130, 137; Bergson, Henri 138–9; time-image 173, 177–8; Waltz
with Bashir 99, 103, 104, 107–109, 120, 122
toleration 88; cinema: seeing the intolerable 82, 83, 86, 88
torture 4, 21; Hidden 175, 180, 181, 183, 192
totalitarianism 64, 65, 105, 149, 150 ; fascism/totalitarianism
distinction 44, 55–6, 148–9, 150, 152–3, 157, 159, 163, 187; fear 55–
6; Japan 164, 166–9; liberalism/totalitarianism distinction 56;
macropolitics 150, 157; mistakenly associated with fascism 2, 42–3,
44; Nazism 148, 150, 153, 158, 162; paranoia 56, 153, 154–5; regime
of fear 56; Stalinist totalitarianism 150, 151; transcendence 100, 103,
105–106; see also authoritarianism
transcendence 14–15, 98–9, 100, 103, 105, 117, 122 ;
immanence/transcendence relation 14–15, 98–9; totalitarianism 100,
103, 105–106; transcendental field 98, 99–103, 105, 110, 113, 123; see
also immanence