Learning and memory - Anderson
Learning and memory - Anderson
Learninc
1% “~ ec Waa lo tk wg a rf lL,
1 a) || Lev | ate ( |aeye ‘Cri
a8 - &@ | o | Bl
on |
JOHN R. ANDERSON
7
Ae be
9
ian “a_.
q
a
oe
t ’ ¥ ~
amar :
i} 7 f
-
Van 1 _ : om a
Me / 2s
a..,
* iv ~_ i
4 oo 4 if —,
7 rom ond Ps 7 iy - 4 = ee —7a c,
™, é :
a i ’
©
4
7
ste
=
te
uns
»,
_
=
e
:
/
LEARNING AND MEMORY
AN INTEGRATED APPROACH
LEARNING
AND MEMORY
AN INTEGRATED APPROACH
Second Edition
John R. Anderson
Carnegie Mellon University
This book was set in 10/12 ITC Palatino Light by LCI Design and printed and bound
by Courier-Westford. The cover was printed by Phoenix Color Corp.
Copyright © 1995, 2000 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc. All rights reserved.
Ai) PS YH 5 ZY ey Di
To Lynne, for Everything
4 =
nesnats wites. ° | ’
lL Sea a sa Ve >: ae :
pI? FO Laks Law
CWeR fp 2 & ie= -onmiee
y Tee teggr Geak : .
5 '
Ths Lt @ ree?
; ated Sem sented *
ae ‘. \
— =—
+ —
ane a
mom We
1 he
= S
—— = SS
~~ S71 a i
i Kd
i¢ : :
643 2 «+ “
A - 1
7, V ’
“
my
at
7 vit
_
i
Preface
Research on learning and memory has been part of psychology since it began as
a science in the 1800s. At the height of the behaviorist era, around 1950, learning
was perceived as the key issue in psychology. Behaviorists believed that under-
standing any aspect of human behavior depended on understanding how that
behavior was acquired. Learning was pushed somewhat from center stage by the
cognitive movement in the 1960s. Cognitive psychology emphasized understand-
ing the functioning of the mature cognitive system rather than understanding the
learning that led to the system. The cognitive movement also marked a major
schism in the field. Traditional learning research continued on animals, while
research on human memory became a major part of cognitive psychology. These
two research traditions have evolved as almost completely separate disciplines.
Research on animal learning and research on human memory must
address many of the same issues. For this reason their continued development
independent of one another is not satisfactory. Many colleges recognize the rela-
tionship between the two areas by offering a Learning and Memory course rather
than separate courses for learning and memory. The scientific community is also
starting to recognize that pursuing independent paths is not desirable. Animal
learning research has become more and more cognitive over the decades, and
animal learning theory is no longer cast in such stark behaviorist terms that it is
incompatible with the cognitive perspective. In addition, researchers on animal
learning have profitably borrowed methods and theory from human memory
research. On the other side, research on human memory is turning more and
more to issues concerning the neural basis of memory, which inevitably require
the use of animal models. Cognitive psychology has become increasingly inter-
ested in the adaptive function of human memory, which again brings in the bio-
logical perspective. Finally, cognitive psychologists are beginning to recognize
the centrality of learning to the understanding of memory. In the last ten years,
the two areas of research have come closer together.
This textbook on learning and memory examines the current state of the
traditional learning and cognitive fields, and identifies the exciting opportuni-
ties for the synthesis of ideas. Learning and memory are brought together in one
Vil
Preface
textbook because of my firm belief that one cannot properly describe research in
either field without describing research in the other. Ideally, there should be
only one field to describe. However, research and theory still tend to divide into
that concerned with animal learning and that concerned with human memory.
In addition to reviewing the behavioral research and theory in the various
areas, the discussion of this book emphasizes several themes.
Two of these themes
contribute to the integration of research on animal learning and human memory.
One theme, that of understanding the neural basis of learning and memory, is
presented throughout the text at appropriate places. This accurately reflects the
current state of learning and memory research, as well as the excitement about
new advances in understanding the neural basis of learning and memory.
The second major theme is appreciating the adaptive character of learning
and memory. Learning and memory are processes that arise in all species as solu-
tions to the problem of adapting to the changing structure of the environment.
This functional view of the system is stressed throughout the book, and empha-
sis is placed on how different mechanisms can achieve the same function.
The first edition of the book was, in part, an effort to gain a perspective on
my own intellectual history. I entered psychology in the 1960s, interested in ani-
mal learning. I joined the cognitive movement and spent years doing research
on human memory. Dissatisfied with the rather narrow perspective this research
gave on issues, I gradually shifted to research on cognitive skills and education-
al applications. As part of this experience, I have come to appreciate that human
learning and memory are part of an adaptation of the human to the environ-
ment. These adaptational interests brought me back to the research on animal
learning that I had left more than 20 years earlier. I found that there were many
new and deep analyses in that field, many of which were quite compatible with
the issues that I was dealing with in my own research. Although the first edition
was a textbook and not a monograph, these perspectives did clearly color the
story that I told in that book.
In preparing the second edition I had two major goals. The obvious one
was to update the book to include the new directions in research over the past
five years. Although there are a wide variety of updates, it is clear that research
from cognitive neuroscience forms the largest fraction of the additions. The sec-
ond goal is perhaps not so obvious. The first edition had some unnecessary fea-
tures of a research monograph. I have tried to smooth these out and make the
book more even at the undergraduate level. However, I have been mindful not
to sacrifice the intellectual character of the first edition. Some of my morte grat-
ifying moments of the past few years have involved the compliments I have
received on the book’s character.
It also reviews some of the ideas that have failed. These past efforts have set the
stage for current research, enabling rather dramatic progress toward an under-
standing of human learning and memory.
The rest of the book describes the modern understanding of learning and
memory. Chapters 2 through 4 are devoted principally to research on animal
learning: Chapter 2 addresses classical conditioning, Chapter 3 describes instru-
mental conditioning, and Chapter 4 discusses issues of reinforcement. Although
there have been some useful human studies in these areas, animal research is
the basis for most current progress. This section of the book reflects this fact,
while also noting applications of this research to humans. The principal contri-
bution of this research to human learning is probably the establishment of a
better context in which to understand human learning and memory.
The remainder of the book focuses on human learning and memory,
although in many instances the later chapters turn to animal research for per-
spectives. Chapters 5 through 8 review the rather sophisticated understanding
of the nature of memory that has evolved over the past four decades. Chapter 5
examines how information is processed and stored in temporary memories
when it is initially received. Chapter 6 investigates how a permanent record of
this information is built up in long-term memory. Chapter 7 explores how infor-
mation is maintained over potentially long periods of time and what underlies
forgetting. Chapter 8 looks at the different ways in which information can be
retrieved when it is needed.
The final three chapters examine issues of learning and memory in a larg-
er context. Chapter 9 reviews the learning phenomena that arise when poten-
tially complex skills are acquired, such as learning how to use a word processor.
This topic contrasts with most of the research described earlier in the book,
which is concerned with learning simple facts and behaviors that are more
tractable for experimental study. Chapter 10 focuses on issues of inductive
learning, how people discover things about the structure of their environment.
This chapter returns to some issues of the early conditioning chapters, but it
employs the perspective of the human situation. The final chapter is concerned
with the major application of research on learning and memory to education,
bringing together many of the ideas discussed in the preceding chapters.
This book incorporates a number of features to help achieve instructional
and learning goals. The terminology of the field can be a bit overwhelming. |
have tried to minimize unnecessary jargon, but part of the educational mission
of this book is to introduce the student to the important concepts. Each impor-
tant new term is highlighted in the text and explained. These definitions are
brought together in a glossary at the end of the book. I have also concluded each
section of every chapter with a summary statement that identifies the main
point of the section. This provides students with a way to check their under-
standing of the sections and to quickly identify the content of a chapter. To assist
the instructor, Michael Toglin of SUNY at Cortland has prepared an Instructor's
Manual that includes chapter outlines, teaching tips, media resources, and a test
bank.
1x
Preface
Acknowledgments
My experience with Wiley has been exceptional. Karen Dubno was editor for the
first edition, and Ellen Schatz was editor for the second edition. They have been
earnest both about the need to be true to the intellectual character of the field
and about the needs of communicating that character to an undergraduate
audience. They recruited a set of reviewers who helped greatly in defining and
fine tuning this book. The reviewers of the first edition were Victor Agruso,
Drury College; Robert Allen, Lafayette College; John Anson, Stephen F. Austin
State University; William Baum, University of New Hampshire; Steven
Coleman, Cleveland State University; Robert Crowder, Yale University; Ellen
Gagné, Catholic University; Peter Graf, University of British Columbia; James
Grau, Texas A & M University; Robert Green, Case Western Reserve University;
Mike Grelle, Central Missouri State University; Douglas Hintzman, University
of Oregon; David Hogan, Northern Kentucky University; John Jahnke, Miami
University; Douglas Mandra, Francis Marion University; Philip Marshall, Texas
Tech University; Ralph Miller, SUNY-Binghamton; Tom Moye, Coe College;
Mitch Rabinowitz, Fordham University; Ken Salzwedal, University of
Wisconsin-Whitewater; Michael Scavio, California State University-Fullerton;
Richard Schmidt, UCLA; Robert Schneider, Metropolitan State College; Steven
Sloman, Brown University; John Staddon, Duke University; Edward Wasserman,
University of lowa; Fred Whitford, Montana State University. The reviewers of
the second edition were: Gary L. Allen, University of South Carolina; Sheree
Barron, Georgia College and State University; E. John Capaldi, Purdue
University; David M. Compton, Georgia College and State University; Edward
A. Domber, Drew University; L. Sidney Fox, California State University at Long
Beach; Kevin J. Kennelly, University of North Texas; Robert Madigan, University
of Alaska at Anchorage; Richard L. Marsh, University of Georgia at Athens;
Henry Morlock, State University of New York College at Plattsburgh; Gabriel
Radvansky, University of Notre Dame; Suparna Rajaram, State University of
New York at Stony Brook; Caren M. Rotello, University of Massachusetts;
Kenneth D. Salzwedel, University of Wisconsin at Whitewater; Mark C.
Samuels, New Mexico Tech; Micheal J. Scavio, California State University at
Fullerton; Sonya M. Sheffert, Central Michigan University; Chehalis M. Strapp,
Western Oregon University; Paul D. Young, Houghton College
Besides these many reviewers the expositional structure of the book owes
much to three individuals—Lael Schooler a former graduate student, Jay
Anderson my son, and Ann Boyton-Trigg, Wiley’s developmental editor for the
first edition. Finally, I thank my secretary, Helen Borek, who was responsible for
so many details of both editions while keeping track of all the other aspects of
my professional life.
JOHN R. ANDERSON
Contents
2 CLASSICAL CONDITIONING 39
Overview 39
The Phenomena of Classical Conditioning: Eye Blink in Humans
39
Sensitization and Habituation 41
Conditioning and Awareness 42
What This Chapter Covers 43
xi
Contents
INSTRUMENTAL CONDITIONING 78
Overview 78
Classical and Instrumental Conditioning Compared 79
What This Chapter Covers 80
What Is Associated? 80
Associations Between Responses and Neural Outcomes 81
Secondary Reinforcement 82
What Is the Conditioned Stimulus? 83
Generalization 84
Discrimination 86
Spence’s Theory of Discrimination Learning 88
Relational Responding: Transposition 89
Dimensional or Attentional Learning 90
Configural Cues and Learning of Categories 93
Xii
Contents
Xill
Contents
XIV
Contents
Overview 226
The Retention Function 227
Decay: The Power Law of Forgetting 228
Degree of Learning and Forgetting 231
Environmental and Neural Bases for the Power Law of Forgetting 232
Spacing Effects 234
Spacing Effects on the Retention Function 237
Spacing Effects in the Environment 238
Interference 239
Item-Based Interference 241
A Theory of Associative Interference 243
Relationship to the Rescorla-Wagner Theory 245
Recognition Memory and Multiple Cues 246
Item Strength and Interference 248
Interference with Preexperimental Memories 249
Context-based Interference 252
Is All Forgetting a Matter of Interference? 254
Retention of Emotionally Charged Material 256
Freud’s Repression Hypothesis 256
Arousal and Retention 257
The False Memory Syndrome 259
Eyewitness Memory and Flashbulb Memories 260
Final Reflections 262
Further Readings 264
Overview 265
The Relationship Between Various Explicit Measures
of Memory 266
Recognition Versus Recall of Word Lists 268
Contents
Overview 304
Power Law Learning 307
Stages of Skill Acquisition 310
The Cognitive Stage 311
Difference Reduction 312
Operator Subgoaling 314
The Associative Stage 319
The Conversion of Problem Solving into Retrieval 320
Production Rules 322
The Knowledge-Intensive Nature of Skill 324
The Autonomous Stage 325
The Motor Program 326
Noncognitive Control 328
Generality of Motor Programs 329
Learning of Motor Programs 330
Tuning of Motor Program: Schema Theory 331
The Role of Feedback 334
Final Reflections 336
Further Readings 337
Xvi
Contents
Overview 338
Concept Acquisition 340
Concept-Identification Studies 341
Hypothesis Testing 343
Natural Concepts 346
A Schema Theory: Gluck and Bower 349
An Exemplar Theory: Medin and Schaffer 350
A Pluralistic View of Concept Acquistion 352
Causal Inference 354
Statistical Cues 355
Cues of Spatial and Temporal Contiguity 357
Kinematic Cues 361
Understanding Complex Systems 362
Conclusions about Causal Inference 364
Language Acquisition 364
Character of Language Acquisition 366
Theories of Past-Tense Acquisition 368
A Critical Period for Language Acquisition 370
Innate Language-Learning Abilities 371
Animal Language Learning 372
Final Reflections 375
Further Readings 376
xvii
Contents
GLOSSARY 415
BIBLIOGRAPHY 426
XVili
Pee. AND and,
AN INTEGRATED APPROACH
rite =o
{) Yo
5KOna <]
Ti ees.
Gj
ye
SAOATHA ‘Wath
495 7 > =% en
~ <«@s
OGRAPHY “Die:
PHOTO CRE/NTS te?
AUTTIDEINDEX 46°
CT INDE x at eS
7 fay : -
/ ; i « a a
— -_ 2 ere i- mt 4 - ov
a
<<
3 ” _—
ii “yg .
’ atdes
i ae a
gt nee
¥
7 iri one
ni 45 7
Perspectives on Learning
and Memory
becomes activat
Through |
be innately specified? S
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
#
Behaviorist and Cognitive Approaches
The title of this book is Learning and Memory. The following section of this chap-
ter offers definitions of these two terms. Though related in their meanings, the
two words refer to separate lines of research in psychology. Learning
is associ-
viorof ar ce to what
pat Dehappening te mindof thearganisin. They held that speaking about
things happening in the minds of lower organisms, such as rats, was unscientif-
ic, and they thought only a little better of attributing minds to humans.
Behaviorism dominated American psych
Some ofthe Key’ideas of behaviorism are reviewed iina later section of this chap-
a iioners.
° ie iouiatn arose at the turn of the century when there was still great
excitement about the new ideas-surrounding evolution. Darwin had
argued that humans were continuous with other animals; it was believed
that the laws of learning that held for animals would also hold for
humans.
e Animals might allow researchers to study learning in a purer form, uncon-
tied by bycul
culture and lan
eg
straints
ints than ee
seperformed on humans. .
A major theoretical shift‘in
in psychology began in the 1950s based, in part,
on the beliet et = behaviorists had created too simple a picture of human
human subjects. A typical experiment might involve having subjects study a sec-
tion from a textbook such as this one and later testing the subjects to see what
they cou
the pairingfs on and memory in the title of this t book. The separation of
these two traditions is fundamentally artificial and has begun to break down.
Much current research on“animal learning has a strong cognitive orientation,
and there has been a resurgence of more behavioristic learning theories in
research on human memory.
This book covers the research from both traditions but takes note of the
syntheses occurring in the field today. Throughout, the emphasis is on the sig-
nificance of research results for understanding human learning and memory.
The basic purpose of this chapter is to describe the traditional approaches to
studying learning and memory, thereby setting the stage for the remaining
chapters, which center on what these approaches have revealed. Before pro-
ceeding, we must turn to the thorny issue of defining the terms learning and
memory.
Experience
7 we age, our bodies develop and our " potential oF ores chaos but we
e would not want to consider physical growth as learning. Similarly, a serious
x injury might substantially change a person’s potential for behavior, oe we
be wu not want to consider EELS, an arm asseein ng. The 1 xperience is
©
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
memory constructs has largely disappeared, now that researchers are beginning
to understand the neural changes that embody the memory records. When it is
possible to speak of some precise neural change rather than some vague men-
tal change, the behaviorists’ distrust of memory constructs begins to evaporate.
A portion of this book is concerned with the neural basis of memory.
MASONS SALA ERIESENATE
LAN NEILL S ALE IIL.
History of Research on
Learning and Memory
Psychology as a scientific field is only a little over 100 years old. From the begin- .
ning, learning has been an important area of research. One reason for the early
interest in learning was Charles Darwin's theory of evolution. The publication of
his On the Origin of Species in 1859 captured the imagination of the intellectual
world with its emphasis on how natural selection had changed species so that
they were better adapted to their environment. Learning theorists saw their ¢
research as the obvious extension of Darwin’s. Whereas Darwin was concerned 3)
with adaptation across generations of a species, learning theorists focused on 5 “t
the ongoing adaptation of an individual member of a species within its lifetime. A ¥
Understanding the relationship between species-general acapiation and indi-
vidual learning is still a current research topic.
Three research enterprises begun at the turn of the twentieth century
influenced much of the subsequent history of research on learning and memo-
ty. One was a series of studies undertaken byGerman the psychologist
Hermann
Ebbinghaus, who used himself as his sole subject. The second was a
sods ofstudies comdictad byaRussian physiologist,
physiologist Ivan
Ivan
Pavlov,
Pa on condition-
ingin dogs. The third was aseries of studies directed by anAmericanpsychol-
ogist, Edward —Thomdiks, on_trial--and- error Jeaming 1 in_cats. Pavloy | and
h
started a tradition of research that, after the cognitive revolution in the 1950s
and 1960s, became the dominant paradigm for the study of human memory. The
history of research on learning in the United States is really a history of the
research traditions started by these three individuals and how these traditions
interacted with the intellectual mood of American psychology.
The research of these three pioneers and of other influential psychologists
is presented next. The purpose of this historical review is twofold. First, it intro-
duces the methodologies
that are part ofcurrent research practice, Second, it
sets th
thee background
bac againstwhich current research and theory can be appreci-
AST BAY
History of Research on Learning and Memory
ated, in particular, by showing that a number of ideas about learning and mem-
ory)were sorcidaed before the field settled on the current conceptions.
a aa a -
1e point where he was able to repeat the lists twice in order with-
out error. He then looked at his ability to recall these lists at various delays. He
measured the amount of time he needed to relearn the lists to the same criterion
of two perfect recitations. In one case it took 1156 sec to learn the list initially and
only 467 sec to relearn the list. He was interested in how much easier it was to
relearn the list. In this example, he had saved 1156 — 467 = 689 sec. Ebbinghaus
"expressed this savings as a percentage of the original learning: 689 + 1156 = 64.3
"* percent. Figure 1.1 tion of the delay
60
sofo)
eo)
savings,
Time
%
w je)
500
400
oS
%® 300
2)
2
2 200
ai no
s
iS
100
‘Smaller numbers imply better performance in Figure 1.2, which uses a dependent
measure of trials to relearn; larger numbers imply better performance in Figure 1.1,
which uses a dependent measure of percentage of time savings.
*Ebbinghaus’s theory of remote associations was an exception. It was the dominant
theory of serial list learning until the modern era, when it was replaced by the chunk-
ing hypothesis (see Chapter 6). A series of papers discussing Ebbinghaus’s contribu-
tions was published in 1985 in the Journal of Experimental Psychology on the one hun-
dredth anniversary of his treatise.
History of Research on Learning and Memory
_ As part of
his research, he put meat powder in adog’s mouth and measured salivation.He
discovered that after a few sessions precise ‘Measurement was ines
a
Time
Experimenter’s presentation CS US |
sequence: (bell) (food) |
aS \
Organism’s response: UR
(salivation) ;
Experimenter’s presentation cS US C)
sequence: (bell) (food)
Organism’s response: CR UR
(salivation) (salivation)
(c) Extinction \
Experimenter’s presentation cs
sequence: (bell) \
Organism’s response: is CR
(salivation)
with humans involves conditioning an eye blink (UR), which occurs in response
to a puff of air to the eye (US). A light or tone repeatedly paired with the puff of
air acquires the ability to evoke an eye blink in the absence of the original US.
Eyelid conditioning is also a frequent paradigm with nonhumans.
A classical-conditioning paradigm that has received considerable research
focus in the last few decades involves the conditioned emotional response
(CER). When an animal, such as a fat, is presented *with an aversive stimulus, for
example, a mild shock, it responds in a characteristic way. Its heart rate,acceler-
ates, its blood pressure elevates, and it releases certain hormones. It also tends to
freeze and halt whatever response it has been performing. Parts of this response
pattern can be conditioned to a CS, such as a tone. To measure the CER,
researchers train an animal to perform some task, such as pressing a lever for
food; the degree to which the animal freezes and so reduces its rate of lever press-
ing when the CS is presented is taken as a measure of the strength of the CER. ||
Chapter 2 discusses contemporary research and issues involving the clas-
sical conditioning paradigm, but some of the basic phenomena established by
Pavlov(1927) are worth noting here: Stinaice
in Pie
4-Acquisition. The magnitude of the conditioned response can be mea-"-..
sured as a function of the number of pairings between the US and the CS.
The CR doessuddenly
not appear in full strength. Figure 1.4 illustrates
that the strength of the CR gradually increases withth
repetition. This is
referred to as the process 0 isition. The typical conditioning curve
10
History of Research on Learning and Memory
15
i [e)
Salivation
CS
to
ol
osetia
se i RR
12-34. 5-6 7 — 89101 T 124s Ta 16 134056.
7 8 79°10
Acquisition trials Extinction trials
i
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
12
History of Research on Learning and Memory
FIGURE 1.5 One of the four puzzle boxes used by Thorndike in his doctoral thesis.
repeated trials at this task, and’ Thorndike was interested in how quickly they
learned to get out of the puzzle box. Thorndike’s observation was that cats
would at first behave more or less randomly, moving about the box, clawing at
it, mewing, and so on, until they happened to hit the unlatching device by
chance. Over trials the random behavior gradually diminished as the cats head-
ed for the unlatching device sooner and hence were able to leave the box soon-
er. He referred to this as 'trial=and=errorlearningr Figure 1.6 shows typical learn-
ing curves relating number of trials to time to get out of the box.
Arguments continue as to whether Thorndike’s cats gradually learned
(over a series of trials) to get out of the box or whether they suddenly caught on
and learned on a single trialy Thorndike chose to see gradualness in these learn=
ing curves and proposed that the correct response of hitting the unlatching
device was gradually strengthened to the stimulus situation of being in the puz-
zle box, so that it came to dominate the other random responses. He thought
that this strengthening process was automatic and that it require
did not any
ivit.on the part of the cats.
The kind of learning process Thorndike studied is referred to as‘imstru-
ro mental conditioning, incontrast with Pavlov’s classical conditioning. In both
caséS, aresponse is learned toa stimulus situation. In classical conditioning, the
Ce timulus is the CS and the response is theCR. In Thorndike’s puzzle boxes, the
stimulus isthe puzzle box and the response is
the appropriate unlatching action.
~~ Both Kinds of Tearning show the phenomena of practice, extinction, and spon-
taneous recovery. In instrumental
re ee
conditioning, the response is performed to
i
18
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
120
60 60
0 0
e2 60
a: 180
raf
8
ray
2
2 0 120
=
60 60
0 )
Trials Trials
FIGURE1.6 Learning curves for five cats in Thorndike’s puzzle boxes. Source: From
Psychological Monographs, Volume 2 (Whole No. 8) by E. L. Thorndike. Animal intelli-
gence: An experimental study of the associative processes in animals. Copyright © 1898 by
The Macmillan Company. In the Public Domain.
obtain the
ing.one he originally
formulated his tnsndastzechapsiioroans such as
— tood, as ralStimulus-response_ connections. (or associations), and»
learn punishments,
me such as shock,«weakened.them.
Thorndike that punishment was relatively
Later evidence convinced
ineffective in weakening
14
History of Research on Learning and Memory
d He pointedto experiments
such as that of Trowbridge and Cason (1932) in which subjects practiced
drawing 4-inch lines without any feedback and failed to improve in accu-
- : é:
“lead
improvement—for
to example, rehearsing material for a test. Indeed,
as discussed in Chapter 6, practice seems to be a fundamental variable in
_>learning and memory.
3. Principle of Belongingness, In 1933, Thorndike accepted the notion that
a) B.
some things are easier to associate than others because they belong
together, This was a concession to the
Gestalt psychologists
of the time
who argued that it is easier to associate things if they are perceived as
belonging together. Thorndike accepted the principle of belongingness
with some reluctance because it seemed to involve a cognitive component
in the mechanical process of forming an association. This idea of belong-
ingness has played a large role in modern theories of learning and mem-
ory. Animals have certain biological predispositions to associate things; for
instance, as discussed in Chapter 2, rats are especially prepared to associ-
ate taste with poisoning. Also, in the arena of human memory, the way”
e- for instance, as
shown in Chapter 6, memory for a pair of words is greatly enhanced if they
are imagined in an interactive visual image.
Thorndike
and Pavlov provided much of the inspiration:
for the behaviorist
movement
that dominated American psychology in the first half of the twenti-
eth century under-
ae:
most famous of the early behaviorists, was greatly influenced by Thorndike and
Pavlov. Watson argued that mental constructs such as decision making and
memory were excess baggage and that all human behavior could be understood
as the result of learned associations between stimuli and responses.
15
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
sy PER ESE DCR
D—Drive. Acco
to Hull,
rdin behavior-was
g ggt simply a function of habit
strength, as with Thorndike’s law of effect. A rat satiated after many reinforcing
experiences would no longer run the maze for food. Hull proposed that the
16
History of Research on Learning and Memory
17
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
2)
S
3 6 No food reward
So
oO
g
=x
4
XS
; = Regularly rewarded
No food reward
until day 11
FIGURE 1.7. Average number of incorrect choices for three groups of rats that are
running a maze. Source: From E. C. Tolman, and C. H. Honzik, “Introduction and
removal of reward and maze performance in rats.” University of California Publicaltions
in Psychology. Copyright © 1930 by University of California Press. Reprinted by per-
mission.
his most famous demonstrations involved maze learning by rats, which was the
popular experimental paradigm of the time.
The first ioned
with respect to Thorndike’s law of effect. The basi iment by Tolman and
Honzik (1930b) involved three groups of rats running a maze with 14 choice
points. Rats were put in at one end of the maze and were retrieved when they
got to the other end. All rats ran the maze once a day for 17 days. For one group,
food was always at the end of the maze; for another group, food was never at
the end of the maze; for a third group, food was introduced on the eleventh day.
Figure 1.7 shows the performance of the rats in terms of how many wrong
choices they made before reaching the end of the maze. The group given food
on the eleventh day dramatically improved its scores on the twelfth day and
even performed slightly better than the group that was reinforced all along.
According to Tolman, the unreinforced rats were learning all the while.
18
History of Research on Learning and Memory
So
he
Fo
FIGURE 1.8 Maze used to test the relative ease of learning either the response that
brings reward or the place at which the reward is found. Source: From E. C. Tolman
and D. Kalish. Journal of Experimental Psychology, Studies in Spatial Learning II. Place
learning versus response learning. Copyright © 1946 by the American Psychological
Association. Reprinted by permission.
ot For instance, rats in the maze experiments learned that going to a spe-
_ cific location would lead them to the goal box. These expectations remained pas-
sive until some goal energized them into action. These goals and MERs antici-
pated many ideas of the cognitive era, but the fundamental problem with
Tolman’s theory was that he never explained how goals energized these MERs.
This problem led Edwin Guthrie (1952), another learning theorist of the time, to
complain that Tolman left his rat in the maze buried in thought. A later section
in this chapter describes how Newell and Simon’s computer simulation theory
of problem solving provided the link missing in Tolman’s theory.
19
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
Sec tac ere
B. E Skinner (1904-1990)
B. F. Skinner was a behaviorist whose approach was as different from Tolman’s as
one could imagine. Skinner's influence lasted long beyond the heyday of behav-
iorism. Because of his popular books, Walden Two (1948) and Beyond Freedom and
Dignity (1971), he became synonymous with behaviorism in much of the popu-
lar culture. He is often called el EEEER cons: he carried behavior-
ism to one of its extremes. Not only did Skinnerdlacktolerance for mentalistic
constructs such as memory, but he also had little patience for many of the theo-
retical constructs that occupied other behaviorists. For instance, he criticized'the
‘concepts of drive and habit strength that were part of Hullian theory because
they referred to internal states rather than to observable stimuli and responses.
GTS AEE itismajor SDM eltothe stud cabinstrument i
20
History of Research on Learning and Memory
Es
Fe
ee
in Chapter 4. This work was concerned with how various contingencies between
reinforcement and response affected the frequency with which the response
was emitted. For instance, in an example of what is known as fixed-interval
reinforcement, a rat might be given a pellet for its next response after 2 min had
passed since its last pellet. Figure 1.9 illustrates a fixed-interval schedule in
which a reinforcement is delivered every 2 min. Note that the total number of.
40
Oo
NO
Ww ro)
number
Total
of
responses
= [o)
2h
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
organism behaved inner way; he was content with knowing what kind of
behavior could be expectéd from many different organisms (including humans)
given a fixed-interval schedule.
Figure 1.10 is a striking illustration of the generality of Skinnerian analy-
sis. Weisberg and Waldrop (1972) plotted the number of bills passed by the U.S.
Congress as a function of month. They argued that adjournment was a major
reinforcement for congressional representatives; thus, there should be an
1000 1000
750 750
Te!
oO
a
S
xz)
= 81st Congress
S 500 Jan. 1949
— Jan. 1951 500
s
s=)
£
=J
Oo
250 250
ene 0
TEES NUS ALS NPIS AveS StOlm Naps lina) MierAvee Vue oe a AGES ani INIT)
[espareetis Be1st session Ba A ee by eet ee2nd session eee |
Months
FIGURE 1.10 Cumulation of bills passed by the U.S. Congress. Source: From P.
Weisberg and P. B. Waldrop. Fixed-interval work habits of Congress. Copyright ©
1972 by Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis. Reprinted by permission.
22
History of Research on Learning and Memory
increase in their behavior (bill passing) just before the reinforcer. Indeed, their
behavior showed the same scalloped form as that of rats in a Skinner box. The
exact same mechanisms could not be operating in Congress as in the rats, but
Skinner was not interested in mechanisms—only in the generality of behavioral
laws.
For Skinner, understanding was not found in an explanation of what was
happening inside the organism. A person did not understand a behavior unless
that person knew how to train an organism to perform the behavior. The
ieee. lot of practical knowledge emerged from Skinner's and his stu-
dents’ laboratories about how to control beha
+] at is. an existing
presses, a rat could be aed to press a lever harder. First, presses exceeding
low level of force would be rewarded; as the rat pressed harder, the criterion for
reward would be raised. The rat’s response would gradually move in the desired
direction.
23
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
C CTE z ; ]
T1dJ
Skinner never responded to the Chomsky critique, although others did (e.g.,
MacCorquodale, 1970), and he lived to see the cognitive approach supplant the
behaviorist approach, partly because of the Chomsky critique. Skinner com-
plained bitterly to the end that the criticisms were unjust and that cognitive psy-
chology was full of fanciful mechanisms that failed to achieve the control of
behavior that he took as the true measure of scientific understanding.
Use ESRC eee Aa NEI SO FEES ERA NI SSE IE EIS ESOT LA RE CEO NEES EBS ELIE DEE OLDEST LEDGES SE LLC ELE LINED SLES
omputer
simulation techniques have had a profound effect on the character of theorizing
in psychology. As in all fields of science, they have enabled exploration of com-
plexities that formerly had to be ignored. Many modern theories discussed in this
book depend on computer simulation techniques, including theories of animal
conditioning, human memory, and the neural basis of learning.
Newell and Simon’s use of the computer was more than mere simulation,
however.
Sasa TS eS SoHo ©
metaphor aspect of their theories remains controversial, and its acceptance is
difficult for most psychologists, who believe that the human brain is very differ-
24
History of Research on Learning and Memory
ent from a computer and that theories based on analogy to computers are like-
ly to be misleading (e.g., Rumelhart & McClelland, 1986).
Newell and Simon’s influence led to the development of a number Of sim-
ulations of cognition and learning at Carnegie Mellon and elsewhere. However,
their greatest contribution was not to the study of learning per se but to prob-
lem solving. A difficulty in earlier theories of learning was determining
the rela-
tionship between knowledge (what the organism learned from experience) and
-behaviar How did a creature’s acquisition of new knowledge relate to behavior?
As indicated, some behaviorists such as Thorndike and Hull, merged the two
issues and argued that behavioral tendencies were learned—that there was no
difference between knowledge and behavior. Tolman’s major criticism was
directed against this position, but he was unable to derive a coherent alterna-
tive. Newell and Simon in their theory of problem solving showed how knowl-
edge could be decoupled from behavior and still result in behavior. Along the
way, they showed that rigorous and precise theories of behavior could allow
mentalistic constructs. More than anything else, this demonstration destroyed
the prohibitions against mentalism that Watson had introduced to the field 50
years earlier. In eliminating these prohibitions, Newell and Simon established
the basis for the cognitive revolution that has transformed all of psychology,
including learning theory.
pie
of Newell
center
The cework was the General Problem
and Simon’s
Solver, or GPS (Newell & Simon, 1972).GPS was a computer simulation that
used a way of deploying knowledge in problem solving called means-ends
analThe ysis . in applying means-ends analysis are the
basic steps following:
1. Identify the major difference between the current situation and the goal;
ifm a.- é@##° ~~ ieee
2. Seleet-some-action
that is relevant to eliminating
that difference; that is,
select some means relevant tothat end. Newell and Simon
used the term
operator to refer to the actionormeans. An operator
is much-ike-an-oper-
ant in Skinner’s theory.
Qo. If the operator can be applied, apply it. Ifnot, make the goal to enable the
operator and start over again at step 1; that is, make the means thenew
end.
—
Newell and Simon (1972) give the following everyday example of means—ends
analysis:
25
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
26
History of Research on Learning and Memory
e€ petinahenit TepOsit
Rehearsal
Short-term Long-term
Incoming information Transfer memory
memory
Displaced
FIGURE 1.11 The Atkinson and Shiffrin (1968) theory relating short-term and long-
term memory. Incoming items enter short-term memory and can be maintained there by
rehearsal. As an item is rehearsed, information about it is transferred to long-term mem-
ory. Another item coming in can displace an existing item from short-term memory.
D7.
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
1.0 13}
0.9 11
0.8 2
2 9
3 ®
£07 s
9 i)
eal 37
8
s 0.6
.~ E=
a } 5 5
es |= 2
3
0.4
experimen
for aa Roce to recall the ‘words inany ¢order.
experiment results in what is
is called they
Figure 1. 12a
FoRa
list 0
28
History of Research on Learning and Memory
The recency effect is easiest to explain in the Atkinson and Shiffrin theo-
The last word is definitely still in the buffer. The next tolast word is
in the-buffer
unless it was deleted to accommodate the last. The decreasing
recall farther from the end reflects the decreasing probability that the item is still
in short-term memory.
According to Atkinson and Shiffrin’s theo
they are pushed out by an intervening word. Rundus (1971) asked subjects to
rehearse out loud and was able to show that the probability of recalling a par-
ticular word could be predicted from the number of times it was rehearsed. As
postulated by Atkinson and Shiffrin, the words at the beginning of a list received
more rehearsals. Rundus’s results are displayed in Figure 1.12b, which illustrates
The research paradigms on which this theory was based were rather sim-
ple experiments like this:free=recall experiment. They reflected a return to the
kinds of experimental paradigms introduced by Ebbinghaus almost a century
earlier. As more complex experiments have been performed, doubts have risen
about the Atkinson and Shiffrin theory. -
. The Atkinson and Shiffrin
30
Neural Basis of Learning and Memory
FIGURE1.13_ Representative brains of different animals show how large the human
brain is compared with those of other animals.
tem refers to parts of the brain that are at the border between the cortex and
these lower structures. The limbic system and in particular the hippocampus,
which is embedded within the temporal lobe, are impo are
discussed inma wpters.
The hippocampus is not shown in Figures 1.14 or
1.15 because it is neither a structure on the outside nor a structure at the center;
rather, it is inside the temporal lobe between the central structures and the sur-
face of the cortex.
The cortex itself can be divided by major folds into four regions, shown in
Figure 1.14. The occipital lobe is devoted mainly to vision, The temporal.lobe
has the primary auditory areas and
is also involved in the recognition of objects.
The parietal lobe is involved with a number of higher-level sensory functions,
including spatial processing.The frontal lobe can be divided into the motor cor-
tex, which is involved with movement,
and theprefrontal cortex. The prefrontal
cortex is much larger in primates than in other animals,
in apes (such as chim-
panzees) than in other primates (such as monkeys), and in humans than in apes.
It is thought to be important to planning and problem solving. We will discuss its
role in Chapter 5 on memory and in Chapter 9 on problem solving. Most areas
of the cortex are thought to be capable of supporting various sorts of learning.
31
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
Motor cortex 2 :
Primary somatic
Central sulcus sensory cortex
Parietal-temporal—
occipital association
cortex
Prefrontal Bs
association es Occipital lobe
cortex LP E
a) SSS*
Primary visual
Broca's area cortex
K
——
Temporal | lobe
lob ASSWw” Sylvian fissure
Primary
auditory cortex
Wernicke's
area
FIGURE 1.14 A side view of the cerebral cortex. Source: From E. R. Kandel, J. H.
Schwartz, and T. M. Jessell. Principles of neural science. Third Edition. Copyright ©
1991 by Appleton and Lange. Reprinted by permission.
Corpus
callosum
Optic nerve
Pituitary
Hypothalamus
Midbrain Cerebellum
Pons Medulla
FIGURE 1.15 Major components of the brain. (From Keeton, 1980.) Source:
Reproduced from Biological science, Third Edition, by William T. Keeton, illustrated by
Paula DiSanto Bensadoun, by permission of W. W. Norton & Company, Inc.
Copyright © 1980, 1979, 1978, 1972, 1967 by W. W. Norton & Company, Inc.
on
Neural Basis of Learning and Memory
The Neuron
Dendrite
Receptor
cell
Cell body
Dendrite
Cell body
Peripheral
branch
ae @)
Myelin sheath |
Axon
Schwann cell
pene Central
branch
Neuromuscular
junction
FIGURE 1.16 Some of the varieties of neurons. (From Keeton, 1980.) Source:
Reproduced from Biological science, Third Edition, by William T. Keeton, illustrated by
Paula DiSanto Bensadoun, by permission of W. W. Norton & Company, Inc.
Copyright © 1980, 1979, 1978, 1972, 1967 by W. W. Norton & Company, Inc.
es)
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
Cell body
Arborizations ee
sats EE IE ae
Dendrites Nucleus
34
Neural Basis of Learning and Memory
has, the more rapidly the action potential moves down the axon. When this
moving action potential, called the nerve impulse, reaches the ends of the
axon, it causes the axon to release neurotransmitters, thus starting. a new cycle
of communication among neurons. The time for information to progress from
the dendrite of one neuron through its axon to the dendrite of another neuron
is roughly 10 msec.
It is thought that all information processing in the nervous system
involves this passage of signals among neurons. As you read this page, neurons
are sending signals from your eye to your brain. As you write, signals are sent
from the brain to the muscles. Cognitive processing involves sending signals
among neurons within the brain. At any one time, billions of neurons are active,
sending signals to one another.
Neurons can be thought of as more or less active. Activity level refers both
to the degree of reduction in the difference in membrane potential and to the
rate at which nerve impulses are sent down neurons. The rate at which nerve
impulses are generated along the axon is called the rate
of firing; it is general-
lythought
that the number of firings,not the temporal pattern of the firings, is
__
important. Neurons can fire at the rate of
100/sec or more. Generally, the more
active a neuron is, the stronger the message it is sending. For instance, the way
in which a motor neuron tells a muscle to increase the force of its action is by
increasing its rate of firing.
Learning involves a change in behavior and so must involve some change
in the way neurons communicate. It is currently believed that changes in such
communication involve changes in the synaptic connections among neurons.
Learning takes place by making existing synaptic connections more effective.
The axon may emit more of a neurotransmitter, or the cell membrane may
become more responsive to the neurotransmitter. Recall that neurotransmitters
have either excitatory influences, reducing the difference in membrane poten-
tial, or inhibitory influences, increasing the difference; inhibitory influences can
be as important as excitatory influences. Many cells have spontaneous rates of
firing, and learning can involve lowering these rates.
IS HERI ESSER ASTANA SLES ESI AIR OLESEN NM REIN CELE REELS eee er Dd
aoa,
BE acommunicate
CE Wap one
Ln, DIES mS at synaptic
PUOICT GS SVT GP Tie
COMEconnec-
tions where one neuron may inhibit or excite the neural activi-
tyofanother neuron. BRS WALEED ESSE RSBAS REESE SME NORIO ARMS AE NRE VINO ISEIELE
35
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
regions of cells. This can be done by measuring electrical potentials on the scalp
or by measuring changes in blood flow with new imaging techniques. Such
techniques allow researchers to see what regions of the brain tend to be more
active in particular tasks. For example, during a spatial reasoning task, areas of
the brain that perform spatial reasoning are more active. In another method, sci-
entists insert electrodes in lower animals to record what is happening in specif-
ic cells. They then infer from the patterns recorded in a hundred or so cells what
is happening in the remaining neurons in that region. Another methodology
used with lower organisms is selective removal of areas of the brain. For exam-
ple, as described in Chapter 3, much has been learned about the role of the hip-
pocampus in memory by studying organisms from which it has been removed.
Humans who have suffered damage to specific regions of the brain from acci-
dental injuries can also be studied. Finally, scientists can study the connections
among neurons and how neurons interact with each other. From this informa-
tion, they can devise computer simulation models of possible patterns of inter-
action among subsets of neurons.
Brain study is one of the most rapidly growing areas in psychology and has
provided genuine insights into what may underlie different learning phenome-
na. However, we are still far from an adequate understanding of the neural basis
of learning or memory. Thus, the majority ofthis book isdevoted. to.behavioral
36
Outline of the Book
37
CHAPTER 1 Perspectives on Learning and Memory
Further Readings
Several books recount the history of psychology, including Leahey (1992) and
Wertheimer (1979). Boring (1950) remains a classic review of the early history of
experimental psychology. Bower and Hilgard (1981) provide an excellent dis-
cussion of the major theories of learning. Kandel, Schwartz, and Jessell (1991)
offer a thorough discussion of the nervous system and the neural basis of learn-
ing and behavior. Gazzaniga, Ivry, & Mangun (1998) and Banich (1997) provide
overviews of the neural basis of cognition.
38
lassical Conditioning
Overview
Twenty-five years ago I ate crab for the first time. Shortly thereafter, I developed
a horrific stomach flu (I will spare you the details) which had been going around.
To this day I get nauseous when I am offered crab. This is an example of classical
conditioning. As discussed in the previous chapter, aconditioned stimulus (CS—
this case, crab) had been paired with an unconditioned stimulus (US—in this
case, flu) that produced an unconditioned response (UR—in this case, extreme
nausea). The result was that the CS acquired the ability to evoke a conditioned
response (CR—again nausea in this case). As we will discuss later in this chapter,
food aversion can be a particularly powerful version of classical conditioning. It
certainly is in my case—I am getting nauseous just writing this paragraph.
39
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
Time ——AAARL-AN|NV\_\YNYraa—_—
Experimenter’s presentation cS US
sequence: (tone) (air puff)
Organism’s response: UR
(eye blink)
(b) Conditioned.response
Experimenter’s presentation CS US
sequence: (tone) (air puff)
Organism’s response: CR UR
(eye blink) (eye blink)
(c) Extinction
Experimenter’s presentation CS
i ae ,
sequence: (tone)
\ Tey
Organism’s response: CR
} (eye blink)
FIGURE 2.1 /Experimental procedure for classical conditioning of the eye blink.
Compare with Figure 1.3.
=
tion of the conditioned response. In one experiment (Moore & Gormezano, 1961),
the interval between the CS and the US was 500 msec. Subjects were given 70
acquisition trials in which the CS was followed by the US and then 20 extinction
trials in which the CS was presented alone. Figure 2.2 shows the percentage of tri-
100 Beginning of
extinction
CRs
of
Percent
40
The Phenomena of Classical Conditioning: Eye Blink in Humans
100
80
= 60
So
& 40
20
als in which subjects emitted a CR in anticipation of the puff of air. As in the sali-
vation data presented in Figure 1.4, these human subjects showed a rather stan-
dard conditioning curve, in which the probability of the CR increased, followed by
a standard extinction curve, in which the probability of the CR decreased. If one
waits for a while after extinction, one finds spontaneous recovery of the extin-
guished CR. That is, when tested again without the US, the probability of the CR
increases from its former extinguished level (Grant, Hunter, & Patel, 1958).
Another standard parameter of a classical conditioning experiment is the
interval between the CS and the US. McAllister (1953) varied the time between
a CS of atone and the US of an air puff using intervals of 100, 250, 450, 700, and
2500 msec. Figure 2.3 shows the results in terms of percentage of conditioned
responses after 20 conditioning trials. Nearly maximal conditioning was
achieved in the intervals between 250 and 700 msec, which are typical values for
optimal conditioning in many, but not all, conditioning paradigms.
41
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
a series of tones, but there will not be any relationship between them.
Nonetheless, the subject will show some increase in the tendency to show a CR
of blinking when the tone occurs (Grant & Norris, 1947). Indeed, the experiment
can be run with the US presented alone a number of times before the CS is first
given. Then, upon first occurrence of the CS there is an increased tendency to
emit
an eye blink. Thi
tioning experiments te.g., Beecroft, 1966; Oldfield, 1937). In this case, the mag-
nitude of the response is decreasing as the subject becomes exposed to the US.
It is as if the subject is becominggiiiaae? and no longer has as strong a reac-
tion to the US. As a consequence, the size of the conditioned response can
decrease. For instance, Grant (1939) found a gradual decrease of both the fre-
quency and amplitude of the eyelid response to the CS.
Both nd
Habituationvare classified as
ecause they do not depend on the relationship between the CS and
= — ERTS sgRAPER “
\ abit e From
experiment to experiment, their net effect may be either an increased respon-
siveness or a decreased responsiveness (Groves & Thompson, 1970). In all cases,
it is necessary to separate these nonassociative forms of learning from the asso-
ciative learning that defines classical conditioning.
42
What This Chapter Covers
voluntarily choosing to blink so that they can avoid the light. Human subjects
report being aware of the CS—US relationship and blinking in response to the
US (Grant, 1973). However, they tend to be unaware that they are blinking to
the CS in anticipation of the US. It has nonetheless been argued that certain
eyeblink CRs look like eye blinks that subjects give when instructed to blink; in
particular, the eye closes more sharply, more rapidly, and stays closed longer
when it is a voluntary response (Spence & Ross, 1959). Considerable controver-
sy remains over whether it is possible to discriminate between automatic and
voluntary eye blinks (Gormezano, 1965; Ross, 1965).
At one time, classical conditioning was considered automatic, and instru-
mental conditioning was considered voluntary. This viewpoint led to the argu-
ment that the purported voluntary eye blinks in a classical conditioning para-
digm were really instances of covert instrumental conditioning in which the
human was responding for the reward of avoiding the aversive puff of air. This
distinction has not proved useful and is not pursued here. Whether voluntary or
automatic, certain behavioral regularities tend to be associated with condition-
ing. Research has focused on understanding these regularities. An important
theme in modern research is that classical conditioning servesan adaptive func-
tion, whatever the awareness of the organism or the degree
of voluntariness in
responding.
43
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
After this review, the chapter discusses the behavioral properties of classical
conditioning. In particular, subsequent sections address the following questions:
What is associated?
What is the conditioned stimulus?
What is the conditioned response?
What is the nature of the association?
The answers are surprising in light of earlier views about classical conditioning.
The Rescorla—Wagner theory, an elegant but simple theory that captures much
of the complex structure of the data, is presented later in this chapter.
Neural Basis of
Classical Conditioning
As reviewed in Chapter 1, Pavlov speculated, incorrectly, about what was hap-
pening in the nervous system to underlie classical conditioning. More recently,
researchers have traced the neural bases of certain instances of classical condi-
tioning in certain organisms. This research offers a glimpse of the neural mecha-
nisms behind the behavioral phenomena and may provide a sobering influence
on overly simplistic or overly grandiose interpretations of classical conditioning.
As we have seen, neural information processing takes place through trans-
mission of signals among neurons, which are the individual cells that make up
the nervous system. Neurons transmit signals from one part of the nervous sys-
tem to another by sending electrical pulses along their axons. The axon of one
neuron makes contact with the cell bodies of other neurons. The point of contact
between the axon of one neuron and the cell body of another neuron is called
the synapse, and communication is achieved by transmitter chemicals, called neu-
rotransmitters, going from the axon of one neuron to the other neuron. These
neurotransmitters can increase or decrease the electrical potential of the neuron.
If enough electrical potential accumulates-on-its cell body, a neuron sends-a sig-
nal down its axon.It is_generally-believed_that learning involves changes in the
effectiveness of synaptic connections among neurons, so that one neuron comes
to produce greaterchanges in the
thelectrical
calpotential of
olanother.
44
Neural Basis of Classical Conditioning
Mantle
45
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
(ie)Sensory
neuron
Facilitating
interneuron
Motor
neuron
Sensory
neuron
FIGURE 2.5 Neural connec-
tions underlying the condi-
tioning of the gill-withdrawal
reflex in Aplysia.
siphon and the motor neurons. They change the synaptic connection by increas-
ing the release of the neurotransmitter from the sensory neuron coming from
the siphon. This process is referred to as because it
enhances a process that is occurring on the axon side of the synapse.
studied the-structural basis for these changes in
chemical chain reaction that results in more release sites at the synapse of the sen-
sory neuron from the siphon. This Wl facilitation iis maximal if the senso-
46
Neural Basis of Classical Conditioning
prlisher sett
Classical Conditioning of the Eye Blink in the Rabbit NO
Thompson (e.g., 1986) engaged in an extensive project studying the neural basis
for a more complex example of classical conditioning, the conditioning of the
eye blink in the rabbit. In the standard procedure
ormezano, Kehoe, & Marshall,
1983). The CS is a tone, which also comes to evoke an eye blink (CR), although
at greater latency. (The latency for the UR is about 20 msec from air puff to blink,
whereas the latency for the CR is about 70 msec from tone to blink.)
Figure 2.6 illustrates some of the complex circuitry that is relevant to under-
standing this instance of classical conditioning. Sensory neurons from the cornea
synapse onto the fifth cranial nerve, from which neurons go to the sixth and sev-
enth cranial nerves, from which motor neurons go to produce the eye blink. This
Cerebellum
FIGURE 2.6 Simplified diagram of the neural circuitry responsible for eye blink
conditioning.
47
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
circuit, which produces the UR, takes about 20 msec. A second, longer circuit
goes from the fifth cranial nerve to an intermediate neuron, and from there to the
cerebellum (a subcortical structure—see Figure 1.15). Among other neurons in
the cerebellum, this path synapses onto cells in a structure called the interposi-
tus. There is also a path of synapses going back from the interpositus to the eye
blink, which produces a discrete genoa component to the eye blink
ff of ai (
‘Honing! There is a circuit by which sensory neurons encoding the tone (CS)
synapse onto the ventral cochlear nucleus, and from there by intermediate neu-
. It is generally thought
C\ that the since lesions (selective
removal of neural tissue) to the cerebellum eliminate eyeblink conditioning. In
addition to the paths by which the CS projects to the Purkinje cells, there are
paths by which the US projects to Purkinje cells. The Purkinje cells synapse onto
the interpositus, which is part of both the CR and the UR paths. The logic by
which the CS is thought to evoke the CR is somewhat complicated:
1. The Purkinje cells normally tend to inhibit the interpositus from evoking
the response.
2. Learning involves developing inhibitory connections from the CS path to
the Purkinje cells.
inhibiting the Purkinje cells, which nor-
| = (In effect, two neural neg-
atives are SOMME to make a neural positive.) Electrodes put into the cere-
bellum to record from the Purkinje cells show reduced firing after conditioning,
which is in line with this proposal. This situation is different and more complex
than that of conditioning in Aplysia. The path of conditioning in Aplysia involves
two neurons directly associated so that the sensory neuron turns on the motor
neuron. In the rabbit, the path involves more than a half-dozen neurons and has
the sensory stimulus turning off the cells that normally turn off the eye blink.
Although not as thoroughly studied, other instances of mammalian classical
conditioning appear equally or more complex and involve different neural struc-
tures from the spinal cord to the cortex and different neural circuitry and mod-
ifications (Thompson, Donegon, & Lavond, 1988). No single neural process
underlies all classical conditioning.
Despite the diversity of neural realizations, classical conditioning presents
a rather consistent picture at the behavioral level. These behavioral regularities
are identified next.
48
S-S or S—R Associations
Se ae rn
(a) SS, ea he
to door)
Se ees
(leash)
eee
;
~
(b) us ——————> UR )
SS teh 9
bye to walk) (go to door)
= se (leash)
FIGURE 2.7. The two possibilities for association formation in classical condition-
ing: (a) the CS is associated to the UR, and (b) the CS is associated to the US.
49
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
UR all met in the cerebellum, it could be argued that the CS and the US were
ed at the Purkinje cells.
Response-Prevention Paradigm
50
S-S or S—-R Associations
SN
RP Ral LOMES IRIE EERE RNC ON ERAS ART UL TRB aaa SN aed SUN
US Devaluation Paradigm
A different test of the S-S versus S—R alternatives involves devaluing the US _
after classical conditioning has taken place (e.g., Holland & Rescorla, 1975;
Rescorla, 1973). For instance, aCS of light can be paired with a US of food for
hungry rats. The CS comes to evoke a number of responses associated with the
US of food, including increased activity (Holland & Rescorla, 1975). The rats can
then be satiated. When the rats are no longer hungry, will the CS (the light) still
evoke activity? If the CS were directly associated to the CR, it would still pro-
duce increased activity. On the other hand, if the CS had producedincreased
activitythrough anticipation of the US of food, and the US had lost its power to
produce increased activity, the CS would lose its power to evoke activity. In fact,
it loses itsability toevoke activity implying that S=Sassociations were formed.
This type of test is referred to as a devaluation paradigm. The US is
devalued. Ifthe CSisdirectly associated to the CR, i t if
devaluation, but if it is associated to the US, it will be affected. As another exam-
ple, consider the conditioned emotional response, or CER, behaviors, such as
freezing, shown by animals such as rats to CSs in anticipation of aversive stim-
uli, such as shock (see Chapter 1). The shock US can be devalued by repeated
administration (in the absence of the CS), which makes the rat less sensitive to
it (an example of habituation introduced earlier with respect to the human eye
blink). When the CS is finally presented after such US devaluation, the rat
shows a reduced CER. Generally, the response to the CS is reduced when the
US is devalued, indicating that the CS was associated to the US.
asec ee eee sce CARSINS UR UU EU EI SAE UH EN ELON EEE RIT EEO RAS OOOO seats eens
51
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
What happens if the other neutral stimulus, the light (CS,), is then pre-
sented? If classical conditioning involves associating responses to stimuli, noth-
ing will fips cbceauedtttaclia Honea engined aaieget a OS the
other hand, if stimuli are directly associated,_the
thelight
light (CS.)
(CS,) will
will evoke
evoke the
the antic-
ant
ipation of the tone (CS,), because of their pairing, which in turn will evoke the
5 iT : F
anticipation of the shock (US). Thu
52
What Is the Conditioned Stimulus?
first-order CS,, suggesting an S-S association between CS, and the US.
However, it does not lead to reduced responding to the second- as CS,, sug-
gesting a direct association between CS, (tone) and the CR (activity). If the first-
order association is extinguished by Ee ane light without food, the second-
order association is not extinguished and the tone continues to produce
increased activity (e.g., Amiro & Bitterman, 1980). Thus, the surprising result
from this and other second-order conditioning experiments seems to be that
first-order associations are S-S and second-order associations are S-R.
However, some second-order conditioning experiments (e.g., Rashotte, Griffin,
& Sisk, 1977) have found evidence for S—S second-order associations.
Conclusions
The current conception (e.g., Holland, 1985a) is that both the stimulus and
response aspects of subsequent events compete for association to the stimulus.
Different paradigms produce S-S or S-R associations, depending on whether
the subsequent stimulus or response aspects are more salient or prominent. A
preconditioning expe
experiment provides evidence for S-S associations because no
salient responses are associate er
conditioning experiment supports S—R associations because the prior oe order
conditioning usually gives the CS, response characteristics that are more salient
than_its stimulus characteristics. First-order associations are more often S-S in
character because the US is typically so salient. Table 2.1 attempts to summarize
the results. There are threeparadigms:‘standard,
s which involves one pairing,
and1 (2)the sensory preconditioning and (3) second-order conditioning, which
‘involve two pairings but differ in their ordering. S-osassociations
ns appear to be
the rule* ePL Se Tespe foCS, association sin
53
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
that a slightly different stimulus, such as 1010 Hz, should elicit the association
but that a very different one (the flash of light) should not.
Siegel, Hearst, George, and O’Neil (1968) conditioned the eyelid response
in rabbits to tones of different frequencies. Different rabbits experienced tones
with frequencies of 500, 1000, 2000, 3000, or 4000 Hz paired with a puff of air to
the eye. They were then tested with a variety of stimuli at different frequencies.
Figure 2.8 shov
ot the | \ Ep enomena of
s generalization
and discrimination are discussed at greater length in the
next chapter inasmuch as they have received more attention in research on
instrumental
wiance conditioning.
ue
54
What Is the Conditioned Response?
fe))(=)
f (e)
500 Hz
ie)(2)
o (eo)
Bh(ce
1000 Hz
20
60
40
2000 Hz
20
Total
%responses,
60
40
3000 Hz
fl
al
20
sion. Frequency Hz
55
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
in the organism to begin with because it is adaptive. Thus, the CS-CR connec-
tion also tends to be adaptive.
One kind of evidence for the preparatory character of the CR comes from
cases in which the CR is not the same as the UR. A striking example concerns
heart-rate changes in response to electric shock. The unconditioned response to
electric shock is heart-rate acceleration; but in some organisms the conditioned
response is heart-rate deceleration (Obrist, Sutterer, & Howard, 1972;
Schneiderman, 1973). In anticipation of a shock, the organism relaxes, which
may reduce the perceived magnitude of the pain. This relaxing reduces the heart
rate. Similarly, some organisms, such as rats, tend to show increased activity in
response to shock but freeze in response to a stimulus associated with shock
(Rescorla, 1988b). Thus, the behavioral responses to the CS can be quite the
opposite of the responses to the US, but both can be viewed as adaptive
responses. The shock is a noxious stimulus that requires escape, whereas the CS
is treated as a warning that may require a different response. For example, in
nature when an animal sees a predator (CS), freezing may help it avoid detec-
tion, but once the predator attacks (US), flight is the appropriate response.
A number of unconditioned responses involve a biphasic structure in which
an initial response is followed by an opposing response. One of the most dramat-
ic involves responses to narcotics, such as heroin. The initie
initial
tialrresponse to heroin, a
feeling of euphoria, isfollowed by a second, opponent
response, which tends to
counteract the initial response and produces unpleasant withdrawal symptoms.
Anothér example of Pe gaa See eee The
feelings of terror the skydiver has just before the dive are followed by an antago-
nistic response of pleasure when the dive is successful. Solomon and Corbit (1974)
suggest that the antagonistic opponent response is caused by the body trying to
avoid extreme arousal states, which are demanding of resources. Also, in the case
of heroin, the increased pain threshold it produces can also be dangerous.
Wagner (1981) proposed that in the case of such biphasic URs, the com-
pensatory second response is conditioned to the CS because it isan appropriate
response to blunt the effect of the
US-On the other hand, when the UR is
asic, like an eye blink, and does not involve an opponent process, the
UR is conditioned because the UR is the appropriate response in anticipation of
such a US.* Wagner called his theory SOP, forsometimes opponent process,
because
luse sometimes (i.(i.e., in the case of biphasic responses) the conditioned
response-is the opponent process.
It has been suggested that the conditioning of the opponent process is
responsible for drug tolerance (Siegel,-1983). With repeated use of a drug, the
“However, even in the case of the eye blink, Wagner distinguished two components
and argued that only the second component becomes conditioned. His position is
supported by Thompsons research on the circuitry underlying eyeblink condition-
ing reviewed earlier. This research showed that the unconditioned eye blink had two
components: one with a latency of 20 msec and one with a latency of 70 msec. The
longer-latency component forms the basis for the CR.
56
What Is the Conditioned Response?
high becomes weaker and weaker; consequently, the addict needs to take more
and more of the drug to produce the same high. It is claimed that the stimuli that
accompany drug use (for example, a needle) serve as a CS that becomes ¢ondi-
tioned to a second, opponent process. Thus, the conditioning of the opponent
process is producing the drug tolerance. The CR evoked by these stimuli is the
opponent process that negates the effect of the drug. There is evidence that much
of the tolerance built up to drugs such as morphine can be removed by changing
the stimuli that accompany their administration (for a review, see Siegel, 1983).
Akins, Domjan, and Guitierez (1994) provide an interesting example of
how the CR adapts to the circumstances of the US. They were looking at condi-
tioning of sexual behavior in male quail where the US was access to a female and
the CS was the appearance of foam block with bright orange feathers where the
female would eventually appear. This CS evoked a CR of searching behavior,
which is different from the UR to the US, which would be to engage in courtship
and copulatory responses. Again we can see that the CR is behavior in anticipa-
tion of the US. In this case, the quail is looking for the female that the CS signals.
In addition to this basic result, Atkins et al. manipulated the delay between
the CS and the US in the conditioning experiment. They used either 1 minute
or 20 minutes. These are long CS—US intervals compared to the experiments we
have considered so far (e.g., Figure 2.3). As we will see later in the chapter, how-
ever, conditioning can sometimes be obtained at even longer CS—US intervals
than 20 minutes for some kinds of US. Atkins et al. were interested in the dif-
ference in the nature of the conditioned searching behavior at these two delays.
They classified the searching behavior as focused (the quail actually approached
the CS) or general (the quail just ran around). Figure 2.9 compares the percent-
age of general versus focused search in the two conditions. As can be seen,
14 (-
-= Close to CS
-e Far from CS
fon)
(oe)
Moves
minute
per
Vi
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
search focused near the CS predominated when the CS-US interval was 1
minute, whereas there was general search everywhere (equal amount of move-
ment close and distant from goal) when it was 20 minutes. Again, this makes
sense. If the CS signals a mate in 20 minutes, then the female can be anywhere
and the quail needs to find her, whereasif the mate is about to appear in a
minute, the quail should approach the CS and wait for his impending opportu-
nity. Thus, not only is the CR an adaptation to the US, but the nature of the
wag coon can vary spa with “otlike the CS-US interval.
aN
or instance, when my two sons watch TV, they argue. However, my two sons
argue a lot when they are involved in other activities, too. Thus, the mere co-
occurrence of TV and arguments does not mean that there is a contingency (i.e.,
watching TV causes them to argue). The probability of arguments must be
greater when the TV is on for there to be a contingency. Stated symbolically, a
predictive or contingent relationship requires
P(argument |TV) > P(argument | TV )
where P(argument |TV) is the probability of an argument when the TV is on and
P(argument |TV ) is the probability of an argument when the TV is not on.
Rescorla’s Experiment
Rescorla (1968b) conducted an experiment to determine whether contiguity or
contingency is essential in classical conditioning. He intermittently presented a
2-min tone while rats were pressing a bar. In different conditions, he presented
58
Association: The Role of Contingency
110));=
r + P(USICS) = 0.4
0.8
ie ~e-P(USICS) = 0.2
~- P(USICS) = 0.1
5
fa
FIGURE 2.10 Dependence of condi-
tioning on both P(US| CS) (likelihood
of the US during the CS interval) and
P(US1CS) (likelihood of the US in the
absence of the CS). (Adapted from . 0.0 95 yO. fe pO:2g 00:3. hae 0,4
Rescorla, 1968.) P(US| CS)
shock during 10, 20, and 40 percent of these 2-min tone intervals. Rescorla was
interested in the degree to which the rats would show a CER (freezing) and
decrease their rate of bar pressing during a tone interval.
Rescorla also varied the probability of shock during the 2-min intervals
when no tone was present, creating three separate conditions with 10 percent,
20 percent, or 40 percent probability of a shock during the no-tone intervals.
Figure 2.10 shows the results for various combinations of probability of shock in
59
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
Conditioned Inhibition
The previous paradigm demonstrated that organisms show conditioning when
the probability of the US is greater in the presence of the CS. What if the proba-
bility is lower? it ce ere Ik 1 S
60
Association: The Role of Contingency
SERINE MAAAENRERUN NOE EH AR ES RE ARSON SDA AN DUI AREAS AEDT ES
HSRE SARDITOOOS SMILE EAN ASSO ON EISEN ANTI POE TREN SRNREE EBA
Associative Bias
This chapter has reviewed the evidence that organisms are sensitive to the sta-
tistical regularity between a CS and a US. There is also evidence, however, that
they are predisposed to associate certain CSs to certain USs independent of
their: : reference for certai tions isreferred to as
associative bias, which is similar to ppormcigs s concept ofbelongingness dis-
cussedin the first Chapter.
uppose you heard a loud noise that sounded like an explosion followed
by the shaking of the ground. How likely would you be to think the explosion
sound and the shaking of the ground were related? Suppose, on the other hand,
you heard a bird’s song followed by the shaking of the ground? How likely would
you be to think that the bird sound and the shaking were related? Presumably,
you would think the first pair was more probably related than the second pair.
Certain pairs of stimuli are more likely to be related than are other pairs of stim-
uli, and organisms condition more readily with such pairs of stimuli.
In a well-known study, Garcia and Koelling (1966) used rats whose only
access to water was from a water spout. While drinking the water, the rats were
exposed to a compound CS consisting of a flavor component (a saccharine
taste) and an audiovisual component (light flash and click). Different groups of
rats then received either a shock or an injection of a drug that produced nausea.
Garcia and Koelling tested the rats separately with saccharin-flavored water and
with the audiovisual stimulus to see which had a greater impact on water intake.
Rats that had received a shock later showed greater CER (i.e., reduced drinking)
to the audiovisual stimulus, whereas rats that had received the injection showed
greater CER to the flavor stimulus. Thus, rats were more prepared to associate a
CS of light with a US of shock and a CS of flavor with a US of poisoning. A great
deal of subsequent research has focused on conditioned taste aversions of a dis-
tinctive taste (CS) with a poisoning (US). Rats (and many other organisms,
including humans) learn such taste aversions after a single CS—US pairing and
after intervals between the CS and US up to 24 hours (Etscorn & Stephens,
1973). It is unusual for conditioning to operate over such long time delays (e.g.,
see Figure 2.3). Organisms presumably have this unusually strong propensity to
associate taste and poisoning because it is adaptive.
The associations that organisms are prepared to form are somewhat species
SEE coxon, Dragon, andKralTGS7D compared usingthe CS of water taste
(sour) or water color (dark blue) in conditioning to a US of poisoning .They com-
pared rats and quail and found that rats displayed greater aversion to taste and
quail displayed greater aversion to color. This result makes sense when the two
61
CHAPTER 2 Classical. Conditioning
species are compared. Rats are nocturnal animals with an excellent sense of taste
and smell but with poor vision; quail are daytime animals with excellent vision, and
they use this vision to select appropriate foods (e.g., seeds that are not poisonous).
In some situations, a conditioned food aversion can be a serious problem.
For instance, cancer patients undergoing chemotherapy develop strong aver-
sions to the foods they eat because chemotherapy produces nausea; thus, they
do not eat adequate food. One means of combating this problem is to schedule
eating and chemotherapy so that food intake does not precede nausea. Another
possibility for patients is to consume a bland diet, because nondistinctive stim-
uli do not appear to become conditioned as readily as distinctive stimuli. Yet
another possibility is to have patients consume a very distinctive-tasting food
before the onset of nausea so that the taste aversion will only be conditioned to
that stimulus. For example, the problem of taste aversion with children was
reduced if they received a distinctive-tasting “mapletoff” ice cream before
chemotherapy (Bernstein, Webster, & Bernstein, 1982).
P(HIE) _ P(H)|P(EIH)
P(HIE) P(H) P(EIH)
- where P(H|E) is the posterior probability of the hypothesis given the evidence;
P(H |E) is 1—(P1H); P(H) is the prior probability of the hypothesis; P(H) is 1 -— P(A);
P(E|H) is the conditional probability of the evidence given the hypothesis; and
P(E |H)is the conditional probability of the evidence given that the hypothesis is false.
62
Conditioning to Stimulus Combinations
Blocking
Experiments have shown that an association is not formed with one CS if
another CS is more informative. In one experiment, Kamin (1968) contrasted
two groups:
Control. The animals experienced eight trials in which CSs of noise and
light were followed by shock.
Experimental. The animals received 16 trials in which just the noise was
followed by the shock. Then, like the control condition, the animals
received eight trials in which a CS of noise and light was followed by shock.
Kamin conducted separate tests to determine whether the CER could be evoked
to noise or to light. He found that the CER had been conditioned to both noise
and light in the control group but only to noise in the experimental group. Thus,
for the experimental group, the CER was not conditioned to the light even
though there were eight reliable pairings of light and shock, which normall
would have produced conditioning.
63
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
CER to the light. The light was now informative because it signaled a more
intense shock.
In another variation of this paradigm, Wagner (1969) trained three groups
of rabbits in an eyeblink-conditioning paradigm in which the US was a 4.5-mA
shock to the area of the eye:
Configural Cues
In the experiments discussed thus far, separate stimuli developed separate asso-
ciations to the US. However, it ispossible to conditiona1an-organism to
respond
to
onl “fa particular configuration of stimuli_are present. Organisms can be
trained to respond when both stimuli A and B are — Sas when just one
is present. Although this result could mean that the AB combination is associ-
ated, it could also indicate that A and B are separately associated to the US but
are too weakly associated to evoke the CR individually and are only strong
enough to do so in combination. Whereas it is possible to explain this result in
terms of separate associations, in some situations the only possible explanation
is that a configuration of stimuli have become associated to the response and
that the individual stimuli are not associated separately. For example, organisms
can also be trained to respond when A is present and when B is present, but not
when AB is present (see Kehoe & Gormezano, 1980, for a review). If there is a
positive strength association between A and the US and between B and the US,
an even stronger association would be expected when both A and B are present.
However, it appears that associations can be learned to cue combinations.In
this case, the cues A + noB and noA + B become associated to the US, but the
combination A + B does not. Another situation that shows configural associa-
tions involves four cues—A, B, C, and D. Organisms can be taught to associate
8
64
The Rescorla-Wagner Theory
Conclusions
In some cases (blocking and conditioned inhibition), it seems that the response
to the combination of stimuli can be predicted from the response to the indi-
vidual stimuli, but in other cases (configural cues) it cannot. The next section
reviews the Rescorla—Wagner theory, which accounts for many of the occasions
when the response to the stimulus combination can be understood in terms of
the response to the individual stimuli.
65
CHAPTER 2 Classical. Conditioning
the rate
Pe of learning,
ee oes a, and
the difference. between the maximum strength possible-and+the-current
strength, (A-V).
(A— |
a aad Cre
where AVis the change instrength, One ccan view A as reflecting the strength
of the actual US and V gece SN aaa be. The
66
The Rescorla-Wagner Theory
vie
80 |-
s l
3 60
ae) E
40+
a
S ie
20 r
cial interest from how it deals with compound cues such as those used in block-
ing experiments. Before considering blocking experiments, consider a simpler
situation. Suppose that two stimuli, A and B, are simultaneously presented as
the CSs for the US. For example, the US might be food, A might be a tone, and
B might be a light. The Rescorla—Wagner theory holds that the total strength of
association between the compound cue and the US, which can be denoted Vyg,
is the sum of the strengths of the individual associations of A and B to the US,
which can be denoted V, and V,. That is,
Vip =Vat Vp
When A and B are paired with the US, they will grow in strength of association
to the US as in the case where there is onlyone CS:
AV, = O&A — Vaz)
é Vz = o0(A — Vip) ae Hy
On the first trial, since theré-is_no prior conditioning, these equations become
(assuming o = .20 and A = 100):
AV, = .20(100 — 0) = 20
A Vz = .20(100 — 0) = 20 "
Thus after the first trial, the individual stimuli have strengths of 20 and Va, is
the sum, or 40. On the next trial, the equations become
67
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
100 -—
Compound
association
of
Strength
and the individual stimuli have strengths 20 + 12 = 32. Figure 2.12 shows the
growth in the strength of association to a single cue when the cue is part of a
compound versus when it is alone. The cue strength of A can only reach 50
because it must share the strength of association with B, which will get the other
e preceding equa ons, 0 is the same forA and B. But Rescorla and
re allow
possibility
for the that the stimuli may varyintheir salience and
therefore one-stimulus may have a moreé rapid learning ra rate.>.Suppose that the
rate-oftearning forA is .4 and for Bit is .1. Figure 2.13 plots the rate of strength
accumulation for the two stimuli. As shown, A overshadows B and acquires
most of the strength. When one stimulus is sufficiently less salient than anoth-
er, it fails to be conditioned when presented in a compound cue, even though it
can be conditioned when presented alone (e.g., Kamin, 1969).
HAN OSS ERR ANOLE NER PENNE TREE ITNT ES NAR EIEN NESEY SEEMING MDS ILIA BIEL SEDENTARY
ADELE ECS Ss
INE REST SEAN EEE ISSR ARRON NUE EEE ESS TUTE
SSE ESR
68
The Rescorla-Wagner Theory
:
60 }—-
More salient r
S i
1
2
7)
g 40
&
8
Ay he
<x
Less salient
20 r
The effect of the first 16 trials is that A has already acquired most of the avail-
able strength and nothing is left for B. That is, the effect of the conditioning is to
set the strength of association to A to full value.
V, = 100
V, will start with an associative strength of 0, but the stimulus combination will
have a strength of 100. That is,
V, + Vz = 100
Since the US strength A is also 100, there will be no difference between it and
the strength of the compound stimuli. Since there is no difference between the
US and the strength, there will be no learning and V, will stay at 0.
The Rescorla—Wagner theory also explains why B conditions if a stronger
shock is used for the AB combination than for A alone. Rescorla and Wagner
postulated that the value of A was related to the intensity of the US. Thus, if a
higher value is used for the shock, as in Kamin (1969), the value of A is larger
and strength is available to be conditioned to B. As noted earlier, B can be con-
ditioned if the shock intensity is increased.
The Rescorla—Wagner theory can also predict the phenomenon of condi-
tioned inhibition discussed earlier. In the paradigm, A (e.g., a clicker) is associ-
ated with the US (e.g., a shock) but AB (e.g., clicker plus flashing light) is not.
The Rescorla—Wagner theory implies that the organism will learn strengths of
association, V, to the clicker and V, to the light, such that
V, = 100
V,+Vzp=0
69
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
100
CS+ (A)
50
association
of
Strength
Trials
FIGURE 2.14 Growth in strength of association for the positive and negative CSs in
a conditioned inhibition paradigm. Source: W. Schneider, “Behavior Research
Methods, Instruments, and Computers,” “Connectionism: Is it a paradigm shift for
psychology?” (1987). Reprinted by permission of W. Schneider.
since A is always associated with shock but the AB combination never is. The
only way these equations can hold is for Vz = —100. Thus, B has a negative
strength of association that corresponds to the result of conditioned inhibition.
Figure 2.14 shows the growth in strength to the positive CS+ (e.g., clicker) and
the negative CS-—(e.g., light) over trials, assuming that the trials presented to the
organism alternate between A (CS+) and AB (CS+ and CS-). The learning
curves go to +100 and —100.
SARUM NIA NPA MOM UZ EN NS PLIERS ARR LATIN
70
The Rescorla-Wagner Theory
im
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
already mentioned the theories that focus on the attention the organism pays to
the CS. Yet other theories propose that the organism compares the relative effec-
tiveness of various CSs in predicting the US and shows conditioning to the
extent a CS is more effective than the alternatives (Gibbon & Balsam, 1981;
Miller & Matzel, 1989). However, these theories have their own difficulties.
Suffice it to say that no theory can capture the many phenomena that have been
documented with classical conditioning.
We have focused on the Rescorla-Wagner theory because it has remained
the reference theory for the field for more than a quarter of a century. In 1997 at
the meeting of the Psychonomics Society, a symposium was held to commemo-
rate the twenty-fifth anniversary of that theory. Few theories survive that long in
psychology, and at that symposium Rescorla offered some speculations to explain
the durability of the theory. He proposed that one of its advantages was that it was
relatively simple and captured many of the phenomena of interest to the field. It
helped set the research agenda for the next 25 years as people explored the
strengths and weaknesses of the theory and developed alternatives. It captured
the basic idea that conditioning involved learning to predict the US and that there
would be learning to the degree that the US was not predicted and so was sur-
prising. The basic learning rule has been used by a number of neural models. At
the same symposium, Gluck proposed that the Rescorla-Wagner learning rule
described one kind of low-level neural learning but that often other kinds of neur-
al learning were taking place as well. In the next section we consider how the
Rescorla—Wagner rule has been used as a model of neural learning.
lees
Neural Realization: The Delta Rule
The Rescorla-Wagner theory corresponds to a current idea about how learning
may take place at the neural level, which has played a particularly important role
in a theory of neural processing called connectionism. This theory stresses the
importance of synaptic connections among neurons. Figure 2.15 illustrates a
typical connectionist processing module where neural activation comes in along
a set of input neurons (at the bottom), each of which synapses onto a set of out-
put neurons. Every input neuron is associated to every output neuron. The pat-
tern of connections presents a more complex situation than that found in
Aplysia (Figure 2.5), where one neuron (a motor neuron) becomes more active
when another neuron (a sensory neuron) becomes active.
Researchers have maintained that the greater complexity of such networks
is required in order to reflect the greater complexity of mammalian behavior and
72
The Rescorla-Wagner Theory
<q
SI Ps Output
neurons
BO
ASIESESS
ES
isS24
BB ea?
BSGEES
ce
RS
BS <
<q
<J
<q
EKE
KEKE
KKK
EKE
KEKKKEK
e LO
/y
KOK
KO
Linesman
bogLgBh:valitiglent |
Input neurons
FIGURE 2.15 Schematic representation of a neural net, where input neurons come
in (at the bottom) and synapse on output neurons (at the right). All input neurons
have synaptic connections to all output neurons. Source: From W. Schneider.
Connectionism. Is it paradigm shift for psychology? Behavior Research Methods,
Instruments & Computers, Volume 19, pp. 73-83. Copyright © 1987. Reprinted by per-
mission of Psychonomic Society, Inc.
learning. It has been argued that human cognition corresponds to patterns of fir-
ing over large numbers of neurons. The learning problem for such a network is to
learn strengths of association among neurons such that when a particular pattern
of activation occurs on the input neurons, a desired pattern of activation appears
on the output neurons. Seen in terms of classical conditioning, each input neuron
corresponds to a CS and each output neuron corresponds to a US. One proposal
for how to achieve such association of patterns is connectionist learning rule,
called the delta rule, which is based on the Rescorla—Wagner equation.
Figure 2.16 illustrates an application of this modeling approach to a med-
ical diagnosis problem studied by Gluck and Bower (1988). Their subjects stud-
ied records of fictitious patients who suffered from four symptoms (a bloody
nose, stomach cramps, puffy eyes, and discolored gums) and made discrimina-
tive diagnoses as to which of two hypothetical diseases the patients had. In this
case, the four symptoms are the inputs and the two diseases are the outputs. For
each patient, the input neurons corresponding to that patient’s symptoms
would be active and the goal would be to have the output neuron correspond-
ing to that patient’s disease active. This problem can be mapped onto the
Rescorla—Wagner theory by having the inputs correspond to CSs and the out-
puts to USs. Just as a rat is trying to predict shock in a particular stimulus situ-
ation, subjects are trying to predict a disease given certain symptoms. The delta
73
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
Rare
disease
Common
disease
AV=a
(A- V)
where AV corresponds to AA,.; « corresponds to aA;; A corresponds to Tj; and
V corresponds to A.. As in the Rescorla—Wagner theory, learning is proportional
to the difference T;— A,. According to the delta rule, learning is also proportion-
al to A,, the level of activation of the input neuron. Recall that one proposal for
an extension of the Rescorla—Wagner theory was to make learning proportional
to stimulus salience.
In the case of a network, as shown in Figures 2.15 and 2.16, where there
are m possible inputs and n possible outputs, the system uses the delta rule to
simultaneously learn some men synaptic connections. The behavior of the whole
system can be complicated, but it still reproduces the basic competitive learning
behavior of the original Rescorla—Wagner theory.
The actual Gluck and Bower experiment was quite complex. Subjects saw
hundreds of patient descriptions reflecting different combinations of symptoms.
Each combination had a different probability of each disease. Overall, one dis-
ease was much rarer than the other, and each symptom had a differential asso-
ciation with the disease. The subjects were supposed to learn from this experi-
ence how to predict a disease given a pattern of symptoms. Figure 2.16 illus-
74
Final Reflections on Classical Conditioning
Final Reflections on
Classical Conditioning
Classical conditioning is a phenomenon defined by experimental procedures:
the US is made contingent on the CS, and, as a consequence, the CS acquires
the capacity to elicit a CR. Early in the history of classical conditioning,
researchers tended to view the learning that was taking place as an unconscious
and automatic consequence of the contiguity of CS and US. Classical condi-
tioning was attractive in part because it was seen to embody pure and simple
learning, uncontaminated by cognition on the part of the organism. Just as early
researchers had hoped, classical conditioning studies on some animals, particu-
°Gluck and Bower’s model actually has a single output, which varies from +1 to -1,
depending on the probability of the rare disease. The model in Figure 2.15 is formal-
ly equivalent but more in keeping with the Rescorla—Wagner theory. In this model,
each disease is predicted separately in a 0-1 scale, and the maximum strength of
association is 1. The Gluck and Bower values can be determined by subtracting the
strength of the common disease from the strength of the rare disease.
79
CHAPTER 2 Classical Conditioning
larly simple animals such as the Aplysia that have no central nervous system,
have provided insight into associative learning free of cognition. However,
recent research has also demonstrated that classical conditioning in more com-
plex organisms, including humans, frequently involves cognitive influences.
As discussed at the beginning of the chapter, different processes in the ner-
vous system underlie different instances of classical conditioning. Despite these
many differences, there are strong behavioral similarities across most forms of
conditioning: similar acquisition and extinction histories, spontaneous recovery,
generalization, temporal parameters, relationships between the CR and the UR,
and so on. The reason for the similarities lies in the fundamental adaptiveness of
classical conditioning. Classical conditioning allows organisms to respond adap-
tively in anticipation of a biologically significant UR. The common functionality
of classical conditioning across species underlies its common behavioral proper-
ties. An analogy can be drawn from the relationship between the eye of the
mammal and the eye of the octopus. The two have independent evolutionary his-
tories and are formed from different tissue, but they function almost identically.
They function so similarly because both have to deal with the same problem of
extracting information from light. Likewise, classical conditioning is similar
across organisms in terms of its behavioral properties because it serves the same
function of allowing the organism to respond in anticipation of the US.
Thus, certain generalities at a behavioral level in classical conditioning
may not be supported by generalities at a physiological level. In science diverse
underlying processes often give rise to common higher-order generalities in the
behavior of the system. For example, in economics industries producing very
different products display the same economic realities. Similarly, in biology dif-
ferent organisms display similar relationships. For instance, as reviewed in
Chapter 4, rather different creatures follow rather similar principles of foraging
for food.
This book identifies many generalities in learning that apply to diverse
species. The study of learning and memory has traditionally been about identi-
fying these generalities and understanding them. Much of psychology is devot-
ed to understanding generalities at the behavioral level. However, it should not
be concluded that all species learn the same way at the behavioral level. Species
show different preferences for various CS—-US combinations, reflecting differ-
ences in their biological makeup and in their environment. The closest thing to
a universal claim that can be made about classical conditioning is that it tends
to reflect an adaptive response by the organism to CS-US contingencies.
However, even this claim depends on carefully choosing the meaning of “adap-
tive.” For instance, it is really not adaptive for chemotherapy patients to develop
food aversions, although their tendency to form food aversions might be adap-
tive in other contexts, where it would lead them to avoid poisonous food.
76
Further Readings
Further Readings
A number of texts are devoted to discussion of classical and instrumental con-
ditioning, such as that by Domjan (1998). Wasserman & Miller (1997) provide a
recent review of current research on classical conditioning. Miller, Barnet, and
Grahame (1995) have written a review of the Rescorla—Wagner theory. The
September 1992 issue of Scientific American was devoted to the relationship
between brain and mind and presented a number of relevant articles, such as
one by Kandel and Hawkins on the biological basis of learning and another by
Hinton explaining recent developments in connectionist theories of learning.
Among them is a mechanism called backprop, which is a popular extension of
the delta rule. Thompson, Donegon, and Lavond (1988) published a fairly
exhaustive review of the psychobiology of learning. Bernstein and Borson (1986)
reviewed research on learned food aversions. Journals that frequently publish
research on classical conditioning include the Journal of Experimental Psychology:
Animal Behavior Processes; Behavioral Neuroscience; and Animal Learning and
Behavior.
77
Instrumental Conditioning
Overview
This chapter discusses research and theory on instrumental conditioning. In
instrumental conditioning, an o ism is reinforced if it makes a response (R)
in a certain stimulus (S) situation. For instance, Thorndike’s cats were reinforced
by escape and food if they hit the correct knob in his puzzle box. Just as classi-
cal conditioning is associated with Pavlov,4nstrumental conditioning is some-
times associated with Thorndike, but the association is not as strong because its
use and study did not really originate with Thorndike. In contrast with classical
conditioning, the discovery of which came as something of a surprise, instru-
mental conditioning is what everybody means by learning. It has been used by
teachers and parents since time immemorial, and there has never been any lack
of speculation as to how it should be used. Thorndike was simply the first to
propose a scientific theory of its operation.
Most of what happens in a classroom can be thought of as instrumental
conditioning. Consider a child learning that the sum of 3 and 4 is 7. The stimu-
lus can be thought of as “3 + 4;” the response as,“7;” and the reinforcer, the
teacher’s approval. Or consider a student learning to read a word. The stimulus
is the orthographic representation, the response is saying the word, and the
78
Classical and Instrumental Conditioning Compared
r. Forr instance, if a rat is in a Skinner box and aspresses a lever, a pellet will
appear in the feeder. Thus, the difference is that in instrumental conditioning,
the reinforcer (which is like a US) is contingent on the conjunction of stimulus
and response, whereas in classical conditioning it is contingent only on the
stimulus. Thus, in instrumental conditioning the organism can control whether
the reinforcer occurs.
If i ms in either situation, it begins to behave
as if it had figured out the experimenter’s contingency. In the case of classical
conditioning, it begins to perform a response (the CR) in preparation for ee US.
Int e case of instrumenta conditioning, i the respo: ands:
| Much debate has occurred over whether the process of learning is the
d instrumental conditioning. Cl al
1 instrumental
19
CHAPTER 3. Instrumental Conditioning
lematic. Interest in this distinction has waned, and attention has shifted to the
behavioral similarities between these two types of conditioning, with the implic-
it assumption that the two kinds of conditioning involve the same learning
process. Both kinds of conditioning show the same effects of practice, both
extinguish in the same way when the contingency is eliminated, and both show
spontaneous recovery. Both kinds of conditioning can be hurt if a delay is placed
in the contingency. Both paradigms result in successful conditioning only if
there is a contingency among the elements (not just a contiguity). With respect
to stimulus control, both show blocking effects, both can show configural learn-
ing, and both show similar generalization and discrimination processes. In addi-
tion, both show effects of associative bias. Since classical and instrumental con-
ditioning are so similar, this chapter essentially uses research on instrumental
conditioning to expand on the nature of conditioning in general.
eee SE PORT SLE IDRES EE AON
Instrumental
ee
and classical
a
conditioning
ae
share ee
many similar
behavioral properties.
iO LLL OE TNE AM DSN SE LETT LEE TOONS ESERIES IES ETRE SHG UI SIN er om oN ease ap
After addressing these questions, this chapter considers the similarity between
conditioning and causal inference and the evidence about the important role of
a particular brain structure, the hippocampus, in conditioning.
What Is Associated?
! N.Q1t1lonir VCS a STIMULUS TOL C IWC
by a reinforcement-For instance, a dog might lear sspond to the stimulus
“sit” with the response of sitting and receive food as a reward. As |in the case of
classical conditioning, a number of possibilities exist regarding what is associat
ed to what. One possibility is that the stimulus becomes associated to the
response. In this case, the reinforcer would stamp in the association but would
not pe bartol theassociation, This was the original idea of Thorndike and some
+L ns
vas
80
What Is Associated?
nelle to two different responses (lever pressing and chain pulling). When fed
with one kind of food pellet outside the experiment, they performed a predomi-
nance of responses that yielded the other kind of food pellet. Colwill and Rescorla
argued that organisms develop expectations; that is, if a certain response is emit-
ted in the presence of a certain stimulus, it ome a certain Sasa
pushing a tod to the left and to the right. One response was always rewarded
with food and the other with a sugar solution. Then one of the reinforcers was
paired with an injection of lithium chloride to produce a taste aversion to that
reinforcer. The rate of response associated with the devalued eens
One might argue from these studies that what the animal has really learned
is a two-term association between the response and the reinforcement. The stud-
ies just cited do not show that the animal will make the res ponse only in a partic-
the appropriate condition for that response is met. For instance, suppose the rat
learned that pulling a handle would produce food pellets in the presence of a tone
but liquid sucrose in the presence of a flashing light. If satiated on sucrose, this ani-
mal would stop pulling the lever only in the presence of the flashing light.
MELE NES OEE SELLER ERLE LL DELLE ENOL RL,
81
CHAPTER 3. Instrumental Conditioning
between stimuli and other neutral stimuli in classical conditioning (see the dis-
cussion of sensory preconditioning and second-order conditioning in Chapter
2). Can they similarly acquire such neutral associations in an instrumental con-
ditioning paradigm? In one experiment by St. Claire-Smith and MacLaren
(1983), as part of their free exploration of a Skinner box rats learned that a lever
press produced a noise. The experimental group was then trained on pairings of
the noise with food without a lever present in the box, and the control group
was trained on pairings of light and food. When the lever was reintroduced (but
no food was given), rats.in the experimental group pressed the bar more often
than did the control rats who had not learned the noise—food pairing. As a result
of their earlier free exploration, they appeared to have learned that lever press-
ing produced the noise. Putting this result together with the classical condition-
ing of noise and food, they acted as if the inferred that lever oe might also
produce food. Thus, it :
Secondary Reinforcement
The previous section described a situation in which the rat first learned the asso-
ciation bar press—noise and then the association noise-food. This situation is sim-
ilar to sensory preconditioning in classical conditioning in that the organism first
learns a neutral association, then a biologically significant association, and finally
puts them together. Reversing the order of learning the associations a in the
equivalent of second-order conditioning; the animal first learns iologically
significant association noise-food and then bar press—noise. The sae acquires the
82
What Is the Conditioned Stimulus?
83
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
Generalization
In a prototypical study of stimulus generalization, Guttman and Kalish (1956)
trained pigeons to peck at a key of a particular color (measured by wavelength).
During 60-sec intervals, the key was lit with a certain color, and pecking produced
a reinforcement of food. These intervals were separated by 10-sec intervals of total
darkness during which the pigeons did not respond. Following the experiment,
the key was illuminated at different wavelengths, and the number of key pecks
was recorded to test for generalization. Four conditions were defined by the wave-
length of the original key:'530 nm (green), 550 nm (greenyellow), 580 nm (yellow),
or 600 nm (yelloworange). After training, the pigeons were tested without rein-
forcement. Figure 3.1 shows, for each training condition, the number of respons-
es for different test wavelengths. Pigeons showed maximal response when the
test wavelength matched the wavelength on which they were trained. Their rate
of responding decreased as the difference increased between training and test
wavelengitt These:regulis donot, simpli rehec e Se Sta the
study stimulus from the test stimulus—that is, that pigeons responded to a test
color to the degree that they thought it was the study color; pigeons are capable
of making much sharper discriminations than those illustrated in Figure 3.1. In
some sense, pigeons were registering their’ opinion” on whether this difference in
wavelength was likely to be relevant to their reinforcement.
The curves in Figure 3.1 are often referred to as generalization gradients.
Many generalization gradients are not as steep as those depicted in Figure 3.1.
Figure 3.2 from Jenkins and Harrison (1960) illustrates a generalization gradient
from an experiment in which pigeons were trained to peck when a key was lit
and a 1000-Hz tone was on and then were tested for tones that varied from 300
to 3500 Hz. The data are plotted in terms of the percentage of all responses
500
600
400
3 530 580
a. S 300
g 550
Ke)
o
200
FIGURE 3.1 Pigeons are %
trained to peck at lights with
wavelengths of 530, 550, 580, 100
and 600 nm. The curves show
the total responses to stimuli of
similar wavelengths. These are 0
cumulative responses for 6 min. 460 500 540 580 620
(From Guttman & Kalish, 1956.) Wavelength, nm
84
What Is the Conditioned Stimulus?
Ww jo)
NOoO
250
200
Yn
B
S 150
ce
g
a)
®
—€ 100
=
=
50
given to that tone.! The generalization gradient curve is nearly flat, showing lit-
tle decrease in response as the tone varied from the training stimulus of 1000
Hz. Pigeons were registering their” opinion” that the actual pitch of the tone was
irrelevant to whether reinforcement would be delivered. The pigeons behaved as
if the only critical feature was that the key was lit and that it did not matter what
the tone was. In effect, they ignored the pitch of the tone. /
Figure 3.1 shows a positive generalization gradient, but negative general-
ization gradients are possible, too. Terrace (1972) created a situation in which
pigeons could receive reinforcement for pecking when the light was homoge-
neous white light and not when the light was a specific color (570 nm). They
were then tested with lights of specific colors. Figure 3.3 shows their rate of
responding as a function of wavelength. The minimum rate of responding
! The original Jenkins and Harrison data included a no-tone condition, which is not
shown.
85
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
Discrimination
Although organisms have biological predispositions to attend to certain dimen-
sions Britciteererigea GRU 19apenore“omereothey ualitche epee Eee if
experience contradicts their biases. For instance, what happens if the organism
is exposed to multiple stimuli that it initially treats as equivalent, but learns that
some are accompanied by reinforcement and others are not? The simplest pos-
sibility is an experiment in which the presence of a stimulus is associated with
reinforcement and its absence is not. Jenkins and Harrison (1960) looked at
what would happen in such a condition. Recall from Figure 3.2 that, when there
was only a positive stimulus of 1000 Hz, pigeons pecked at the lighted key no
matter what the frequency of the tone. Jenkins and Harrison compared this con-
dition with a condition of differential training: when the key was lit and there
was a 1000-Hz tone, the pigeons were reinforced for pecking the key, but when
the key was lit and there was no tone, they were not reinforced for pecking the
key. Figure 3.4 shows the results. There are strong generalization gradients
around 1000 Hz. The effect of the discrimination training was to indicate that
the tone was relevant.
This experiment compared the presence of a tone with the absence of a
tone, in contrast with many other experiments in which different values of a
stimulus were positive and negative. In another experiment by Jenkins and
Harrison (1962), pigeons were first reinforced for pecking in the presence of a
1000-Hz tone and not in the absence of a tone, as described earlier. Then the
pigeons were trained to respond to a 1000-Hz tone but not to a 950-Hz tone.
Figure 3.5 compares the generalization gradients of a pigeon before and after
learning that the 950-Hz tone was negative. The generalization gradient is much
steeper after the animal was trained to discriminate between a 1000-Hz tone
86
What Is the Conditioned Stimulus?
40
205
10/=
FIGURE 3.4 Generalization gradi- total
of
Percent
responses
ents following differential training Pe
with a 1000-Hz tone. Individual gra- 0
dients are based on the means of 0 1000 2000 3000
three generalization tests. Frequency, Hz
and a 950-Hz tone. This pigeon actually showed maximum response to a tone
of 1050-Hz, which is away from the negative 950 Hz. This kind of” overshoot’is
common in human behavior. If students observe that a 400-word essay got a C
and a 500-word essay got an A, they might write a 600-word essay. To explain
this phenomenon, the next section considers a popular theory of discrimination
wale:
Tran SR oa en eT ELLE SSL LI ELT ELLE
LL LAER LLL LDL E ELLEN DEERE LE EAE
1000 Hz
positive stimulus
100
60
40
min
Responses/
87
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
10
Positive effect
Net effect
Magnitude
excitation
of
Negative effect
© 1Orcs ic DONA
Stimulus size
FIGURE 3.6 Spence’s theory of how inhibitory influences from the negative stimu-
lus subtracted from excitatory influences of the positive stimulus yield a net general-
ization gradient.
88
What Is the Conditioned Stimulus?
that the positive peak of this gradient has been shifted from 256 in a direction
away from the negative stimulus. This is the prediction of a peak shift—the
stimulus that evokes the most responding is not the positi ini imulus
but one shifted away from it and the negative stimulus. This prediction is some-
what counterintuitive, since the organism 1s responding
i ae oaceipamied GithanteaSemele haeboca hohe TNS be
more to a stimulus that
organi wastesponding fo
thelationship PebuseaEh tenth
and had learned to select the larger. A long history of controversy has sur-
rounded relational accounts an unts like that of Spence, which propose
that the organism responds to the absolute value of the stimulus. This contro-
versy has been settled with the conclusion that both sides are right. Under
appropriate circumstances an organism can be trained to respond to a relation-
ship between two stimuli, and under other circumstances it can be trained to
respond to the absolute properties of the two stimuli.
An experiment by Lawrence and DeRivera (1954) provides an example of
animals responding relationally. Figure 3.7 illustrates the stimuli used: cards of
two shades of gray. In Figure 3.7 these shades are indicated by the numbers 1
through 7: 1 is white, 7 is black, and the other numbers denote the various
shades between. The bottom half of the card was always 4 and the top half var-
ied. When the top half was lighter (1 to 3), rats were trained to turn right; when
it was darker (5 to 7) they were trained to turn left. The critical test occurred after
89
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
6
Test stimuli
vate
FIGURE. 3.7 Stimuli used by Lawrence and DeRivera
(1954). The numbers 1 through 7 denote shades of gray.
training.The rats were presented with a card with 3 on top and 1 on the bottom.
Both 3 and 1 were associated with moving right, but the top was darker than the
bottom and this relation was associated with turning left. The rats responded to
the relational information and turned left. In contrast, when they were tested
with a 5 on the top and 7 on the bottom, they went right, again confirming the
relational theory.
The fact that organisms can encode and respond to either relational or
Aisharea mecerttreng resem SciYaiccai cam problem
IS TN in the
eTdiscussion
of what constitutes the conditioned stimulus. It is not immediately apparent
ee adc aC
be way(6g,absolutesis)an-anoMr-a-atTen ayGelalve ize),
Without Knowing how the stimulus is encoded, it is not possible to know what
patterns of generalization and discrimination will take place. Researchers and
theorists typically assume what seems to be the obvious encoding. But what
seems obvious to the experimenter may not seem obvious to the organism.
Chapter 6 has more to say about how information is represented, particularly in
the human case.
90
What Is the Conditioned Stimulus?
attention to a new dimension. Most betes and higher apes find reversal shifts
easier, whereas very young children and nonprimates find nonreversal shifts
easier (Mackintosh, 1975). Interestingly, adult humans with damage to their
prefrontal cortex often have difficulties in reversal conditions as well (Owen,
Roberts, Hodges, Summers, Polkey, & Robbins, 1993). The frontal cortical areas
are much expanded in primates and mature in children later than most other
neural structures. Chapters 6 and 9 will elaborate on the role of the frontal cor-
tex in primate and human learning.
Figure 3.8 also illustrates intradi shift, which requires the sub-
ject to learn to discriminate betw as blue and green) on the
previously relevant dimension. Thissituation iscontrasted withlearning new
values on
onthe
theother
otherdimension
mens (extradimensional
shift). Intradimensional shifts
shifts(c.g., Mackintosh & Little,
afealmost always easierthan-extradimensional
91
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
Training
Positive |F|
Negative
Reversal shift
Positive Y
Negative
iva
Nonreversal shift
Positive ¥.
eld
Negative
Intradimensional shift
Positive
Negative | G
tele
aieie
Paleer
Extradimensional shift
92
What Is the Conditioned Stimulus?
FIGURE 3.9 Four typical pictures used in the experiment by Herrnstein, Loveland,
& Cable (1976). (Negative stimuli are on the left; positive on the right.)
93
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
them from the negative pictures) was that they involved a tree. The positive pic-
tures could not be discriminated from the negative pictures on the basis of sim-
ple features. Thus, pigeons could only make this discrimination if they knew
what a tree was. For humans, this is a relatively easy discrimination because they
possess the category of trees. It also turned out to be a fairly easy discrimination
for pigeons. Pigeons not only were able to learn to make such discriminations,
but they learned in fewer trials than needed in the simple one-dimensional
problems described earlier. Moreover, after being trained to discriminate one $et
of pictures of trees from a set of pictures of nontrees, the pigeons were capable
of generalizing this ability to new pictures that had not been used for training.
Wasserman, Kiedinger, and Bhatt (1988) demonstrated category learning
by pigeons in a slightly different paradigm. Pigeons were trained to peck at four
different keys according to the rules:
Pigeons got quite good at discriminating keys 1 and 2 from 3 and 4, corre-
sponding to the cat—flower distinction. However, they had great difficulty in dis-
tinguishing key 1 from 2 (the cat pictures) or key 3 from key 4 (the flower pic-
tures). They found it difficult to learn discriminations within a category. Humans
would show similar patterns, finding discriminations between categories easy
and discriminations within categories hard.
Chapter 10 provides much more information on concept learning, focus-
ing mainly on human learning of concepts. The experiments just described illus-
trate that lower animals as much as humans see the world in terms of categories
and specific objects and not in terms of single dimensions like colors and
shapes. Often this meaningful representation of the world is much more salient
than the simple dimensional representation, and animals find it easier to learn
discriminations when the discriminating factor is a salient category.
94
What Is the Conditioned Response?
they pressed with one paw, sometimes with another, and sometimes even with
their teeth! Macfarlane (1930) taught rats to swim through a maze for food and
then found that they were capable of running the maze for food. Lashley (1924)
taught monkeys to solve a manipulation problem with one hand and found they
could generalize the solution to the other hand when the first was paralyzed. It
seems that organisms come to some representation of the functional structure
of their environment and sélect their responses appropriately. Thus, the guinea
pigs in Muenzinger’s experiment wére learning not that a particular response
was associated with reinforcement, but rather that depression of the bar was
associated with reinforcement. As in classical conditioning, the response is the
organism’s adaptation to what it has learned about the environment.
Sra eerie vecrerreeet GRE rte OFtheTeopOTce Tene definition of
an operant. Different responses that had identical effects in the environment
(had identical reinforcement consequences) were defined to be instances of the
same operant. Organisms can be trained to discriminate among responses that
appear to have equivalent effects on the environment (e.g., use of the left hand
versus the right hand to press a bar) if the experimenter sets up reinforcement
contingencies that differentiate them. However, they behave as if their default
assumption were that actions with equivalent effects on the world produce
equivalent rewards—certainly a plausible default assumption.
Maze Learning
Maze learning by rats provides some of the strongest evidence that the organism’s
response is an adaptation to what it has learned about its environment. Rats are
animals whose natural environments are much like mazes, and they are skillful at
learning complex mazes, challenging humans in their ability. As noted in the dis-
cussion of Tolman in Chapter 1, rats’ ability to navigate in mazes depends in part
on their developing cognitive maps. They learn the locations of food and other
objects in space and traverse the maze to get to those locations. However, there is
also evidence that rats can learn the specific turns involved in navigating a maze.
More recent research has revealed some of the other ways in which rats
cope with mazes. Research (e.g., Olton, 1978) has been conducted with a radial
maze such as that shown in Figure 3.10; the rat is put in the center of the maze,
and food is placed at the end of each of the eight arms. Rats on their first
encounter with this maze tended to perform very well, visiting about seven of the
eight arms in their first eight choices. The rats displayed an amazing ability to
avoid revisiting these arms.* How were they able to explore these mazes so effi-
ciently? One might think that the rats had some systematic plan such as going
2 Only in the second edition did I notice the pun in this sentence.
=)3)
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
through all the arms in a left-to-right order. This does not seem to be the answer,
however, because they did not display any specific order in visiting the arms.
Rather, the evidence is that rats have good memories for locations and avoid
repeating visits. This is an adaptive trait in their natural environment, where they
need to keep track of where they have been and consumed food. If they have
depleted the food in a particular location, there is no point in repeating the trip.
Other research on rats has compared their ability to learn shift versus stay
strategies in a T-maze (Haig, Rawlins, Olton, Mead, & Taylor, 1983). AT-maze (see
Figure 3.11) is a simple maze in which a rat runs from a start box to a choice point,
at which it must go in one of two directions. There are goal boxes to the left and
to the right, and one of them contains food. Shift and stay strategies refer to two
different principles experimenters have used to determine which goal box to place
food in. The strategies differ in terms of where to look for food after the first trial.
If the rat is being trained with a stay strategy, it finds food if it goes down the path
that had food before. In a shift strategy, it finds food if it goes down the other path.
96
What Is the Conditioned Response?
Rats find it much easier to learn the shift strategy. This result is just the opposite
of what would be predicted if rats were learning specific responses, but it is exact-
ly what would be predicted from their foraging habits in the wild, where they need
to avoid food locations that they have already depleted. Several other species also
show this tendency to learn better with a shift strategy (e.g., Kamil, 1978).
Interestingly, animals find shift strategies harder to learn when they are not
allowed to deplete the food in the goal box (Haig, Rawlins, Olton, Mead, & Taylor,
1983); then they have a reason to return to the same part of the maze.
97
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
The Brelands reported a variation of this problem when they tried to train
raccoons to place coins in a container. The raccoons began engaging in behaviors
that corresponded to washing and cleaning the food. Although the intrusive
behavior was different from that of the pigs, the behavior was part of the species-
specific food-gathering behavior of raccoons. Thus, organisms’ instinctive response
patterns can overwhelm responses carefully shaped by instrumental conditioning.
Autoshaping
The previous subsection described how conditioning efforts can be frustrated by
organisms’ biological predispositions toward appropriate response patterns. A
somewhat different result can also happen: experimenters can train a behavior
without trying. A much-studied example, called autoshaping, was discovered
by Brown and Jenkins in 1968 in their work with pigeons. At irregular intervals
they illuminated a response key and then followed the key with food from a
grain dispenser. Although the birds did not have to peck at the key to obtain the
food, they all started to peck at the key. They wound up behaving as if there had
been a contingency between pecking and food.
Considerable effort has been made to understand why the pigeons would
peck at a key when it was unnecessary. One enlightening experiment was per-
formed by Jenkins and Moore (1973). They deprived the pigeons of either water
or food, and then they used the autoshaping procedure of the illuminated key
followed by the appropriate reinforcer. All the pigeons began pecking at the key,
but the way in which they pecked at it differed depending on the reward. When
a pigeon had been deprived of food and the reward was food, the pigeon pecked
with an open beak and made other movements similar to those that pigeons
make when they are eating. When the reward was water for a pigeon deprived
of water, the bird pecked at the response key with a closed or nearly closed beak;
again, this and other features of the pecking movement were like the move-
ments that pigeons make when drinking.
These results can be interpreted as examples of classical conditioning. That
is, the lit key is a CS that predicts the US of food or water, and the animal is giv-
ing a conditioned response of pecking to that CS. Although this interpretation
may be basically correct, it fails to capture the full complexity of autoshaping
behavior. A good example of this complexity was observed by Timberlake and
Grant (1975) in a study of autoshaping in rats. Two groups of rats received differ-
ent CSs presented in advance of the delivery of a food pellet. For one group the
CS was a block of wood; the rats came to gnaw at the wood. For the second group
the CS was another rat; in this case the rats approached the other rat and engaged
in various social behaviors, such as sniffing and grooming. Thus, depending on the
CS, rather different behaviors were autoshaped. The difference makes sense if the
98
Association: Contiguity or Contingency?
Pigeons pecking for water (top row) and for food (bottom row).
eating behaviors of rats are considered. Rats usually eat in groups and display
social behaviors to other rats while eating; they also gnaw at inanimate objects as
part of their eating behavior. There is a complex species-specific pattern of eating
behavior, and different aspects of it are selected by different stimuli.
Generally, the lesson of the research on autoshaping and instinctive drift
is that animals come to learning situations with strong patterns of instinctive
behavior. These patterns may cause the organisms not to learn what the exper-
imenter intended but rather something else. With respect to the issue of what
the conditioned response is, this research shows that the organism is not just a
bundle of simple muscle movements waiting to be conditioned to a stimulus.
Rather, the responses are parts of existing behavioral systems, and their condi-
tioning cannot be understood unless these systems are understood. Timberlake
(1983, 1984) uses the term behavior systems analysis to refer to this approach
that emphasizes the natural, unlearned organization of behavior for a species.
99
CHAPTER 3. Instrumental Conditioning
Phase 1. If the rats pressed the bar in any 1-sec interval, they had a
chance of a reinforcer. Hammond shaped the rats to a point where they
were receiving reinforcers after only 5 percent of these response-filled, 1-
sec intervals. The rats were making about 3000 bar presses an hour.
Phase 2. Hammond began giving reinforcements 5 percent of the time
when 1 sec passed and no response had been made. He still gave a reward
5 percent of the time when a response was made, but the reward was no
longer contingent on response—it was equally likely whether or not a
response had been made. The rats’ rate of responding dropped off rapidly
until they were making virtually no responses. Thus, even though the
same degree of contiguity of response and reward was maintained, rats
stopped responding because there was no longer a contingency.
5000
= 4000
wn
a
S 3000
[oy
3
= 2000
1000
FIGURE 3.12 Responses per hour for rats when there is a contingency between
pressing and reinforcement and when there is not. Source: From L. J. Hammond.
Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, The effect of contingency upon the
appetitive conditioning of free-operant behavior, 34, 297-304. Copyright © 1980 by
the Society for the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, Inc. Reprinted by permission.
100
Association: Contiguity or Contingency?
Phase 3. Hammond stopped giving reinforcers when the rats did not
respond, and the response rate of the rats picked up.
Phase 4. Hammond removed the contingency again, and the response
rate went down again.
Superstitious Learning
Some of Skinner’s famous experiments (Skinner, 1948) on what has been called
superstitious learning were thought to be evidence that contiguity was suffi-
cient for learning and contingency was not necessary. Food was made available
to pigeons from a feeder at fixed intervals (e.g., 15 sec for some, longer for oth-
ers) regardless of what they were doing. Although there was no contingency
between behavior and reinforcement, pigeons in this situation developed high-
ly routinized behaviors. One pigeon turned counterclockwise; another thrust its
head into the upper corners of its cage. Skinner reasoned that these systematic
behaviors appeared because of accidental contiguities between what the pigeon
was doing and the delivery of food. For instance, when the food was delivered,
the pigeon might be hopping from one foot to the other. The contiguity between
this response and the food would increase the pigeon’s tendency to hop from
one foot to the other and would thus increase the chance that the pigeon would
be engaged in this behavior the next time the food was delivered, increasing the
tendency for the behavior even more, and so on, until the pigeon would always
be hopping from foot to foot. Thus, even though there was only accidental con-
tiguity between behavior and reinforcement and there was no contingency, con-
ditioning would occur. In effect, the pigeons developed the superstition that
their behavior was necessary for the reinforcement. Skinner speculated that this
might be the cause of superstitious behavior in humans, such as rain dances to
produce rain; sometimes rain dances are indeed followed by rain, but, presum-
ably, they do not produce the rain.
Subsequent research and analysis have raised doubts about Skinner’s
interpretation of these experiments. Staddon and Simmelhag (1971) repeated
the superstition experiment and replicated many of Skinner’s results. However,
they demonstrated that the situation was more complicated than Skinner real-
ized. They noted that the pigeons’ behavior could be divided into two categories.
Immediately after receiving a reinforcement, pigeons displayed interim behav-
iors. There was a wide variety of such behaviors, including the sort Skinner
reported. After a while, pigeons began to engage in terminal behaviors, clearly
101
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
in anticipation of the next feeding. This terminal phase always involved some
variety of pecking.
Staddon and Simmelhag’s results present serious difficulties for any
attempt to explain superstitious behavior as learning by contiguity. First, there is
no reason for two segments; second, there is no reason for all pigeons to peck
in the terminal segment, which is contiguous with the reinforcement. Staddon
and Simmelhag argued that terminal behaviors should be understood as exam-
ples of autoshaping, which, as we have discussed, is perhaps best thought of as
a classical conditioning phenomenon.
Although each pigeon evolved systematic interim behaviors, these behav-
iors were not contiguous with reinforcement and thus whatever caused them
was not learned by contiguity. Therefore, what was contiguous was not instru-
mentally conditioned but was classically conditioned, and what might be instru-
mentally learned was not contiguous. Staddon (1983) suggested that these
interim behaviors often served other functions, such as grooming or exercise.
According to this view, human behavior is often analogous to that of rats
in these experiments. Many of us eat on rather fixed schedules. When food is not
likely, we often engage in predictable interim behavior (e.g., studying or watch-
ing television). When food is likely, we engage in predictable terminal behavior
in anticipation of the food (e.g., going to the kitchen and setting the table).
Partial Reinforcement
The experiment by Hammond (Figure 3.12) used a partial reinforcement sched-
ule; that is, only some of the responses were rewarded. It is sometimes hard to
discern that the partial reinforcement rate for a response is greater than the back-
ground rate of reward. Suppose that the probability of getting a reward in 1 sec is
5 percent if an animal presses a bar, but 4 percent if the animal does not press the
bar. The animal might fail to detect the contingency and not display conditioning.
When organisms are being maintained on partial reinforcement schedules,
especially schedules with low rates of reinforcement, they also have a problem
discriminating when extinction begins. It is easy to discriminate 0 percent rein-
forcement in extinction from 100 percent during conditioning, harder to discrim-
inate 0 percent from 25 percent, and much more difficult to discriminate 0 per-
cent from 1 percent. Organisms are found to take longer to extinguish after train-
ing on a partial reinforcement schedule, and their resistance to extinction
increases as the reinforcement rate is lowered. This phenomenon is called the
partial reinforcement extinction effect. It is a bit paradoxical because it implies
that the less reinforcement received in the past, the slower the organism is to give
up on an activity. This effect has interesting implications for molding the behav-
102
Association: Contiguity or Contingency?
ior of people. For instance, if parents want their children to be persistent in pur-
suing a goal in the face of adversity, it suggests that they should only occasional-
ly reinforce their children’s goal-seeking activities. Eisenberger, Heerdt, Hamdi,
Zimet, and Bruckmeir (1979) demonstrated that children completed more work
in handwriting and mathematics if they had been partially reinforced in the past.
Partial reinforcement increases resistance to extinction because the condi-
tions under which the animal learns are similar to the conditions of extinction.
Basically, the animal learns to respond to the features that occur during extinc-
tion. Several researchers have proposed what these features might be. Capaldi
(1967) suggested that during learning organisms come to associate sequences of
nonreinforced responses with eventual reinforcement. Thus, in extinction, when
the organism encounters a sequence of nonreinforced trials, it expects rein-
forcement. Amsel (1967) proposed that during initial training, the organism
becomes frustrated when it does not receive reinforcement and has associated
its frustration with reinforcement. Thus, when frustrated in extinction, it also
expects reinforcement. Both theories have in common the idea that the partial-
ly reinforced organism learns to associate reinforcement to the kinds of features
encountered in extinction.
Learned Helplessness
Perhaps the most dramatic evidence that organisms can be aware of the contin-
gency (or lack thereof) between their behavior and reinforcement is found in the
learned helplessn at a scone experiment by
re given painful shocks at unpredictable
whereas the experimental group could do nothing to escape the shock. Thus,
one group of dogs learned a behavior that would eliminate shock, whereas the
other did not.
Both groups were then placed in the same escape avoidance condition:
they could avoid the shock if they jumped over a barrier after hearing a tone.
Dogs in the control group, which could control their shock in the first phase,
readily learned to jump over the barrier. In contrast, the experimental dogs
whined and yelped but made no attempt to escape the shock. After many trials,
the animals simply lay down and hardly moved at all. They had learned that
nothing they could do would prevent shock—that there was no contingency
between their behavior - 1s nt nl ois
103
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
could learn to escape shock. This situation is like latent inhibition in classical con-
ditioning, where an organism comes to ignore a certain CS (see Chapter 2), or
like dimensional bapeae? in instrumental ea where bie Se oat
- a 8: a
noe and Seligman (1975) showed that humans mee to a long series of
unsolvable anagram problems failed to learn other easy-to-learn experimental
tasks. Seligman (1975) also suggested that clinical depression may be a variety
Associative Bias
Although organisms may be capable of learning many response—reinforcer
associations, they are biologically predisposed tolearncertain associations, just
as they are predisposed to learn certain stimulus-stimulus associations in clas-
sical conditioning (e.g., taste-poisoning discussed in Chapter 2). A pigeon can
more readily learn to peck to receive food than to avoid shock (Hineline &
Rachlin, 1969; MacPhail, 1968; Schwartz, 1973), but it can quite readily learn to
flap its wings to escape shock (Bedford & Anger, 1968). These outcomes make
104
Association: Contiguity or Contingency?
sense because pecking is part of the pigeon’s eating repertoire and wing flap-
pageis tt of itseli ho of escape behaviors.
hettlewor 75) did an interesting analysis
of the effects of reinforce-
msters. She ma that they tended to engage
in1 certain behaviors when hungry, such as standing on their hind legs (which
she called open rear), scraping at walls (scrabbling), and digging in the ground.
Other activities, such as washing their faces, scratching, and marking (pressing
a scent gland), did not increase when they were hungry. Different hamsters
were reinforced by food for each of these six behaviors. Figure 3.13 shows the
results. Subjects learned to increase the oe behaviors but not the noneating
Scrabble
500
400
Open rear
WwoOiS
Mean
sec
105
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
behavior. For instance, rats find it easy to learn to flee to avoid a shock but hard
to learn to press a bar to escape shock. The relative ease of these two responses
is reversed if the reinforcer is food.
Humans face difficulties in skill learning when the skills entail learning
responses that are antagonistic to human predispositions. For example, in
downhill skiing the skier leans forward to control speed and should lean for-
ward more the steeper the hill. Most beginners have difficulty because of their
natural tendency to lean backwards. As another example, when a car is skidding
on an icy road the driver needs to turn into the skid and not slam on the
brakes—drivers have great difficulty learning the appropriate response and
inhibiting the incorrect response.
Instrumental Conditioning
and Causal Inference
We have focused on instrumental conditioning experiments from the animal’s
perspective. But human subjects can be placed in similar situations. Imagine what
it would be like if you were put in a room to explore and discovered that some-
times when you flipped a switch on the wall, money came forth. If you thought
you would be able to keep any money you found, you might find yourself flipping
that switch as fast as a rat pushes a lever or a pigeon pecks a key. Your perfor-
mance could be plotted in cumulative response records, and we could speak of
you as learning an association between the switch and money. To speak of it as an
association, though accurate, would probably not fully express your mental state.
You probably also would have formed the belief that flipping the switch caused
the money to come forth. It is unclear to which other organisms such causal
beliefs may be ascribed, but it is appropriate to ascribe them to humans.
Wasserman (1990) studied the development of humans’ causal beliefs in
instrumental conditioning paradigms and found that these causal beliefs devel-
op much as associations do in lower organisms. Subjects were given a key,
which they were encouraged to press. Sometimes when the subject pressed the
key a light went on, and sometimes when the subject did not press the key the
light went on. The light was like a reinforcer (or in this case more like a neutral
stimulus) that followed the response. Wasserman varied the probability that the
key press would be followed by the light. He broke the experiment into 1-sec
intervals. If a subject pressed the key in the interval, the interval would end with
a light flash with different probabilities in different experimental conditions. He
used probabilities of 0.00, 0.25, 0.50, 0.75, and 1.00. These probabilities were
referred to as P(O|R) for probability of outcome given response. Wasserman also
106
Instrumental Conditioning and Causal Inference
ro)
subject
Average
rating
20)
manipulated the probabilities that a 1-sec interval without a key press would
result in a light. These probabilities were referred to as P(O|-R), for probability
of outcome given no response, and they similarly took on the same values of
0.00, 0.25, 0.50, 0.75, and 1.00. Wasserman looked at all combinations of P(O|R)
and P(O|-R) for 5 x 5 = 25 conditions.
Wasserman asked subjects to rate the causal relationship between the
press and light on a scale that varied from —100 (prevents light) to +100 (causes
light). Figure 3.14 illustrates the results. As in the animal conditioning experi-
ments, subjects’ ratings of causal strength was a function of the difference
between P(O|R) and P(O|-R). The particular level of causal strength for a value
of P(O|R) depended on the value of P(O|-R). This is the same sort of relationship
Rescorla illustrated in his experiment on classical conditioning (see Figure 2.9).
Chapter 10 examines human causal inference further, but the research described
here indicates that causal inference may be closely related to conditioning.
107
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
Interpretations
Two rather different conclusions are possible from this research on causal infer-
ence and the Rescorla-Wagner theory. One conclusion is that the simple associa-
tive learning processes of the Rescorla—Wagner theory are responsible for human
causal inference. As noted, Chapman and Robbins showed that the theory results
in strengths of association between response and outcome that are exactly equal
to the difference P(O|R) — P(O|-R). The theory in no way explicitly estimates prob-
abilities P(O|R) and P(O|-R), let alone takes their differences. Nonetheless, it esti-
mates this quantity, supporting the point made in the previous chapter that sim-
ple associative learning judgments can mimic sophisticated statistical inference.
A dramatically opposite conclusion can also be drawn. Subjects in these
experiments were not in conditioning experiments; that is, they were not in sit-
uations in which experimental contingencies reinforced their responses. Rather,
they were asked to make judgments of causal relatedness between response and
outcome. The fact that their causal inferences were like conditioning suggests
that causal inference, and not simple associative learning processes, underlies
108
The Hippocampus and Conditioning
109
CHAPTER 3. Instrumental Conditioning
5mm
(a) rat >
5mm
More recent research, using more refined techniques, has tried to separate out
the contribution of the parahippocampal areas to learning from the contribution
of the hippocampus (and we will describe these studies momentarily). Rats with
lesions to the parahippocampal area and the hippocampus perform poorly in a
wide range of instrumental and classical conditioning paradigms. They show a
particular deficit in tasks involving a substantial spatial component, such as
maze learning. An example that illustrates the deficit involves the Morris water-
escape task (Morris, 1981). Rats are placed in a circular pool of water and must
swim to an escape platform. If they climb onto the escape platform, the experi-
menter removes them from the pool; otherwise they are left to swim around.
The water is murky, and so the rats are unable to see anything below the sur-
face. In some conditions, the escape platform is above the water’s surface and
the rats can see it; in other conditions, it is just below the surface and they can-
not see it. In the original experiment Morris contrasted these four conditions:
110
The Hippocampus and Conditioning
Cortical areas
Parahippocampal
region
Sle
Hippocampus
(a) (b)
1. Cue + place. The escape platform is always visible and always in the same
location.
2. Place. The platform is submerged but always in the same location.
3. Cue only. The escape platform is always visible but in different locations
on different trials.
4. Place random. The platform is submerged and in different locations.
Rats learned to swim quickly to the escape platform in all conditions but the
last. Figure 3.17 shows the tracks taken by a rat in each group on the last four
trials. Only the rats in the last group wandered much in the pool. This task is sig-
nificant because it shows that rats are excellent in using a spatial representation
to navigate through their environment. As Figure 3.17 illustrates, although rats
in the place condition started from a different part of the pool on each trial, they
knew where the submerged platform was and swam to it.
This experimental paradigm has become important for understanding the
role of the hippocampus. Rats with hippocampal lesions perform poorly in the
place condition—no better than normal rats perform in the place-random con-
dition. In contrast, normal and lesioned rats behave similarly when the platform
is visible (Morris, Garrud, Rawlins, & O’Keefe, 1982). Results such as this have
been used to argue that the hippocampus is significant in spatial learning. Some
other kinds of learning are not impaired by hippocampal lesions. For instance,
lesioned rats can still learn taste aversions and how to make simple visual dis-
criminations.
111
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
Trial
17 18 19 20
Cue + place
Place
Cue only
Place random
BOWL BO
BDO
VOL
FIGURE 3.17 A vertical view of the tracks taken by rats in each group. Source: From
R. G. M. Morris. Learning and Motivation, Volume 12. Copyright © 1981 by Academic
Press. Reprinted by permission.
SeoEEE a%
112
The Hippocampus and Conditioning
(Figure 3.10). Olton et al. reported a study that used a 17-arm version of this
maze in which 8 of the arms were baited with food and the other 9 were not.
With experience with this maze, normal rats learned two things:
1. Never to enter the 9 arms that were never baited with food.
2. To efficiently explore the baited arms to avoid repeat visits, as discussed
with respect to Figure 3.10.
Rats with hippocampal lesions learned 1 but not 2. Both sorts of information are
spatial, but lesioned rats can learn one and not the other. In Olton’s terms what
they cannot do is rapidly update their working memory to avoid repeated visits
(2). Given enough experience, however, they can learn permanent properties of
their spatial environment (1).
Sutherland and Rudy (1991), taking a more traditional conditioning per-
spective, argued that the deficit is in the ability to form configural associations.
(See the discussion in Chapter 2 of the distinction between associations to stim-
ulus configurations versus stimulus elements.) They argued that to solve the
Morris water-escape task when the platform was submerged, the animal had to
respond to a configuration of spatial cues, whereas when the platform was vis-
ible the animal could simply respond to the visible platform. Eichenbaum,
Stewart, and Morris (1990) ran a variation of the submerged condition in which
rats always started from the same location. In this case, hippocampal lesioned
rats learned the task. In this condition, they did not have to respond to the con-
figural cues but could just swim in the same direction.
Sutherland and Rudy (1991) performed the following experiment, which
showed that rats with hippocampal lesions had difficulty learning a nonspatial
task that involved forming configural associations. Animals were rewarded with
food for pressing a bar when a light alone or a tone alone appeared. However,
they were not reinforced for responding when the light and tone were present-
ed simultaneously. As discussed in Chapter 2, normal animals can perform this
task, which requires learning associations to stimulus configurations of light +
no tone and tone + no light. Rats with hippocampal lesions are unable to learn
these associations, although they can learn to respond to the simple single stim-
uli. Thus, this is a nonspatial task in which lesioned rats show a deficit.
In recent years, the field has been developing elaborations of this config-
ural cue proposal. The basic idea is that an organism without a hippocampus can
only respond to single stimulus dimensions, but with a hippocampus, the
organism can respond to stimulus combinations. It has been shown that hip-
pocampal cells will fire selectively to various combinations of cues (for instance,
odors in rats—Otto & Eichenbaum, 1992) just as O’Keefe and Nadel found cells
that responded to combinations of various spatial cues.
Both Eichenbaum and Bunsey (1995) and Gluck and Myers (1995) have
made a similar distinction between two ways in which the hippocampus can
join different elements into a whole. In one case, the elements are fused into a
single whole in which the identity of the elements are lost. Eichenbaum and
Bunsey (1995) suggest the analogy of combining two words like hell and o into
113
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
the word “hello.” The other way is to join the elements into an association in
which the individual element identity is preserved. The analogy suggested by
Eichenbaum and Bunsey is joining the same words in English, army and table,
into a paired-associate army-table. There is evidence that the parahippocampal
region performs stimulus fusion, while the hippocampal region performs the
element combination (see Figure 3.16).
Gluck and Myers use this distinction to explain latent inhibition and the
effect of hippocampal lesions on latent inhibition. Recall from Chapter 2 that
latent inhibition refers tg the phenomenon that if a CS is presented a number
of times before a US, it becomes harder to condition to a US. According to Gluck
and Myers, this is because the CS becomes fused with the context and is hard
to separate from the context. Lesions that include both the parahippocampal
region and the hippocampus abolish latent inhibition and make it easier for the
lesioned animals to condition in a latent inhibition paradigm. However, latent
inhibition is maintained if just the hippocampus is affected. According to Gluck
and Myers, this is because the parahippocampal region performs the fusion that
is responsible for latent inhibition. Recall that latent inhibition was one of the
problems with the Rescorla—Wagner theory. Gluck (1997) has argued that the
Rescorla-Wagner learning rule describes cortical learning but that different
learning rules are required to characterize hippocampal learning.
PSS SLSMON Rate ay Naat oe reopen EERE ESR UNIS REE EOE EE SNE ES NT CEI SS RPI RET
114
The Hippocampus and Conditioning
increase in the number of spines is more long lasting. In addition to these post-
synaptic changes there are presynaptic changes involving an increase in the
release of neurotransmitters. Recall that the neural basis of learning in Aplysia
also involved an increase in the presynaptic release of neurotransmitters.
Considerable work has been done on the biochemistry of these changes
in the spines. Certain receptors in the postsynaptic membrane on the dendrite
(NMDA receptors) are normally blocked and become unblocked only if the
postsynaptic cell has fired. If the presynaptic cell fires and sends a neurotrans-
mitter to the postsynaptic membrane at the same time that the postsynaptic cell
is firing, then these unblocked receptors can receive the neurotransmitter. It is
thought that the unblocking of these NMDA receptors is the critical step in the
production of LTP. This unblocking in turn enables calcium to enter into the
postsynaptic neuron, resulting in an increase in both the receptors in the post-
synaptic neuron and the presynaptic release of the neurotransmitter. Kandel
and Hawkins (1992) speculated that the postsynaptic influx of calcium may
cause chemical messengers to be transmitted to the presynaptic axon, resulting
in the increased release of neurotransmitter.
ERR reeennRRessaRe sscayentennesvons
115
CHAPTER 3 Instrumental Conditioning
role in learning, it does not seem to be all that there is to hippocampal involve-
ment. More recent research (Bannerman, Good, Butcher, Ramsay, & Morris,
1995; Saucier & Cain, 1995) has found totally normal learning of the water maze
in drug-injected rats that have had some general training in this kind of task,
although not the specific water maze. Thus, it seems that the LIP component
may only block general learning of how to do the task and not the actual spa-
tial properties of the water maze. The spatial structure of the maze appears to be
learned by some other hippocampal process not involving LTP.
Sana
sr een meee sen
116
Further Reading
Further Readings
The textbooks and journals cited at the end of Chapter 2 are also excellent
sources for research on instrumental conditioning. In addition, many research
articles on instrumental conditioning are found in Learning and Motivation and
Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior. Balsam (1988) reviews the
research relevant to stimulus generalizations and discriminations. Staddon and
Ettinger’s (1989) text on learning emphasizes its adaptive function. Gluck and
Meyers (1997) and Eichenbaum (1997) are two reviews of research relevant to
hippocampal function, and Landfield and Deadwyler (1988) edited a series of
articles on LTP. The November 1996 edition of the journal Hippocampus was
devoted to theories of the role of the hippocampus in learning.
slslys
Reinforcement and Learning
118
Some Basic Concepts and Principles
Although organisms tend to do the right thing, this chapter reviews situ-
ations in which they produce behavior that is far from optimal. This situation
can be viewed as a glass half full or half empty. Historically, psychology has
taken a half-empty perspective and emphasized deviations from optimality.
More recently, psychologists have become impressed with how well even sim-
ple organisms do at behaving in near optimal ways. Often cases of nonoptimal-
ity can be understood as generally adaptive behavioral tendencies that go astray
in situations for which they did not evolve. For instance, human affection for
sweet food reflects a tendency that selected food of high nutritional value at one
time in our evolutionary history. However, in modern society with its capacity to
create almost arbitrary food products, this tendency often selects the least nutri-
tious of the food alternatives.
NSN TET ENE SESE ENS EOE NTE RELAIS SOR BE
Rational Behavior
What is meant by rational behavior? Consider a situation that a rat might
encounter in a laboratory experiment. Suppose that three significant actions are
available to the rat: It can press a bar, play in an activity wheel, or do nothing
(or, at least, do neither of the first two activities). Suppose there are four possi-
ble consequences of its actions: it will receive food; it will be shocked; it will
receive exercise; or nothing will happen.
The experimenter has arranged contingencies between each activity and
each outcome, as shown in Table 4.1. If the rat presses the bar, there is a 67 per-
cent chance of getting food and a 33 percent chance of being shocked. If it
enters the activity wheel, there is a certainty of exercise. If it does nothing, there
is a 90 percent chance of nothing happening and a 10 percent chance of getting
food. The rat has learned these behavioral contingencies from its exploration of
Outcomes Behaviors
Food
Shock
Exercise
Nothing
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
the experimental situation. The knowledge in Table 4.1 reflects the product of its
learning.
Simply knowing the behavioral contingencies in Table 4.1 does not tell us
what is optimal behavior for the rat; we also need to know the value it places on
various outcomes. Assume that the outcome’of nothing has a value of 0, food
has a large positive value of 10, shock has a large negative value of —25, and
exercise has a mild positive value of 1. Now it is possible to predict what the rat
will do if it is behaving rationally. Rational theory states that the rat should select
the behavior with the highest expected value. The expected value of an action
is calculated by multiplying the probability of each possible outcome by its value
and taking the sum of these products. This result reflects the average value that
can be expected from that action. In the case of the bar press, there are two pos-
sible outcomes—food and shock. Performing this calculation for these two
yields
Probability(food) x Value(food) + Probability(shock) x Value(shock)
= .67 x 10.0 + .33 x —25.0 = -1.55
In the case of entering the activity wheel, there is only one possible outcome. Its
value is calculated as
Probability(exercise) x Value(exercise) = 1 x 1.0 = 1.00
Finally, in the case of doing nothing, there are two possible outcomes:
Probability(nothing) x Value(nothing) + Probability(food) x Value(food)
= .90 x 0.0 + .10 x 10.0 = 1.00
Thus the exercise wheel and doing nothing are of equal value, and the rat would
be predicted to alternate between them. If the rat became satiated so that food
lost its value, the rat would be predicted to select the exercise wheel exclusive-
ly. If the rat became hungrier and food increased its value, the rat would select
nothing; if it became hungry enough (and food approached a value of 15 or
more), the rat would select to press the bar despite the shocks.
If the hunger of the rat were manipulated, the rat would probably shift
between the activity wheel, doing nothing, and pressing the bar as implied by
this rational analysis. This behavior would not mean that the animal was explic-
itly representing probabilities, values, and calculating expected values, which is
extremely implausible in the case of the rat. Rather, the rat would probably be
doing something much simpler that allowed it to behave as if it were engaged
in rational calculation. This chapter discusses several such simple mechanisms
for selecting appropriate behavior.
120
Some Basic Concepts and Principles
121
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
= 70 : 1 point
op 2 7.0
rs) 2
e |
5 = 6.0 5 points
= 5
a 5 5.0
6 60 E
As Zz
4.0 9 points
3.0
2.0
1 3) 2) 1 5 9
Value of picture (points) Value of picture (points)
(a) (b)
FIGURE 4.1 (a) Probability of recognition and (b) mean number of fixations for pic-
tures worth 1,5, and 9 points. Separate curves are plotted for each of the three values
of the paired-with picture. (From G. R. Loftus, 1972.)
0.8
O57
% i=
Ss
5, 0.6
5
2
x)
£05
=
FIGURE 4.2 Probability of recog- 4
nition as a function of number of & “o>1 point
fixations. A separate curve is plot- — “> 5 points
ted for pictures worth 1, 5, and 9 ~~9 points
points. Source: G. R. Loftus. “Eye
fixations and recognition memory
for pictures,” Cognitive Psychology,
Vol. 3 (1972). Reprinted by permis- 0-1 2-3 4-5 6-7 8+
sion of the author. Number of fixations
122
Some Basic Concepts and Principles
Figure 4.2 confirms, when Loftus controlled for the number of fixations received
bya picture, value had no effect. These results sous the general understanding
isms oredues the response in1 question, the contingency can be one such that the
stimulus is given or not given. Table 4.2 illustrates the four logical possibilities
obtained by crossing desirable or aversive stimuli with different contingencies
between the stimulus and the response. In the first case, reward is made contin-
gent on a behavior. For instance, a child may be ee a sum of money for mow-
einforc ement and should
sayoaergon the eeu This is the favorite response of many parents to misbe-
es “You'reeed. situation is referred to as omission training and
123
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
124
Aversive Control of Behavior
Punishment
Sometimes punishment can be so effective that a single learning experience
eliminates a behavior. A child who touches a hot stove is unlikely to do so again.
In one experimental paradigm (Jarvik & Essman, 1960), a rat is placed on a plat-
form above a grid floor. When it steps off the platform it receives a painful shock.
After a single experience, the rat will not step down again. It learns to com-
pletely suppress a natural response in a sing
(just as
as . delay of BDA aneeat Tes,aetane effooo THonePeeence
illustrating the effects of delay, Camp, Raymond, and Church (1967) contrasted
several groups of rats. Each group was first trained to press a lever in response
to a clicking sound; they were reinforced with food. After this training, half the
presses resulted in a shock at varying delays. For one group, the shock came
immediately after pressing the lever, and for other groups it came 7.5 or 30 sec
after pressing the lever. A control group of rats received as many shocks, but the
shocks were unrelated to when they pressed the lever. Figure 4.3 plots the per-
centage of clicks to which the rats pressed the bar. Note that the group with a
30-sec delay showed only a little more suppression of bar pressing than the con-
trol group for which there was no contingency. (That is, shocks were delivered
on a schedule completely unrelated to when the bar was pressed.) Much more
suppression of bar pressing occurred in the rats with immediate shock.
It is easy to extrapolate from such a result with rats and leap to the con-
clusion that punishment should be immediate with humans, particularly with
children. However, because children can be told the contingency that exists
between the behavior and the punishment, the immediacy of punishment is
probably not so critical.
The erity of the puni shmer nt ca n also have
a strong influence on response
sup ‘igure 4.4 displays data from Church (1969) on the amount of sup-
pression (see the discussion of response suppression in CER with respect to
Figure 2.9) in lever pressing for different levels of severity of shock (including no
shock). There was only a little suppression with .15 mA (milliampere) of shock, a
125
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
80
+
o(@)
jo)
“1
‘\
Mean
of NOS) T
percent
responses
FIGURE 4.3 Mean percentage of
responses as a function of sessions for
groups with 0.0-, 7.5-, and 30.0-sec.
delay of punishment and for a noncon-
tingent-shock control group. (From aN ES 30 Control
good deal more with .50 mA, and still more with 2.0 mA. Extrapolating this result
to human beings raises some of the ethical issues in using punishment. Certain
degrees of oS Dine are simie too extreme to be used.
introduced and then econ in severity, the organism became less sensitive to
punishment and the severest level of punishment was then not as effective as it
would have been if introduced immediately (an example of habituation described
in Chapter 2). Azrin, Holz, and Hake (1963) found that the effectiveness of the
punishment was reduced if only some responses were followed by punishment.
0.8
SoS py
oO)
%
suppression,
of
Degree
o iN)
FIGURE 4.4 Median suppression
ratio as a function of intensity of non-
contingent shock. Lower values reflect
0.0
increased suppression of responses. 0.15 0.5
(From Church, 1969.) Strength of shock, mA
126
Aversive Control of Behavior
fect. noncontine
inget punishmenton later
Poy ee oie
vonageso that they a not have to steal, punishments for stealing (e.g., impris-
onment) will be more effective in deterring the behavior.
An experiment by Azrin and Holz (1966) illustrates the importance of
offering an alternative behavior if punishment is to be effective. Pigeons were
first trained to peck at a key to receive food. Then they were shocked for peck-
ing at the key. There were two conditions: in one there was another key that they
100
leo))
oO[e)
-e No shock
-o- Shock (110 V)
B (e)
baseline
Response
of
rate
percent
as
NO(s)
FIGURE4.5 Median response rate to
a punishment of 145 V as a function of
prior exposure to noncontingent 10 15 me’ 25
shock of 105 V. (From Church, 1969.) Session
127
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
300
--c--r--r-—ft
pe)fo)fo)
| \.
Cc
§ Alternative
D response
2 available |
2 \
100 \ No alternative
. \ response
available
;
(a | rere
0 20v 40v 60v 80v
Punishment intensity, V
FIGURE 4.6 The rate of punished responses as a function of the punishment inten-
sity. (From Azrin & Holtz, unpublished data.) Source: Figure 4.6 from N. H. Azrin and
W. C. Holz. Punishment, in Operant Behavior: Areas of Research and Application, Honig
ed., Copyright © 1966, p. 405. Reprinted by permission of Prentice-Hall, Englewood
Cliffs, New Jersey.
could peck at, and in the other there was only the single key. Figure 4.6 shows
response to the shocked key as a function of the intensity of the shock. Up to
about 40 V, the shock intensity was not severe enough to affect responding to
the key. However, at 50V it was intense enough to produce a complete cessa-
tion of response and a shift to the alternative key in the condition that had an
alternative key. In the condition without an alternative key, the pigeons persist-
ed in pecking when the shock was much more intense.
This review of punishment should not be read as encouragement to use it
as a major mechanism for controlling the behavior of children or others.
Punishment can have a number of serious negative side effects. Azrin and Holz
(1966) argued that punishment can lead to a general suppression of all behav-
iors, good and bad; it can lead to anger in the punished person, and it can moti-
vate deception to avoid punishment. Children sometimes lie to their parents to
get even for past punishment and to avoid future punishment. Also, there is evi-
dence that punishment leads to more aggressive behavior in the punished
(Ulrich & Azrin, 1962). Finally, children may inappropriately use punishment in
interactions with their peers, modeling their parents’ behavior toward them
(Eron, Walder, Toigo, & Lefkowitz, 1963).
128
Aversive Control of Behavior
Negative Reinforcement
mail L achieves | timuli, behav-
ain ecal muli. Solomon and Wynne
(1953) site arae ina compartment with a steel grid floor. At the beginning
of a trial, the light went off; 10 sec later a severe shock was sent through the grid,
causing the dog to run about trying to escape. The dog could leap over a barri-
er to escape the shock, and eventually it jumped over this barrier into another
compartment that was shock free. Within a few trials, the dog learned to jump
the barrier on the signal and thus to avoid shock completely.
A curious feature of such avoidance behavior is that it can be much more
difficult to extinguish than behavior maintained by positive reinforcement. If food
is no longer given conditional on some behavior, such as jumping over a barrier
in response to a stimulus, a dog soon stops the behavior. On the other hand, if the
shock is removed, the dog will continue aria eat without any ae of extinction
shorten aatari ne barrier that neal the rats from escaping. After
about 5 min of forced exposure to the formerly aversive situation, the rats seemed
to learn that there no longer was a eas atedbetween the tone ne the shock.
129
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
First, it does not appear that it is conditioned response of fear that is learned to
the CS. As we noted in Chapter 2 on classical conditioning, rather it is the US
that is typically conditioned to the CS. That is, the animal comes to expect that
the US will follow the CS. The avoidance response is made in anticipation of the
US. Although the CS will often evoke fear, the animal will make the avoidance
response even when the CS no longer evokes fear. For instance, Kamin, Brimer,
and Black (1963) showed that animals continued to avoid the response even
after the CS had lost its ability to evoke a conditioned emotional response (sup-
pression of bar pressing—see Chapters 1 and 2).
Second, elimination of the CS is apparently not necessary to learn the
avoidance response. Kamin (1956) showed that animals would learn an avoid-
ance response even when the CS remained after the avoidance response. Thus,
animals were learning even though they were not eliminating the CS. Another
demonstration that CS elimination is not necessary to learning is provided by
the Sidman shock-postponement procedure (Sidman, 1966) in which there is
no overt CS. This procedure involves presenting an aversive stimulus like shock
every so often without warning. However, the animal can avoid the stimuli if it
performs some response. For instance, by pressing a lever, an animal might be
able to postpone shock for 30 sec. If it presses the lever in that 30-sec period, it
gets another reprieve of 30 sec from the point of this new press. If the animal
presses the lever at least once every 30 sec, it permanently avoids shock. Dogs
master this task well, responding only a few times a minute and avoiding virtu-
ally all shock. The experimental context serves as the CS for this behavior, but
the response does not get rid of this CS, only the US.
In Chapter 3 we discussed the evidence that, in the case of positive rein-
forcement, the organism has learned an association between the CS, the
response, and positive reinforcement. The corresponding analysis in the case of
negative reinforcement (e.g., Seligman & Johnson, 1973) is that what animals
have learned is an association between the CS, the response, and avoidance of
the aversion stimulus. Just as organisms use what they learn to select behavior
in the case of positive reinforcement, they use knowledge of this association in
the case of negative reinforcement.
aversive consequences. ;
130
The Nature of Reinforcement
and maximization of the number of its offspring. The problem with this view is
that an erating RE not really know coe is good foritin such abstract
Ranees and thirst, this proposal is particularly intuitive. Almost all of us ‘have felt
hunger, found it aversive,and more So as de privation SOR AAS: 1
ree instance, Butler (1953) found that monkeys learn to perform a behavior just
for the opportunity to look around the laboratory for a few moments. Rats learn
behaviors for the opportunity to run in an exercise wheel. One could postulate
curiosity drives and exercise drives (perhaps with boredom as the aversive state)
and speculate about their potential biological value (for instance, the values of
learning about the environment and keeping fit), but this has struck many peo-
ple as creating a rather hollow theory. Any behavior could be explained by pos-
tulating a drive for it and proposing some fanciful biological function. Also, such
hypothetical drives do not fit well with experiences of deprivation with more
basic biological needs. Many people live a complete life without a strong desire
to exercise e similar to the desire they have to eat after a day without food.
ven more the t is that beha r can be reir
why ae rats ran a maze ie the Sorority to copulate with a female rat, even
though they were not allowed to ejaculate (Sheffield, Wulff, & Backer, 1951). The
male rats were being reinforced for a behavior that left them with increased
drive. Ina less extreme mode, humans find the company of attractive members
1 However, there often seems to be a limit to the increase in aversiveness as the peri-
od of deprivation continues.
2 Some athletes and other people do report such desires, however.
131
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
each activity
when the organism has
ponemore timeseeae than running i
in anTaN wheel. Another met
he ani y to get either rcement—for instance, pressing
ehavior. Thus, eens children ane ser tae candy to ai the pinball
machine if they ate candy would reduce their rate of eating candy.
Premack (1971) described an experiment by Weisman and Premack (1966)
that illustrates the relativity in the concepts of reinforcement and punishment.
They compared rats that were deprived of water and rats that were not deprived.
When offered simultaneous access to an activity wheel and a drinking tube,
deprived rats spent more time licking from the tube than running, whereas non-
deprived rats spent more time running. Figure 4.7 shows the amount of time
spent in the two activities in the two conditions when rats could choose to do
either. Premack used such free-choice information to establish the relative value
of the two activities. For the deprived rats drinking water was more valued,
whereas for the nondeprived rats running the activity wheel was more valued.
Then Weisman and Premack introduced a contingency such that if a rat
licked the tube 15 times it had to run for 5 sec and could run for no more than
5 sec. What should this contingency do to their licking? For the nondeprived
132
The Nature of Reinforcement
400
g 300
2) + .
e | Licking
=
8
= 200-
i=
o
oe L
®
= 100 Running
rats, the activity wheel was more valued, and this contingency should reinforce
licking. For the deprived rats, the wheel was less valued, and so having to run in
it should punish licking. Figure 4.8 compares the rates of licking before and after
introduction of the contingency. As predicted, the contingency reinforced lick-
ing for the nondeprived rats and increased their rate of licking. On the other
hand, it Ngaio the ie for the deprived rats and decreased their rate.
Sat aera SSE URINE EN seo ence tea OLR SNARE TREES OPER ULES ELE ETERS ELITES ETE SESE NENG BE
400
Ww[e)oO
Water-deprived rats
3 Oo ]
Time
licking,
spent
sec Nondeprived rats
100
133
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
| (they reduce no
drive) and Premack’s Denner teary (they volves no behaviors).
Se a SRS NEE La RON soa ANP HST IEE TACRT ROTTER
ECC itt
134
The Nature of Reinforcement
ing stimuli (like food), by behaviors (like running in an activity wheel), and by
things that are neither (like brain stimulation).
given the enone between two saccharin solutions, spent more time on the
sweeter of the two when drinking freely. Premack would predict that drinking
the less sweet solution would punish drinking the sweeter solution. For
instance, suppose rats had to lick the less sweet solution once for every time
they licked the sweeter solution (a 1-to-1 response ratio). Rats should decrease
their rate of licking the sweet solution because a less desirable solution fol-
lowed. This is probably what Allison and Timberlake would have found with a
1-to-1 ratio, but in their study the rat had to lick the sweeter solution 10 times
to get access to the less sweet solution. Since the 10-to-1 ratio was greater than
the natural distribution between the solutions, if the rats licked the sweeter
solution as much as they did in the free drinking situation, they would get less
of the less sweet solution than in the free situation. In this experiment, the rats
increased their rate of drinking the sweeter solution iin order to gainmore access
135
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
Bliss
point
150
<x
ro} .
= 100°
=
a
FIGURE 4.9 Behavior B as a function of 50
Behavior A under a condition that con-
strains the two behaviors to be equal. The
arrow points from the place on the curve i:
closest to the bliss point. (From Allison, 0% 50 100 150 200
1989.) Behavior B
136
Studies of Choice Behavior
Schedules of Reinforcement
The publication of Ferster and Skinner's Schedules of Reinforcement in 1957
marked a sharp increase in interest in the relationship between the schedule
with which reinforcements are delivered and the resulting behavior. Four basic
schedules have been studied, akthough there are many exotic variations. In the
reinforcement
is given after every so many
‘s. For example, a schedule with a reinforce-
sehediile the organism receives a reinforcement for its next ieeoanse after 15 sec
have elapsed; the organism then waits another 15 sec before its next response
produces a Sibi 8 and so on. Finally, inav
i e
137
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
>
Cumulative
responses
———
ne
FIGURE 4.10 Stylized cumulative response records obtained under four common
schedules of reinforcement. The ticks on the functions denote delivery of reinforce-
ments.
variable rates.In the fixed-interval schedule, the organism appears to have come
close to figuring out what the interval is and does its responding at about the end
of that interval. In the fixed-ratio schedule, the organism pauses after each rein-
forcement, as if it is taking a rest before starting the next set of responses.
Response rates are generally higher in the ratio schedules than in interval
schedules, an adaptive behavior, since the rate of reward in such schedules is
directly related to the rate of response. Animals will respond to extreme ratios,
as high as 1000 responses to one reinforcement; however, they have to be
shaped to do so, starting with much lower ratios and slowly working up. The
rate of nesponding. is little related to the reinforcement rate in a ratio schedule.
poetnigher the ratio ofresponses to reinforcers,the longerthe organism pauses —
after a reinforcement. There is a big burst of effort followed by a rest.
The organisms’ pattern of behavior under these various schedules appears
quite adaptive. It need not be the case, however, that they caieaianale know
what the schedule i
is andRC Ree Bate it is thoug th
es re ey are adapted rf)
the CORRES emadon & renen 1989). For instance, in a fixed-inter-
val schedule, the animal is indirectly reinforced for interspersing other behaviors
(such as grooming) between the bar presses, since such composite behavior
produces the food plus other benefits (i.e., closer to bliss point). Animals can
also learn to respond according to a differential low-rate schedule, in which they
are reinforced only if they do not respond too rapidly. Under such a schedule,
intervening behaviors not only produce their own rewards but also serve a tim-
138
Studies of Choice Behavior
ing function to enable the animal to wait long enough to receive the primary
reinforcement (Hemmes, Eckerman, & Rubinsky, 1979).
ge but also most other organisms, including humans. The law also holds
3 The weak dependence is produced because once the time for the reinforcer has
come up, the food remains idle until the pigeon pecks. Only after the pigeon pecks
does the timing begin for the next reinforcer.
139
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
09
0.8
0.7 +
0.6
0.5
0.4
Responses
A%
Key
on
0.3
OFZ
0.1
0
FIGURE 4.11 Choice and reward ©) 101, O2200)30.4..0'5 0160057 10:20.
proportions from Herrnstein (1961). % Rewards on Key A
Momentary Maximizing
It can be shown mathematically that for an organism to optimize its rate of rein-
forcement in a situation in which it is choosing between two VI schedules, its
behavior should correspond closely to the matching law.* Thus, the organism’s
140
Studies of Choice Behavior
behavior in matching can be nearly optimal. It could be argued that the organ-
isn guring out what pattern of behavior will achieve a global optimum, or
me im, in terms of overall intake of food. Such behavior is referréd to as
maximization. It is unlikely, however, that the animal has consciously
figured the contingencies and calculated the behavior that will result in optimal
reward. Herrnstein and Vaughan proposed the melioration theory of choice,
and others (Shimp, 1969; bees ne Hamilton, Ziriax, & Casey, 1978) have pro-
eon e Sem de
italy
diod ch loose
5 The two theories are subtly different. Momentary maximizing claims that the organ-
ism makes the best response now, whereas melioration claims that the response dis-
tribution shifts toward the current best. They differ in the time window over which
the local optimization takes place.
141
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
oi lees Petia:
Probab 7 mate hing i sg afie on Ot an the ~ Ww It has
more Sen been studied 1in ene aerate the ee law has been more
often studied in lower organisms. A typical experiment (e.g., Friedman, Burke,
Cole, Keller, Millward, Estes, 1964) presents the subject with a pair of buttons
with two associated lights. On each trial the subject must predict which light
will come on by pressing the associated button. Different conditions are defined
by the probability with which each light comes on. In the Friedman et al. exper-
iment, one light came on,with probabilities of 0.1, 0.2, 0.3, 0.4, 0.5, 0.6, 0.7, 0.8,
and 0.9, and the other light came on the remaining time. kick choose ane
142
Studies of Choice Behavior
ed according to a VR 4/3 (it gets three rewards for every four trials on average)
schedule, while on the other arm it gets rewarded according to a VR 4 schedule.
As we noted, in situations that offer a choice between two VR schedules, organ-
isms will choose the schedule with a smaller ratio of trials to rewards—that is,
in this case theVR 4/3 arm. The rat does not see what happens in the other arm.
It does not know that when it failed on one arm it would have gotten rewarded
on the other arm. In contrast, the class has access to this information. When ani-
mals have access to the outcome of the other side, they also probability match
(Graf, Bullock, & Bitterman, 1964; Sutherland & Mackintosh, 1971).
143
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
0.6
0.5
0.44
0.3
% 0.2
Probability
changing
of
keys
FIGURE 4.12 Probability of remain-
ing in the presence of the stimulus 0.1
leading to the less preferred outcome
as a function of the duration of the 60
changeover requirement (travel time). . fo) 4 8 12 16
(From Fantino & Abarca, 1985.) Changeover delay, sec
could be pecked. If the pigeon started out on the VI 60 key, it could switch to the
superiorVI 30 key by pecking a changeover key. However, a delay of 0, 4, or 16
sec was introduced before the other key became operative. Figure 4. 12 shows
Humans can be similarly observed to forage and shift patches for foraging.
A good analogy to foraging in the human case is working. People switch jobs if
a new job offers a high enough increase in income. People are also sensitive to
the travel time involved in making the switch. They are much more willing to
change jobs if the new job is in the same city and quite reluctant to change if it
is in a different country. If the economic disparity is great enough, however,
humans move great distances, as evidenced by the waves of immigration to the
United States. Recently, Pirolli and Card (in press) have applied optimal forag-
ing theory to how people seek information from sources like the World Wide
Web. They show that humans looking for information behave in many ways like
animals looking for food.
Another complication of foraging is that repeated foraging of some patches
tends to deplete them. This situation was explored in the laboratory by giving blue
jays a choice between a depleting and a nondepleting key (Kamil, Yoerg, &
Clements, 1988). The probability of a peck being reinforced with a moth for the
nondepleting key stayed constant at 25 percent. The probability of a peck being
reinforced on the depleting key started at 50 percent, but only a fixed number of
prey were available. When the last prey was taken, the probability dropped from 50
° The blue jays were shown pictures of moths, but they were actually given pieces of
mealworms.
144
Studies of Choice Behavior
percent to zero. Blue jays learned to be adaptive in their strategy, starting with the
depleting key but switching over when that key began to reach depletion. Kamil et
al. found that blue jays showed a strong tendency to switch over after experiencing
a string of three failed pecks at the depleting key. After three such failed pecks, the
odds were in fact fairly high that they had depleted the food source.
EA Re ONS ss
145
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
2.0 =
1 versus 4 sec
ON
value
Subjective 4 versus 8 sec
10 versus 14 sec
ereen light that gave them a large reward at a 4-sec delay. It is difficult to know
how to judge this issue. It could be argued that in the real world of pigeons
things in the future are so uncertain that it makes sense for the pigeon to take
what it can get right away.’ The situation with our children turned out to illus-
trate the uncertainty of calculations about the future. Eventually, they were able
to cajole their parents to get a puppy despite the bargain to the contrary. In this
case a potential future loss (no puppy) turned out to be unreal.
is ee twice the value of the small reward, but the subjective values drop off
quite rapidly. Thus, when a small reward at 1 sec is compared with a large
reward at 4 sec, the small reward has greater subjective value. This explains why
pigeons might choose the small reward at the short delay.
These curves decay in an interesting way. Suppose that a pigeon is offered a
choice between a small reward at a 10-sec delay and a large reward at a 14-sec
delay. The pigeon should choose the large reward at a 14-sec delay, which is of
greater value; Ainslie and Herrnstein (1981) confirmed this prediction. Figure 4.13
implies that pigeons should also be relatively indifferent to a choice between a
small reward at 4 sec and a large reward at 8 sec; this prediction was also con-
firmed (Ainslie & Herrnstein, 1981; Rachlin & Green, 1972). The way these curves
7 T could not resist making a pun about a bird in the hand being worth two in the
bush.
146
Studies of Choice Behavior
Small reward
Red key
10-sec delay ;
Second choice
Green ke
Right key ‘i 4-sec delay
Large reward
First
choice
Left key
FIGURE 4.14 The procedure in the experiment by Rachlin and Green (1972).
decay with time determines how sensitive one is to delay. Humans (e.g., King &
Logue, 1987) and other primates (e.g., Tobin, Logue, Chelonis, Ackerman, & May,
1996) are less sensitive to delay than pigeons and rats. On the other hand, young
children respond more like pigeons (Sonuga-Barke, Lea, & Webley, 1989).
Rachlin and Green studied this issue in an interesting paradigm illustrat-
ed in Figure 4.14. At the beginning of a trial, pigeons pecked at either a right key
or a left key. If the right key was chosen, after 10 sec of darkness they were
exposed to a choice between a red key that gave the small reinforcement imme-
diately or a green key that gave the large reinforcement after another 4-sec
delay. They manifested an inability to delay gratification and almost always
chose the red key. Thus, if they chose the right key initially, they were effective-
ly choosing a small reward at a 10-sec delay. If they chose the left key, 10 sec of
blackout was followed by a green key that, if pecked, gave them a large reward
in 4 sec. Thus, if they chose the left key they wereicaiagial choosing a large
Hees at resec. peal BEER the leftheThey wer making a choice early
147
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
Mechanisms of Choice
Animals have thus far been described as being quite rational in their decision
making. They strive to achieve the optimal tradeoff among their competing
needs, displaying rates of responding under different schedules that comes as
close as possible to their bliss point. They make appropriate choices foraging in
the wild (and between alternative schedules in the laboratory), behaving in a
way that can be viewed as maximizing their net energy intake. Their discount-
ing of time corresponds to economists’ prescriptions for rational behavior.
This discussion raisés the question of how animals achieve the near opti-
mality of their choice behavior. It is unlikely that they are engaging in anything
like explicitly calculating the prescription for rational choice set forth at the
beginning of the chapter. It also is implausible that they are always correct in the
choices they make. Rather, animals can be viewed as being governed by what
amounts to rules of thumb, which serve them relatively well in most situations.
For instance, an animal could produce the matching law by always choosing the
alternative with the higher momentary rate of reward. Similarly, the blue jays in
the Kamil et al. (1988) experiment chose to leave a depleting patch after a string
of three failures (which happened to be quite predictive of patch depletion).
Animal behavior is probably controlled by such simple near-term rules that tend
to approximate global optimal behavior.
148
Mechanisms of Choice
Number of
rooms
Distance
from work
Parking
Condition
Apartment
A: =2 +8 +0+3+48=17
Apartment B:10+4+4+3+4+5= 26
Apartment C:9+4+6+0+5=24
Apartment D:6+8+6+0+2=22
149
CHAPTER 4 Reinforcement and Learning
Because it does not consider all the alternatives, satisficing may miss the
best choice.
Although these strategies do not always yield the best results, they often pro-
duce the best result or a result close to the best and they give results quickly
because they allow the decision maker to focus on a subset of the information.
Payne, Bettman, and Johnson (1988) showed that under time pressure, the elim-
ination-by-aspects strategy more often yields the correct decision than the com-
plete rational decision strategy. When the time is up, the rational decision strat-
egy may not yet have considered the correct alternative, whereas the elimina-
tion-by-aspects strategy may have already identified the correct alternative.
They also showed that subjects are sensitive to time pressure and tend to switch
from an exhaustive strategy to an elimination-by-aspects strategy when time
pressure increases.
Thus, humans, like lower animals, use rules of thumb for making deci-
sions, and these rules of thumb do not always yield the optimal choice. The
Payne et al. study identified another important aspect of the process of making
rational choice: different strategies take different amounts of time to execute. An
individual cannot exhaustively consider all the apartments listed in a typical
urban newspaper; nor can an animal in the wild spend inordinate amounts of
time making decisions. It might therefore be rational to use rules of thumb that
only approximate the best decision but to do so quickly. Economists refer to this
consideration as the cost of information. In judging what the best choice is, we
need consider not only the value of the choice but also the cost of seeking the
information that went into making that choice.
a eSSRNR a aT Nd
Final Reflections
This chapter concludes the discussions of research focused on animal learning,
although later chapters will return many times to issues of animal cognition and
memory. In general, animals learn the contingencies in the environment and
behave in a way so as to nearly maximize what they desire. Issues of reinforce-
ment necessarily play a major role in-research on animal learning because
appropriate reinforcement conditions are needed to get the animal to display
what it has learned. In contrast, humans can be directly queried, and experi-
menters can count on their general social cooperativeness to say what they have
learned. .
Much of human learning is available to consciousness, and humans often
consciously decide what knowledge to display and how. For instance, students
can tell what they know of a history lesson and why they chose to display this
150
Further Readings
Further Readings
In addition to the sources suggested in Chapters 2 and 3, much of the research
on schedules of reinforcement can be found in the Journal of the Experimental
Analysis of Behavior. B. Williams (1988) provides an overview of research of
choice behavior under different schedules. Herrnstein (1990) offers a readable
discussion of the matching law and other issues about choice behavior. Staddon
(1983) and Staddon and Ettinger (1989) present an adaptive analysis of behav-
ior. The book edited by Klein and Mowrer (1989) contains a number of recent
articles on the nature of reinforcement. The May 1993 edition of Psychological
Science contains a series of articles on comparative cognition—relating animal
cognition to human cognition.
151
Transient Memories
Conditioning Research
Versus Memory Research
This chapter marks a transition from research focused on animal conditioning to
research focused on human memory. The critical distinction is not so much the
species of the subject as it is the methodology used—the conditioning experiment
versus the memory experiment. The typical conditioning experiment involves a
rather complex situation from the point of view of the organism. The organism is
placed in a novel environment and is given some experiences that typically include
strong manipulations of motivation. The experimenter is interested in the behavior
that arises as a function of these experiences and motivational manipulations.
Figure 5.1 illustrates one way to conceive of what is happening in a con-
tioning experiment Theorganism explo imply hastofigureoutthe
structure of the environment, including reinforcement contingencie
experiences. The process by which it does so is Sometimes calle
input to this process is its experience, possibly combined with biological predis-
positions and, in the case of humans, with some instructions. The result of this
process is some knowledge of the environment, and this knowledge is deposit-
ed in memory. A process called Fi verts_this
knowledge into behavior. Figure 5.1 illustrates that this process of motivation is
also affected by the organism's current goals. Memory is just one part of a larg-
er system that is involved in a conditioning experiment; memory experiments
try to focus on that one part.
Figure 5.1 also embodies the important discovery that learning processes
are separate from motivational processes. Chapters 1 and 4 reviewed the evi-
dence that motivation does not influence what is learned but how organisms
display this learning. For instance, Tolman’s rats learned about mazes in the
absence of reinforcement, but displayed that knowledge only when food was
put in the goal box. Thus, Figure 5.1 illustrates that motivation does not control
what goes into memory, but rather how memory maps onto behavior.
152
Conditioning Research Versus Memory Research
Environment
Instructions — Experience Behavior
Biological
Organism
predispositions
Knowledge of environment
Memory
. .
153
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
more suited for the study of the complete system. Animals are also often more
suited for the study of a single aspect of the system as well because there are
fewer ethical constraints regarding their treatment. Many experiments on the
motivation and physiology of learning involve extreme manipulations that can
only be done with animals. -
Humans often offer advantages, however, because they can be more care-
fully directed through instructions and experimenters can count on their social
cooperativeness to obtain appropriate information. The advantage of human
subjects
DN1eCC is
| strongest
Noes in the e behavioral study of the me ystem. In thetypi-
cal conditioning experiment, the memory system is only indirectly connected to
the environment. The induction phase intervenes between the input from the
environment and the memory system. The induction system figures out what
goes with what and hence what should be stored in memo
A simple human
memory experiment might require subjects to learn 20 stimulus—-response
paired associations, such as dog—6, where they must respond with the second
term when shown the first. Twenty such pairs are a herculean number of stim-
ulus—response associations to train in a conditioning experiment. With human —
154
Sensory Memory
Sensory Memory
How does information from _ GSS ORs ou Peper iL Some perma”
nent memory? t
X M R J
C N K 1?
Ww F L B
FIGURE 5.2 Type of visual display used in visual report procedures.
205
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
the retina. She showed that many of the timing and sensitivity properties of the
iconic image mirror those of the rods, which are the photoreceptors in the eye
responsible for night vision. According to this analysis, the icon is very much like
the afterimage of a bright light at night. However, there has to be more to icons
'That their reports were not always perfect probably reflected difficulties in execut-
ing the reporting and the fact that some of that row might have faded before it could
be reported.
156 i
po
Sensory Memory
4.0
2 cola
recalled
letters
of
number
Mean
‘Haber (1983) questioned the relevance of the icon for normal visual per-
ception because humans do not usually perceive the world in such brief flashes;
64 OOD) tee
Hiidt DIOCESSITL?E 15 OL
157
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
third from directly above the subject. As in the visual report procedures, subjects
were not able to report all nine items (3 lists x 3 items) when asked to recall
everything. However, the researchers also used a partial report condition simi-
lar to that used by Sperling. They asked the subjects to report just one of the
three lists. They cued subjects as to which listto report by presenting a visual
indicator on the right, middle, or left of a screen.
Subje i centage oO
they were cued than when they were told to recall the total list. Like Sperling,
Darwin et al. interpreted this to mean that there were items in an auditory buffer
that could not be recalled’in the whole report procedure because they had faded
from memory before the subject was able to report them. In the partial report
procedure, subjects had to report fewer items and so got to reporting the criti-
cal items sooner. Darwin et al. also showed that the amount that could be
reported in the partial report procedure decreased as the delay between the end
of the lists and the cue increased) After 4 sec there was very little advantage for
the partial report procedure.Asin the case of iconic memory, this result indicat-
ed that items were decaying and that subjects were only able to remember
something from the critical list if they encoded it before it had faded.
Neisser called the auditory sensory memory that held these items echoic
memory. As in the case of iconic memory, he argued that people need some
‘memory to hold the sensory experience so that it can be analyzed and encoded
into a more permanent form.
Glucksberg and Cowan (1970) conducted a rather different experiment,
which resulted in a similar estimate of the duration of the echoic store. They pre-
sented subjects with two spoken messages, one in each ear, and they required
subjects to repeat the message that was being said in one ear. This task, called a
shadowing task isvery demanding, and subjects typically remember nothing of
what is said in the other ear. From time to time, the experimenters said a digit
to the ear that was not being shadowed. They stopped the subjects and asked
whether a digit had occurred. They found that if they asked subjects right after
the digit, subjects could still detect it with some success. This performance
dropped off dramatically over the first 2 sec, and after 5 sec the subjects showed
no ability to detect the digit. Thexesearchers concluded that in less than 5 sec
echoic memory was completely lost for the unattended digit.
Conrad (1960) and Crowder and Morton (1969) showed not only that
ecays from echoic memory with the passage of time but also that
additional auditory information can interfere with it. orton pre-
ented thewordzerojustbefore asking subjecis Torecall a list of digits. Subjects
were told to ignore the last zero and to recall the preceding digits. This final digit
seriously impaired memory for the list. This phenomenon is called the suffix
Impairment occurs because the zero enters auditory memory and interferes with
the target list.
The interference associated with the suffix effect seems to be verbal in
character. Crowder and Morton found that if they used a buzzer rather than a
158
Sensory Memory
before it decays, itislost. What subjects encode depends on what they are pay-
ing attention to. Typically, the environment offers much more information at one
time than we can attend to and encode. Therefore
beeconrs fae ear MRR SEte Similarly, instrumental conditioning
research (see the discussion of dimensional learning in Chapter 3) has shown
that animals often do not initially attend to certain aspects of the stimuli pre-
sented to them. Presumably, nonhumans are also overwhelmed by the richness
of the stimuli they experience and can only pay attention to certain things.
Although the auditory and visual systems are perhaps the most important,
they are not the only sensory systems that display transient memories for infor-
mation. a pe rd
performance of a skill. Information,
etas it is by many of ourersensory
systems s. In some cir-
cumstances,
The remainder of the chapter describes
‘the overall information processing, including their roleincreating permanent _
ies. At one time it was thought that there was a sequence of memories,
SF ction passed from sensory memory to short-term memory and then
to long-term memory. The next section discusses the problems associated with
the concept of an intermediate short-term memory. The remainder of the chap-
ter describes the more current idea of a working memory.
ESERIES IRON ELIE OLE NREL
SLL LLANELLI LELAND PILLLELEL INE HERA IRAE IOUSLESNON NUNES REPRESS
159
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
Each of these claims was based on some empirical data. However, it has become
apparent that all the data cannot be properly understood if there is assumed to
be a short-term memory between sensory memory and long-term memory. This
section considers each claim, the evidence for it, and the problems with it.
Effects of Rehearsal
As discussed in Chapter 1,
He asked subjects to rehearse out loud and
counted the number of times they r ehearsed each wor
at \ ehearsed more were better recalled (see Figure 1.12).
This result
was just as predicted by the Atkinson and Shiffrin theory, which proposed that
information got into long-term memory by being rehearsed in short-term mem-
ory. Sometimes, however, rehearsal does little to improve long-term memory.
977) had subjects study a four-digit number for 2
sec, then rehearse a word for 2, 6, or 18 sec, and finally recall the four digits.
Subjects participated in 64 trials. Subjects thought that the experimenter’s inter-
est was in digit recall and that the words were only being used to fill up the reten-
tion interval. After the experiment, subjects were asked to recall the words they
160
The Rise and Fall of the Theory of Short-Term Memory
had been rehearsing. Their recall averaged an abysmal 11, 7, and 12 percent,
respectively, in the 2-, 6-, and 18-sec rehearsal intervals. Thus, subjects showed
little recall and no relationship between the amount of rehearsal and the amount
of recall. Glenberg et al. also tried a recognition test for the words and found only
a weak effect of amount of rehearsal on memory performance.
Craik and Watkins (1973) used another paradigm to show the lack of an
effect of passive rehearsal‘on memory. Their subjects heard a list of 21 words and
were supposed to recall the last word that began with a certain letter. Thus, if the
critical letter was G, subjects might hear daughter, rifle, garden, grain, table, foot-
ball, anchor, giraffe, fish, tooth, book, heart, mouse, gold, can, ball, paper, fire, glass,
house, shoe, and should recall glass. When the subjects heard the first G-word,
they did not know whether it was the word they would have to recall; therefore,
they had to rehearse it until they heard the next G-word. Different words had to
be rehearsed for different lengths of time. In the example given, garden would
be rehearsed for zero words, grain three words, giraffe five words, gold four
words, and glass two words. After studying 27 such lists, subjects were given a
surprise recall of all the words. Craik and Watkins found no relationship
between how long the word was rehearsed and its final probability of recall.
Perhaps the most dramatic evidence for the lack of relationship between
the amount of rehearsal and long-term recall is the report cited by Neisser (1982)
of a Professor Sanford, who estimated that he had read the family prayers at
meals some 5000 times over 25 years. Despite all this rehearsal, Professor
Sanford found that when he tested his memory, he had very little memory for the
prayers. | ee good long-term memory.
If it is not sheer repetition, what does determine how much we remem-
ber? Rundus (refer to Figure 1.12) found a relationship between number of
rehearsals and recall, but, unlike the experiments just cited, his subjects were
actively processing the material with an eye to remembering it. In an influential
article, Craik and Lockhart (1972) argued that what _was critical was the depth
to which information was processed. According to this theory, called the depth.
r i
of processing arsal_ improves
theory, rehearsal improves memory only if
memory only if the
the material
material is
_is
rehearsed in a deep and meaningful way; passive rehearsal does not result in
better memory. This point of view was nicely illustrated in a series of experi-
ments by Craik and Tulving (1975). In one experiment they showed subjects a
word, such as table, and asked them to make three types of judgments. The shal-
low-level judgment, about case, was whether the word was in capitals. The
intermediate-level judgment was whether it rhymed with another word, for
example, cable. The deep-level judgment was whether it fit in a sentence, for
example, “He put the plate on the .” They later asked subjects to rec-
ognize the words. Figure 5.4 shows the proportion of words recognized as a
function of the type of processing of the words. The more deeply processed
words were better remembered. Similar effects of depth of processing can be
shown in memory for faces. Subjects show better memory for photos of faces if
they are asked to judge whether the person is honest rather than whether the
person is male or female (Bloom & Mudd, 1991; Sporer, 1991).
161
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
.80
Ss
aS)oO
recognized
Proportion
Nm fo)
Coding Differences
162
The Rise and Fall of the Theory of Short-Term Memory
‘Memory for these letters was supported by semantic information which, accord-
. ing to the short-term memory theory, is a long-term memory coding. In addi-
tion, the fact that people can remember rhymes and sounds for long periods of
time provides evidence of acoustic codings in long-term memory.
People can also make semantic confusions in a short-term memory task.
Potter and Lombardi (1990) presented subjects with sentences such as
163
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
Subjects then heard a list that included the word castle. After hearing the list,
they were asked to recall the original sentence. About a quarter of the subjects
recalled
and thus intruded the semantically related word. This semantic confusion indi-
cates that our immediate memory for a list of words (in this case a sentence)
involves semantic information as well as acoustic information.
An alternative proposal, based on the concept of depth of processing
2 (Craik & Lockhart, 1972; Wickelgren, 1974), proposes that different types of
information are forgotten at different rates and that sensory information may be
more shallowly processed and may be forgotten more rapidly. Initially, memo-
ries may show a preponderance of sensory traces, but as time passes, semantic
traces remain. (This issue of differential forgetting for different types of memo-
ry is addressed in more detail in Chapter 6.) Thus, acoustic confusion predomi-
nates early in the Kintsch and Bushke experiment because the acoustic infor-
mation has not been forgotten. As time passes the acoustic information is for-
gotten, leaving primarily semantic information, which was there all the time,
and resulting in mainly semantic confusions.
ORSON
recall. Note that retention decreased to about 20 percent, not to zero, supposedly
reflecting what the subjects were able to store in long-term memory. Given longer
initial study, subjects would have shown a higher level of performance after 18 sec,
reflecting the transfer of more information to long-term memory.
There are several problems with such demonstrations. Such steeply
decreasing retention functions are not obtained for subjects’ recall of their first
164
The Rise and Fall of the Theory of Short-Term Memory
100
80
60
40
recall
Percent
20
0 S 6 9 ee 15 18
Time, sec
nonsense trigram (Keppel & Underwood, 1962); in this case they show relative-
ly little forgetting.
i Thus,
animportant
Chapter 7 examines these
studies and retention effects at greater length, but for now it should be noted
that the forgetting in Figure 5.5
committed
to long-term memory.
The retention curve in Figure 5.5 appears to show rapid initial forgetting
followed by no further forgetting. This apparent discontinuity of the forgetting
curve was used to argue for two stores (e.g., Waugh & Norman, 1965). The ini-
whereas the flat portion of the curve was supposed to represent what got into
long-term memory. However, note that performance is still dropping off from 9
to 18 sec (and this curve would continue to drop off beyond 18 sec).
pointed out that all retention curves for any period of time show negative accel-.
Consider the retention study of Ebbinghaus (Figure 1.1 from Chapter 1). He
looked at retention of material that was much better learned than that repre-
sented in Figure 5.5 over intervals of up to 30 days. Figure 1.2 shows a negatively
accelerated retention curve with an apparent discontinuity at around two days,
where the curve is flattening. Clearly, there is not a short-term memory of two
days! The forms of retention curves are not evidence for a discontinuity between
short-term and long-term memory; the curves are really continuous, and their
apparent discontinuity is merely an artifact of the scales on which they are
graphed. Chapter 7 discusses the nature of these retention functions more fully.
165
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
The shape of the early part of the retention function and the
factors that influence it are the same as for the later part of the
retention function.
Rehearsal Systems
A previous section reviewed the evidence for the existence of sensory memories
that maintain transient records of our experience. For instance, we have an
acoustic memory that holds information for a few seconds. What happens if we
say a set of numbers to ourselves? Presumably, we are filling our echoic mem-
ory with a sensory record of our own speech. If we do this over and over again,
we can keep a record of those digits in echoic memory. By rehearsal, we are
making our echoic memory a system for holding the digits. There are other ways
‘in which we can use our bodies as systems for holding information. We can
remember a digit by holding out the appropriate number of fingers; we can
remember where something is in space by staring at that location; we can
remember the width of a board by placing our two hands at its sides and then
keeping our hands that far apart. People can be extremely imaginative in how
they use their bodies as transient memories to hold information. The verbal sys-
tem is particularly important, and a great deal of research has been devoted to
how this system may be used to hold information. Baddeley used the term
phonological loop to refer to our use of the verbal system as a transient mem-
ory.
166
Rehearsal Systems
to five syllables,
Figure 5.6 shows the recall results. Recall decreased as the number of syllables
increased, falling from about 4.5 words for the one-syllable words to 2.6 words
for the five-syllable words. Figure 5.6 also plots the reading rate—the number
of words of each syllable length that can be said in 1 sec. The reading rate also
decreased as number of syllables increased. Dividing the number recalled by the
reading rate produces a value of about 2 for all syllable lengths. For instance,
a8 2.00 $
fs
© 3
=
2)
5
CJ
167
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
subjects could recall about 3.5 of 5 three-syllable words and their reading rate
was about 1.8 words/sec—giving 3.5/1.8, or approximately 2-sec worth of
words. This result implies that subjects can recall what they can rehearse in 2
sec. The capacity of the phonological loop is limited by how far back the inner
ear can remember hearing a word. The research of Darwin, Turvey, and Crowder
(1972) and Glucksberg and Cowan (1970), reviewed earlier, indicated that
echoic memory had a span of 4 or 5 sec. This span is a good bit longer than that
estimated for Baddeley’s phonological loop, but these studies involved rather
different procedures and measures.
The crucial variable is spoken duration, not number of syllables. Words with
long vowels, such as Friday and harpoon, show shorter spans than words with short
vowels, such as wicked and bishop (Baddeley, 1997). There is an interesting rela-
tionship between speech rate and digit span. Digit span is afairly standard test of
memory that appears in intelligence tests. ILinvolves seeing how many single-digit
numbers aperson can repeat back perfectly. Adult speakers ofEnglish have spans
of about seven or eight digits. There is a correlation across languages between span
and articulation length for digits. The articulation rate for Chinese is 265 msec/digit
(Hoosain & Salili, 1988), compared with 321 msec/digit for English and 385
msec/digit for Welsh (Ellis & Hennelly, 1980). Correspondingly, spans are longest
for Chinese (9.9), intermediate for English (6.6), and shortest for Welsh (5.8).
Trying to maintain information in the phonological loop is analogous to
the circus act that involves spinning plates on reeds. The circus performer starts
one plate spinning on a reed, then another on another reed, then another, and
so on. The performer must return to the first before it slows down and falls off,
respin it, and then respin the rest of the plates. There are only so many plates
that the performer can keep spinning. Baddeley proposed the same situation
with respect to working memory. If we try to keep too many items in working
memory, by the time we get back to rehearse the first one, its representation is
no longer available in the phonological store.
This phonological loop seems to involve speech. Conrad (1964) performed
some of the original research establishing this point. He showed that when sub-
jects misremembered something from a memory-span task, they tended to
recall something that sounded similar. In his experiment, subjects were asked to
recall a string of letters, such as HBKLMW. They were much more likely to mis-
recall B as its soundalikeV than as an S, which does not sound similar. Conrad
also found that subjects had a harder time recalling a string of letters that con-
tained a high proportion of rhyming letters (such as BCTHVZ) than a string that
did not (such as HBKLMW). He speculated that this problem arose because of
confusion among the similar-sounding letters.
Further evidence that the phonological loop involves speech is provided
by articulatory suppression techniques, which require the subject to say repeat-
edly an irrelevant word, such as the (Baddeley, Lewis, & Vallar, 1984). Subjects
repeat the word while they listen to a list of words and while they try to write
down the list in recall. Requiring the subject to say the word prevents the
rehearsing of anything else in the phonological loop. When subjects are required
168
Rehearsal Systems
169
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
FIGURE 5.7 Example of material used by Baddeley in his study of the visuo-spatial
sketch pad. Source: From A. D. Baddeley, S..Grant, E. Wight, and N. Thomson.
Attention and Performance V, Volume 5. Imagery and Visual Working Memory.
Copyright © 1975 by Academic Press. Reprinted by permission.
only five of the nonsense sentences; this suggests that they were able to use the
image of the 4 x 4 matrix to supplement their memory for the sentences.
In an important elaboration on this basic study, Baddeley, Grant, Wight,
and Thomson (1975) looked at the effect of a concurrent spatial tracking task on
memory for the sentences. The concurrent tracking task involved keeping a sty-
lus in contact with a spot of light that followed a circular track. Subjects had to
remember eight spatial sentences or five nonsense sentences like those in
Figure 5.7. Figure 5.8 shows the total number of errors made in remembering
these sentences when the subjects were and were not simultaneously perform-
Nonsense material
3.0
Spatial material
S©
S 2.0
&
=
=
5
= 1.0
ing a spatial tracking task. The error rate was approximately the same for spatial
and nonsense material without a spatial tracking task and was not impaired for
nonsense sentences given a spatial tracking task. The error rate rose dramiatical-
ly when subjects had to perform a spatial tracking task concurrently with mem-
orizing the spatial sentences. This result indicates that the visuo-spatial sketch
pad that supports the memory of the spatial sentences is tapping the same sys-
tem that supports the representation of the tracking task.
FIGURE 5.9 Baddeley’s theory of working memory where a central executive coor-
dinates a set of slave systems. Source: From A. D. Baddeley. Working memory: Oxford
psychology series No. 11. Copyright © 1986. Reprinted by permission of Oxford
University Press.
171
‘Chapter 5 Transient Memories
observe what you do. You might try to hold an image of the multiplication,
which looks like
37
x
28
296
_740
1036
You might verbally rehearse information to help you retain it. Thus, you might
well use both your phonological loop and your visuo-spatial sketch pad to help
you perform the task. But you need to access information that is in neither store.
You have to remember that your task is multiplication; where you are in the
multiplication; and temporary carries, such as 5 from 56. All this information is
held by the central executive and is used to determine the course of solving the
problem and the use of the slave systems. In addition, you would have to
remember information such as 7 x 8 = 56 from permanent memory. Another
function of the central executive is to coordinate all of these memories.
172
Rehearsal Systems
600— @ Positive
o Negative
oO
eo — Mean
&
oO
£
c
2 500
oO
8
=
®
=
400
il 2 3 4 5 6
Number of items
probe the subject would have to exhaust the list. However, Sternberg proposed
that, even in the case of a positive probe, subjects exhausted the list before
responding. He argued that the scanning was taking place very rapidly and that
checking whether to stop (because the probe had been found) would take
longer than just going on to the end. Subjects certainly are not aware of doing
any of this scanning; it is all happening too fast.
Many studies have involved variations of Sternberg’s paradigm, and many
alternative theories have been advanced for his data (see Glass, 1984, for one
review). The functions are frequently not as linear as reported by Sternberg and
have a decided curvilinear trend such that the rate of increase slows down for high
memory set sizes. Even Sternberg’s data contain a hint of this trend, since the
increase for positive probes is largest in going from memory set sizes of one to two.
Some researchers (e.g., James Anderson, 1973) have argued that 38 msec is
too rapid a comparison process to implement neurally. They have therefore advo-
cated a parallel comparison process in which all the digits in the memory set are
compared simultaneously against the probe. A single neural firing takes about 10
msec (see review in Chapter 1); thus, there can be a sequence of only about four
neurons involved in checking an element for a match, which some people con-
sider too few to perform a comparison. Parallel processing models have been
proposed (e.g., Jones & Anderson, 1987) in which all the items in the memory set
are processed at once, but the time to process the items is a function of how
active they are. These models assume that there is a limit on how much activa-
tion can be allocated to the items. The more elements there are in this memory
set, the less active any one item is, and the slower it will be processed.
173
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
80
e Nonsense syllables
e@ Random forms
60
Geometric shapes @ =
Words
40
® Digits
20
msec/item
time,
comparison
Memory
FIGURE 5.11 Memory comparison rate and memory span covary. (From
Cavanagh, 1972). Source: From J. P. Cavanagh. Relation between the immediate mem-
ory span and the memory search rate. Psychological Review, Volume 79. Copyright ©
1972 by the American Psychological Association. Reprinted by permission.
In terms of Baddeley’s theory, the digits are presumably being held in the
phonological loop. Thus, Sternberg’s results are apparently related to the
rehearsal process. Cavanagh (1972) looked at the relationship between memo-
ry span (the maximum number of elements that can be recalled perfectly) for
various types of materials and the slope in a Sternberg task (e.g., the 38-msec
increase shown in Figure 5.10). Figure 5.11 displays his results. Some of the
material is verbal (nonsense syllables, words, letters, digits) and presumably is
rehearsed in the phonological loop, whereas other information is visual (ran-
dom forms, geometric shapes, colors) and presumably is rehearsed in the visuo-
spatial sketch pad. The abscissa (memory span) in Figure 5.11 reveals a wide
variation in how many items can be held in a span, and the ordinate (memory
comparison time) reveals a wide variation in slope in a Sternberg task. The
straight-line function in Figure 5.12 reveals that the two are closely related such
that shorter spans are associated with larger slopes.
One explanation of the results of Cavanagh goes as follows: As Baddeley
argued (see the discussion relating to Figure 5.6), memory span for these items
varies because they vary in the speed at which they can be rehearsed. Compare
digits (memory span of eight) and words (memory span of five) and assume a
phonological loop of 2.0 sec. The digits would be rehearsed at the rate of 2.0 +
8 = 0.25 sec/digit, and the words would be rehearsed at the rate of 2.0 + 5 = 0.40
sec/word. Suppose that the subject was trying to hold a four-item memory set
in memory. In the case of digits, the subject would be able to rehearse the dig-
its every 0.25 x 4 = 1 sec, but the words would be rehearsed every 0.40 x 4 = 1.6
sec. On average, the digits would have been rehearsed more recently and would
174
Rehearsal Systems
be more active. If time to access these items is a function of how active they are
in the rehearsal system, Cavanagh’s function would be expected, because slow-
er rehearsal would result in less active elements and in shorter memory spans.
100 ;-—
80 |-
ZO
Percent
correct
60
50
ed 0 20 40 60
Retention interval, sec
FIGURE 5.12 The percentage of correct choices (which key to peck) made by
pigeons as a function of delay between the presentation of the information and
opportunity to respond. Source: From D. S. Grant. Learning and Motivation. Volume 7.
Copyright © 1976 by Academic Press. Reprinted by permission.
175
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
keep it active in working memory. There is evidence that pigeons also engage in
rehearsal during this interval. For instance-humans show-more-rapid forgetting
when they are distracted from rehearsal, and pigeons appear to do the same.
Pigeons show better retention when the factors that might distract them from
rehearsing are reduced, such as when the lights are turned off during the reten-
tion interval (e.g., Grant & Roberts, 1976; Roberts & Grant, 1978). With the
lights out, the pigeons can no longer look around the experimental chamber
and process distracting stimuli.
One mechanism that pigeons use to rehearse this information is body
position; they remain oriented toward the critical key during the interval. This is
a particularly clear case of how an organism can use its body as a transient
memory for information. Postural rehearsal is not the only way in which pigeons
can perform this task, however; they can also perform the task when the posi-
tion of the colored key shifts from study to test and they must remember the
color and not the location.
It further appears that pigeons can be “instructed” whether or not to
rehearse the material (Maki & Hegvik, 1980). This phenomenon was demon-
strated in experiments that were identical to match-to-sample experiments
except that on some trials the pigeons did not get the opportunity to peck the
key after the delay. They were given a cue to tell them whether or not they could
peck. That is, after the pigeons had seen the original sample, a signal told them
whether this was a trial in which they could peck or not peck. These cues are
called remember cues and forget cues. For some pigeons, turning the house
light on served as the remember cue, and its absence as the forget cue; for oth-
ers, the cues were reversed. The pigeons remembered which key to peck quite
well after a remember cue. Occasionally, they were given a surprise test after a
forget cue; on such surprise trials, they were observed to show rapid forgetting.
These results are illustrated in Figure 5.13, which shows some data from
Maki and Hegvik (1980). The percentage of recall in a delayed match-to-sample
experiment is plotted for forget cues and remember cues at short delays (2 sec) and
long delays (7 sec). Right after seeing the sample there was relatively little differ-
ence in performance with forget and remember cues. However, without the moti-
vation to rehearse, the ability to remember where to peck dropped off dramatical-
ly over the 7-sec retention interval (forget cue). Apparently, the pigeons’ ability to
remember what to do was maintained by an active rehearsal process over the inter-
val and they engaged in this rehearsal process only if they expected to be tested.
There is also evidence for a role for rehearsal in classical conditioning.
Wagner’s (1981) SOP theory of conditioning (mentioned in Chapter 2) claims
that immediately after a conditioning event the organism is actively rehearsing
the CS-US pairing and that the success of conditioning depends on this
rehearsal successfully taking place. Evidence for this assertion was demonstrat-
ed in an experiment by Wagner, Rudy, and Whitlow (1973) on eyelid condition-
ing in rabbits. They followed a pairing of a CS and a puff of air by a surprising
event (an unexpected pairing of two other stimuli). They predicted that this
would cause the rabbit to cease rehearsing the CS—US pairing and start rehears-
176
Rehearsal Systems
1.0
0.8
8
+ 0.6
e
ae Forget cue
ing the new event. Figure 5.14 displays the degree of conditioning as a function
of the interval between the CS-US pairing and the surprising event. The longer
the interval before the surprising event, the more time the rabbits should have
to rehearse the CS—US pairing. As shown, conditioning did increase as the rab-
bits had longer to rehearse the pairing.
Wagener (1978) also suggested that such rehearsal processes might be part
of the explanation of latent inhibition, which causes difficulty for the
80
70
Median
CRs
of
percent
60
310 80 300
Trial-posttrial episode interval, sec
£77
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
178
The Neural Basis of Working Memory
Response
FIGURE 5.15 An example of a delayed memory task. (a) Food is placed in well on
the right and covered; (b) curtain is drawn for delay period; and (c) curtain is lifted
and monkey can lift cover from one of the wells. Source: From P. S. Goldman-Rakic.
Child Development, Volume 58. Development of cortical circuitry and cognitive func-
tion. Copyright © 1987 by the Society for Research in Child Development. Reprinted
by permission.
Rakic speculated that the prefrontal cortex is parceled into many small regions,
each responsible for remembering a different kind of information.
The prefrontal cortex has strong connections with the hippocampus, a
subcortical structure that has a major role in learning (see Chapters 3 and 8). The
different regions of the cortex have appropriate connections to the other more
179
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
Sey Ses,
7
y- hs
h7
#Lt 4 es
FIGURE 5.16 Lateral view of human and monkey cerebral cortex, with area 46
shaded. Source: From P. S. Goldman-Rakic. Handbook of physiology: the nervous system,
higher functions of the brain. Copyright © 1987 by the American Physiological Society.
Reprinted by permission.
sensory parts of the cortex. For instance, area 46, which serves as spatial work-
ing memory, has connections to the region of the parietal cortex that is respon-
sible for processing spatial information in the world.
serene a ee ASN N
180
The Neural Basis of Working Memory
centrated in regions of the brain with greater blood flow. {MRI measures the dif-
ferent magnetic field caused by the fact that there is greater oxygen-rich blood
(which has greater magnetic properties because of the iron in blood) in regions
of greater activity.
Smith and Jonides (1995) used PET to compare the working memory
required for spatial memory and object memory. Figure 5.17a illustrates the
design they used to test spatial memory. In the memory condition, subjects saw
a set of three dots that they had to remember for 3 seconds. Then a circle
appeared, and they had to press a key once or twice to indicate whether the cir-
cle included the dot. This was contrasted with a control”perception” condition
illustrated in Figure 5.17b. In this condition, subjects saw the dots and circle
together and simply had to indicate whether the circle included the dot. Thus,
they did not have to remember the spatial location of the dots. Smith and
Jonides were interested in the differential activation produced by these two
tasks. They found that the memory condition produced greater activation in the
500 msec
200 msec +
3000 msec +
(b)
@
+ 1500 msec
500 msec +
3000 msec
"Perception" Condition
1500 msec
FIGURE 5.17 Schematic drawings of the events on each trial of the spatial memory
and spatial perception conditions. Source: E. Smith and J. Jonides, The Cognitive
Neurosciences, MIT Press. Copyright © 1995. Reprinted by permission.
181
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
right prefrontal cortex in a region close to area 46 (actually area 47—consult the
human brain in Figure 5.16). Humans differ from other primates in that their
brains are strongly lateralized, with the right hemisphere more involved in spa-
tial and perceptual processing and the left hemisphere involved in more lin-
guistic and symbolic tasks. Thus, it is not surprising that Smith and Jonides
found activation concentration in the right frontal cortex.
Figure 5.18 illustrates the procedure Smith and Jonides used in the object
memory task. In part (a), the experimental memory condition subjects saw two
objects on either side of a cross. After a delay of 3 seconds, they saw one of these
objects and had to press a key once or twice to indicate the object was identical
to one of the original objects. In the “perception” control condition, they were
shown three objects and had to press once or twice to indicate whether the cen-
tral object matched either of the two peripheral objects. In a contrast between the
memory condition and the control condition, Smith and Jonides found that the
memory condition produced more prefrontal activation in the left hemisphere in
area 6 (again consult the human brain in Figure 5.16). This is a region of the pre-
(a)
500 msec
a aa
oa ie
1500 msec
500 msec +
400 msec
"Perception" Condition
1500 msec
FIGURE 5.18 Schematic drawings of the events on each trial of the object memory
and object perception conditions. Source: E. Smith and J. Jonides, The Cognitive
Neurosciences, MIT Press. Copyright © 1995. Reprinted by permission.
182
Final Reflections
frontal cortex in a region that has been associated with linguistic processing
(Petrides, Alivisatos, Evans, & Meyer, 1993). Smith and Jonides suggest that their
subjects may have been verbally labeling the shapes to help remember them.
Final Reflections
This chapter has described some of the systems that hold temporary informa-
tion. It is remarkable how many there are. Sensory systems briefly hold the
information they are receiving so that the organism has a chance to encode it
into a permanent memory. Information can also be maintained in various sen-
sory-like buffers by slave rehearsal processes. The information in these various
transient memories is used to guide our information processing. For this reason
they can be collectively referred to as working memory.
It might seem a bit peculiar to speak of lower organisms, such as pigeons
and rabbits, as having expectations and engaging in active rehearsal processes.
However, it is to the advantage of lower organisms as well as humans to keep cer-
tain information available even when it is no longer present in the environment.
Although nonverbal organisms do not have phonological loops for rehearsal,
which often seem the preferred means of rehearsal for humans, they probably do
have other rehearsal systems for maintaining information in an active state when
it is no longer present in the environment. For instance, pigeons orient to the key
they will have to peck and maintain that orientation over a delay. In this case, they
are using their body posture as a slave system to rehearse the information they
have to remember. Although these animals are rehearsing information, as do
humans, this similarity to human behavior does not imply that they are acting in
the same conscious ways in which humans can act.
In all of these working memory tasks, there is some change in neural acti-
vation that encodes the information. The location of this neural activation can
vary from the peripheral sensory systems to the prefrontal cortex. In all cases,
however, when the activation returns to its base level the memory is lost.
Therefore, we called this chapter a study of transient memory. However, pat-
terns of activation can also produce changes in synaptic efficacy which will
result in relatively permanent memories. The next three chapters are concerned
with these relatively permanent memories.
NARS RORRIOR NL VE LRG LLLLLL LODE LEE LN LOL INTELNSSELLE SLE MERTENS IE LIE EEE BERETA TEST TI LL INTELL NEE ELE
183
Chapter 5 Transient Memories
Further Readings
Crowder (1976) is a classic text surveying memory. Baddeley’s textbook (1997)
on human memory provides a good exposition of his theory of working memo-
ry, and his research monograph (1986) also presents his theory. Journals devot-
ed to human memory include the Journal of Language and Memory (formerly the
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior), Memory and Cognition, and the
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition. The Scientific
American article by Goldman-Rakic (1992) discusses the role of the prefrontal
cortex in the working memory of primates. Roitblat, Bever, and Terrace (1984)
review research on animal memory and cognition.
184
Acquisition of Memories
Stages of Memory
The previous chapter dealt with how information comes in and is maintained
in an active state within working memory. These next three chapters discuss the
subsequent course of information through memory.
ocuses on retention—
ormation is maintained in memory. Chapter 8 examines retrieval—
how information is brought out of memory when needed. This organization fol-
lows Melton’s (1963) classic division of memory into these three processes.
It is not possible to study just one of these processes in isolation. Any
experiment involves initial acquisition of material, followed by some minimal
retention interval, followed by a test that requires retrieval of information. Each
chapter focuses on experiments that reflect mainly on one of the processes. As
the chapters review, however, in some cases the interest is in the interaction
between processes—for example, how the way we encode material at study
determines the best retrieval conditions, how different types of memory records
decay at different rates, how learning one type of material can cause us to for-
get another, how different retrieval conditions display different amounts of for-
getting, and so on.
This chapter focuses on two principal issues. First,
185
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
ere are other ways in which subjects show improved memory with fur-
ther practice after they are able to recall the memory. As Chapter 1 discussed,
nani
enn ona
ings measure, which involved looking at how much
S>binghaus used a sav-
faster the list was relearned
the next day after varying amounts of practice. As Figure 1.2 showed,
0.5 jeg
0.4
2.0
8o 0.3 8
_
3S 32 1.8
a £
[e)
a 0.2 2
rai =
} 1.6
OM
0 1.4
2 4 6 2 4 6
Practice trials Practice trials ;
(a) (b)
FIGURE 6.1 (a) Probability of recall and (b) time to recall paired associates as a
function of amount of practice. (From Anderson, 1981.)
186
Practice and Trace Strength
instance,
Those earlier chapters noted that researchers often
thought of strength of conditioning in terms of the strength
ofsynaptic connec-
tions. For instance, Chapter 2 discussed thelearning
delta rule, a neural embod-
—imentvof*the Rescorla-Wagner theory. The concept of strength is often given
A fair amount of research has studied how memory improves with mas-
sive amounts of practice.
A recognition memory test was used to test their memory for these sentences.
After having memorized the sentences, subjects were required to discriminate
them from sentences that they had not studied but that were made up of the
same words. Examples of such foil sentences are
Subjects had to press one button if a test sentence had been studied and anoth-
er if it had not; the speed with which they were able to make this recognition
judgment was measured. Subjects spent 25 days practicing these judgments and
hence practicing the sentences.
improvement was rapid over the ini-
tial days, but the rate of improvement slowed down with the amount ofpractice.
asserts eee ames cAS CEN SRS YS SSPE RO
EONS EEECO SELDEN SOUL SSSA eB A RE ARSE CRN SHALES HCN EOOI SPIN ESN
187
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
time,
Recognition
sec
used just as well.) The logarithm compresses the differences among larger num-
bers. Some examples of log days for certain of the numbers of days in Figure 6.2
are as follows:
The difference between 25 days and 20 days is much smaller on the logarithmic
scale than is the difference between 5 days and 1 day.
Figure 6.2b shows the data from Figure 6.2a replotted on a log-log scale.
Consider how the data point for day 1-is plotted. The latency on day 1 is 1.61
sec. Log 1 = 0 and log 1.61 = .47. Therefore this point is plotted with coordinates
of 0 and .47. Similarly, all the other points are replotted in Figure 6.2b on the
transformed scale. Since the logarithm of a value less than 1 is negative, many
of the log latencies are negative. The untransformed times and days that corre-
spond to the transformed logarithm values are given in parentheses.
Figure 6.2b Fexeaiasainesr Vincente onsis Se,
»
Practice. That is, the points fall very close to the straight line plotted in the fig-
188
Practice and Trace Strength
ure. If T is used to denote the time in seconds and P the amount of practice in
days, this linear relationship is described by the following function:
log T = .34 — .24 log P
The value .34 is where the function crosses the y-axis (i.e., when log P = 0), and
-.24 is the slope of the line. When this equation is transformed back into the
original scales of time and practice, it becomes a power function,!
a1 .40.P 28
aiiontpmartise . The fact that almost all learning functions are power functions
has been called th ewell osenbloom, 1981).
Newell and Rosenbloom (1981), following up on the work of Lewisene
brou ght this ubiquitous law of learning to the attention os:the field.
‘shown in-Figure 6.2. Since its identification by Newell and Rosenbloom, the
power law has attracted a great deal of attention in psychology, and researchers
have tried to understand why learning should take the same form in all experi-
ments (e.g., Anderson, 1982; Lewis, 1978; Logan, 1988; MacKay, 1982; Shrager,
Hogg, & Huberman, 1988).
Figures 6.2 and 6.3 look at the decrease in time with practice. Often error
rates also improve according to power functions. Figure 6.4 replots the data
from Figure 6.1 in terms of log errors against log trials of practice. The approxi-
mately linear relationship implies that error rates decrease as a power function
of time. Not all dependent measures show this power function relationship, but
many, like performance time and error rate, do. Such power functions are dis-
tinguished by the property of negative acceleration; that is, each unit of prac-
189
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
(log
Time,
scale)
sec
0:10
of
Probability
scale)
(log
error
190
Practice and Trace Strength
e 2 hr of food deprivation
Log sec = 2.22 — 0.22 log trials
= 22 hr of food deprivation
Log sec = 1.96 — 0.26 log trials
8.0
C)oO
2 6.0
2g
°°
D
191 .
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
100
90
» 80
(ni
Z RID
°
; ©
o 60
S
2 50 i
FIGURE 6.6 Acquisition § 40
of an avoidance response. 5
Source: From W. J. Brogden. ae
Journal of Comparative and 20
Physiological — Psychology,
Volume 42. Copyright © i”
1949 by the American 0
Psychological Association. Thetis 2 3 a4 Ota Gas! 1S Sun BLO! ctl
Reprinted by permission. 11ths to criterion of acquisition
192
Practice and Trace Strength
100 100
80 80
© 60 & 60
8 8
& 40 a 40
20 20
) 0
25 50975 1007 125 150 25 SON 75) LOO 25) 150)
Trials Trials
100 100
80 80
© 60 & 60
S 8
& 40 © 40
20 20
(6) 0
50 100 150 200 SOS 1000 150\.6200)5 250
Trials Trials
quency electrical current, the sensitivity of cells along that pathway to further stim-
ulation is increased. Barnes (1979) studied this phenomenon in rats, measuring the
percentage of increase in excitatory postsynaptic potential (EPSP) over its initial
value.* She stimulated the hippocampus of the rats each day for 11 successive days
and measured the growth in LIP in terms of the percentage of increase. Figure 6.8a
displays the results, plotting percent of change against day of practice. There
appears to be a diminishing increase with the amount of practice. To determine
whether there is a power function, Figure 6.8b plots log percentage of change
against log practice. The relationship appears approximately linear; thus, it appears
that neural activation changes with practice just as do behavioral measures.
? As discussed in Chapter 1, as the dendrite and cell body of a neuron become more
excited, the difference in electric potential between the outside and inside of the cell
decreases. EPSP refers to the size of this change.
193
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
3.8
50)j-
3.6
WwWro)
change
Percent Log oS fo)
change
percent
20 ee
2.8
2 4 6 8 10 0
Days of practice Log days of practice
(b)
(a)
FIGURE 6.8 Growth in LTP as a function of number of days of practice: (a) in nor-
mal scale; (b) in log-log scale. (From Barnes, 1979.)
Note that the activation measure in Figure 6.8a increases more and more
slowly, whereas the performance measures, such as errors (Figure 6.1a) and time
(Figure 6.1b), decrease more and more slowly. These performance measures are
assumed to be inverse reflections of the growth in strength that is happening
internally. As the strength of the record increases (reflected in Figure 6.8), the
performance measures get better (which means shorter times and fewer errors).
It has been suggested (Anderson & Schooler, 1991) that memory (both its
behavioral and its neural expressions) displays properties such as the power law
of learning because these properties reflect an optimal response to the environ-
ment. A very general characterization of the learning functions reviewed in this
chapter is that the more something is encountered, the more available it is in the
future. A conjecture about the environment is that the more an organism has
needed to remember something, the more likely it is that it will need to remem-
ber that thing again. Thus, memory can be viewed as making more available
information that is more likely to be needed.
This viewpoint raises the question of whether the power function dis-
played in the learning behavior of subjects mirrors a similar power function in
the environment. Anderson and Schooler (1991) studied the patterns by which
information tends to repeat in a number of different environments, including
parental speech to children, electronic mail messages, and newspaper head-
lines. In the case of parental speech to children, the frequency of various words
in parental utterances was examined. For example, if the word ball occurred 8
times in the last 100 utterances, what is the probability that it will occur on the
101st utterance? Figure 6.9 shows the relationship between the log frequency
194
Practice and Trace Strength
35
Log probability = e
-4.96 + 1.05 log frequency
scale)
(log
probability
Future
FIGURE 6.9 Relationship between log
frequency with which a word has
occurred in the last 100 utterances and
log probability of it occurring in the
101st utterance. (From Anderson & 1 5 20 50
Schooler, 1991.) Past frequency (log scale)
that a word has appeared in the last 100 utterances and the log probability that
it will appear in the 101st utterance. The linear relationship is striking, implying
a power function. The functional form of memory seems to mirror the function-
al form in the environment. Similar patterns were found in mail messages and
newspaper articles. The more often one has had to retrieve the meaning of a
word, the more likely one will have to do so again.
In summary, three types of dependent measures change as power func-
tions of practice: behavioral measures, such as error rate and latency; percent-
age of change in LIP; and probability of repetition in the environment. One pro-
posal (Anderson, 1993) is that neural activation, which controls behavior,
reflects the probability of an item occurring in the environment; thus, the neur-
al processes are designed to adapt behavior to the statistical properties of the
environment.
195
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
1!
1.0
0.85
0.6
Performance
0.2
The natural hypothesis that formerly dominated psychology was that per-
formance was an exponential function of practice. If a time were an exponen-
functionof practice (P), it would take the form of a fraction raised to the
tial
amount of practice. For instance, one possible exponential function is:
T=10x.8?
(where the 10 and the .8 are just arbitrary choices chosen for illustration). This
exponential hypothesis was natural because it implied that with each trial, per-
formance improved by a constant fraction. In the example given, each trial takes
80 percent, or .8, of the time of the previous trial. If the previous trial took 10 sec,
a .8 reduction would yield 8 sec, for a 2-sec gain for the current trial. When the
time is 1 sec, a .8 reduction results in a .2-sec gain. Thus, the function was neg-
atively accelerated (showed less and less decrease) because the base time
(which was being reduced by .8 each trial) was going down.?
Figure 6.10 compares an exponential function with a power function. Both
functions are negatively accelerated, but the power function is much more so.
Only after collection and analysis of a great deal of data was it established that
learning functions are better described by power functions than by exponential
functions (Newell & Rosenbloom, 1981). The rate of improvement with practice
turns out to be even slower than formerly believed.
Psychologists find it exciting to be able to find simple functions, like the
power function, that fit such a wide range of data. It is similar to discovering
laws of the sort that physicists find (and psychologists have always had physics
envy). However, the power function that describes the learning curve does not
have the same status as the equations in physics books. The data from learning
196
Elaborateness of Processing
Elaborateness of Processing
The preceding analysis implied that items accrue strength at a rate that depends
only on how much the item has been studied. However, a great deal of evidence
also indicates that how an item is studied can have an enormous impact on how
much the subject remembers of the item. In some cases people can process
items many times without much benefit. Chapter 5 discussed Neisser’s descrip-
tion of Professor Sanford, who remembered little from thousands of repetitions
of his prayers.
4 Heathcote and Mewhort (1995, 1998), for instance, have argued that the learning
function is really an exponential with an asymptote I: 1 + B f? where f is a fraction less
than 1. However, a simple power function, AP~’ gives a good approximation to such
a function.
5 The exponent b is positive because strength is assumed to increase, producing
decreases in measures of performance difficulty, such as time and errors.
197
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
Bekerian and Baddeley (1980) reported a study of the efforts BBC radio
made to get its listeners to learn the new wavelength at which it was going to
broadcast. The BBC saturated the airwaves with announcements of the new
wavelength. Bekerian and Baddeley tested subjects who had been exposed to
the information for over 25 times a day for many weeks. Less than a quarter of
the people they surveyed had learned the new wavelength. Sheer exposure to
material is not enough to guarantee learning. Chapter 5 also discussed Craik
and Lockhart’s (1972) depth-of-processing theory, which held that memory
improves only if information is processed at a deep level. This chapter describes
a variant of the depth-of-processing proposal, which emphasizes that what is
important is how elaborately we process the to-be-remembered information.
For instance, if we
be-remembered word, we recall less than
if we think about what words ar . The latter activity forces us to get at
the . Although the depth of processing seems to have an
effect, several studies have also shown that superior memory is achieved by active-
ly processing material in a way that does not involve its meaning.
° There was a flurry of debate about whether the original Slamecka and Graf result
was due to the fact that it involved a within-list design and subjects gave differential
practice to the generate items. Slamecka and Katsaiti (1987) claimed it was an artifact,
but others (e.g., Begg, Snider, Foley, & Goddard, 1989; Burns, 1992; Hirshman & Bjork,
1988; McDaniel, Waddill, & Einstein, 1988) have found effects in between-list designs.
198
Elaborateness of Processing
1.0
Generate
Read
0.8
s
a 0.6
2
6
2
= 0.4
S
2
oO
~ 0.2
FIGURE 6.11 Probability of recognition as a
function of type of elaboration and whether it
was generated or read. (From Slamecka & Graf, 0.0
1978, experiment 2.) Synonym Rhyme
generate
for themselves.
@) Burns (1992) and Hirshman and Bjork (1988) have provided an explanation
of the advantage of generative processing in experiments in which subjects must
learn paired associates, such as the Slamecka and Graf experiment. According to
these authors,
or instance, generating cave as a rhyme of save
guarantees that subjects encode that both stimulus and response in the save—cave
pair are in fact rhymes, whereas they might not attend to this common feature if
they just read the pair of words. If the rhyme relationship is encoded at study, the
G) subject can use it to retrieve the response at recall.
at gives the added advantage when the subject has to generate the
verb? The subject is likely to generate a verb that is easy for that subject to recall
and from which it is easy for that subject to recall bike. When subjects can choose
their own verbs, they generate items that make for particularly good retrieval
199
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
get memory and do not increase the strength ofaparticular memory record. The
experiment looked at subjects’ ability to learn some little-known information
about some famous people. In one condition subjects studied just a single fact:
In another condition subjects learned two additional facts that were causally
related to the target fact:
200
Elaborateness of Processing
-orating sentences were presented at study. However, when subjects were tested
for their ability to recognize the target sentences, there was no latency advantage.
for the elaborated sentences. If anything, they were slower, Earlier, this chapter
noted th The target sentences were
not any stronger when studied with elaborations; however, these elaborations
offered subjects another way to retrieve the target sentence if they were unable
to recall the sentences directly.
BSCR HIER a
201
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
TABLE 6.2 Percent Recall as a Function of Orienting Task and Intention to Learn
Orienting Task
Incidental - 68 39
Intentional 69 43
subjects to sort a set of words on cards (one word per card) into categories. One
group of subjects was told that they would be tested later for their memory of
the words; a second group was not so warned.
The failure of motivation to affect learning can be seen from the viewpoint that
people cannot learn what is important to them or from the viewpoint that they
cannot avoid learning things that are unimportant. The latter interpretation
seems more appropriate. People are best viewed as storing in memory every-
thing they attend to, whether or not they want to remember it. To understand
why there are memory failures, the next two chapters examine the processes of
forgetting and retrieval.
ete penceneonemesicemsas aes
202
The Structure of Memory
ing the SQ3R method (Robinson, 1961) and the PQ4R method (Thomas &
Robinson, 1972). PQ4R stands for preview, question, read, reflect, recite, and
review. The rea osed to preview the text to be read (e.g., a chapter of a
book) and identify the main’sections, make up questions relevant to each section,
and read the section trying to answer the questions and reflect on the text. After
each section, the reader is supposed to recite the material from that section. At the
end of the text, the reader should review the main points of the text. This method
and methods like it require the reader to attack a text aggressively, making up
questions about it and thinking about its implications. This is just the sort of elab-
orative and generative processing that has proved effective in the laboratory.
One experimental study (Frase, 1975) on the effectiveness of such pro-
cessing techniques for study involved a collaborative learning technique. The
text was divided into sections, and two people read it together. For each section,
one person read with a mind to making up questions about that section, and the
other read and then had to answer those questions. Then roles were switched
for each section. A control group of subjects who just read the material without
doing anything special got 50 percent correct on the posttest. For the experi-
mental subjects, the posttest questions could be divided roughly in half accord-
ing to whether they were anticipated by the subjects’ questions. The experimen-
tal subjects also got 50 percent correct of the unanticipated posttest questions
but 69 percent correct of the anticipated posttest questions.
Chapter 11 further reviews research establishing the importance of such
elaborative study skills. That chapter argues that this may be the most important
educational application of research on human memory.
203
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
Second, there are the various areas of prefrontal cortex that serve as work-
ing memory to hold information over delays, as discussed in Chapter 5.
However, it is generally believed that neither the hippocampus nor these pre-
frontal areas are where memories are actually stored. The OC peem
Se
2 AN QMA®
FIGURE 6.12 Examples of the shape paired associates used in the experiment of
Sakai and Miyashita (1991). Source: [Redrawn from “Neural Organization for the
Long-Term Memory of Paired Associates” by Sakai, K. & Miyashita, Y., Nature,
354,
pages 152-155, (1991). Reproduced with permission from Nature, 1991, Macmillan
Magazines Limited. ]
204
The Structure of Memory
Memory records
FIGURE 6.13 Memory records in permanent memory and their connections to var-
ious cues.
205
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
o prompt recall for that memory. When cues are attended to, either because
they are in the environment or because the person is thinking about them, they
activate their associated records in permanent memory. A person has access to
these memory records to the degree to which they are active. The state of being
active
AC or available
C QO] Ta IDLE is a transient property of memory records: Therefore, the cur-
rently active information in permanent memory is, in effect, another transient
memory (the topic of Chapter 5) and an important part of the person’s overall
working memory. By focusing on different information in the environment or by
rehearsing different information, a person can make different parts of perma-
nent memory active. Thus, on hearing the word mother, information about a per-
son’s mother becomes active; similarly, on viewing a picture of the Eiffel Tower,
information about Paris and France becomes active. In these examples mother
and the Eiffel Tower are the cues, and the retrieved memories are the records.
A number of different theories in cognitive psychology embody this basic
analysis of memory as records and cues, although they use different language to
describe it. The language used in this chapter is similar to that of my ACT theory
(Anderson, 1983a, 1993). Another well-known theory, SAM (Gillund & Shiffrin,
1984; Raaijmakers & Shiffrin, 1981), speaks of images (memory records) becom-
ing more or less familiar (active) as a function of the cues in the context.
Connectionist theories, reviewed in Chapter 2, are theories of neural information
processing and have similar assumptions, except that the cues and records are
referred to as neural units. Thus, the system in Figure 6.13 reflects an emerging
consensus in the field, although there is not yet consensus on the language that
describes it. Much of the evidence for this system is presented in subsequent
chapters. The following section reviews some of the data indicating how the pre-
sentation of appropriate cues can facilitate access to memory records.
Ce ee
Priming
only some memory records. For instance, the word cow is associated to memo-
ty records concerning cow-like things, such as giving milk. A fair amount of
work has been done documenting the effects of such associations in what is
called a lexical decision task. These are experiments in which subjects are given
strings ofletters, such aS milk or milc, and have to decide which are words
and
which are not. The experiments manipulate whether subjects also see an asso-
ciate of a target word, for example, cow. In the experimental condition, subjects
206
The Structure of Memory
might first see cow and then have to judge whether milk is a word, whereas in
the control condition they might first see cot and then milk. Using the analysis
of record activation just given, we might expect the word cow to activate the rep-
resentation of the memory record that encodes the spelling of milk (since cow is
associated to milk), and so the lexical decision could be made faster in that case.
There have been numerous experiments showing just this (e.g., Meyer &
Schvaneveldt, 1971; Neely, 1977). In one cxperiment(Balatarand pieh11986)
One of his subjects was stuck on this particular problem and could not solve it
for days. Kaplan arranged to have the subject receive what appeared to be a mis-
taken phone call during which the caller asked if she had left her umbrella in
the subject’s office. Shortly after that, the subject reported the solution to this
problem—umbrella—even though he was unaware that als ils phone ae was
james to his eeitie the answer. Over
Chunking
_
Research indicates that relatively little information can be stored in any one
memory record, and therefore many records have to be used to store large
amounts of information. People tend to store about three elements in any
record. Much of the research demonstrating limited record size has involved
subjects trying to remember a series of letters, for example, DRQNSLWCF.
Subjects break oe series into a nisms of pale amencce of— Miller secs
7 The 48-msec difference might seem small, but it reflects about a 10-percent differ-
ence, and these experiments achieve very accurate measurements.
207
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
sigs wena aah ACRE ag AHe presented his subjects with random
strings of letters but encouraged them to use a particular chunk structure by plac-
ing spaces between the letters. So, he might have presented his subjects with
DY JHOQ GW
&
For instance, Qcsparen Hardy, and Hirtle (1989) looked at memory for the 28
objects illustrated in Figure 6.14. Subjects saw these objects laid out in a 20 x 22 ft
area. By looking at their patterns of recall, McNamara et al. found evidence that
subjects organized these objects into groups. Specifically, subjects tended to recall
certain groups of objects always together. Figure 6.14 illustrates the groups used
by one subject. These objects can be chunked in many different ways, and differ-
ent subjects came up with different organizations. Subjects gave evidence by other
behavioral measures that el from within a chunk were organized together
in memory. For instance M@leNamaig sal.(1985)used a priming paradigm such
208
The Structure of Memory
scissors
ring
e button £
rubber band
e
eraser
e
envelope
e
flashlight
e
cufflink
thimble
e
light bulb
e
e cigarettes
FIGURE 6.14 A layout used in the experiment by McNamara et al. (1989). The cir-
cles indicate hierarchical organization imposed by one subject on this array. Circles
enclose objects in the same chunk or enclose chunks in the same higher order units.
Source: From T. P. McNamara, J. K. Hardy, and S. C. Hirtle. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, Volume 15. Copyright © 1989 by the
American Psychological Association. Reprinted by permission.
as the paradigms discussed in the previous subsection. Subjects saw the name of
one object (prime) from the array, followed 150 msec later by the name of anoth-
er object (target). Subjects had to judge whether the second object was from the
array. They compared target objects that either were or were not from the same
chunk as the prime. In both cases, the targets were the same physical distance
from the primes .
Agetne
209
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
25/3 IEEE TEP EN TNL ELE SLL SEERA LOLS OL EULSERED LEELA LEE LE LLLILIES DL LLLLELVERL LLL
Representation of Knowledge
As we have noted, different types of information appear to be stored in differ-
ent cortical areas. It has been pror hat these di : vforr
stinctive forms of encoding referred to as (remor Tes One popular
theory of memory is thé dual- theory
code (Bower, 1972; Paivio, 1971), which»
red in_picturelike
Cil memory records. An experiment by Santa (1977) provides a
nice illustration of the different properties of these two memory codes.
Subjects studied an array of three geometric figures. Then the subjects had
to judge whether a test array contained the same elements as the original stim-
ulus. Some of the possible test arrays are illustrated in Figure 6.15a. In many of
Test
arrays
Square
aa Ve
The Structure of Memory
the test arrays, the same elements were arranged in a different order from that
of the study array. Subjects were to give affirmative responses to the array even
though the order was different. Santa was interested in how Eas it took sub-
The stimuli in Figure 6.15b offer a striking contrast. These are the same
stimuli as in Figure 6.15a except that the subjects studied words instead of geo-
metric figures. Santa reasoned that subjects would encode these stimuli verbal-
ly rather than visually. In this case, subjects might actually do better when test-
ed with the linear array because this encodes the items in the order in which
they would occur if read left to right and top down, which is the standard read-
ing order. As Figure 6.16 shows, Santa.was zs ht.(hihiensianedackinalssnen gem
Teesis pat
a autrade ae eta en, ie asneer ee Mer
verbal ees
SSE RNASE RES EN AEONLR NERO
BNI ETS LE ELLE SEES LEE LEED LEE SLL LMLESAER SIMA
211
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
It is not the case, however, that people have photographic memories and
can remember whatever they see Goldstein and Chance 0 970) studied memo-
ry for two types of visual materia faces and snowflakes)Figure 6.17 shows
examples of the snowflakes. The individual snowflakes are quite distinct and
seem at least as discriminable perceptually as individual faces. Subjects studied
either 14 faces or 14 snowflakes and for their recognition 48 hr later.
, (Subjects were able to recognizd74 percent of the facesYbut sriradimereenreah
‘Qe snoMATERES Thusgood memory for pictorial material reflects not only how
/\) distinctive the stimuli are but also how well the subject can encode the materi-
\ al. Subjects are capable of attributing more significance to the features that sep-
'arate faces than those —— a
Memory for pictorial information seems to be determined by the ability of
subjects to place a meaningful interpretation on the picture. An amusing
demonstration of this fact was performed by Bo Karlin, and Dueck (1975).
They had_subjects study what are called droodles, such as those illustrated in
Figure 6.18. One group of subjects saw both just the droodles, without tae
ex lanatory labels. Another jects saw the droodles and the explana-
tory labels, Subjects displayed better recognition memory for the pictures when
they wereaccompanied
by the labels, presumably because the labels enabled
the subjects to elaborate. the pictures.
.4
“FIGURE 6.18 Droodles: A midget
playing a trombone in a telephone
booth. Panel b—An early bird who
caught a very strong worm. Source:
From G. H. Bower, M. B. Karlin, and
A. Dueck. Memory & Cognition, -—
Volume 3, pp. 216-220. Copyright ©
1975. Reprinted by permission of Hones)
Psychonomic Society, Inc. (a) (b)
212
The Structure of Memory
*K FIGURE 6.19 Pictures used by Mandler and Ritchey (1977). Source: From J. M.
Mandler and N. S. Johnson. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and
Memory, Volume 2. Copyright © 1976 by the American Psychological Association.
Reprinted by permission.
S UT eittatl p C C 5 UL C me
U :&
identifywhich picture the had originally sta Ted TE e distractors sould Beeither
token_distractors or type distractors. A token d orthanged some semanti-
ea (relevant detail for example, in Figure 6 heteacher’s dress is changed.
shanged a detail that might bejaan an interpretation of
ne picture; in Figure 6.19, the material on the board is changed (trom a geog-
raphy lesson to perhaps an art lesson). Subjects falsely recognized 40 percent of
LUA ALLL RATE ANRC AEN SHEE REE ELTA LOL IER MIELE LEE NEILL EDEL LLL LD ELE LENE
Effects of Imagery
As a reflection of our high level of memory for visual material, we can improve
visual
memory for verbal material by constru images of the material to be
cting
memorized. In one experiment, Bower (1972) had subjects try to commit to
As indicated in this example, the visual images can be bizarre (a dog riding
a bicycle) or more common (a dog chasing a child on a bicycle). Another dimen-
sion of difference is that images can involve objects interacting (as is true of both
the previous examples) or objects not interacting (e.g., a dog standing beside a
bicycle). Wollen, Weber, and Lowry (1972) studied the relative contribution of
bizarreness and interactive quality to memory. They gave their subjects pictures
to help them learn paired associates, such as piano-cigar. Figure 6.20 illustrates
the four kinds of pictures they used to realize the four possible combinations of
bizarreness and interaction. Table 6.3 shows the levels of recall in the four condi-
tions. There is a large effect of interaction but not of bizarreness; the effect of
interaction is probably related to the effects of elaboration reviewed earlier. The
interactive images promoted elaborative encoding that helped later recall.
Studies of whether the bizarreness of the imagery improves memory have
had varied results. McDaniel and Einstein (1986) and Hirshman, Whelley, and
Palu (1989) found cases in which subjects displayed better memory for bizarre
images. McDaniel and Einstein related this finding to whether a within-subject
or between-subject design was used. The original Wollen et al. study used a
between-subject design, in which some subjects studied all bizarre images and
other subjects studied all nonbizarre images. In this kind of design, there is usu-
ally not an effect of bizarreness. In a within-subject design, half the items the
subjects study involve bizarre images and half do not. In these designs bizarre
images usually have advantages. MeDaniel/and Einstein argued thatinawith:
Interactionjnluiged
esthicly cones
W wenersontehieeswivtehrte
BE are more ape pes mak are aad
SESS ESSIEN TA IONS SAE SE Rte re
ee sssseenusreNty
214
The Structure of Memory
FIGURE 6.20 Examples of pictures used to associate piano and cigar in the Wollen
et al. (1972) study of image bizarreness. Source: From K. A. Wollen, A. Weber, and D.
H. Lowry. Cognitive Psychology, Volume 3. ae i:
1972
ae Academic Press. ol
Reprinted by permission. Bikes! ‘
mone) ie
Meaningful a eae
Qo p ovdS
As reviewed earlier, when subjects remember a os eytend to> Femiember
See. rerpretanon of the picture-Mlila o-evidence- n pe
TABLE 6.3 Mean Percentage of Recall in Wollen, Weber, and Lowry (1972)
Bizarre Nonbizarre
Interacting
Noninteracting
215
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
(Anderson, 1974b) illustrates this abstract memory for sentences. Subjects were
asked to remember sentences such as:
This sentence is in the active voice. Other sentences were in the passive voice,
for example:
Later, subjects were asked to recognize which sentences they had heard. If they
had studied the first sentence in the example, they were tested with any of the
following sentences:
Subjects had no difficulty in rejecting sentences such as 3 and 4 that had a dif-
Ae ae nee
ferent meaning.
ad ce
the latter explanation. Forgetting is discussed more thoroughly in the next chap-
ter, but this section reviews two studies showing that different types of materi-
al have different rates of forgetting.
*
216
The Structure of Memory
FIGURE 6.21 Pictures displayed in one orientation and the reverse. Source: From M.
A. Gernsbacher. Cognitive Psychology, Vol. 17. Copyright © 1985. Reproduced by per-
mission of Academic Press.
centat
a2-mindela:Thus,subjectsmaintained nearlyperfectmemory.Subjects
ability to discriminate between the following pair of sentences was also tested:
‘ 1. The missionary shot the painter.
é 2. The painter was shot by the missionary. x
217
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
AEE NSN RAYS LOLA ENROI ELEN AN MERE
meme
for making this distinction between the sentence and the proposition is the evi-
dence that subjects tend to remember thegeneral meaning_of even such simple
sentences rat the exact wording of the sentences.
Kintsch (1974) advanced a proposal for how to represent the propositions
that convey the meaning of these sentences. According to Kintsch, the proposi-
tions underlying sentences 2 through 4 are represented by the following list
structures:
218
The Structure of Memory
Critical in the Kintsch representation is the issue of what the relations are and
what the arguments are. The list notation in 2a through 4a is only a convenient
way of denoting that. Thepropositional lists in2athrough 4acan beregarded.
One line of evidence = i ro oe analysis comes from looking at
patterns of recall for sentences. Gaal IRS! 97) had subjects study
sentences such as:
Subjects who could recall the noun lawyer were more likely also to recall the
verb hated, which appeared in the same proposition, than the verb liked, whic
219
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
set of sen-
interesting demonstration of this fact. They had subjects study a
tences, including:
The ants ate the sweet jelly which was on the table.
The rock rolled down the mountain and crushed the tiny hut.
The ants in the kitchen ate the jelly.
The rock rolled down the mountain and crushed the hut beside the
woods.
The ants in the kitchen ate the jelly which was on the table.
The tiny hut was beside the woods.
The jelly was sweet.
These sentences are all composed fronytwo sets of four propositions) One set of
four propositions can be represented as follows:
Bransford and Franks then presented subjects with various sentences and asked
them to judge whether that exact sentence had been studied. The following
illustrates the three types of sentences they used:
The first sentence has been studied, whereas the other two had not. The second
sentence, however, was composed of the same propositions that the subject had
studied. Subjects showed almostnoabilityto discriminate theNEW sentences)
from the OLD. These sentences seemed equally familiar, and the subjects sim-
ply could not remember which sentences they had studied. eee
: hicl Lf iene
220
Memory Representation in Other Species
When the subjects heard the sentences, they abstracted the propositions
and remembered them. They did not keep track of what propositions they had
seen in what sentences. Indeed
The ants in the kitchen ate the sweet jelly that was on the table.
Memory Representation
in Other Species
It is interesting to ask whether other species think about the world in the same
way that we do. A way to formulate this question more specifically is to ask
whether their memory representations are similar to that of humans. Therevis
evidence that other animals encode information into serial and spatial patterns _
(e.g., Roberts, 1984; Terrace, 1984). Pigeons are capable of learning specific
sequences of pecks just as humans can remember sequences of letters (Terrace,
1984), and, as reviewed in Chapter 3, rats can learn the location of objects in
space as well as humans can (Roberts, 1984). In addition, evidence
there is that »
qiinalsaneeapeblsnehis
enlidyingdhom caning etpicnessitependentinpitiog
exact physical details. For instance, Chapter 3 reviewed the evidence that pigeons
prerearaeae’
can instances of natural categories, such as“ tree.” In this section, we will
discuss memory representations in two common laboratory species—one far
from us phylogenetically (pigeons) and the other close (other primates).
221
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
to chunk long lists into sublists, aswe noted earlier for humans. Monkeys’also
show a capacity for transitive inference that pigeons do not. Transitive inference
222.
Final Reflections
Final Reflections
This chapter has addressed the topic of acquisition—that is, how information is
stored in memory. One view of memory is that everything we attend to is orga-
nized in terms of small, chunk-like records and stored away in memory. It does
223
CHAPTER 6 Acquisition of Memories
FIGURE 6.22 The tests are for cutting, wetting, and marking, respectively. The
missing item is the instrument. In the lower right is the chimpanzee Elizabeth enthu-
siastically cutting an apple.
224
Further Readings
not matter what the memory is about or whether we want to remember it at all;
we are always storing away the things we attend to. The animal learning litera-
ture often creates a picture of rather little learned, but this is because it is so dif-
ficult to get nonhumans to display what they have learned. With human sub-
jects, there is evidence of relatively rapid rates of learning.
Further Readings
In addition to the sources mentioned in the previous chapter, several works pre-
sent the topics of this chapter in greater detail. The power law of learning is
examined by Anderson and Schooler (1991) and Newell and Rosenbloom
(1981). The book edited by Cermak and Craik (1978) presents a number of dis-
cussions on depth and elaborativeness of encoding. My cognitive psychology
text (Anderson, 2000) discusses the issue of knowledge representation at greater
length. Kintsch (1998) is a good source of ideas about representation and lin-
-guistic processing. Roitblatt (1987) presents extensive discussion of knowledge
‘representation in nonhuman animals. Finally, Premack and Premack (1983)
offer an interesting description of the cognitive capabilities of chimpanzees.
225
Retention ofMemories
Overview
I don’t know how many times I have had the same conversation with people on
planes, on ski slopes, at baseball games, and wherever strangers meet. The con-
versation follows the same script with slight variations:
This dialogue reflects the fact that many people’s most salient experience of their
memories is that they are aware of having known many things that they can no
longer remember. This chapter is concerned with what underlies forgetting.
Along the way the chapter notes two possibilities that might surprise people:
However, there is some territory to cover before expanding on these two curiosi-
ties.
There are three basic hypotheses about what causes forgetting. T
- bloc - 1
. eR . est
pri
- a ae ee :
cue-hy pothesis asserts that@
226
The Retention Function
overall forgetting process. This chapter examines the first two hypotheses in
some detail, postponing full discussion of the third hypothesis until Sees 8.
CUMS RE Nena REN SS MPN SSW seis anit
LLL
All retention functions show this same basic form. Initially, forgetting is
etention functions dif-
fer with respect to the scales on which they display these basic phenomena.
Other measures, in addition to Ebbinghaus’s savings measure, include proba-
bility of recall or time to recall memories that can be recalled. These measures
60
4.2
Log P = 3.862 - 0.126 log H
4.0
50
2 E§
2)
ny oo 3.8
8n ~
z 40 5 3.6
3) ®
oD Qa
a 00
5 3.4
30
ae
20 3.0
0 200 400 600 800 -2 0 p> 4 6 8
Delay, hr Log delay, hr
(a) (b)
FIGURE 7.1 Ebbinghaus’s classic retention data (a) showing percentage of savings
as a function of retention interval; (b) with both scales log transformed to reveal a
power relationship.
227
CHAPTER 7 Retention.of Memories
eared in the preceding chapter, taking the logarithm of both the perfor-
mance measure and the practice measure reveals a regularity with respect to the
learning function. Figure 7.1b shows the regularity that is revealed by taking log-
arithms of the performance scale Be the time scale for retention functions.
Again, the a(inear tel 1
Ebbinghaus’s data, this functionis
Log savings = 3.86 — .126 Log delay
where 3.86 is the sabe ofthe line inMaes. 7.1b and — .126 is the slope. As »
As noted in Chapter 6, a
as noted, power functions are not the only negative-
lyaccelerated functions that could be fitted to the data. The more obvious neg-
atively accelerated functions are exponential functions, which have been partic-
ularly popular for theories of forgetting because they describe many decay
processes in nature, including radioactive decay. Only recently Rubi &
ee 1996; Wixted & Ebbesen, aide as it b
The Retention Function
1.30
L [ Log T = 0.64 + .08 log$
3,50 Lao
oO
o i B
d o 1.10
a £
£ 3.00;- e
fe}
a
iS = 1.00
= - 30
2 8
® bp 0.90
9 5) ES
0.80
229.
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
6.0 .
Log N = 2.03 - 0.82 log D
5.0
Pray
4.0 Boag!
3 8
ral o
25 3.0 2
5
a =]
Ee ic
=] y felt)
FDO £0
ie
-l
one 10 20 30 0 1 2 3 4
Days Log days
(a) (b)
FIGURE 7.3 (a) Krueger’s (1929) data showing number of paired associates recalled
as a function of retention interval; (b) log transformation of the data.
age of recognition as a function of number of years since the show last aired.
Recognition dropped more rapidly initially and then slowed down. Figure 7.4b
regraphs this data on log-log coordinates, revealing a linear relationship indica-
tive of a power function in the original scale.
80 4.4
Log P = 4.36 - 0.13 log Y
4.3
70 a2)
@
w @o
a
5 4.2
oO
s)
we =
wo
S cu a
60 S
4.0
50 3.9
5 10 15 0.0 1.0 2.0 3.0
Years since TV show Log years
(a)
(b)
FIGURE 7.4 (a) Probability of recognizing a TV show as a function of time since
cancellation; (b) the same data on a log-log scale. (From Squire, 1989.)
230
The Retention Function
a0
iA
g
oO
a 3 study trials
15) 0.8
e
1.0 ri aI ‘teh ae eal lalla om
0.0 2.0 4.0 6.0 8.0 10.0 0.0 1.0 2.0 Sh) 4.0
Log min Log sec
(a) (b)
FIGURE 7.5 (a) Data from Slamecka and McElree (1983) showing the effect of an
extra trial practice in the retention function. (b) Data from Wixted and Ebbesen (1991)
showing the effect of 1 versus 5 sec of study in the retention function.
7 al
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
100 ;—
90 |
So 80
3
eo 70
8 14-sec presentation
ae 60 - 8-sec presentation
4-sec presentation
50 ie 1-sec presentation
40 a
0 20 40 60
Retention interval, sec
material. The figures plot the data in log—log form. Increased practice resulted in
increased retention, but performance fell off linearly in the log-log scale for all
degrees of practice. In both cases the underlying functions are not only approx-
Tete near buttheyare approximately parallel, indicating that materials at
different degrees of learning were being forgotten at the same rate.
Similar retention curves are found in studies of animal memory. Chapter
5 described the matching-to-sample paradigm used to study pigeon memory
(see Figure 5.16). Pigeons are shown a color and must remember it for some
period of time so that they can later peck a key of that color.
Zon
The Retention Function
13 past occurrences
8 past occurrences
3 past occurrences
233
CHAPTER 7 Retention.of Memories
4.5
e 4 stimulations
Log change = 4.20 — 0.10 log min
= iS)
BaD)
baseline
above
percent
Log
(1979), who examined how LTP in the hippocampus decreased with time. Recall
that the LIP procedure involves administering a high-frequency stimulation to
a neural path. Afterward this path shows increased response to further stimula-
tion. As discussed with respect to Figure 6.9, LTP is frequently measured in
terms of how much more responsive the neural pathway is to stimulation over
its baseline responsiveness.
Barnes investigated the decrease in LIP for periods from 2 min up to 14
days, and she also looked at retention after one or four high-frequency stimula-
tions. As Figure 6.9 showed, LTP increases with frequency of stimulation. Figure
7.8 plots log percentage above baseline against log delay. Individual data points
are somewhat noisy, but Figure 7.8 shows the best-fitting linear functions for
one and four stimulations. The rates of decay are approximately linear and par-
allel. Thus, the behavioral retention functions shown in Figures 7.1 through 7.5
may reflect changes in the strength of neural association. To reiterate a theme
from the previous chapter, the neural learning function may have this form
because it mirrors the structure of the environment (Figure 7.7).
Spacing Effects
Scientists love parsimonious theories of empirical phenomena. From a scien-
tist’s perspective, it would be nice if memory were just a matter of practice and
retention interval. However, things are a good bit more complicated in many
234
Spacing Effects
bank-tail
fish-home
fish—??
bank-tail
pail—nose
frog—girl
pail—??
snow-ball
bank—??
aGimple forgetting>However, the effect of the interval between the two study
presentations changed with the test interval. At long test intervals, there was an.
curvilinear. The study interval that gave the best performance for each test inter-
val is starred in Fi
235
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
* Retention
interval
2 events
8 events
eX
32 events
64 events
*
FIGURE 7.9 Results from
Glenberg (1976). The effect of dif- Proportion
recalled
3
ferent spacings between two
studies at different retention
intervals. Source: From A. M. 2
Glenberg. Journal of Verbal Learn-
ing and Verbal Behavior, Volume
15. Copyright© 1976 by Academic o1°4 8 20 40
Press. Reprinted by permission. Number of events between two presentations
first tested for the Spanish equivalent of the vocabulary item, and,
if they
In
condition anes pas he delay pewccn. these cles. In'the@ne)
vies. guslesih at is, ach day subjects were tested for the 50 vocabulary items
and then had an climes to study them.
Howeyer, all groups were administered one final testat aa 30-day delay from
their last test-study cycle. In this case the ord erof the results was reversed; the.
Fe ELE ETS Se
TABLE 7.1 Percentage of Recall of Spanish Vocabulary Items for Various Delays
Between Studies
Intersession Test
Interval Final
(days) 1 2 3 4 5 30-Day Test
0 82 92 96 96 98 68
1 53 86 94 96 98 86
30 Bill 51 ie: 79 82 95
Source: Data from Bahrick, 1984.
236
Spacing Effects
Distributed practice
Mean
recalled
number
Massed practice
237
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
Ped icreeitn
the Pe saysoci sel had aes eadied once or twice, and
pace the pOrauaes in ave they had been one Semen,
entices a word that is first apes cisally and ar then auditorily (presenta-
tions were counterbalanced; this discussion refers to one specific case). If the
subject remembers only one presentation, will it be the auditory or the visual
presentation! At short delays between the presentations, subjects tended to
D1ICTV C
Interference
Short interval
between
occurrences
-4.2
Long interval
FIGURE 7.11 Probability that a word between
that has appeared twice in the New York occurrences
Times will appear again. The curves are 101
probability
day
Log
on
a function of the amount of time since
the last occurrence. The two curves 4.6
reflect cases when the two presenta-
tions were either close together or far
apart. (From Anderson & Schooler, 1 2 3 4
1991.) Log days since last occurrence
spacing effect in (Ae memory does appear to mirror a spacing effect in the
environment. Memory identifies massed items and makes them unavailable _
lati
show that there
Both Figures 7.7 and 7.11 a:re ipthe
between
is onsh
emory seems to be adapted to these patterns and
adjusts the strengths of records accordingly.
the most likely to be needed. Recall from Chapters 2 and 3 that animal condi-
tioning appears to reflect near-optimal statistical inference about the causal
structure of the environment.
. In both cases, the apparent opti-
mality of these basic phenomena has come as something of a surprise to psy-
chologists. However, the caveat from previous chapters needs to be repeated:
the apparent optimality does not imply that the system is engaged in explicit
statistical inference. Simple associative learning processes can display these
properties of statistical optimality.
BLN SI RT niu tei RO COSINE NEL SRN ENR MESES EHR REN EEE ESN SOAS EOIN NTE
Interference
Thus far, this chapter has described forgetting as if it were just a function of time.
However, the amount and rate of forgetting can vary dramatically with what is
learned before and after the critical material. Consider again the
239
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
iin L i aR ra GF
BE ae Naeat 2
hang rena example iis parking one’s car in a lot. Some people find
it eta and harder to remember where they parked the car. Is this because
they learn less well the new location (negative transfer) ornrforget it more rapid-
ly kproachne antemenence)
Other methods have been used to show that the poorer performance in the Brown
and Peterson task is due to proactive interference and not to negative transfer (Loftus
& Patterson, 1975; Watkins & Watkins, 1975).
240
Interference
Item-Based Interference
uly into the natureat EMSS comes— nae OU bees the
2There is a fourth logical possibility that the learning of the second material can
impede the learning of the first material, but this situation would be a scientific con-
tradiction inasmuch as it would require causality to work back in time such that a
later event would affect an earlier event.
241
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
242
Interference
243
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
with information about the relevant list. Figure 7.13 shows the stimuli, respons-
es, and lists as different elements that can serve to activate the target memory.?
The assumption is that any item (like the stimulus frog) has a fixed capac-
ity for activating memories. Thus, if an item is part of two memories, it cannot
activate either as well as it could if it were associated with only one. It takes
longer to learn a new response to the same stimulus because the new response
must compete with the other record for activation, producing negative transfer.
Once the new response has been learned, the existence of this new association
takes activation away from the old response, producing retroactive interference.
The basic theory can be described with the following two equations. The»
h ‘a
’Figure 7.13 has compressed the A-B, A-D and A-B, C-D paradigms together, where-
as more typically they are between subjects; thus, it illustrates a mixed-list design,
where a single subject sees both conditions.
244
Interference
The two equations can be combined to predict the basic interference phe-
nomenon. Consider the situation in which a subject learns one paired-associate
list and then learns a second associate list involving the same stimuli. Since each
stimulus must be associated to two responses, the association strength will be
divided by 2 and hence will be 4/2. Therefore, there is less association strength
than when each stimulus has a unique response. Thus, there will be more for-
getting of the first list, resulting in retroactive interference. The lower associative
strength will also lead to poorer learning of the second list, resulting in negative
transfer or proactive interference.
This
one would seem to imply
nply that the Rescorla—Wagner cheowy and the
Association Equation are diametrically opposed in terms of where the competi-
tion lies. However, upon closer inspection it turns out that the two rules are con-
sistent and, in fact, thatthe
Rescorla-Wagner
theory provides a mechanism for
Consider the implications of the Rescorla—Wagner rule for the learning of the
paired associates shown in Figure 7.13. Since the stimulus frog is associated to
two different responses (tire and door) in two different lists, each response is
being reinforced only some of the time. Consider the association between frog
and tire. On trials in which fire occurs as a response, the strengthening rule
according to Rescorla—Wagner is
AV = a(A
- V)
245
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
where 0 is the strength of association that can be maintained when the response
does not occur. The Rescorla-Wagner role will learn the value of V that will
result in the minimal AV. In the case of an equal mixture of list 1 and list 2, con-
tinued learning will result in an asymptotic value of V = 4/2. More generally, if
there are n responses equally practiced to a stimulus, the resulting strength of
association is A/n. This result is exactly the Association Equation, which asserts
that there is a fixed value for the sum of associative strengths to one stimulus.
ASSAD REN ECMO TESTOR,
As can be seen, the same profession could occur in multiple sentences, and the
same location could occur in multiple sentences. The sentences here are prefixed
by two digits. Thefirst digit indicates how many sentences the profession occurs _
in anc in. In the experi-
ment, some professions and locations occurred in three sentences as well as in
the one- and two-sentence cases shown here. Figure 7.14 illustrates the mem-
ory records that are being created and their associations. terms:such
Note that
mais Hae ore ords.and.se-shouldsbedeass.
a : 7% anecueses ada Aa el linia
Subjects practiced this material until they could recall all the material cor-
rectly. Then they were asked to perform a fact-recognition task. They were sup-
246
Interference
Memory Records
posed to recognize sentences they had seen when those sentences were mixed
in with combinations of professions and locations that they had not seen, for
example,”The doctor is in the park.”Table 7.3 displays the speed with which sub-
jects made these judgments as a function of the number of facts they had stud-
1 ?4 3
247
CHAPTER 7 Retention.of Memories
(e.g., Postman, Stark, & Fraser, 1968). For instance, when subjects try to recall
Asya
7.13). consequ
door to frog in list 1, tire from list ‘ 2 intrudes (see ; Figure iat ence,
: al oni
e 1
This theory also explains why performance is usually better on recognition
memory tests than on recall memory tests. A recognition probe typically pro-
vides more stimuli from which to probe memory. For instance, the recognition
question, “True or False: Harding was the president after Wilson,” provides one
more item to probe memory than the recall question, “Who was the president
after Wilson?” This extra item is the term Harding. The Association Equation
implies that activation sums from this additional cue and increases the avail-
ability of this memory record. Chapter 8 expands on the difference between
recall and recognition.
248
Interference
Interference
be pe)io)
time,
Judgment
sec
fe)
: oO
Noninterference
1 5 10 15 20 25
Days of practice
249
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
judge the known facts and the studied facts is shown in Figure 7.16 at the two-
week delay. (Similar results were found in the immediate test.) Since subjects
knew the studied facts less well than the known facts, they recognized them less
well. However, recognition memory for both studied and known facts was influ-
enced by the number of experimental facts learned. These interference effects
were weak—in no case much more than 0.1 sec. A careful experimental design
is required to detect such weak effects. It is particularly interesting that these
interfering influences remained two weeks after the initial learning.
1.9
3
2.1.7
=
S
& 1.6
oO
i Known facts
FIGURE 7.16 Reaction times from
Peterson and Potts (1982). The task was pa oO
to recognize known and experimental-
ly learned facts about public figures.
Data shown are a function of number 14
of experimental facts learned and %0 1 2 = 4
delay for testing. Number of experimental facts
250
Interference
This last result brings up what has been called the paradox of the expert
(Smith, Adams, & Schorr, 1978). The results thus far indicate that the more a
person knows about any particular topic, such as Julius Caesar, the harder it is
to remember anything more about that topic. This implication paints a pretty
dismal picture of memory in everyday life. The paradox of the expert is so called
because it implies that the more expert a person is on a topic and the more that
is known about the topic, the greater the interference and the poorer memory
will be for that material. However, even though there are times when new infor-
mation is hard to retain, such as when children try to remember all their addi-
tion and multiplication facts, most of the time people do not feel hard-pressed
to learn new material.
There are boundary conditions on these interference effects. A boundary
condition means that the result does not apply in some situations. For instance,
interference occurs only when the memories people are trying to associate to a
term are unrelated. When the memories are related, memory does not worsen,
and it often improves as additional facts are learned. For example, Chapter 6
described an experiment by Bradshaw and Anderson (1982) in which subjects
learned some little-known information about famous people. In one condition,
subjects studied just a single fact:
In another condition, subjects learned two additional facts that were causally
related to the target fact:
Subjects who learned two such unrelated facts showed worse memory for the
target facts than subjects who studied just the target fact. This experiment shows
that whether additional facts are facilitating or interfering depends on whether
251
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
they are consistent with the target material. Since an expert’s knowledge about
a topic is usually consistent, they do not suffer serious interference.
Subjects’ tmemory
fag th
ict- knowledge ccan ye peer mate
by unrelated material learned in the laboratory.
Context-Based Interference
The previous sections documented that item-based interference is a robust phe-
nomenon that happens for all sorts of materials in all sorts of conditions.
However, interference can be obtained among materials that do not explicitly
overlap in any component items. For instance, in an A-B, C—-D condition, there
is interference in retention of the A-B items, even though their stimuli do not
overlap with the C—D items.
On deeper analysis it turns out that the lists A-B and C-D may overlap in
items that might cue their memory. For instance, they are learned in the same
laboratory. Rather than committing to memory “B is the response for A,” the
subject must actually commit to memory something like,“B is the response for
A in the laboratory.” Then laboratory becomes an element that could cue the
recall of the paired associate. This is an example of a context cue. Context cues
are elements of the general learning situation that can become associated to the
memory record. There are many potential context cues, including things like the
temperature of the room or the sound of a bird chirping outside. Context cues
also include internal items, such as the subject’s mood and hunger pangs. In our
discussion of animal conditioning (Chapters 2 and 3), we also saw that contex-
tual cues were important stimuli for association. The basic idea is that the exter-
nal and internal environment of the subject provides items that might become
associated to the memory record. In the A-B, C-D paradigm, memory records
from both lists are likely to be associated to some of the same contextual cues
and so interfere with each other for association to these cues. The interference
in such a paradigm may be a case of item-based interference, where the items
are parts of the context.
Anderson, (1983b) performed an experiment that found evidence for inter-
fererice as a result of shared context. The experiment contrasted two groups’ of
subjects who learned three lists of paired associates on three successiverda
Two experimental contexts were used. In one context, subjects learned the rd
from a computer in a windowless cubicle. In the other context, they learned the
lists from a human experimenter in a windowed seminar room. They learned a
list on one day and were retested on the next day. There were two conditions for
learning lists 2 and 3; they could be learned in the same context as the previous
lists or in a different context. (The assignment of context to conditions was
counterbalanced over subjects.) Figure 7.17 plots the retention performance of
subjects with the chee context versus those with the nonchanging context.
The subjects with the constant context showed less retention of each successive
252
Interference
90
Changing
context
jee)ol
Constant
context
e
80
253
CHAPTER 7 Retention. of Memories
4McGeoch (1942) considered the possibility that decay should be given a neural inter-
pretation, but he believed such a view was unsupported by neural evidence. As he
wrote, “No one has ever published experimental evidence that synaptic junctions
decrease in intimacy, or in anything else, when one forgets” (p. 24). On this score, the
experimental evidence has changed dramatically in the last 50 years (e.g., Figure 7.8).
254
Interference
60
50 i
40
~€ 30
8
&
20
10
FIGURE 7.18 Mean percent recall after
48 hr, as a function of lists and succes- 0
sive blocks of three lists. (From Keppel 2 a TRS epee yor 12
et al., 1968.) Successive blocks of 3 lists
syllables and were tested after 1, 2, 4, or 8 hr, during which they were awake or
asleep. Much less forgetting occurred during sleep, during which there should be
less interference. Ekstrand (1972) reviewed a great deal of research consistent
with the conclusion that less is forgotten during the period of sleep.
, Unfortunately, these results are not conclusive evidence against the decay
theory. Decay theorists (Wickelgren, 1977) have argued that the rate of decay is
slower during sleep. Particularly compelling for this point of view is the study of
Hockey, Davies, and Gray (1972). They observed that previous studies of sleep
compared retention during the night (sleep condition) with retention during the
day (waking condition). When they kept subjects awake during the night and
had them sleep during the day, they found that night versus day. and not sleep,
was.the critical factor. This result suggests that forgetting may vary with the daily
thythms of the body. A later section of this chapter discusses the effect of time
of day on retention.
Although the sleep studies do not support the interference hypothesis, it
is nonetheless possible that forgetting is entirely a function of interference.
Sleep studies test only the hypothesis that forgetting is due to retroactive inter-
ference—that is, that forgetting is influenced by other materials learned in the
retention interval. As can be seen in Figures 7.12 and 7.18, a more potent factor
might be proactive interference—that is, influence of material prior to retention.
There is not a good theoretical understanding of proactive interference.
Proa e when it is properly demonstrated by experiments such as
that of Keppel et al. (1968), involves accelerated Joss of material that was
brou the same level of initial learning. It is extremely difficult to explain
why materials brought to the same level of learning then display different for-
getting functions over intervals in which the subjects’ activities are identical.°
299
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
Retention of Emotionally
Charged Material
Before concluding the topic of retention, it is worth considering whether the
retention of materials might be affected by their emotional content. As it turns
out, there does appear to be an effect, but it is rather different from what most
scholars had initially expected.
256
Retention of Emotionally Charged Material
charged words, such as quarrel, angry, and fear, in contrast to neutral words, such
as window, cow, and tree. They looked at the number of associations recalled in
the two categories immediately and at a seven-day delay. Table 7.5 shows their
results. Consistent with Loftus and Burns and Peters, they found superior mem-
ory neutral
for the words in an immediate test. However, at adelay the results
were reversed and memory was better for the emotional words. These results are
the
ees opposite
8 of what Freud’s repression hypothesiswould have predicted.
6 GSR measures the capacity of the skin to conduce electrical current by passing a
small electrical current through the skin. Because one component of arousal is per-
spiration, this measure of skin conductance increases at points of arousal.
257
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
recalled
Percent
1 10 10,800
Log time, min (1 week)
258
The False Memory Syndrome
17
a |
N
eS
o= |. Study at 3:00 p.m.
8
S14
5
=
13
ET
259
CHAPTER 7 Retention of Memories
260
The False Memory Syndrome
Mistaken identity: The men on the left and right were arrested for the crimes per-
formed by the man in the middle.
Yerkes—Dodson law has interesting implications for test anxiety: a little test anx-
iety may improve performance on a test, but too much is detrimental.
261
CHAPTER 7 Retention. of Memories
bien may
ts Pen eaieee erspat begsexperience in a eh
eae state,eehe re CESTretaineeea Ey do nee?
RHR v6 ANNAN AGRON
Final Reflections
Laypeople typically view forgetting as one of the most frustrating aspects of
their minds. However, numerous memory theorists have pointed out that for-
getting can be quite adaptive. Maintaining a memory has costs, both because of
the physical cost of storing it and because it can intrude when it is not wanted.
Every other system that stores records (e.g., libraries, computer file systems, per-
sonal records of bills and payments) eventually reaches its capacity for storage
and must throw something out. It is in the interest of our memories, too, to for-
get (throw out) those things that are not useful.
The factors that influence retention can be seen as examples of memory
throwing out the less useful information. The retention and spacing functions in
memory mirror similar functions in the environment. These environmental
functions measure how likely the information is to be useful. Item-based inter-
ference can be understood in terms of a similar tendency to favor likely memo-
ries. When an item like frog appears, it is likely that we will need to retrieve some
262
Final Reflections
memory involving it. As an item is associated with more memories, any partic-
ular memory is less likely to be the one that is needed when the item appears.
An interesting question, considered in detail in Chapter 8, is whether for-
getting amounts to the actual loss of the information from memory or whether we
just no longer can retrieve the information. Often, retrieval failure is the better
interpretation of forgetting. Less useful memories may not be truly lost—they may
just become less accessible. There are many analogies in information storage sys-
tems. Less useful books in libraries are often moved to auxiliary storage buildings
where they are not so readily accessible. Data not currently used in computer sys-
tems are stored on tapes, which can be a bother to retrieve and read.
Nelson (1971, 1978) conducted a series of experiments to show that mate-
rial that subjects can no longer recall or recognize is still there. Subjects learned
paired associates and were then retested at delays varying from two to four
weeks. Nelson identified items that subjects could no longer recall or recognize
in the retention test. A subject may have learned a pair like 43—dog but could no
longer recall or recognize it. Subjects then learned a new list that involved either
the old paired associate, 43-dog, or a repairing, such as 43—house. He found that
subjects were able to better learn the unchanged 43-dog, even though they
could not recall or recognize having seen it from their earlier learning experi-
ences. They showed savings in relearning for old material. Although this result
does not establish that everything that has been forgotten is still there, it does
show that there are some remnants of some memories that we no longer
retrieve. It may make more sense to think of forgetting as resulting in memories
becoming less and less available rather than being deleted.
Further Readings
Two reviews of the classic research on retention are found in works by Postman
(1974) and Wickelgren (1977). Rubin and Wenzel (1996) review the literature on
the retention and the fit of various mathematical functions. Bahrick (1984) pre-
sents some data on retention functions over 50 years, in which he characterizes
their asymptotic levels as being in a”perma store.” Neisser (1982) presents a
series of articles concerned with the relationship between memory and every-
day life. Christianson (1992) presents a review of research on the effects of emo-
tional arousal, particularly on eyewitness testimony. The April 1996 issue of the
Journal of Memory and Language was devoted to the issue of memory illusions,
including the false memory syndrome.
264
Retrieval of Memories
Overview
This chapter considers issues about the retrieval of information from memory.
The retrieval process logically follows the acquisition and retention processes
addressed in the two previous chapters. Retrieval is perhaps the most critical
process in that often information can_be in memory and _yet_not retrieved.
Chapter 7 ended with the research of Nelson which demonstrated that subjects
enjoyed savings in relearning for memories they could no longer recall or rec-
ognize. That research raised the tantalizing possibility that people may never
truly forget memories but rather may just lose access to them. Unfortunately,
the question of whether this haunting possibility is really true has no resolution,
but this chapter discusses how memories can be unavailable for recall in one
situation and yet show their influences in another situation. It reviews the three
main approaches to this issue:
1. The Relationship among Explicit Measures of Recall. Everyone has-had
the experience of being unable to recall something on one occasion but
able to recall the same thing on some other occasion. Although memory
is inherently variable, some ways of testing it are more sensitive than oth-
ers. The most common example of this situation is the different perfor-
mance people display on recognition versus recall tests. For instance, stu-
dents almost always claim that multiple-choice questions are easier than
fill-in-the-blank questions.
2. Interactions between Study and Test. How well people perform on a test
of memory depends not only on the conditions of test but also on the
relationship of these conditions to the conditions of learning. adenaaas
have had the_experience of ret
years and being flooded with memories that we had enbinets we sae
Or we have gone to see a movie that we seem to have forgotten and find
ourselves remembering everything once we begin to watch. Apparently,
being placed back in the context in which these memories were learned
265
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
makes them available again, A great deal of research has been done on
Such effects. Such interactions may underlie some of forgetting in that
with thepassage oftime people may loseaccess tocues that hadallowed
them to recall their memories.
3. Implicit Measures of Memory. People know many things of which they
are quite unaware. If explicitly asked about these things they may draw a
blank, but in an appropriate circumstance they give evidence of what they
know. For instance, students often claim that they have completely forgot-
ten what they have learned in abstract mathematics courses, but they are
nonetheless able td relearn the material faster (just as Nelson’s subjects
were able to relearn the paired associates faster). This chapter reviews
some of the many ways in which people give evidence of things they can-
not consciously remember.
These three topics reflect the shift of interests in the psychology of memory.
Research on the relationship between explicit measures of memory was an
important topic in the 1960s and 1970s, to be replaced by research on interac-
tions between study and test in the 1970s and 1980s, and in turn to be replaced
by research on implicit memories in the 1980s and 1990s. As understanding of
one topic was reached, attention shifted to the next topic.
266
The Relationship Between Various Explicit Measures of Memory
20
Cued recall
3
8eee)
3
S
S Free recall
= 10}
president after Wilson?” presents two relevant cues, namely, Harding and Wilson.
With two cues, the memory record is more active and more likely to be recalled.
How well we can remember something depends in part on how well we
can regenerate the cues to which the memory is associated. An experiment by
Tulving and Psotka (1971) showed that what might appear to be recall failure
may really be loss of access to appropriate retrieval cues. Subjects studied from
one to six lists of 24 words. Each list consisted of four members of each of six
categories, for example, dog, cat, horse, and cow from the mammal category. After
they had studied all the lists, subjects were tested for their memory of the first
list under two conditions:
1. Free recall. They were to recall the words from the list in any order.
2. Cued recall. They were shown the six category names and were asked to
recall the words in any order.
Figure 8.1 shows the number of words successfully recalled from list 1 as a func-
tion of the number of subsequent lists learned. The free-recall data show a stan-
dard result of retroactive interference in that recall goes down as a function of
the number of subsequent lists. When subjects were given the category labels as
cues, there was relatively little forgetting. Tulving and Psotka argued that forget-
ting is largely loss of access to retrieval cues, such as category labels.
267
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval.of Memories
Dog
[dog in list 7 ball in list rock in list hat in list gun In list
Memory Records
ie
FIGURE 8.2 Memory records encoding some of the words in a list and their con-
nections with the list context.
268
The Relationship Between Various Explicit Measures of Memory
In a recall task, subjects are informed of the list they are to recall and must /
retrieve the words. Thus, they are given the list context as the cue and must
retrieve memories of words seen in that context. Because the list context is asso-
ciated to all the records, this is a massive interference paradigm; it is not sur- c
prising that performance is usually poor in a recall test-In contrast, subjectsina __)
recognition test are given basically two cues to memory—the list context and
the word to be recognized. The word is a much better cue than the list context .
because there is no experimental interference involving the word. It is not sur- y,
prising, then, that recognition memory is much better.
Anderson and Bower (1974) conducted an experiment in which subjects
studied a number of lists of words, with certain words reappearing in varying
numbers of lists. They found that as the same word appeared in other lists,
recognition memory for whether the word appeared in a target list deteriorated.
Figure 8.3 shows how recognition performance, measured by a d-prime (d’)
measure,” declined with the greater number of additional lists, just as this asso-
ciative analysis predicted. There would be a different list context element for
each list. Thus, not only would there be multiple associations to the list context,
but as seen in Figure 8.2, there would also be multiple associations to the words.
As a word appears in more lists, it acquires more a ist con-
texts,
Lt Bi
andeR
these interfere
Se
with
ee
one another.
Tae
In list memory, both the word and the list context are avail-
able as retrieval cues in a recognition test, whereas only the
list context is available in a free recall test.
2Later this section discusses the d-prime measure, which has been advanced as a
superior measure of recognition memory.
269
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval. of Memories
As the subject said each capitalized word, she wrote it down as part of the recall.
Subjects often use interword associations to avoid having to cue all their recall
from just the list context. If they can retrieve one word, they can use it to cue
recall of associated words, and these to cue recall of associated words, and so on.
Much of the behavior of subjects in a free-recall experiment can be under-
stood in terms of their attempts to come up with additional retrieval cues to help
recall. The subject just quoted was spontaneously using a story-making strategy
to help retrieve the words. Bower and Clark (1969) performed an experiment that
looked explicitly at the effect of story making on memory for a list of words. They
told their subjects to commit to memory lists of 10 unrelated nouns by making
up a story involving the words. One subject made up the following story:
270
The Relationship Between Various Explicit Measures of Memory
ing his STOCKING, while hastening toward the PILLOW where his
MISTRESS lay.
The control group was given equal time to just study the words. Subjects in the
two groups studied 12 lists of 10 words. At the end of the experiment they were
asked to recall all 120 words. The experimental group was able to recall 94 per-
cent of the words, whereas the control group could only recall 14 percent. This
271
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
memories for the information to be recalled. There are several such mnemonic
s. section describes two of the more famous techniques, the peg-
techniqueThis
word method and the method of loci, and shows how their effectiveness can be
understood in terms of the generate-recognize theory.
One is a bun
Two is a shoe »
Three is a tree
Four is a door
Five is a hive
Six is sticks
Seven is heaven
Eight is a gate
Nine is wine
Ten is a hen
Suppose you want to remember the following grocery list: milk, hot dogs, dog
food, tomatoes, bananas, and bread. You would take the first item and try to asso-
ciate it to the element that corresponds to one—bun. Perhaps you would develop
an image of a bun floating in milk. Similarly, you would develop images for the rest
of the list: hot dogs sticking out of a shoe like toes, a tree bearing cans of dog food
as fruit, a door with a tomato for a handle, a hive with bananas flying in and out of
it, and sticks that when broken turn out to be bread (i.e., breadsticks). These images
are bizarre, but as reviewed in Chapter 6, they are effective ways of associating
items. When you wanted to recall the list, you could retrieve the word that corre-
‘sponded to one, namely, bun, and then retrieve the item associated with it, name-
ly, milk, and then continue through the rest of the list. The pegwords, such as bun,
can be used over and over again to learn new lists (Bower & Reitman, 1972).
This technique is very successful and confers on the user near perfect
memory for the items to be remembered. The basic technique capitalizes on two
things. First, memorizing a sequence of items, such as bun, shoe, tree, ahead of
time provides an orderly way of going through the material to prompt recall of
each item. Second, the concrete pegwords provide excellent cues to memory
when combined with learning by imagery. Both of these advantages have their
effect by helping the person generate items for recognition.
272
The Relationship Between Various Explicit Measures of Memory
goes from a service station past a police station, a department store, a movie
theater, and a restaurant, to a beach. Suppose you want to use this path to mem-
orize the same list of six items: milk, hot dogs, dog food, tomatoes, bananas, and
bread. You would mentally walk along the path forming visual images that link
the locations and the items. Thus, you might imagine the service station atten-
dant pumping milk from the gas pump, a police officer at the station smoking a
hot dog, a mannequin holding dog food in the department store window, a
movie theater advertising The Attack of the Killer Tomatoes, the restaurant’s menu
written on a banana, and loaves of bread washed ashore by waves at the beach.
To recall these items at a later date, you would walk down this path in your
mind, reviving the images associated with each location. Like the pegword
method, this method has proved an effective way of learning multiple lists
(Christen & Bjork, 1976; Ross & Lawrence, 1968).
Both the method of loci and the pegword method combine the same two
principles to achieve high levels of recall. They start with a fixed sequence of ele-
ments that the memorizer already knows. Then they use vivid, interactive visu-
al images to ensure that the new items get associated to these elements. Their
effectiveness can be understood in terms of the generate-recognize theory. They
are designed to try to guarantee success in the difficult generation phase. The
assumption is that once the items are generated, memory will be able to recog-
nize them. The next section considers situations (different from those created by
these mnemonic techniques) in which the assumption of successful recognition
memory is not valid.
russe Scns
273
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval'of Memories
Recall condition. Subjects were presented with cues, such as train, and
were asked to recall the target words, here black. Note that this is not the
free-recall condition for which the generate-recognize theory was devel-
oped; this condition provides a much better cue for recall (namely, train)
than does the typical free-recall experiment in which the subject only has
the list context.
Recognition condition. Subjects were presented with a high associate of
the target word, for example, white (people frequently generate black as an
associate of white), and asked to generate four free associates to the word.
Typically, one of these free associates was the target word, black. The sub-
jects were asked to judge if any of the words generated was the target
word. Thus, the subjects were put in a situation in which they would have
a high probability of generating the word, and their only difficulty should
be recognizing the word.
The results from such an experiment can be classified both according to whether
a word is recalled and according to whether the word can be recognized. Table
8.1 shows some data from Tulving and Wiseman (1975) classified according to
these factors. The table reports the proportion of words in each of the four states
obtained by crossing these factors. Two results from this paradigm are thought
to challenge seriously the generate-recognize theory. One is that memory per-
formance is sometimes higher in the recall condition than
in the recognize con-
dition. Table 8.1 shows that subjects can display a higher probability of recalling
black to train (60 percent) than of recognizing black (40 percent) when they gen-
erate it as an associate to white. This result is surprising because it seems to vio-
late the common wisdom that recognition is easier than recall.
The second result involves a comparison of the conditional probability of
recogniofaword,given thatitis recalled, with the unconditional probabil-
tion
ity of recogni the word. The unconditional
oftion probability of recognition is
calculated by dividing the number of words recognized by the number tested.
The unconditional probability is 40 percent in Table 8.1. The conditional proba-
bility is the number of recalled and recognized words divided by the total num-
ber recalled. The conditional probability might be expected to be much higher
than the unconditional probability and close to 1.0 on the view that any word
274
The Relationship Between Various Explicit Measures of Memory
Recalled .60
Not Recalled 40
Totals 1.00
that can be recalled should be able to pass the easier recognition test. In fact, the
conditional probability is only slightly higher than the unconditional probabili-
ty. In Table 8.1, it is 30/60 = 50 percent, which is only slightly higher than 40 per-
cent, the unconditional probability. Many words can be recalled but not recog-
nized when they are generated in the free association test. Failure to recognize
recallable words is called recognition failure. Although these results do not
irectly a question of what is happening in a free-recall experiment,
they do call into question the view that recognition is easier than recall—one of
the basic assumptions of the generate-recognize theory of free recall.
These results can be understood by considering the retrieval cues available
for the subjects to access their memory in the two cases. In the recall case the
cue was train; in the recognition case it was black. In each case there was just one
cue. In cases in which recognition is superior to recall, the recognition test has
provided more cues to memory. These words were not chosen randomly—train
was chosen because it has a low but nonzero probability of evoking black in a
free association test, not vice versa. Thus, the reason for better performance in
the recall situation may be that train is a better cue for the memory than black.
Subjects were also instructed to study the words so that they could recall black
given train. Rabinowitz, Mandler, and Barsalou (1977) turned the typical exper-
iment around. They looked at the relationship between recognition of black (as
before) and recall of train given black as a prompt (turned around). They found
that recall was much poorer in the reverse direction (black as a prompt for train),
confirming that target words (black) are poorer cues to memory than cue words
(train). Moreover, recognition failure was much lower when conditional on
recall in the reverse direction. That is, the probability was very high that the sub-
ject could recognize black in a recognition test conditional on being able to recall
train to black. Tulving and his associates were able to get recall to be better than
recognition because they created a situation in which the recall test provided
better cues for memory than did the recognition test.
ers Soe UNH EN SEPA EASE MESA aASO RSE ES ESA SHEE SNS a
20
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
P (YES|Target) =p + (1—p) g
A little algebra reveals the following correction for guessing to obtain the true
probability:
p = P(YES|Target) — P(YES|Distractor)
1 — P(YES|Distractor)
substituting P(YES|Distractor) for g. In the example, where P(YES|Target) = .8
and P(YES|Distractor) = .2, the actual probability, p, of recognizing a target, can
be estimated to be p = .75.
276
The Relationship Between Various Explicit Measures of Memory
times it reflects a deeply held belief. For instance, subjects can be asked to assign
confidences to their recognition judgments, for example, on a 1 to 7 scale, with
1 indicating a guess and 7 indicating high confidence. Subjects identify some of
their false alarms (and some of their correct recognitions) as guesses, but assign
considerable confidence to others. More than once I have had heated arguments
with subjects who insisted that Iwas wrong when I informed them that a word
did not occur on a list.
How can a subject hallucinate that a word occurred on the list? It is impor-
tant to appreciate what a recognition experiment is from a subject’s perspective.
A distractor word has occurred in many contexts, and the subject may confuse
some other context with the list context. Anderson and Bower (1974; see Figure
8.3) presented words in multiple lists. Subjects frequently thought a word
occurred in a target list if it occurred in the preceding list, consistent with the
notion that subjects were somewhat confused about just what context defined
the list context. Subjects decided that a word was studied if it occurred in a con-
text similar to the study context.
Researchers have suggested other bases for deciding whether a word has
occurred in a target list. As discussed later, a common idea is that subjects use the
raw sense of familiarity that they have about the word; a word that occurred in
the most recent list might seem particularly familiar, and subjects use this feeling
of familiarity to infer they have seen the word. Words not in the target list might
be familiar for other reasons and so might be the source of false alarms.
There are probably other bases for making recognition judgments besides
similarity of context and familiarity. Abstracting over these various possible
bases, a word can be considered as offering some evidence for being in the tar-
get list. A word that is in the target list usually offers greater evidence than a
word that is not, but sometimes a word not in the list offers more evidence than
a word in the list.
A methodology see aycece eer peer been developed to
help psychologists model how subjects make decisions when faced with the
need to discriminate between two stimuli of this kind. In the case of recognition
memory, the assumption is that there is a distribution of evidence for list mem-
bership for those words that are in the list and another distribution of evidence
for distractor words. Figure 8.4 illustrates these two distributions as normal dis-
tributions, which is what they are usually assumed to be. These distributions
reflect the probability that a particular word has a particular degree of evidence.
As shown, most target words have higher evidence than most distractor words,
but there is some overlap in the distributions, and some distractor words show
more evidence than some target words.
What subjects do is to select some criterion of evidence such that if the
word is above this criterion they accept it and if it is below this criterion they
reject it. The target words above the criterion point correspond to those words
that are correctly recognized. The distractor words above the criterion point cor-
respond to the false alarms. The proportions of these two types of words can be
used to estimate how far apart the two distributions are in terms of distance
210
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval.of Memories
Criterion
Distractors
Correct Correct
rejections recognitions
Frequency
—>
False
rejections alarms
from the center of the target distribution to the center of the distractor distrib-
ution. This distance is measured in terms of standard deviations, often referred
to as a d’ (d-prime) measure.*
Signal detectability theory is not an esoteric model that applies only to
deciding whether a word has been seen in a list memory experiment. Judgments
of this sort are constantly involved in memory decision judgments. When we
decide whether we have met someone before, we ate judging some sense of
familiarity in the person’s face and trying to decide whether it is the high famil-
iarity we would associate with a face we have seen before or whether it reflects
the low familiarity associated with a novel face. When we try to remember
whether we have been in a particular location, we are judging how similar that
location is to other locations where we have been. Signal detectability theory
provides a helpful way to model these decisions. It has also been used to
describe sensory judgments, such as deciding whether a faint tone is heard.
Indeed, the signal detectability methodology was originally developed to
describe sensory judgments.
This analysis of recognition memory implies that a subject’s performance
on a recognition memory test is a function of how difficult it is to discriminate
distractors from targets. Presumably, if the targets were words and the distrac-
tors were numbers, subjects would display very good recognition memory. In
this case, the two distributions would be very far apart in terms of degree of evi-
dence. If the distractors were very similar, recognition memory would be poor.
For instance, subjects fare worse in recognition memory tests in which the dis-
tractors are semantically similar to the targets (Underwood & Freund, 1968).
4Massaro (1989) is one source for the details of how to compute these quantities.
278
Interactions Between Study and Test
EMM SRE ERA O RRL NA
279
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval. of Memories
52) —
ss 13 Dry recall
3 12 i environment
2)
2
tuilillal is
So
B10F
5 gL Wet recall
< environment
®
=> 8 “Y
| scaly deen
Dry Wet
Recall environment
FIGURE 8.5 Mean number of words recalled as a function of study and test envi-
ronments. (From Godden & Baddeley, 1975.)
The effect displayed in the Godden and Baddeley study is much larger than
most other context effects reported (e.g., Smith, Glenberg, & Bjork, 1978), which
have used less substantial manipulations of context. Several researchers have failed
to find context effects at all (e.g., Fernandez & Glenberg, 1985; Saufley, Otaka, &
Bavaresco, 1985). Eich (1985) argued that the magnitude of these effects depends
on the degree to which the context is integrated into the memories. He contrasted
two conditions in which subjects learned a list of nouns by means of imagery. In
one condition subjects were to imagine the nouns alone, and in the other case they
were to imagine the nouns integrated into the context. Eich found larger effects of
context variation when subjects imagined the words integrated with the context. In
terms of the cue-record representation (e.g., Figure 8.2), such integration manipu-
lations can be thought of as affecting whether contextual elements, such as the
experimental room, get associated as cues to the memory record.
Context-dependency effects have interesting implications with respect to
tasks such as exam taking. Such effects imply that people will do best on an exam
if they study in the same context in which they will take the exam, and that test
performance will be further enhanced if students try to integrate what they are
studying with the test context. Unfortunately, it is not always easy to gain access
to a test room or to get a match on many of the internal components of context.
State-Dependent Memory
The concept of context can be extended to the internal state of the subject,
which can vary depending on whether the subject is happy or sad, hungry or
sated, excited or calm, and so on. In some cases subjects show better recall when
280
Interactions Between Study and Test
Test while
intoxicated
o1
Test
recalled
number
Mean
while sober
their state at test matches their state at learning. This phenomenon is referred
to as paledependent meniony One dimension of state dependency on which
there has been considerable research involves various drug-induced states. With
drugs like alcohol and marijuana, there is some evidence that subjects show bet-
ter recall if they study and are tested while sober or if they study and are tested
while intoxicated than if they study in one state and are tested in another state
(Eich, Weingartner, Stillman, & Gillin, 1975; Goodwin, Powell, Bremer, Hoine, &
Stern, 1969). A representative experiment (Goodwin et al., 1969) from this area,
illustrated in Figure 8.6, looked at the effect of being tested while sober or intox-
icated with alcohol after studying while sober or intoxicated. Subjects on the
first day (learning) were asked to make up eight paired associates and then on
the second day (recall) to recall them. There is an interaction in this figure such
that subjects who learn sober remember better when tested sober and subjects
who learned intoxicated remember better when tested intoxicated. Figure 8.6
also reflects another effect frequently found in this research: subjects performed
worse when they studied while intoxicated. This result is particularly evident in
the poor performance of subjects who studied while intoxicated and were test-
ed while sober. Depressant drugs, such as alcohol, tend to lower the amount
learned, and this effect often overwhelms any effects of state dependency.
Subjects tend to show poor memory for material they learned while in an intox-
icated state, independent of how they are tested. This outcome may in part
reflect the effect of lack of arousal on retention. As reviewed in Chapter 7, there
is better retention for material learned in a high arousal state.
SRROEDILLEDN LANE RTE NERA TR NILE LAE LN LE METI SOND SELLE NEL LTE ELT LI ELE ELLE DENA LOLA ROLL
x bjects c
study and at test matc.
\aerereeinieeza ast RSE I MN SAAN LINERS INNER IRA RIO LEONE
SRRIRAINE NELLIE SST UNL NEE NIRA
281
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval.of Memories
0.4
0.3
a)
£ > Generate condition
oO
6 0.2
ie
a L Test sad
(e}
o
OL Test happy q
282
Interactions Between Study and Test
the fact that people find it easier to remember happy memories when ha
12
il
1.0,
FIGURE
.
8.8 Recall of
:
positive,; neg- ©ov 0.8
ative, and neutral trait words in elat- co
ed and depressed mood states. Source: =
From J. D. Teasdale and M. L. Russell. ail Negative words
Differential effects of induced mood
on the recall of positive, negative, and ag
neutral words. British Journal of ae Neutral words
Clinical Psychology, Volume 22, pp.
163-171, Figure 1. Copyright © 1983 5
by the British Psychological Society. Elation Depression
Reprinted by permission. Mood state at test
283
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval. of Memories
284
Interactions Between Study and Test
0.4
Associate test
3 0.3
=
2
25
Sally
2)
a 0.2
Rhyme test
that a semantic associate was a better cue if the processing at encoding was
semantic, whereas a rhyme was a better cue if the processing at encoding was
phonetic. Since the cues were always changed from study to test, the results are
not a matter of simple overlap in the cues. What is critical is the processing that
these cues induced. Transfer-appropriate processing is further discussed in the
section on implicit memory.
285
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval.of Memories
Vader evil?” Again, you might not remember whether this trait was ever asserted
in the movie series, but you can recall various events that allow you to answer this
question in the affirmative. Thus, people can use memories that they can retrieve
to infer what must be true. This ability to extend our knowledge inferentially is an
important additional attribute of our memory-system.
The British psychologist E_C, Bartlett wrote an important treatise on mem-
ory in 1932.and is famous for emphasizing the reconstructive character of
uman memory. Neisser, an American psychologist, reemphasized the recon-
i on-
structing a memory from what could beretrieved as similar to the process a
paleontologist follows to reconstruct a dinosaur from bone chips:
The basic idea is that people retrieve whatever they can from memory and then
infer what the experiences must have been that gave rise to these memory frag-
ments. Reconstructive memory is the term used to refer to the processes b
which people try to inferentially recreate their memories from what they_can
recall,—
How would a psychologist go about documenting that people actually
engage in such inferential processes when trying to recall information? One way
is to contrast conditions that facilitate or inhibit such inferences. Bransford and
Johnson (1972) looked at the effect of enabling or not enabling inferential elab-
orations. They had two groups of subjects study the following passage, which
you should try to read and then recall:
The procedure is actually quite simple. First arrange items into dif-
ferent groups. Of course one pile may be sufficient depending on
how much there is to do. If you have to go somewhere else due to
lack of facilities that is the next step; otherwise, you are pretty well
set. It is important not to overdo things. That is, it is better to do too
few things at once than too many. In the short run this may not seem
important but complications can easily arise. A mistake can be
expensive as well. At first, the whole procedure will seem complicat-
ed. Soon, however, it will become just another facet of life. It is diffi-
cult to foresee any end to necessity for this task in the immediate
future, but then, one never can tell. After the procedure is complet-
286
Interactions Between Study and Test
ed one arranges the material into different groups again. Then they
can be put into their appropriate places. Eventually they will be used
once more and the whole cycle will then have to be repeated.
However, that is part of life. (p. 322)
Before reading this passage, some subjects were told that the passage involved
washing clothes. Given this information, they found (and presumably you would,
too) that it was easier to elaborate on this material with inferences. For instance,
the beginning of the passage could be elaborated with information about sorting
clothes by colors, and the middle of the passage, with information about costly
mistakes in washing clothes. Subjects who were told that the passage was about
doing laundry before they read it were able to recall more of the story than were
two control groups. One control group was not given this information at all. The
other control group was given this information only after reading the story. So,
knowing that the passage was about doing laundry only at test was not ade-
quate; the material had to be encoded in this way at study. This experiment pro-
vides a nice example of Bransford’s transfer-appropriate processing. By studying
the story with the knowledge that it involved washing clothes, subjects enabled
themselves to take advantage of that information at recall.
Chapter 6 discussed how memory for information is better if it is processed
more elaborately at study. One explanation is that this practice allows for recon-
structive retrieval at the time of recall. The elaborations generated at study can be
used at test to infer what the actual studied material was. There can be a benefi-
cial interaction between elaborative processing at study and test, as in the
Bransford and Johnson experiment. These findings have implications for reading
a text such as this: by placing as much meaning as possible on the text while
studying it, the reader is optimally positioned for meaningful reconstruction later.
287
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
There was no good institution for her problem in her state. Her par-
ents finally decided to take some action. They hired a private teacher
for Carol. (p. 256)
One group of subjects studied this paragraph, but another group of subjects
read a paragraph that substituted”Helen Keller” for“Carol Harris.”° Later, sub-
jects were asked whether they had read the following sentence:
Subjects are much more likely to think that they had studied this sentence if
they had read the Helen Keller passage than if they had read the Carol Harris
passage. From the point of view of a laboratory memory experiment, such a
recognition is often classified as an error. However, from the point of view of
adapting to the world at large, such inferences can be seen as quite appropriate.
For instance, in taking an exam, a student is expected to include plausible infer-
ences from the study materials as part of the answer to a question.
Researchers have been interested in how subjects come to recall such sen-
tences that are not part of the original passage. One possibility is that subjects
make the inference while reading the passage, and the other possibility is that
they make the inference only at the time of recall. Dooling and Christiansen
(1977) tested these possibilities by having subjects study the Carol Harris pas-
sage and then presenting them, just before test, with the information that Carol
Harris was really Helen Keller. Subjects were much more inclined to believe
they had studied the”deaf, dumb, and blind” sentence when informed about the
identity of Helen Keller just before test than when not informed at all. Since
they could not have made the inference when they studied the paragraph, they
must have made the inference when tested with the sentence.
An experiment by Owens, Bower, and Black (1979) showed that when
subjects engaged in inferential processing, there was an increase not only in
their ability to retrieve the information that they had read, but also in their intru-
sion of information that they had not read. They had subjects read a story about
a typical day in the life of a college student. Included in the story was the fol-
lowing paragraph:
Nancy went to see the doctor. She arrived at the office and checked
in with the receptionist. She went to see the nurse, who went
through the usual procedures. Then Nancy stepped on the scale and
the nurse recorded her weight. The doctor entered the room and
examined the results. He smiled at Nancy and said, “Well, it seems
my expectations have been confirmed.” When the examination was
finished, Nancy left the office. (p. 186)
°Helen Keller is famous to most Americans as someone who overcame being both
blind and deaf.
288
Interactions Between Study and Test
Two groups of subjects studied the story. The only difference between the groups
was that the theme group had read the following information before reading
any of the story:
Nancy woke up feeling sick again and she wondered if she really
were pregnant. How would she tell the professor she had been see-
ing? And the money was another problem. (p. 185)
Much like telling subjects that Carol Harris was Helen Keller, this additional
information made the passage much more interesting and enabled the subjects
to make many inferences that they might not otherwise have been able to make.
Owens et al. asked subjects to recall the story 24 hr later. They looked at facts
recalled from the story that were either actually stated in the story or could be
inferred from the story—for example, “The doctor told Nancy she was preg-
nant.”Table 8.2 displays the number of facts of each kind that were recalled as a
function of whether or not subjects were given the additional thematic passage.
Given the thematic passage, subjects recalled many additional facts that were
studied as well as many that were inferred. By increasing the subjects’ ability to
make inferences, the experimenters enabled them to remember a much richer
version of the story.
289
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval.of Memories
’ Feeling of Knowing
Sometimes memories can be just on the verge of consciousness. When people
can almost recall an item but not quite, they are said to be in a tip-of-the-tongue
state. An example is almost remembering someone’s name but not quite being
able to recall it. This phenomenon was investigated experimentally by Brown and
McNeill (1966), who presented subjects with dictionary definitions, for example,
“an instrument used by navigators to measure the angle between a heavenly
body and a horizon” or“a flat-bottomed Chinese boat usually propelled by two
oars.”” Sometimes the subjects were able to recall the word being defined or
could confidently report that they had no idea of what the word was. However,
other times the subjects reported that they felt the word was on the tip of their
tongues. If the target word was sampan and the subjects were not quite able to
recall the word, they reported that it sounded like saipan, Siam, Cheyenne, and
sarong. For words that subjects identified as being in tip-of-the-tongue states,
Brown and McNeill asked subjects questions like,“What is the first letter?”” How
many syllables does it have?” and”Can you tell me what the word sounds like?”
Subjects were able to answer such questions quite accurately.
Subjects are fairly accurate in judging whether they know something. In
one of the original studies of the feeling of knowing, Hart (1967) presented sub-
jects with questions like,“Who wrote The Tempest?” and“What is the capital of
Colombia?”Ifsubjects were unable to recall the answer, they were asked to rate
whether they would be able to recognize the answer. Subjects were able to pre-
dict quite well whether they would be able to recognize the answer. Other
research has demonstrated the accuracy of such feeling-of-knowing judgments
in other ways. Freedman and Landauer (1966) and Gruneberg and Monks
(1974) showed that subjects who thought they knew the answer were better
able to recall the answer when cued with the first letter. Nelson, Gerber, and
Narens (1984) showed that subjects who reported high feelings of knowing
were better able to perceive the answer when it was presented in a brief visual
flash. All these experiments converge in demonstrating that subjects can quite
accurately judge that they know facts they cannot consciously recall.
61 would like to thank Lynne Reder for her assistance in pointing out the studies
reviewed in this section.
7Sextant, sampan.
290
Explicit Versus Implicit Memories
Familiarity
The earlier discussion of recognition memory spoke of subjects judging whether
they had seen an item in terms of the degree of evidence they had for its list
membership. Two types of evidence were suggested: an explicit memory that the
word was seen in the list context and a sense that the word just seemed more
familiar. Subjects sometimes are not sure why the word is familiar but judge that
they have seen the word because of its familiarity.
Tulving (1985) developed a paradigm for studying these two bases for
making a recognition memory judgment. He asked subjects to indicate whether
they explicitly’remembered’a prior presentation of the items or only”knew” the
item was in the list. This remember/know distinction has been extensively
investigated by Gardiner (e.g., Gardiner & Java, 1993). They present evidence
that subjects can accurately discriminate between these two bases for a recog-
nition judgment.
Other evidence for this distinction came from earlier research of Atkinson
and Juola (1974), who had subjects study a list of words and then looked at sub-
jects’ recognition for these words when they were mixed in with distractor
words. Subjects underwent a series of four tests in which they had to discrimi-
nate the targets from the distractors. Atkinson and Juola were interested in the
speed with which subjects could make these recognition judgments. Figure 8.10
291
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
850 |—
; fe Targets
ee Distractors
3 g00 +
2
®
a
5
3 750}
shows that the speed of these recognition judgments varied with the number of
times subjects had been tested on the target or distractor. With repeated testing,
subjects got faster on the targets but slower on the distractors. Atkinson and
Juola argued that in the first test subjects could reject the distractors quickly
because they were unfamiliar, but with repeated testing the distractors became
more familiar and subjects had to consciously decide whether they occurred in
the list. The targets, with repeated testing, became so familiar that subjects could
quickly recognize them.
Jacoby (1991) used a paradigm in which subjects read a list of 15 words
and then heard a list of 15 different words. Then subjects were presented with a
recognition test in which they saw these 30 words plus 15 more new ones.
Subjects were instructed to recognize only the last 15 words they had heard and
not the earlier ones they had seen. They were tested under two conditions. In a
divided-attention condition, subjects had to monitor a sequence of digits spo-
ken on a tape recorder, looking for a sequence of three odd digits in a row (e.¢.,
9, 3, 7); in the full-attention condition, they could devote their full attention to
the primary task. Figure 8.11 shows the results. First, subjects falsely recognized
many of the words they had seen. Thus, having read the words created a sense
of familiarity, which led them to believe they had heard the words. Second, this
tendency was enhanced under conditions of divided attention. Subjects were
less able to engage in a process of conscious recollection and so had to count
more on their sense of familiarity.
Reder (Reder & Gordon, 1997; Reder, Nhouyvanisvong, Schunn, Ayers,
Angstadt, & Hiraki, 1997; Reder & Schunn, 1996) developed a theory that
explains this result and a great many other phenomena in implicit memory. She
proposed that in judging the familiarity of items subjects may simply be
responding to the strength of the memory records that underlie these items.
Subjects can more rapidly and more easily judge how strong a memory record
292
Explicit Versus Implicit Memories
Full attention
0.60
[7] Divided attention
a=!
8
50 0.40
oO
£
s=
fo}
S
= 0.20
is than what its actual contents are. Thus, strength serves as a basis for rapid
judgments of familiarity in the Atkinson and Juola experiment or as a basis for
judgment under divided attention in experiments like that of Jacoby.
Jacoby, Woloshyn, and Kelley (1989) showed that the sense of familiarity
can lead subjects to make a number of memory misattributions. First, they had
subjects read a series of names, for example, Sebastian Weisdorf. Subjects stud-
ied this material in a divided-attention condition or in a full-attention condition.
Then subjects were presented with these names mixed in with names of famous
people, such as Wayne Gretzky, as well as names of other, nonfamous people.
Subjects were to judge who was famous and who was nonfamous. An impor-
tant aspect of this experiment was that subjects were explicitly told that names
from the earlier, study phase were not famous. Figure 8.12 shows the results.
Subjects who were in the full-attention condition were better able to reject stud-
0.4
3
E03 Full
ss attention
2
8
FIGURE 8.12 Probability of judg- >
ing a nonfamous name famous 4%
after reading a list on which the B02 Divided
name appeared. Source: From L. L. a attention
Jacoby, “Subjective hierarchies in
spatial memory,” Current Directions
in Psychological Science, Volume 1.
Copyright © 1992, Blackwell New Old
Publishers. Type of name
293
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
ied names than other new names as nonfamous. They were able to use their
explicit recall of studying these names in the experimental context as a basis for
rejecting them. On the other hand, subjects in the divided-attention condition
tended to false alarm to names they had studied. Reder has explained this result
by assuming that when subjects studied the.names under divided attention,
they increased the strength of the memory records encoding these names but
did not explicitly associate the experimental context with the names.
Note that the experiment depicted in Figure 8.11 manipulated attention at
test, whereas the experiment depicted in Figure 8.12 manipulated attention at
study. Divided attention at test produces greater reliance on record strength
because the subject cannot process the test material so carefully. Divided atten-
tion at study makes it harder for the subject to encode the source of strength and
so makes it harder to filter out records that are strong for spurious reasons.
Arkes, Hackett, and Boehm (1989) and Hasher, Goldstein, and Toppino
(1977) showed that this sort of familiarity can lead subjects to come to believe
various assertions. They had subjects study sentences such as“The largest dam
in the world is in Pakistan,” and then the subjects were asked whether they
believed these assertions when mixed in with others. The previously studied
sentences received increased credibility. This is a potentially frightening result in
that it implies that propaganda does work. Merely exposing people to assertions
increases the credibility of these assertions.
Retrieval Facilitation
People can also show implicit memory for material by showing facilitation in
their processing of material as a function of exposure to the material. They can
sometimes show improved processing of material when they do not even
remember the material. Jacoby, Toth, and Yonelinas (1993) had subjects study
words under full- or divided-attention conditions as in the earlier Jacoby stud-
ies (Figures 8.11 and 8.12). They then tested the subjects in a stem-completion
task in which subjects were given a word stem and asked to complete it. For
example, the word might be motel and the stem, mot—. Some of the subjects
were explicitly instructed not to complete the stem with a word that they had
studied, whereas others were told that they could complete the stem with any
word that came to mind. Figure 8.13 shows the results in terms of how fre-
quently subjects completed the stem with the target (i.e., motel in this example).
When subjects studied the target and were told they could give it as a response,
they generated it much more frequently than when they did not have prior
exposure (inclusion instructions versus no prior exposure). Thus, they were facil-
itated in their retrieval of the target. The more interesting contrast involves sub-
jects’ performance under exclusion instructions. Particularly when they had
294
Explicit Versus Implicit Memories
S0y=
m 40 L
£ Full
S attention
3
®
9 Divided
@ 30 attention
jou
studied the words under divided attention, they were more likely to recall the
target word, even though they had been explicitly instructed not to do so. The
word was more available because of its prior exposure, but they did not remem-
ber having experienced it.
Jacoby argued that the bases for implicit and explicit memory are inde-
pendent. Implicit memory is relatively unaffected by divided attention, whereas
explicit memory is seriously impaired. In the experiment depicted in Figure 8.13,
Jacoby argued that only implicit memories were formed when subjects studied
under divided attention. Since no explicit memories were formed, subjects did
not have the advantage of them to boost recall in the inclusion condition or to
filter recall in the exclusion condition.
295
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
These three conditions manipulate the degree to which the subject engaged in
elaborative processing of the material. As indicated in Chapter 6, more elabora-
tive processing results in better memory in a standard memory test. Jacoby then
tested his subjects’ memories in one of two ways:
1. Explicit. Subjects were given a standard recognition test—they saw a list
of words and had to recognize which they had studied.
2. Implicit. Subjects were presented with the word for a brief period of time
(40 msec) and had to simply say what the word was. This was a test of their
ability to perceivesthe word when presented briefly.
The results from these two tests are displayed in Figure 8.14. The explicit condi-
tion showed the classic generation effect, with best memory in the condition
that involved the greatest semantic engagement by the subject. The results were
just the opposite in the implicit condition. Identifications were best in the No
Context condition that involved the least semantic processing. In all study con-
ditions, word identification was better than in a condition of no prior exposure.
In this control condition, subjects were able to perceive only 60 percent of the
words. Jacoby interpreted these results in terms of the match between the pro-
cessing required at study and at test. In the no-context condition, when subjects
originally encountered the word they had to rely mostly on perceptual process-
ing to identify it, whereas in the generate condition there was not even a word
to read. The result that perceptual identification is better in the no-context con-
dition than the generate condition has not always been found (e.g., Masson &
MacLeod, 1992); in some experiments, there is no difference. However, there is
always the interaction between type of processing and type of test.
Schacter, Cooper, Delaney, Peterson, and Tharan (1991) demonstrated
another example of perceptual facilitation. They presented their subjects with
drawings similar to those shown in Figure 8.15. Some were possible figures, and
90
Perceptual identification
80
(implicit memory)
(3)
~S
Percent
correct
296
Explicit Versus Implicit Memories
BIe
OO©4||81&aS
|S
FIGURE 8.15 Representative examples of target objects. The figures in the upper two
rows depict possible objects, and the figures in the lower two rows depict impossible
objects. Source: From D. L. Schacter, L. A. Cooper, S. M. Delaney, M. A. Peterson, and M.
Tharan. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, Volume 17.
Copyright © 1991 by the American Psychological Association. Reprinted by permission.
some were impossible figures. Subjects were asked to judge whether these
objects faced primarily to the left or to the right. Some subjects were also asked
to make a conceptual decision—whether the object best fit the category type of
furniture, household object, or type of building. Thus, Schacter et al. manipulat-
ed the depth at which their subjects processed the material, with the perceptu-
al judgment being shallow and the conceptual judgment deep. At test the sub-
jects were presented with figures they had studied and figures they had not
studied and were asked to make one of two decisions about these objects:
1. Perceptual decision. The object appeared for just 100 msec, and the sub-
ject had to decide whether or not it was a possible object. This is an implic-
it memory test in which the experimenters were interested in how much
better subjects judged studied versus nonstudied objects.
2. Object recognition. Subjects were given unlimited time to view the
objects and had to decide whether they were objects that had been stud-
ied. This is an explicit memory test.
297,
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
LOim
0.9 |—
; Object recognition
io i
ie
7 0.8 |—
S
‘ rm Perceptual decision
0.7
The results are displayed in Figure 8.16. Typical of other explicit memory tasks, sub-
jects showed a large advantage of a conceptual or semantic processing. In sharp
contrast, there was no significant effect in the implicit perceptual-decision task.
Both the Jacoby and the Schacter et al. studies involved an interaction
between the mode of processing at study and the type of test. Elaborative or
conceptual processing led to enhanced performance on a test of subjects’ abili-
ty to consciously recognize what they had studied. Subjects showed no advan-
tage of such processing in a task that only implicitly tapped their memory for
such a task. Roediger and Blaxton (1987) interpreted such results in terms of
Bransford’s notion of transfer-appropriate processing, discussed earlier in this
chapter. They argued that tests of implicit memory, such as stem completion,
word identification, or object recognition, involve perceptual processes, where-
as tasks such as explicit recall and recognition memory are more conceptual in
nature. Therefore, only the explicit memory tests should be facilitated by study
tasks that involve conceptual processing. They argued that high performance is
obtained when the type of test matches the type of processing at study.
Amnesia in Humans
The distinction between implicit and explicit memory is important in under-
standing the data on amnesia in humans. Amnesia refers to the loss of memo-
ry. It can be caused by many insults to the brain, such as a blow to the head;
298
Explicit Versus Implicit Memories
Trauma Examination
a ag
A Trauma Examination
23 weeks
FIGURE 8.17 Recovery of a patient from amnesia (a) after 5 months; (b) after 8
months, (c) after 16 months. Source: J. Barbizet, Human memory and its pathology. W. H.
Freeman and Company, New York, Copyright 1970. Reprinted by permission.
299
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
total period of retrograde amnesia had shrunk to 1 year and the period of par-
tial amnesia only went back to 4 years. Also, the anterograde amnesia was
beginning to diminish, and the patient was able to remember some of the things
that had happened in the three months since the previous testing. When tested
16 months after injury, the retrograde amnesia had shrunk to just the two weeks
prior to the injury, which the patient never recovered. The deficit in learning new
things had totally disappeared—while the patient still had no memory for the
events in the 3.5 months after the coma, memory appeared normal for events
after that period. This patient illustrates how retrograde amnesia and antero-
erade amnesia often go hand in hand. As the retrograde amnesia shrinks, to
include only events just before the injury, the anterograde amnesia also dimin-
ishes and the patient is more successful in forming new memories. However,
anterograde amnesia and retrograde amnesia are not always perfectly correlat-
ed. Patients with damage to the anterior temporal lobe can_show relatively
strong retrograde amnesia with weak anterograde amnesia. The severity of the
two types Of amnesias is often reversed in patients whose damage is confined
more to the hippocampal formation.
The most famous amnesic patient is H.M., who showed no recovery. He
had large parts of his temporal lobes and related subcortical areas removed to
relieve intractable epilepsy. Included in the subcortical areas removed was the
hippocampus. H.M. has poor memory for events before his surgery (retrograde
amnesia) but apparently suffered no loss of memories from his early childhood.
Most dramatically, he appears to have lost all ability to learn new information
(anterograde amnesia). Because of the removal of his temporal lobes, his
amnesia is permanent and has lasted 40 years. He quickly forgets people he has
met and has virtually no memory for what has happened in the 40 years since
his surgery. A number of other patients with hippocampal and temporal lobe
damage show severe memory loss, though usually not as complete as that of
H.M.
There are also patients who suffered severe damages to the hippocampal
area because of a history of severe alcoholism coupled with nutritional deficits.
They show memory loss, known as Korsakoff’s syndrome, with a pattern sim;
ila a atients like H.M. Such patient roximatel mal
i information but_show severe deficits in tests of long-
t ired_after developin toms.
Korsakoff’s patients and other patients suffering hippocampal damage show
some loss of memories acquired before the onset of their condition. However,
the loss before the onset is not as dramatic as the near total inability to form new
memories after the onset.
Nonhuman primates with hippocampal lesions also show relatively pre-
served memory for information learned prior to hippocampal damage. In the
case of humans and primates, the hippocampus cannot be the site of permanent
memory storage, or there would be greater loss of memories acquired before the
injury. Rather, it seems that the hippocampus must be critical in the creation of
permanent memories, which are stored elsewhere, probably in the cortex.
300
Explicit Versus Implicit Memories
OVP SENDESSAA ESSE SEE MERI RNASE ALUM CN CORES AIOE ROS EN SUNS EECA OS sericea megs anaes a Neo
Selective Amnesia
As noted in Chapter 3, lower organisms do not show complete loss of ability to
learn after removal of the hippocampus; however, there is some controversy
about how to characterize their selective learning difficulty. Such selective loss
also occurs in humans, and the amnesia (both retrograde and anterograde)
appears to be restricted to what are called explicit memories or declarative
memories. De clarative memories are_memories for factual knowledge and
ex ware.
GrafSquire, and Mandler (1984) performed an experiment that illustrates
one of the ways in which amnesiacs have preserved memory. Subjects were
shown a list of common words, such as cheese, and then later tested for their
memory of these words in one of three conditions:
1. Free recall. They were simply asked to recall all the words they had studied.
2. Cued recall. They were shown the three-letter stem of the word (e.g., che
for cheese) and asked to recall the word they had studied that began with
that stem.
3. Completion. They were shown the stem and asked to say any word (not
necessarily from the list) that began with that stem.
Figure 8.18 compares the performance of normal and amnesic subjects in these
three conditions. Normal subjects did better in the free-recall condition. This
advantage was much reduced in the cued recall condition and was actually
reversed for the completion task. In the completion task, the baseline probabil-
100
Control
80 1 Amnesic
301
CHAPTER 8 Retrieval of Memories
ity of completing the stem with the target word was only 9 percent when the
target word had not been studied. So, both normal and amnesic subjects
showed large effects of their exposure to the words, but amnesiacs were only
able to make this information available when they were not explicitly trying to
recall it. This experiment is an instance of a priming paradigm. Amnesiacs show
normal levels of priming in most paradigms.
Priming is only one of the paradigms in which amnesiacs show preserved
learning. Amnesiacs also show preserved ability to learn new skills. They have
been shown capable of learning many skills, such as rotary pursuit tasks, mirror
reading, or finger maze tasks. They show normal learning curves on such tasks,
even though they claim on the next day of training not to have seen the task.
Phelps (1989) argued that amnesic subjects are capable of learning any skill that
does not require explicitly retrieving information from long-term memory. Under
appropriate circumstances patients even appear capable of learning a new lan-
guage (Hirst, Phelps, Johnson, & Volpe, 1988) or a new mathematical algorithm
(Milberg, Alexander, Charness, McGlinchey-Berroth, & Barrett, 1988). The
patient H.M. (Cohen, Eichenbaum, Deacedo, & Corkin, 1985) has been shown
capable of learning a complex problem-solving skill over days, even though each
day when he was shown the task he protested that he had never seen it before.
Thus, skill learning is another major type of learning left intact in such patients.
It appears that it is a very select kind of knowledge that cannot be remem-
bered by amnesiacs with hippocampal damage: they seem unable to create new
declarative memory records. They can strengthen existing memory records and
thus show priming, and they can learn new skills. Chapter 3, in discussing the
effects of hippocampal damage in rats, reviewed the theory that the effect of hip-
pocampal lesions was to prevent learning of configural associations. Configural
associations link a number of elements together in a conditioning experiment. A
memory record is essentially a configuration of several cues. For instance, mem-
ory for the chunk RXL involves associating R, X, and L together in one configu-
ration. Since humans with hippocampal lesions have difficulty with just such
tasks, it may be that the nature of the deficit is similar in humans and in rats.
Final Reflections
One way to review the research presented in this chapter is to consider its impli-
cations for good memory performance. Suppose you are trying to remember
some past memories. Given that they are in the past, there is nothing you can
do to better encode these memories or retain them—the topics of the previous
two chapters. Worrying about these factors would be worrying about spilled
milk. What can you do to help retrieve those old memories?
302
Further Readings
This chapter demonstrated that people enjoy better memory if they can
recreate the elements that were associated with the memory. If you are trying to
retrieve a former acquaintance’s name, it might help to recreate in your mind
past experiences and contexts in which you used that name. For example, you
might think of names of people associated with the person whose name you are
trying to recall. It would also help if you could convert the task to a recognition
task, such as going through.an old class list.
The chapter also reviewed the importance of inferential memory for
reconstructing what can no longer be recalled. Suppose that you are trying to
remember where you placed an object. You might try to reconstruct where you
might have put it, perhaps retracing your steps, and so on.
The last part of the chapter was devoted to the notion that people have
implicit memories of which they are not consciously aware. This implies that we
should try to engage in some task that might involve the information and see if
our task performance does not have the critical knowledge embedded in it. A
classic example is knowledge of the positions of the keys on a standard type-
writer keyboard. Many people are not able to recall this information but are
nonetheless successful touch typists. They can remember where a letter is by
imagining themselves typing a word that involves the letter and seeing where
their finger goes.
Further Readings
Massaro (1989) provides a review of the high-threshold and signal detectability
theories of recognition memory. Tulving’s (1983) book is an extensive develop-
ment of his theory of memory. Hintzman (1992) and Tulving and Flexser (1992)
engaged in an exchange on recognition failure. Squire (1987) reviews the phys-
iology of memory, including a thorough discussion of amnesic dissociations.
Schacter (1987) provides a classic article reviewing the research on implicit
memory. Squire (1992) reviews the research on the role of the hippocampus in
human memory. Roediger (1990) also provides a review of the distinction
between implicit and explicit memory and discusses this distinction in terms of
the concept of transfer-appropriate processing. Reder (1996) contains a set of
recent papers on implicit memory. Tulving and Schacter (1990) discuss research
on priming and its relationship for various memory systems.
303
Skill Acquisition
Overview
The last four chapters, which have concentrated on the human memory system,
have ignored how our memories participate in a full functioning system. The
goal of the last three chapters of this book is to put the full system back togeth-
er. Figure 9.1 (a variation of Figure 5.1 cast more in the language of cognitive
psychology) shows how memory functions in a more general system to produce
adaptive cognitive function. Memory stores our knowledge of the world, but
there is the issue of how this knowledge is shaped in the first place and how that
knowledge is organized to produce adaptive behavior. This chapter will focus on
how the knowledge we learn is organized to provide skilled performance in var-
ious situations. The next chapter will look at how human inductive processes
play a major role in interpreting experiences to create useful memories. The final
chapter will consider how the whole system functions within an important
Environment
Instructions Experience Adaptive
cognitive functions
Human
Innate Mind Goal
constraints structures
304
Overview
305
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
Figure 9.3 shows how the time to make the edits to each page decreased
as a function of the number of days of practice. Subjects took an average of
almost 8 min per page on the first day, which became about 2 min per page by
the sixth day. This total time was divided into two categories. There were peri-
ods of time during which the subjects were not typing; any period of time when
more than 2 sec elapsed between keystrokes was classified as thinking time. The
remaining time, when keystrokes were produced at a rate of more than one
every 2 sec, was classified as keystroking time. Most of the reduction in time
resulted from a reduction in thinking time. Keystroking time was somewhat
reduced but not as a result of an improved rate of typing; rather, because the
subjects were making fewer errors and more efficient edits, they were produc-
ing fewer keystrokes. The subjects’ rates of keystroking remained constant
throughout the experiment at about two and a half keystrokes per second.
Figure 9.3 reflects the basic characteristics of many examples of skill acqui-
sition. Skill acquisition starts out with a large cognitive component. With prac-
tice, that cognitive component decreases. By day 6 shown in Figure 9.3, the
thinking component was reduced to taking the same amount of time as a motor
component (keystroking). As this chapter documents, with continued practice
306
Overview
8.0
6.0
o
oy
ion
5 /
7 4.0
£ Thinking
= time
=
2.0
307
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
solution,
to
Time
sec
20 40 60 80 100
Number of problems
(a)
2000
1000 ;—
iBfe}(oe)
a
Log,
sec
200 ;-—
100
2 4 10 20 40 100
Log problems
(b)
The fact that skill learning tends to display this continuous power law
learning may seem surprising. Over the course of many years of practice mak-
ing cigars, the skill itself undergoes rather dramatic shifts in the nature of its
performance, which might be expected to be mirrored by shifts in the learning
function. Anderson (1982) argued that the reason for the uniformity in the
learning function is that all the changes, including the qualitative changes,
depend on simple associative learning, which obeys a power law, as discussed
in Chapter 6. The complex skill obeys a power law because each of its compo-
nents does.
308
Overview
30
20
i)
oO
Pa
00
x)
°
d
£10
@
oO
oO Minimum machine
cycle time
5 (1 year) (7 year)
2.50
ov
o
2g
=(e}
§
2 1.00
@Qa
E
8
2
é
§ 0.50
FIGURE 9.6 Time to complete a book
as a function of practice, plotted with
logarithmic coordinates on both axes. 100 200 300 500
(From Ohlsson, 1992.) Number of books (log scale)
309
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
ee LALO LEER ENROLL MEN LL OLET LER INE EEE,
or instance, I slowly learned to coordinate releasing the clutch in first gear with
applying the gas so as not to kill the engine. Verbalization of the skill drops out
in this phase. I no longer rehearsed where second was, and I went to it much
more rapidly.
The third stage isthe autonomous stage,The skill becomes continuously
more automated and rapid, and cognitive involvement is gradually eliminated.
Sometimes a person even loses the ability to verbally describe the skill. In such
a case, the skill becomes totally a matter of implicit memory (see Chapter 8). An
interesting example involves my wife, who was teaching me how to shift gears.
She had completely forgotten whether the gas should be released when engag-
ing the clutch; that is, she could not say what she did, though her foot knew per-
fectly well what to do. When she wanted to find out what to tell me, she had to
assume the driver’s seat and see what she did.
This chapter is organized according to these three stages. These are not
discrete stages, but they characterize approximate points in the qualitative evo-
lution of a skill. The continuous nature of the power law improvement reviewed
in the previous section seems somewhat at odds with the fact that a skill under-
goes what amounts to a dramatic qualitative evolution. The apparent power law
improvement is probably only approximate; it is as good an approximation as it
is because associative learning (which also approximates a power function) gov-
erns the qualitative changes.
RETNA STANLEY
NIA TELLIN TT TIS
310
The Cognitive Stage
311
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
the existence of two principal mechanisms by which people and other organ-
isms select operators to perform tasks:
1. Difference reduction. People select operators that will eliminate differ-
ences between their current states and their goals. A simple case is when
a single operator transforms the current state into the goal state, such as a
bar press delivering food. Often the problem solver must settle for an
operator that removes a single difference between the current state and
the goal state. For instance, a subject in the text-editing experiment, faced
with the markedsup page shown in Figure 9.2, might choose to delete
“illustrates,” because this action would move the page one step closer to
the target state but leave more changes to be performed.
. Operator subgoaling. In the process of trying to achieve a goal, people set
subgoals when operators do not work because some precondition is not
satisfied. For example, the subject may want to delete a word but first must
find where that word is in the manuscript. Locating the word in the man-
uscript file becomes a subgoal to deleting it. A subgoal is a goal pursued
in service of a higher goal. This is the means—ends step in the Newell and
Simon theory of problem solving, which was discussed in Chaptert—
The next sections describe difference reduction and operator subgoaling in
human problem solving. These mechanisms are used to convert what one has
learned into adaptive behavior. Basically, we are addressing one aspect of the
motivation issues discussed in Chapter 4, but from a more cognitive perspective.
Difference Reduction
Difference reduction is a guiding force in many domains. When people try to get
ion to another, they choose moves that reduce their distance from
the goal. When I need to tidy up my office, I choose to tidy up part of it at a time,
confident that by eliminating differences one at a time between the current
office and a tidy office I will finally arrive at a tidy office.! More often than not,
problem solving that focuses on difference reduction is successful because we
can usually get from where we are to where we want to be by reducing the dif-
ferences. However, puzzles can be created that violate this general rule of
thumb. Sometimes the only way to solve a problem is to temporarily increase
the differences between the current state and the goal. Some of the best evi-
a2
The Cognitive Stage
On one side of a river are three hobbits and three orcs. There is a
rowboat on their side, but only two creatures can row across at a
time. All of them want to get to the other side of the river. At no
point can orcs outnumber hobbits on either side of the river (or the
orcs would eat the outnumbered hobbits). The problem, then, is for
the creatures to find a method of rowing back and forth in the boat
such that they all eventually get across and the hobbits are never
outnumbered by the orcs.
Figure 9.7 illustrates a solution to this problem. It represents where the hobbits
(H) are, where the orcs (O) are, and where the boat (b) is relative to the river,
which is the line. The transition between state 6 and state 7 is critical. On the far
side of the river in state 6 there are two hobbits and two orcs, whereas in state
7 there is only one hobbit and one orc. This transition goes against the grain of
difference reduction, but it is absolutely critical to solving the problem. Subjects
have particular difficulty with this move and often give up finding a solution at
this point (e.g., see Greeno, 1974; and Jeffries, Polson, Razran, & Atwood, 1977).
y PHHHOOO
Kane
HHOO
b HO
i
bHHHOO
O
Y
HHH
bOOO
‘i
bHHHO
HO
b HHOO
bHHOO
HO
00
bHHHO
g b_000
HHH
g
ni bOOHHH
313
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
Frequently, what makes a puzzle a puzzle is that it requires the problem solver
to temporarily abandon difference reduction.’
Difference reduction describes the approach to solving problems used by
almost all species. Even the simplest organisms have tropisms, which are ten-
dencies to approach various desired states. For instance, the wood louse (Gunn,
1937) continuously moves in the direction of moister areas because it will dehy-
drate if the air is too dry, and cockroaches flee light as a general defense mech-
anism. Organisms generally behave in a way that reduces the difference
between their current state and their goal state (“bliss point” in the language of
Chapter 4). To reiterate the theme from that earlier chapter, this tendency does
not mean that organisms consciously choose such operators (e.g., move from
light); it means only that they act as if they are choosing them.
Humans and other primates are capable of organizing their behavior in
ways that are more complex than difference reduction. This more complex
behavior is produced by operator subgoaling, the topic of the next section.
Operator Subgoaling
When humans set an operator subgoal, they suspend the attempt to achieve
their main goal and pursue the subgoal, which has no intrinsic value; its pursuit
is justified by the belief that it will help achieve the main goal. Most of the goals
people try to achieve, for example, good grades, are really subgoals in service of
higher goals, such as graduation from college, which in turn are in service of yet
higher goals. Tool building, a trait associated primarily with humans and to a
much lesser degree with higher primates, such as chimpanzees, is an exercise in
subgoaling. Creating a tool means creating an object whose justification is the
higher goals it helps achieve.
Tool building is almost unique to the human species. The only other species
that have been observed to engage in novel tool building to any significant extent
are the apes, particularly the chimpanzees. Chimpanzees have been observed to
make novel objects to serve as weapons, to shelter them from rain, and to reach
food (Beck, 1980). A clever episode (Kéhler, 1927) concerned a chimpanzee that
was trying to reach food outside its cage with two poles, each of which was too
short. Finally, the chimp fitted one pole inside the other and so made a compos-
ite pole long enough to reach the food. Figure 9.8 shows the chimpanzee at the
critical moment of insight. The chimpanzee already knew about sticks and reach-
ing for food from past experience and now put all its experiences together into a
*However, illustrating the general theme of skill acquisition, Greeno did find that
with repeated exposure to this problem students no longer found this move difficult.
314
The Cognitive Stage
PR
ee a ak ie ie ee
5 OI EERGINONeee
solution of a novel problem. Without the insight produced by this operator sub-
goaling, all of that past learning would have been useless.
It is significant that only the species closest to humans have been observed
to engage in novel tool building. This fact indicates that the capacity to learn to
handle goals and subgoals is a relatively species-specific skill, unlike many of the
phenomena reviewed in this book. The ability to engage in operator subgoaling
‘does not reflect, strictly speaking, a greater ability to learn; rather, it reflects a
greater ability to use what we have learned. Despite the accomplishments of
chimpanzees and other apes, humans far exceed them in the ability to manage
goal structures. It has been speculated that the process of handling goals is per-
formed by the frontal cortex of the brain (Anderson, 1993), a structure that is much
expanded in primates over most mammals and much expanded in humans over
primates. (For evidence of the critical role of the frontal cortex in working memo-
ry, see Chapter 5.) Memory for goals is a special kind of working memory.
A fair amount of research on the moment-to-moment dynamics of human
subgoal creation has been conducted using the Tower of Hanoi problem. (A
simple version of this problem is illustrated in Figure 9.9.) There are three pegs
and four disks of differing sizes. The disks have holes in them, so they can be
stacked on the pegs. The disks can be moved from any peg to any other peg.
Only the top disk on a peg can be moved, and it can never be placed on a small-
er disk. All the disks start out on peg A, but the goal is to move them all to peg
C, one disk at a time, by means of transferring disks among pegs.
315
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
A B C A B C
Disk Disk
oes » <—
eae eae
nag = 4
This problem can be mimicked with paper and coins. Draw three circles in
a row on a sheet of paper and place four coins (a quarter, a nickel, a penny, and
a dime) in order of sizein one circle. Your task is to move all of the coins to anoth-
er circle one at a time. The constraint is that you can never place a larger coin on
a smaller coin. This is an analogue of the Tower of Hanoi problem in which the
circles are the pegs and the coins are the disks. Try to solve this problem.
Table 9.1 attempts to illustrate the goals that have to be created to solve the
Tower of Hanoi problem using a subgoaling approach. At the beginning the
focus is on the biggest difference, which is to move disk 4 from peg A to peg C.
Disk 4 is blocked by disk 3, which is on top of it. A subgoal is created to move
disk 3 out of the way to peg B. But movement of disk 3 is blocked by disk 2, and
a subgoal is created to move it out of the way to peg C. To move disk 2, a subgoal
is created to move disk 1 out of the way to peg B. This goal can be achieved
directly by a move, and this is the first move made in Table 9.1. Before this move
could be made, four subgoals had to be created. After each move in Table 9.1, the
number of goals necessary before that move could occur is given in parentheses.
Subjects are often quite explicit about their subgoaling. Consider the fol-
lowing protocol of a subject (Neves, 1977) who was faced with the Tower of
Hanoi problem shown in Figure 9.10. This is the problem in an intermediate
state, with disks 1 and 2 moved off peg 1. The subject chose to move disk 1 to
peg 3, but before doing so gave the following justification of the choice.?
The 4 has to go to the 3. But the 3 is in the way. So you have to move
the 3 to the 2 post. The 1 is in the way there. So you move the 1 to
thers.
The subject began by setting the subgoal to remove the largest difference
between the goal and the current state—“The 4 has to go to the 3.”The opera-
tor to move this disk was blocked by the precondition that there could be noth-
ing on disk 4. The subject then saw a subgoal of getting disk 3 out of the way;
this was the second subgoal. To achieve this subgoal, the subject had to set a
third subgoal—to get disk 1 off peg 2. This third subgoal was actually governing
the move that the subject made. The second and third subgoals were operator
subgoals that would enable moves; in contrast, the first goal was a difference
reduction goal designed to get a disk to the target peg.
3 In this protocol the subject is using digits to refer to pegs as well as disks; see Figure
9:10;
316
The Cognitive Stage
TABLE 9.1 Goals, Subgoals, and Moves in Solving the Tower of Hanoi Problem
(Moves are numbered)
Difference Reduction Goal: Move disk 4 to Peg C
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 3 out of the way to Peg B
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 2 out of the way to Peg C
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 1 out of the way to Peg B
Move disk 1 to Peg B (4 goals)
Move disk 2 to Peg C (0 goals)
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 1 out of the way to Peg C
Move disk 1 to Peg C (1 goal)
Move disk 3 to Peg B (0 goals)
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 2 out of the way to Peg B
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 1 out of the way to Peg A
Move disk 1 to Peg A (2 goals)
Move disk 2 to Peg B (0 goals)
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 1 out of the way to Peg B
Move disk 1 to Peg B (1 goal)
Move disk 4 to Peg C (0 goals)
Difference Reduction Goal: Move disk 3 to Peg C
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 2 out of the way to Peg A
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 1 out of the way to Peg C
Move disk 1 to Peg C (3 goals)
10. Move disk 2 to Peg A (0 goals)
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 1 out of way to Peg A
11, Move disk 1 to Peg A (1 goal)
12. Move disk 3 to Peg C (0 goals)
Difference Reduction Goal: Move disk 2 to Peg C
Operator Subgoal: Move disk 1 out of the way to Peg B
{keh Move disk 1 to Peg B (2 goals)
14. Move disk 2 to Peg C (0 goals)
Difference Reduction Goal: Move disk 1 to Peg C
a5: Move disk 1 to Peg C (0 goals)
Although Neves’s experiment gave verbal evidence that one subject might
have used subgoaling once, it did not address the issue of how prevalent this
strategy was in solving the Tower of Hanoi problem. Anderson, Kushmerick, and
Lebiere (1993) examined the problem solving of a large number of subjects and
Disk 3
FIGURE 9.10 The state of the Tower of Hanoi problem facing the subject whose
protocol was reported in Neves (1977).
317
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
—e Goals
—= Sec
of
Number
goals
2 4 6 8 TO S12 4
Move
FIGURE 9.11 A comparison of the number of goals and latencies associated with
the steps of solving the Tower of Hanoi problem illustrated in Figure 9.8. The left axis
gives the number of goals, and the right axis gives latencies in seconds. (From
Anderson et al., 1993.)
determined how many subgoals subjects had to set before each move if they
were engaged in operator subgoaling. This number was inferred by assuming
that the subjects were using an optimal subgoaling strategy to solve the prob-
lem. Fifteen moves were required to solve the problem. For each move the num-
ber of subgoals was determined from Table 9.1, and the average amount of time
the subject took to make the move was calculated. Figure 9.11 shows the rela-
tionship between these two measures. The time to make a move strongly mir-
rored the number of subgoals that had to be set. It appears that goal setting is a
major determinant of problem-solving time.
The evidence for such goal structure involvement occurs only when we are
solving novel problems. As we practice the same problem over and over again,
we learn the solution and can simply retrieve it without going through the sub-
goaling to discover it. For instance, Ruiz.(1987) found that the latency peaks like
those in Figure 9.11 disappeared as subjects practiced solving the problem. The
next section, on the associative stage, is concerned with how we come to mem-
orize solutions to problems.
NOY SNE
318
The Associative Stage
Given: 21 and
22 are right angles
R S JS =Ks
Prove: ARSJ = ARSK
FIGURE 9.12 The first geometry proof problem that a student encounters that
requires the side-angle-side postulate. (From J. R. Anderson, 1982.)
319
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
by, Given: 21 = 22
ip athe! 45E 56
BK =CK
2» Prove: AABK = ADCK
c
D be
FIGURE 9.13. The sixth geometry proof problem encountered after studying the
side-side-side and side-angle-side postulates. (From J. R. Anderson, 1982.)
After solving two more problems by means of side-angle-side (and two by side-
side-side), the student faced the more difficult problem illustrated in Figure
9.13. The method-recognition portion of the protocol follows:
Right off the top of my head I am going to take a guess at what Iam
supposed to do: Angle DCK is congruent to Angle ABK. There is only
one of two and the side-angle-side postulate is what they are getting
to. (Anderson, 1982, p. 382)
The contrast between these protocols is striking. The student no longer had to
verbally rehearse the postulate and search for correspondence between it and
specific pieces of the problem. Rather, the student simply recognized the applic-
ability of the rule. Because the application of the protocol switched to a pattern
recognition, there was no longer a need to hold information in a rehearsal
buffer, and so there were not the frequent failures of working memory when the
student lost track of what he was trying to do. This is part of what is involved in
reducing the cognitive component in a skill. Much of the effort that went into
recognizing an appropriate problem-solving operator (in this case side-angle-
side) has disappeared.
320
The Associative Stage
—- 4 Addend
== 3 Addend
—e 2 Addend
(sec.)
Latency
321
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
Production Rules
Numerous researchers (e.g., Anderson, 1983; Bovair, Kieras, & Polson, 1990;
Newell, 1991) have postulated that much of the knowledge underlying a cogni-
tive skill takes the form of what are called production rules. The following pro-
duction rule corresponds to the recognition of the applicability of the side-
angle-side postulate:
IF the goal is to prove that triangle 1 is congruent to triangle 2,
and triangle 1 has two sides and an included angle
that appear congruent to the two sides and included angle of
triangle 2
THEN set as subgoals to prove that the corresponding sides and angles
are congruent
and then to use the side-angle-side postulate to prove that
triangle 1 is congruent to triangle 2.
322
The Associative Stage
A production rule contains a condition in its IF part, which specifies when the
rule is to apply. In its THEN part is an action, which specifies what to do in that
situation. Rules like this correspond to the basic steps of solving a problem, and
a complex cognitive skill involves many of these rules. As described in Chapter
11, the competence needed to do proofs in high school geometry involves many
hundreds of such rules.
One consequence of transforming knowledge into a production rule form
is that use of the knowledge becomes asymmetrical. Singley and Anderson
(1989) studied the development of asymmetry in rule application by looking at
the relationship between differentiation and integration in calculus. The exper-
iment involved calculus rules, such as the rule for powers:
323
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
“Frequently cited as an exception to this generalization is Mozart, who wrote his first
symphony when he was 8 years old. However, his early works are not of genius cal-
iber and are largely of historical value only. Schonberg (1970) claimed that Mozart’s
great works were produced after the twentieth year of his career.
324
The Autonomous Stage
325
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
to drive, initially they need to pay all their attention to driving and they are
unable to maintain a conversation. As they become more practiced, they are able
to maintain a conversation while driving. The driving skill becomes so automat-
ic that it seems to require no attention at all, at least when driving conditions are
not demanding. People report driving miles on a highway without recalling any-
thing of what they did. )
Spelke, Hirst, and Neisser (1976) reported an interesting experimental
demonstration of the growth of automaticity. Their subjects performed an odd pair
of tasks simultaneously. The first task was to read a text for comprehension. The
second was to transcribé\(without looking at what they were writing) material that
was being spoken. At first, subjects found this a difficult combination of tasks. Their
comprehension of the text suffered dramatically. The rate at which they read also
slowed down dramatically. Over a six-week period they gradually improved their
speed of reading until they were reading at preexperimental speeds without any
loss of comprehension. However, they showed almost no ability to remember what
they were transcribing, just as someone loses memory for what happens on the
road if engrossed in conversation. Spelke et al. were able to show that, with even
further practice, subjects could also remember what they were transcribing.
Two key features characterize a skill when it becomes totally automatized:
it can be performed without engaging the cognitive system, freeing the person
to pursue other cognitive goals in a dual-task situation; and it becomes less
interruptible. When learning to shift gears, for instance, a driver can choose to
stop at any point in the process, but once the driver is proficient, the shifts are
produced in one fluid motion and it is difficult to stop at a particular point. Skills
develop these two features because more and more of the skill becomes imple-
mented as a motor program and less and less is performed at a cognitive level.
The next section discusses motor programs.
Shin PARTE LETTS
326
The Autonomous Stage
waits for feedback from one action before taking the next action. A thermostat
that controls a furnace is an example. After turning the furnace on, it waits until
the temperature reaches the target level before turning the furnace off. An open-
loop system executes a fixed sequence of actions without checking to see that
the earlier actions achieved their intended effects. Old-fashioned copiers
worked this way; they continued to feed paper after a jam had occurred. Modern
copiers are closed loop and sense whether there is a paper jam.
Motor programs are open-loop segments of behavior. They are typically
embedded in a larger, closed-loop structure, as in the case of a typist who may
encode a familiar sequence of letters, type them in a closed-loop fashion, check,
encode, execute, and so on. Also, what might be open-loop at a higher neural
level is often closed-loop at a lower neural level. For instance, this section
reviews the evidence that the cortex issues open-loop instructions to the effect
that a hand should push and does not provide further monitoring. Closed-loop
circuits at the level of the spinal cord monitor the execution of these commands.
Schmidt (1988b) cited three lines of evidence for the existence of open-
loop motor programs at the cortical level. One is the slowness of closed-loop
behavior. It takes about 200 msec for information to be perceived from the envi-
ronment and registered in the cortex and for an appropriate reaction to be
taken. (This estimate comes from the fact that the shortest simple reaction time
is about 200 msec.) People are capable of executing actions much faster. Skilled
pianists can perform as many as 16 finger movements per sec. There is no time
for the person to sense the result of one movement before executing the next.
Schmidt’s second argument is that movements appear to be planned in
advance. As the complexity of the movement increases, it takes longer to initi-
ate the movement. If a typist is shown a single word and has to type it, the time
from the presentation of the word to the first keystroke increases with the
length of the word (Salthouse, 1985, 1986). The delay that increases with pro-
gram complexity reflects the time needed to prepare the open-loop program.
The third argument comes from the results of deafferentation studies of
monkeys (e.g., Taub & Berman, 1968). The deafferentation procedure eliminates
sensory input by cutting through the dorsal roots of the spinal cords. It does not
affect motor signals to the effectors. This procedure creates an organism that can
move its limbs but has lost all sensory feedback from them. Such animals are
still capable of learning to perform complex actions and then performing them
in the dark (lights out) so that they cannot receive any visual input to guide the
limbs. These animals receive no sensory feedback, and yet their limbs execute
learned sequences, such as moving a hand to a lever.
There is evidence that at a certain point the instructions in the motor pro-
gram are sent to the effectors (muscles) and the response cannot be stopped.
Skilled typists type the next few characters after being told to stop (Salthouse,
1985, 1986). In a study by Slater-Hammel (1960), subjects watched the hand of
a sweep timer that made one revolution per second. They were supposed to stop
the movement by lifting a finger from a key when the hand reached a certain
position. To do this successfully, they had to send a signal to their hand in antic-
327
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
ipation of it reaching the target location. Occasionally, the timer hand stopped
before it reached the target position, and the subjects were to inhibit lifting their
fingers. If the timer hand stopped at least 250 msec before reaching the target
position, the subjects were able to stop their movement, but when it stopped
less than 150 msec before the target, the subjects were unable to stop lifting
their fingers. Subjects reported that they saw the clock stop and their hands
responded anyway, as if they had no control over their hands.
Global control of behavior is a closed-loop routine that calls many open-loop
motor programs. A tennis player responds to where the ball is by positioning the
body and choosing the ténnis stroke. Once the stroke begins its execution, it large-
ly runs in an open loop. A person composing at a typewriter may deliberately
choose a word and then type it in an open-loop manner. The closed-loop phase
involves the more deliberative processes of the cognitive and associative stages.
What has been totally routinized gets packaged into open-loop motor programs.
Successful performance depends on being able to assign much of the behavior to
these open-loop segments that do not require cognitive monitoring. For instance,
successful tennis is very much a game of strategy in terms of positioning on the
court and choosing where to place the shots. Professional players can focus on this
strategy because the actual process of executing a tennis shot has been automated.
Noncognitive Control
There can be nonconscious control over the execution of a behavior. As a skill
develops, more and more of the control shifts to this nonconscious level. A good
fraction (but hardly all) of this nonconscious control is performed by neural
structures that are below the cortex. In one experiment, Dewhurst (1967) had
subjects hold a light weight at a particular angle. When the weight ddenly
changed, compensating activity could be rec in the muscles j Sgc
atter the change. [his activity was initiated in the spinal cord where the senso-
ry neurons synapse onto the motor neurons.
— = : 4
The spinal cord”knew”
e to be held in a certain position and began to take compensato
action as soon as a change occurred.
Other motor controf takes € above the spinal cord but still at a sub-
conscious level. This control occurs in-both the cortex and the cerebellum. The
cerebellum in the brain stem is particularly important in motor control (see
Figure 1.15). The Dewhurst study demonstrated another compensating reflex to
pressure changes that took about 80 msec. Unlike the spinal reflex, this reflex
was to some degree instructable. If the person was told to let go when there was
increased pressure, there was no compensatory response at 80 msec, but the
spinal 30 msec reflex still occurred. This 80 msec is still much quicker than the
200 msec for conscious reaction time.
328
The Autonomous Stage
320
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
330
The Autonomous Stage
feo]
i
Ss
00
RD
x n
eh
§ s 2 s&
Seb dy tee,oS 153
~ x x
ee
8 oe Ee a he
O.) Gave ue) oo
cayactce—>
(1)(2)(2)(4)(5)(6)
Ac
~)
Celery,
ator
dow,
FIGURE 9.16 Keele’s proposal for the process by which individual components of
the gearshift change become composed into a single production. Source: From R. A.
Schmidt, motor control and learning: a behavioral emphasis, Third Edition (p. 477)
Champaign, IL: Human Kinetics, copyright’© 1999. Reprinted by permission of
Richard A. Schmidt and T. D. Lee.
the skill of shifting gears. The process starts out as individual actions, such as
lifting the foot, which the person presumably already knows. Eventually, these
actions become packaged into an overall behavior, which is shifting gears.
It seems that different regions of the brain are involved as the performance
of a sequence of actions becomes organized into a motor plan. Jenkins, Brooks,
Nixon, Frackowiak, and Passingham (1994) studied subjects learning to execute
a sequence of eight button presses and the researchers imaged which regions of
the brain were active. Figure 9.17 illustrates the results. Early in learning the lat-
eral prefrontal area, associated with planning in general, and the posterior parietal
cortex, associated with motor planning (Andersen, 1995) in particular, were
highly active. However, with practice the more active areas became the supple-
mental motor area, which is responsible for guidance of action, and the hip-
pocampus, which is responsible for retrieval of memories. It appears that the
sequence no longer has to be planned but rather can be retrieved and directly
executed.
331
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
Premotor
Supplemental cortex Parietal
motor area cortex
Occipital
regions
Lateral
prefrontal
cortex
Hippocampus
Cerebellum
elaborated by Schmidt (1988b) in his schema theory. Schmidt holds that the
learner develops two representations of the skill. One, called the recall memory,
is the motor program itself—a prepackaged sequence of actions. The second,
called the recognition memory, is a representation of the desired outcome of the
action in terms of both the response-produced feedback and the external sen-
sory consequences. A player taking a basketball shot can compare the outcome
with the ideal (recognition memory) and adjust the motor program (recall
memory) appropriately.
Schmidt emphasizes that neither the recall memory nor the recognition
memory is for a specific action but rather is for a class of actions. Different
actions can be achieved from the same motor program by evoking it with dif-
ferent parameters. A person can throw a ball a novel distance, having been
trained on specific distances, by extrapolating the forces used for the training
distances to the force needed for the new distance. In numerous studies, sub-
jects have been trained to perform a skill that involves different positions or to
react to objects at different speeds (see Shapiro & Schmidt, 1982, for a review).
People show considerably greater success in extrapolating to new values if they
have practiced with a variety of values.
332
The Autonomous Stage
1200
1000
334
The Autonomous Stage
an internal representation, and the motor program is corrected after each trial.
It is not necessary to have feedback after every trial to build up this internal rep-
resentation of what the skill is like. Occasional information about how the per-
formance is progressing is sufficient to update the representation of the desired
behavior.
Is it better to give only intermittent feedback for other learning tasks
besides motor skills? What about academic learning tasks? As Schmidt and
Bjork (1992) lamented, there has not been a great deal of research on this topic.
Schooler and Anderson (1990) did one study of the acquisition of computer pro-
gramming skill, which showed that at least sometimes feedback disrupts the
learning. While students try to understand the feedback, they lose track of
where they are in the problem.
Wulf, Schmidt, and Deubel (1993) pointed out that learning a motor pro-
gram really involves two components: learning the general structure of the pro-
gram and learning how to parameterize the program. They looked at subjects
making the sinusoidal movements illustrated in Figure 9.19. All the movements
in Figure 9.19a illustrate the same general program. The only difference is the
timing of the up and down movements. Similarly, all the movements in Figure
9.19b reflect the same program and vary only in the force with which the up and
down movements are made. Wulf et al. contrasted intermittent feedback (63
70 80
)
oD
oO
no}
oO
no)
ee
=
27
Amplitude,
degrees
&y7®
12 10
0 908
¢)
P bese, Time, msec
Time, msec
(a) (b)
FIGURE 9.19 (a) A set of actions reflecting the same motor routine but varying in
timing; (b) a set of actions reflecting the same motor routine but varying in force.
Source: From G. Wulf, R. A. Schmidt, and H. Deubel. Reduced feedback frequency
enhances generalized motor program learning but not parameterization learning.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, Volume 19.
Copyright © 1993 by the American Psychological Association. Reprinted by permis-
sion.
335
CHAPTER 9 Skill Acquisition
percent of the time) with constant feedback (100 percent of the time). They
developed separate measures of whether the subjects had learned the general
pattern of the movement and whether they had learned the precise timing and
force of one of these movements. They found that learning the general move-
ment was better with intermittent feedback. However, learning the timing and
the force was as good, and even a little better, with constant feedback.
Final Reflections
This chapter has followed the process of skill learning from its initial organiza-
tion in the first performances to the point at which the detail of the performance
of a task is lost to cognition and becomes embedded in motor programs. The
production rule is the key construct unifying the course of skill acquisition.
Production rules embody the organization placed on the cognitive skills by the
problem-solving processes during the cognitive stage. The development of the
336
Further Readings
skill in the associative stage can be decomposed into the learning histories of
the many component production rules. A motor program is essentially the
action (or THEN) part of a production rule, and its learning in the autonomous
stage amounts to the fine-tuning of a production rule.
Several studies of transfer among skills indicate that the degree of trans-
fer is a function of the overlap between the skills in terms of production rules.
As a person becomes more advanced in a domain, the person acquires addi-
tional production rules that take advantage of the special characteristics of that
domain. One consequence of this specialization of skills is that there is less and
less transfer among skills as the skills become more advanced (Henry, 1968).
The picture of learning from the skill-acquisition literature is much more
complex than the picture painted in the early chapters of animal learning and
human memory. Skill acquisition is concerned with behaviors of true signifi-
cance that develop over scales of time more typical of learning outside the lab-
oratory. Problem-solving organization has a role in human (and probably pri-
mate) skill acquisition that was not apparent in the simpler laboratory studies of
learning. However, the processes of learning and strengthening apply to the
component production rules much as they apply to the learning seen in the sim-
pler laboratory studies.
Further Readings
The book by Newell and Simon (1972) remains a classic on problem solving. The
artificial intelligence perspective on problem solving can be found in Russell &
Norvig (1995). Research on cognitive skill acquisition is reviewed in Anderson
(1990) and Van Lehn (1989). Singley and Anderson (1989) review production
rule theories of skill acquisition and transfer with a particular discussion of text
editing. Klahr, Langley, and Neches (1987) review production system theories of
skill acquisition. Newell (1991) describes his SOAR theory, and the ACT theory
is described in Anderson and Lebiere (1998). Rosenbaum (1991) and Schmidt
(1988b, 1991) discuss motor performance and motor learning, and Schmidt
includes an exposition of his schema theory. A comparison of motor learning
and verbal learning is found in the work of Schmidt and Bjork (1992). The sec-
ond half of the book edited by Osherson, Kosslyn, and Hollerbach (1990) con-
sists of a series of review chapters on motor behavior and motor programs.
337
Inductive Learning
Overview
Most laboratory research on human learning has studied learning in a setting
that is much like a traditional classroom. Subjects are supposed to learn basic
facts or skills and are trained until these facts or skills are mastered. This sort of
paradigm is useful for understanding the principles of memory, but it ignores a
critical component of learning—determining just what it is that should be
learned. This component looms large in the conditioning experiments where the
organism has to determine what controls the appearance of a reinforcer. Figures
5.1 and 9.1 show that a critical inductive component determines how experience
gets represented in memory. Induction refers to the process by which the sys-
tem makes probable inferences about the environment on the basis of experi-
ence. For instance, in a typical conditioning experiment the inductive compo-
nent figures out what caused what. In contrast, the need for this process is large-
ly bypassed by the use of instructions in a memory experiment.
Much of human learning avoids the need for induction because many fea-
tures of our environment are understood and we can be directly instructed on
them. Still, a significant fraction of human learning involves induction. We have
to figure out what things annoy or please an acquaintance. We have to figure out
how to operate many appliances without direct instruction. Children manage a
great deal of learning without instruction. For instance, they figure out which
animals are dogs and which are cats without being told what makes an animal
a dog or a cat. Perhaps most impressive, they learn to speak their first language
without direct instruction.
Learning the structure and rules of a particular domain without direct
instruction is referred to as inductive learning. Inductive learning involves
making uncertain inferences from experience. Suppose that you come upon a
microwave oven and press 1 followed by start on its button panel. You observe
that the oven runs for exactly 60 sec. You might make the inference that press-
338
Overview
ing the 1 caused it to run for 1 min and that pressing the 2 would cause it to run
for 2 min. This conclusion is an inductive inference. It may not be correct—the
1 may control the power level at which the oven operates—but supposé your
inference is correct. Now you want to run the oven for 10 min, but there are only
buttons with the digits 0 through 9. What do you do? You might infer that press-
ing a 1 followed by a 0 would achieve the goal. This is another inductive infer-
ence. What if you want the device to operate for only 30 sec? You might notice
a button labeled seconds and infer that pressing seconds before pressing 3 and
0 would yield the desired effect. What if you want to have it run 2 min and 20
sec? What if you want it to run at half intensity? By a process of hypothesis and
test, you would probably come to an understanding of how the device functions.
The total episode is an example of inductive learning.
Philosophers make a contrast between induction and deduction. In
deduction, inferences are logically certain, whereas in induction they are not. If
told that an animal is a poodle, a person can infer with certainty that the animal
is a dog. This type of inference is a deductive inference because all poodles are
dogs. If an animal is heard barking, a person might also infer that the animal is
a dog. This is an inductive inference, because it is conceivable that some other
animal might bark. As this example makes clear, inductive inference really adds
something to knowledge and so counts as a kind of learning. In contrast, there
is a sense in which deductive inference adds nothing but only makes explicit
what is already known.
An element of inductive learning is involved in nearly every learning situ-
ation—even direct instruction. A tennis coach illustrates how to hold the racket
for a two-handed backhand but leaves the player to figure out which aspects of
the demonstration are the critical aspects. A geometry teacher works through
the steps of a proof and usually does not tell the students why an inference is
made at one point rather than another—the student must figure it out. In
English class a teacher marks a sentence as awkward—but what aspect of the
sentence is awkward?
Much of what the earlier chapters reviewed about conditioning was con-
cerned with inductive learning. Here we return to these earlier issues but focus
more on human inductive learning. The chapter addresses the topics of concept
formation, causal inference, and language acquisition, three types of human
inductive learning that have received much research. It reveals that the induc-
tive learning required of people can be very tricky indeed. This chapter also
reviews the arguments that it would be impossible for children to learn a lan-
guage unless they were born knowing a great deal about language already and
that language acquisition is a uniquely human ability.
_
EREDAR NIRA ER IES AMAL
ESEAN REN ELLIE wets
339
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
Concept Acquisition
Concept acquisition research is concerned with how we learn natural cate-
gories, such as“ dog,” “chair,” “car,” and “tree.” It is not particularly obvious how
children learn what separates a dog from a cat or a chair from a table. Adults
have difficulty articulating the difference between these concepts—how do chil-
dren figure it out? The mystery of this learning process is intensified by the fact
that most of it happens in childhood when the learners are not particularly
articulate. However, concept learning does extend to adulthood. When I visited
Australia, I learned new animal concepts, such as “echidna” and “kookaburra,”
and I learned to recognize a number of categories of birds for which I never did
learn the verbal labels. It is no more clear to me how I learned to recognize these
animals than it is to a child how he or she comes to recognize a dog. However,
researchers have used a number of different approaches to shed light on what
is involved in learning a new concept. Much of this research has been done with
adult subjects.
A major issue in this research concerns the degree to which concept acqui-
sition is like the associative learning characteristic of conditioning experiments.
An early experiment by Hull (1920) suggested that concept learning is like con-
ditioning. His subjects learned to categorize different Chinese alphabet charac-
ters, such as those shown in Figure 10.1; each row reflects a different concept
Radical
(concept) List 1 Liste2 List 3 List 4 List 5 List 6
SRVRS &ES
B
UdOF
Dw
Say
Ws SynN SS
Qe
FY
ch
Sh&Se
OR
ny
SS Pe Ba
RY
Vt
eo
me
FIGURE 10.1 Example of stimulus material used by Hull (1920). Each row repre-
ey a category defined by the presence of the Chinese radical. Source: From C. L.
ull. Quantitative aspects of the evolution of concepts: An experimental study. Copyright
© 1920 in the Public Domain. ‘ 4 ee
340
Concept Acquisition
defined by the presence of a Chinese radical. Subjects were not informed about
the critical feature. Gradually, they learned how to classify the stimuli, but they
were quite incapable of saying what they did to classify these stimuli. Hull con-
cluded that concepts are learned by simple associative learning.
Since Hull’s research, the field has vacillated in terms of how to think about
the nature of human concept learning, moving full circle from Hull’s position to
regarding human concept learning as dramatically opposed to associative learn-
ing, back to seeing much in common between the two types of learning.
Concept-Identification Studies
A new view about human concept learning began with a classic series of exper-
iments by Bruner, Goodnow, and Austin (1956). Figure 10.2 illustrates the kind
of material they used. Eighty-one stimuli varied along four possible dimensions:
number of objects (one, two, or three); number of borders (one, two, or three);
shape of objects (cross, circle, or square); and color of objects (green, black, or
red—shown as white, black and grey). There were three possible values on each
of the four dimensions and thus 3 x 3 x 3 x 3 = 81 possible ob =ects. Subjects were
Hig
8®@
3+] [sll°
ap oP oP ©©O
EEG
=
AIC
FEERIEEEE
lelSET (EEE
eteielel
oP
EIEIEIE)
8)0)
60/8] oO
ot ot at
HiB/o
QEIERLEEE
OOO O OO ap ap ¢F ©@@
FIGURE 10.2 Material used by Bruner et al. (1956) to study concept identification.
Source: From J. S. Bruner, J. J. Goodnow, and G. A. Austin. A study of thinking.
Copyright © 1956 by J. S. Bruner et al., p. 42. Reprinted by permission...
341
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
told that there was some concept that referred to a specific subset of the objects,
for instance, all green squares. Subjects were instructed to discover the concept
and were shown various stimuli identified as members or not members of the
concept. When they thought they knew what the concept was, they could
announce the concept.
Given the research of Hull and others, psychologists had thought of con-
cept learning as involving the simple associative learning processes discussed in
the conditioning chapters. Thus, for the concept of “green squares,” “green” and
“square” would gradually get associated to the category. Bruner et al. and sub-
sequent researchers fottnd evidence that subjects engaged in conscious hypoth-
esis testing. This research helped fuel the cognitive revolution against the pre-
vailing behaviorist paradigm. Before describing the results of this research, it is
important to identify its methodological features.
The Bruner et al. paradigm is somewhat different from concept learning in
real life. For instance, people normally do not suddenly announce that they have
a new concept. A person displays knowledge of the concept “dog” by success-
fully classifying new instances as dogs. Research subsequent to that of Bruner et
al. has used successful classification behavior as evidence for knowing the con-
cept; that is, if the subjects could correctly categorize new instances, they were
credited with having the concept.
Another dimension of the experimental design is whether subjects select
instances to get information about or whether they receive a series of instances
classified for them. The former paradigm is called the selection paradigm, and
the latter the reception paradigm. Subjects in a selection paradigm can behave
more like a scientist and select instances to test their current hypothesis about
what the concept is. Learning in the reception paradigm is more like learning
concepts in the real world, where we encounter instances and noninstances of
categories, with little control over which instances we encounter. Although
Bruner et al. studied both paradigms, subsequent research has tended to focus
on the reception paradigm.
Figure 10.3 contains three examples of what subjects might see. Each col-
umn contains a sequence of objects associated with a different category. A plus
sign (+) beside the object means it is a member of the category, and a minus sign
(-) means it is not. Subjects are presented with these instances one at a time.
You should try to figure out the category represented by each column.
The category for the first column is“two crosses,” for the second column,
“two borders or circles,” and for the third column,”“number of borders equals
number of objects.” The first category probably seems the most natural. It is
referred to as a conjunctive concept because it requires that all of a set of features
be present. The second is called a disjunctive concept because it only requires that
at least one member of a set of features be present. The third is called a relation-
al concept because it involves a relationship among the dimensions. Subjects find
conjunctive concepts much easier than disjunctive or relational concepts and
learn them after seeing fewer instances (Bourne, 1974; Bourne, Ekstrand, &
Dominowski, 1971).
342
Concept Acquisition
eS oP |
Hypothesis Testing
These tasks are not all that different from conditioning experiments (Chapters 2
through 4) in which the organisms must figure out what features in the envi-
ronment are controlling reinforcement. The earlier chapters reviewed the evi-
dence that organisms tend to strengthen associations between various features
in the environment and responses. One feature of their learning is that it is
gradual. In contrast, human learning in these experiments seems to be anything
but gradual. Bruner et al. characterized their subjects as engaging in hypothe-
sis testing. Subjects have specific hypotheses, such as“I think it is three cross-
es,”and they may completely change their hypothesis from one trial to the next.
Bruner et al. characterized hypothesis testing as following roughly these steps:
1. Pick some hypothesis consistent with the instances that have been
encountered. (In some experiments the instances are arrayed in front of
343
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
344
Concept Acquisition
100
ol fo)
FIGURE 10.4 Probability of
classifying an instance as a func-
Percent
successes
tion of trial in the typical concept-
identification experiment. The
probabilities in this hypothetical P | | | |
curve have been averaged over 5 10 15 20 25 30
subjects. Trials
100
90
®72)
2)
n
o
rs} eve | °
phy
Ss
we
A
e
a eae
e
ir ey
po
Oo
o
oO
{o)
te
Single trials
345
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
8, trial 2would come from trial 7, and so on; finally, trial 8 would come from trial
1. For another subject whose last error was on trial 21, trial 1 in Figure 10.5
would come from trial 20, trial 2 would come from trial 19, and so on; finally,
trial 20 would come from trial 1.1 Thus, trial 1 is the trial just before the last error
for all subjects, trial 2 is the second trial before the last error for all subjects, and
so on. The curve illustrated in Figure 10.5 is called a backwards learning curve.
If each subject had been gradually learning the concept, this backwards
learning curve would gradually improve as it approached trial 1 (the trial before
the last error for all subjects). However, probability correct hovers around the
chance level of 50 percent right up to the trial just before the last error (trial 1 in
Figure 10.5). These data are good evidence for all-or-none learning. That is, on
the last error subjects made a complete switch from a wrong hypothesis, which
was yielding chance performance, to the correct one, which yielded perfect per-
formance. This analysis contains a significant lesson: an average learning curve
(Figure 10.4) that apparently displays gradual learning can actually be hiding
all-or-none learning, which can be uncovered by a backwards learning curve
(Figure 10.5).
Natural Concepts
Research on hypothesis testing was in its heyday during the 1960s. After that
time there was increased questioning of what these laboratory experiments on
concept acquisition revealed about human learning of natural categories, such
as “dog” or “tree.” Subjects approach such experimentswith a problem-solving
orientation, which does not seem to be how natural categories are learned. This
approach certainly appears too sophisticated and conscious for children learn-
ing in a natural environment. Moreover, it has been argued (Rosch, 1973, 1975,
1977) that natural categories are not the sorts of things that have the all-or-none
logical structure of these laboratory categories. One of the major characteristics
of natural categories is that they are not defined by the presence of a few fea-
tures. Rather, many features tend to be associated with the category, and an
instance is a member of a category to the degree that it possesses these charac-
teristic features. For example, birds are characteristically of a certain size and can
fly. However, an ostrich, which cannot fly and is very large, is recognized as a
bird because it has other birdlike features, such as feathers, wings, and a beak.
Even though an ostrich can be recognized as a bird, a person seeing one for the
first time might certainly hesitate in making the classification.
1One consequence of this process is that fewer and fewer subjects contribute to trials
that are more and more removed from the trial of last error.
346
Concept Acquisition
347
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
348
Concept Acquisition
The next two sections describe examples of these two kinds of theories and how
they can be tested.
349
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
lar) would be associated with category A and the features (two objects, small,
blue, and circular) would be associated with category B. Consider how it would
respond to the stimuli:
1. One large red triangle (in category A): 4A features, 0 B features
2. Two small red triangles (in category A): 2A features, 2 B features
3. One large blue circle (in category A): 2A features, 2 B features
4. Two small blue circles (in category B): 0A features, 4 B features
5. One large red circle (in category B): 3A features, 1 B feature
6. Two small blue ciréles (in category B): 1A feature, 3 B features
If the subjects adopted the rule to classify in category A all stimuli with two or
more A features, they would correctly classify all but stimulus 5. The
Rescorla-Wagner rule cannot correctly categorize stimulus 5 because it contains
more A features than B features. To deal with such problems, Gluck and Bower
proposed that subjects use configural stimuli. For instance, subjects might asso-
ciate the feature combination of red plus circle with category B. Chapter 2 dis-
cussed how it was necessary to augment the Rescorla-Wagner theory with con-
figural stimuli to account for results in the conditioning literature. The same his-
tory of theories that appeared in the conditioning literature is being played out
in this categorization research.
The Gluck and Bower theory illustrates the apparent cyclic character of
theories in psychology. Psychologists such as Hull originally proposed using
strength-of-association theories to account for human concept formation.
Subsequent research on hypothesis testing in concept formation indicated that
categories were learned in a more all-or-none manner than envisioned in those
theories. Later researchers questioned whether the concepts learned in the
experiments were like natural concepts. When the learning of natural concepts
was studied, the process of learning appeared to be much more similar to that
proposed by Hull.
350
Concept Acquisition
TABLE 10.3 Calculation of the Similarity of One Large, Blue Triangle to Each
Study Stimulus in Table 10.2
Number Size Color Shape Similarity
Category A
Study Item 1 1 x 1 x 12. x 1 = .200
Category A
Study Item 2 se x ea. x 2 x it = .008
Category A
Study Item 3 il x 1 x 1 x 2 = .200
Category B
Study Item 4 p72 x 2 x 1 x 2 = .008
Category B
Study Item 5 1 x 1 x wa x 2 = .040
Category B
Study Item 6 2 x 2. x il x 1 = .040
NE... eee
351
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
The exemplar theory is able to predict certain results that simple versions
of schema theory cannot. Consider classification of the problematical item 5, one
large red circle, given the items in Table 10.2. Since the features one, large, and red
are all associated with category A, the schema theory would predict that the
item would be classified in that category. To account for the correct classification
of this item, Gluck and Bower assumed that subjects responded to configural
cues, which are combinations of features. The Medin and Schaffer theory has no
problems accounting for the successful classification of this item. Since the item
was studied as being in category B and is maximally similar to itself, subjects are
likely to retrieve and usé@it for its own classification. Put another way, the Medin
and Schaffer theory proposes that subjects classify this item by remembering it
specifically and the category it came from.
Estes, Campbell, Hatsopoulos, and Hurwitz (1989) compared the Gluck
and Bower network model with the exemplar model. Their experiment involved
subjects categorizing patients’ symptoms into a rare versus a common disease
(the same sort of experiment as described with respect to Figure 2.15). Subjects
practiced categorizing the symptoms of 240 patients. Various symptom combi-
nations occurred with various probabilities with the two diseases. Figure 10.6
compares the subjects’ success in predicting blocks of 10 patients with the suc-
cess of the two models. Since symptom combinations occurred with the dis-
eases with only certain probabilities, subjects could not be perfect. The fluctua-
tions in Figure 10.6 from block to block reflect how difficult each block was.
Subjects showed some tendency to improve (chance is 50 percent). What is
remarkable is how well the two theories do at predicting the ups and downs in
subject accuracy. Both theories seem to do a good job in predicting all the ups
and downs in the data. The Gluck and Bower model does a little better, but the
real message of this figure is that two very different theories can yield such sim-
ilar predictions.
352
Concept Acquisition
100
80
Data
Percent
correct
60
Schema
40 Tact TT es sae ae ie ge ee
6 12 18 24
10-trial block
(a)
=
Data
80 |-
Exemplar
Percent
correct
60 |-
6 12 18 24
10-trial block
(b)
FIGURE 10.6 Comparison of schema and exemplar models in accounting for block-
by-block learning data. Source: From W. K. Estes, J. A.Campbell, N. Hatsopoulos, and
J. Hurwitz. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, Volume
4. Copyright © 1989 by American Psychological Association, p. 561. Reprinted with
permission.
in Table 10.2, an exemplar theory, like that of Medin and Schaffer, may be appro-
priate. There is probably not one correct theory of category learning. It is more
likely that the different theories reviewed in this section are correct in different
situations.
353
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
Recently, the field has become attracted to the idea that there might not
be a single categorization process and that different subjects might be doing cat-
egorization by different mechanisms. Indeed, the same subject might be doing
categorization by different processes at different times. For instance, Erickson &
Krushke (1998) show that subjects categorize some stimuli according to rules
and that they categorize other stimuli according to exemplars. Similarly, Smith,
Patalano, Jonides, and Kleppe (1998) find different patterns of brain activation
depending on whether subjects are categorizing examples by rules or exem-
plars. In particular, when using rules there was activation in the frontal cortex
which was not present When using exemplars. As we have noted elsewhere in
this book (Chapters 5 and 9), the frontal cortex tends to be active in tasks that
make high demands on the working memory or that involve substantial goal
manipulation. This would seem to imply that using rules to categorize is a more
demanding endeavor.
Causal Inference
Another critical kind of inductive learning involves figuring out what causes
what in our environment. People frequently engage in such causal inference.
Every time we come across a new device, we have to figure out how it works. A
person entering a new room may need to determine what causes a light to go
on. Children try to figure out what gets their parents angry, and parents try to
figure out what gets their children to obey. Police try to find out who committed
crimes, and physicians try to identify the causes of symptoms. It is important to
understand the causal structure of our environment because knowing that
allows us to use it to achieve our purposes. Indeed, as suggested in Chapters 2
and 3, much of animal conditioning was really concerned with how animals, in
effect, inferred the causal structure of their environments. Research with
humans sheds further light on causal inference.
It is useful to appreciate how both categorization and causal attribution
are instances of inductive inference but also how they are different. Categorical
inference involves noting that a set of features cluster together. In forming the
category of“bird,”a person is responding to the fact that the same kinds of ani-
mals tend to have feathers, to have beaks, and to lay eggs. Causal inference
involves noting that one set of events tends to predict another. For instance, a
person may determine that flipping a switch causes the light to come on or that
pressing a bar causes food to appear. In both cases, the person infers a predic-
tive relationship in the world—in one case among features of an object and in
the other case among events. Causal inference is inherently directional. If a bar
is pressed, food is expected to appear in the feeder, but if food is put in the feed-
er, the bar is not expected to depress. Categorical inference is symmetrical. An
354
Causal Inference
animal that has feathers is expected to have a beak, and an animal that has a
beak is expected to have feathers.
The general approach to understanding human causal inference has been
to study how people use various cues to causality (e.g., Einhorn & Hogarth,
1986). When two events (such as flipping a switch and turning a light on) are in
a cause-and-effect relationship, there are certain telltale cues as to that relation-
ship. The following sections review some of the cues people use to determine
causality.
Statistical Cues
Perhaps the most obvious cue is that of statistical contingency. Recall from the
discussion of conditioning that contingency refers to whether one event predicts
another. If whenever event A occurs, event B follows, and B never occurs unless
A has occurred, then there is strong evidence for the proposition that A causes
B. However, things are often not that certain. Consider the proposal that smok-
ing causes heart disease. Suppose that we observe some people who smoke and
others who do not. Some people who smoke will develop heart disease, some
who smoke will not develop heart disease, others who do not smoke will devel-
op heart disease, and yet others who do not smoke will not develop heart dis-
ease. The data can be organized according to a 2 x 2 table, as in Table 10.4, which
gives the number of observations of the four kinds.
The data in Table 10.4 (totally hypothetical) appear to provide evidence for
a causal relationship: a person who smokes has a 75 percent chance of devel-
oping heart disease, and a person who does not smoke has only a 40 percent
chance. Table 10.4 uses the variables a to d to stand for the frequencies in vari-
ous cells. The greater a (co-occurrence of cause and effect) and d (occurrence of
neither) are, the stronger evidence there is for an effect. The greater b (occur-
rence of cause but not effect) and c (no occurrence of cause but effect) are, the
less evidence there is for a relationship. Researchers have studied how sensitive
subjects are to variations in these four quantities—a, b, c, and d. The animal
research considered earlier (e.g., Figures 2.9 and 3.12) indicated a general sen-
sitivity to these factors. The human research (e.g., Crocker, 1981; Jenkins &
Cause Present:
Smoking a=75 B= 25
Cause Absent:
No smoking c= 40 d = 60
355
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
Ward, 1965; Schustack & Sternberg, 1981; Shaklee & Tucker, 1980) has been
specifically concerned with how people respond to variations in the four indi-
vidual quantities. In general, people behave in a rational way by increasing their
belief in a causal relationship as a or d increases and decreasing their belief as b
or c increases. Subjects appear to be most sensitive to changes in a, about equal-
ly sensitive to changes in b or c, and least sensitive to changes in d.
In a typical experiment performed by Anderson and Sheu (1995), subjects
tried to judge whether or not a drug had a side effect. Three of the variables a
through d were held constant, and the remaining variable was manipulated
from values of 1 to 15. Subjects had to judge on a scale from 0 to 100 how like-
ly it was that the drug caused the side effect. Figure 10.7 shows how these judg-
ments varied with changes in these variables. Changing a (cause and effect pre-
sent) from 1 to 15 increased judged causal effectiveness by 40 points; changing
b (cause but not effect) decreased judged effectiveness by 30 points; changing c
(no cause and effect) decreased judged effectiveness by 20 points; and changing
d (neither cause nor effect) increased judged effectiveness by only 5 points.
Subjects were sensitive to all variables but certainly differed in how sensitive
they were.
Chapter 3 noted that, according to the Rescorla-Wagner theory inferences
(see the discussion pertaining to Figure 3.14), the strength of association learned
between cause and effect is proportional to the differences between the proba-
bilities of the effect in the presence of the purported cause and the probability of
the effect in the absence of the purported cause. That is, the strength of associa-
tion between possible cause C and effect E is proportional to P(E|C) — P(E|-O)
where
PEIChe a 7 b
PEE|-O)i= C :d
This model predicts a general sensitivity to the variables a through d. One prob-
lem with this model is that it predicts that subjects should be as sensitive to
a change in a or b affecting P(E|C) as they are to a change inc or d affecting
P(E| — C). However, Figure 10.7 shows that subjects are not equally sensitive.
It seems unlikely that human subjects are simply forming strengths of
association as the Rescorla-Wagner theory suggests. When queried by
Anderson and Sheu, the majority of subjects reported that they were explicitly
trying to calculate P(E|C) and P(E|-C) and compare them. However, a sizable
2P(E|C) is to be read as probability of effect given cause, and P(E |-C) is to be read as
probability of effect given absence of cause.
Wasserman et al. (1993) showed that having different learning rates for the four
cases can yield different effects of a through d.
356
Causal Inference
0a
L
= (cause
60 and effect) d
(no cause
and no effect)
Rating aij Cc
(no cause
and effect)
b
(cause and
20 no effect)
minority of subjects reported calculating only P(E|C) and basing their judgments
on this. The majority showed relatively equal effects of a through d, whereas the
minority showed only effects of a and b. It seems that subjects followed con-
scious strategies of probability estimation and that the variables had different-
sized effects because some subjects ignored some of the information. Subjects
behaved in a rather conscious hypothesis-testing manner, which happened to
be mimicked by the Rescorla—Wagner theory. It is quite plausible that lower
organisms are incapable of such conscious calculations but do behave in accord
with the Rescorla—Wagner theory. This is another instance of rather different
mechanisms producing similar results.
357
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
|
SAE
FIGURE 10.8 The apparatus used by Bullock et al. (1982). Source: From M. Bullock,
R. Gelman, and R. Baillargeon in W. J. Friedman, Ed. The developmental psychology of
time. Copyright © 1982 by Academic Press. Reprinted by permission.
Figure 10.8 shows the device used by Bullock, Gelman, and Baillargeon
(1982) in a study of causal attribution. Subjects saw two balls drop into tubes at
the end of a box. Then a jack-in-the-box appeared in the center of the box. There
were four conditions that varied in terms of the temporal proximity and spatial
proximity of the dropping of the two balls. In condition 1, the two balls were
equally distant from the jack-in-the-box, but one was dropped before the other.
In this condition, 65 percent of the subjects attributed the appearance of the jack-
in-the-box to the dropping of the second ball, which was closer in time. In condi-
tion 2, the two balls were dropped at the same time, but one was closer to where
the jack-in-the-box appeared. In this circumstance, 100 percent of the subjects
attributed the cause to the closer ball. In a third condition, one ball was close in
both time and space to the appearance of the jack-in-the-box. In this condition,
100 percent of the subjects also chose the closer ball. The fourth condition
involved a conflict: one ball was closer in time, but the other was closer in space.
In this condition, 70 percent of the subjects chose the ball that was closer in space.
Subjects in the Bullock et al. experiment tended to prefer the cue that was
closer in space over the cue that was closer in time. Other researchers (e.g.,
Shultz, Fischer, Pratt, & Rulf, 1986) found that subjects preferred as a cause what
was closer in time. Thus, one cue is not always dominant. Both cues are effec-
tive, and which is dominant depends on the particular situation.
Figure 10.9a shows a computer display used to study the role of temporal
and spatial contiguity in causal attribution (Anderson, 1991). In this experiment,
a hand dropped a weight on a beam and a trapdoor opened up, releasing a ball.
Subjects were asked to rate how compelling was the perception of a causal rela-
tionship between the dropping of the weight and the popping out of the ball.
The distance was varied between the weight and the door, and the delay was
varied between the dropping of the weight and the opening of the door.
Subjects rated the causal link between the two events on a 1 to 7 scale, where 7
meant definitely causally related and 1 meant no causal relationship. Figure
10.9b shows how the strength of causal attribution varied with these two fac-
tors. In this experiment, time was the dominant variable, and distance only
entered into strength of attributions when the delay was short.
Researchers (e.g., Shultz, 1982) have argued that subjects do not blindly
use spatial and temporal contiguity to infer a causal relationship but that they
358
Causal Inference
es
Click mouse for next trial
o
A
Distance
5 —o- 15 units
=>7 units
— 3 units
25 —= 1 unit
Cc
oO
52
&O4
2 | | | |
0.1 0.3 0.9 2.7 8.1
Time, sec
(b)
FIGURE 10.9 The vibratory wave model: (a) the computer display; (b) strength of
causal perception as a function of distance in space and time. Source: From J. R.
Anderson. Is human cognition adaptive? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Volume 14.
Copyright © 1991. Reprinted by permission of Cambridge University Press.
359
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
ing of the door would appear causally inconsistent. The closer the weight to the
door, the more force the wave has, and so the more likely it is that the wave will
jar loose the mechanism. Thus, at short delays, subjects should prefer the cause
when it is closer in space, which is just what is shown in Figure 10.90.
Figure 10.10a shows an interesting contrast condition (Anderson, 1991) to
the one in Figure 10.9a. A hand dropped a ball into a hole in the beam.
Distance
: -o 15 units
— 7 units
6 —> 3 units
—= 1 unit
Confidence
(b)
FIGURE 10.10 The ball and projectile model: (2) the computer display; (b) strength
of causal perception as a function of distance in space and time. Source: From LR
Anderson. Is human cognition adaptive? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Volume 14.
Copyright © 1991. Reprinted by permission of Cambridge University Press.
360
Causal Inference
Sometime later a trapdoor opened and a ball appeared, just as in Figure 10.9a.
As with Figure 10.9a, the distances in time and space between the first event
and the second were manipulated. Figure 10.10b shows how subjects’ causal
attributions varied in this condition. The results are in considerable contrast to
the data in Figure 10.9b. In Figure 10.10b there is no favored time or distance.
Rather, as the distance increased, subjects favored longer and longer times.
Subjects reported looking for a match between distance and time. Their model
was one in which the ball traveled through the beam to appear at the trapdoor,
and they were looking for a situation where the time was appropriate (not too
long or too short) for the distance traveled.
Human subjects are quite sophisticated in their interpretation of temporal
and spatial contiguity. Earlier chapters reviewed the evidence for a similar
degree of sophistication in animals in how much they rely on temporal conti-
guity. For instance, rats connect taste with poisoning after much longer delays
than usually work in conditioning. A possible reason is that poisoning is the
kind of effect that often appears at a considerable delay after ingestion. It seems
unlikely, however, that rats behave with as explicit and conscious a model as
human subjects sometimes do.
Kinematic Cues
Subjects often display great sophistication in their interpretation of kinematic
cues. Kinematic cues refer to properties that would be expected of events
causally related according to the laws of physics. When the conditions are right,
kinematic cues can give rise to extraordinarily compelling perceptions of causal-
ity. Some of the original research on this topic was performed by Michotte
(1946). Subjects observed a black circle move across a screen and touch a sec-
ond circle; then the second circle moved off. When the second circle moved
immediately after it was touched, subjects had a compelling impression of a col-
lision in which the first object set the second in motion, as when one billiard ball
hits another. When there was any delay between the two events, the perception
of a causal connection dissolved.
In variations on Michotte’s experiment, Kaiser and Proffitt (1984) manip-
ulated the velocity and angle at which the two objects parted after the collision.
Subjects’ perceptions of causality were sensitive to the laws of physics govern-
ing such collisions, and they judged as causally anomalous collisions that
involved impossible angles or rates of acceleration. Subjects could also judge the
relative mass of the two objects from the velocity and angle at which the objects
separated.
In some situations, subjects’ judgments are not so in tune with the correct
scientific model. Consider the situation in which an object moves off a surface,
361
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
such as when a ball rolls off a table. The correct scientific model is one in which
the trajectory of the object after it leaves the table is a curve reflecting a combi-
nation of the original horizontal velocity and the downward negative force
caused by gravity. Some people believe that the object will go directly down, and
others predict an L-shaped trajectory in which the object goes straight forward
for a while and then falls down. Judgments in this domain show a definite
developmental trend, with older subjects showing fewer misconceptions.
Apparently, people come to tune their models with experience and education
(Kaiser, Proffitt, & McCloskey, 1985).
Even more curious are judgments about the trajectory of an object after it
leaves a curve-shaped tube, such as the one in Figure 10.11 (Kaiser, McCloskey,
& Proffitt, 1986; McCloskey, 1983). A common misconception is that it will show
a curved trajectory rather than a straight one. This belief shows a U-shaped
developmental trend, with children around the sixth grade showing the most
misconceptions and preschoolers and college students about equivalent and
somewhat better.
People possess models for how physical events should take place and use
these models to make judgments of causality. Sometimes their physical models
are correct, and sometimes they are not. People are referred to as having naive
physics models that are partially correct. One goal in modern physics education
is to better train these naive physics models (e.g., Champagne, Gunstone, &
Klopfer, 1985).
362
Causal Inference
ihe: By
<— 7,
ies
— 15,
Hold 5,
Fire 2,
8
the tank would move forward 5 ft, rotate counterclockwise 7 clock ticks, move
forward 3 ft, rotate clockwise 15 ticks, pause 5 sec, fire twice, and move back 8
ft. Most of Shrager’s subjects, who were undergraduates, were able to figure out
within an hour how to program the tank by simply experimenting with various
key combinations. He noted that a key to their success was that subjects made
constant reference to past experiences they had with similar objects that had to
be programmed (e.g., a microwave) and to their prior knowledge about the
kinds of behavior one might expect to see from a toy tank.
Klahr and Dunbar (1988) studied in detail how subjects learned about one
aspect of the device—the RPT key. When this key is followed by a number, it
repeats that number of previous moves. For example, RPT 3 repeats the last
three moves. However, subjects had many different ideas about what the key
did. A favorite hypothesis was that RPT 3 would repeat the whole sequence of
actions three times. Klahr and Dunbar found that subjects behaved basically like
scientists in determining what the key did, designing experiments and formu-
lating hypotheses on the basis of the results, and then designing new experi-
ments to test these hypotheses. However, their hypotheses were strongly biased
by their past experiences with what a key labeled RPT might do.
Learning can be greatly facilitated if we can learn something new as analo-
gous to something else. Blessing (1996) showed that key to students learning a
particular, new formal mathematical system was seeing how it was similar to stan-
dard algebra. Kieras and Bovair (1984) had subjects learn to operate a control panel
for a novel device. They gave subjects instructions about how to perform all of the
)
(7) (8) (2) er)
FIGURE 10.12 Key pad for programming a toy tank.
(4)(5)(s)
Source: From J. C. Shrager. Instructionless learning: Discovery bai} 2 (3) (cx )
of the mental model of a complex device. Copyright © 1985 by
Jeffrey C. Shrager. Reprinted by permission. (0)
363
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
procedures. This was all one group was told. However, a second group was told
that the device they were operating was the control panel for the phaser bank on
the Starship Enterprise.They were provided with a totally made-up story about how
the panel controlled the phaser bank. Nonetheless, given this model, the subjects
learned the procedures faster, retained them more accurately, executed them faster,
and found efficient shortcuts more often. Usually, when we learn to deal with
something new, we can recall experiences of dealing with something similar.
Success in learning the new often depends on making successful bridges to the old.
Language Acquisition
Some researchers believe that acquisition of a natural language is the most
impressive inductive learning feat of the human species. Many argue that only
humans can learn a language and that our language facility reflects something
unique about the human mind (e.g., Chomsky, 1965, 1975). In a few short years
young children figure out what generations of Ph.D. linguists have not—the
rules of language. This contrast needs to be emphasized—scientists have not
364
Language Acquisition
been able to characterize what the rules of language are, and yet children figure
it out with relative ease. Of course, children cannot say what the rules are that
they have learned. In the terms of Chapter 8, this is an instance of implicitdearn-
ing. The fact that people are so successful in such implicit learning of a first lan-
guage has been used to argue that we must have special innate and unconscious
knowledge as to the structure of language.
It is important to recognize what makes language learning such a difficult
task. Most people are quite aware that language contains many words—tens of
thousands in fact. Studies of young children have suggested that they learn
more than five new words each day (Carey, 1978; Clark, 1983). Learning the
meanings of all of these words defines an enormous concept-acquisition task.
Unlike learning a second language, a person learning a first language cannot
rely on the assistance of definitions stated in another language.
Although vocabulary is the most obvious aspect of language learning, it is
generally not considered the most daunting aspect. Learning the mor-
phophonology and syntax of language is more demanding. Morphophonology
refers to how the sound system determines meaning (for example, adding an s
in English to indicate possession—*Fred’s sister”), and syntax is concerned with
how word order determines meaning (for example, “sister of Fred”). Languages
may possess tens of thousands of such rules, many of which are rather subtle.
Long after second-language learners have mastered the vocabulary of the lan-
guage, they continue to make errors in pronunciation and grammar.
Not only are there many phonological and syntactic rules to be learned,
but the conditions in which children learn them seem far from ideal. No one
explicitly instructs children as to what the rules of language are. Children have
to induce these rules by hearing language spoken to them. Any particular sen-
tence involves many rules acting together to determine the sentence. The many
components of the sentence must be unraveled. Parents and other caregivers
might be thought to teach children by explicitly correcting their speech.
However, many children learn a language just fine without receiving such cor-
rection, and the available evidence suggests that such correction does not help
those children who receive it (e.g., Braine, 1971; McNeill, 1966; for a recent dis-
cussion, see MacWhinney, 1993). McNeill (1966) cited a famous example of how
impervious children can be to correction:
Child: | Nobody don’t like me.
Mother: No, say,” Nobody likes me.”
Child: | Nobody don’t like me.
Mother: No, say,“ Nobody likes me.”
Mother: No, say,“Nobody likes me.”
Child: | Nobody don’t like me.
[dialogue repeated 7 more times]
Mother: — Now listen carefully, say,“ Nobody likes me.”
Child: | Oh! Nobody don’t likes me.
365
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
Children accomplish an enormous task in acquiring language, and they put a lot
of time into it. Children do not master the subtleties of language until age 10
(Chomsky, 1970). By that time, they have put thousands of days and presumably
tens of thousands of hours into language acquisition. Recall from the previous
chapter the evidence that mastery of any complex skill involves an enormous
investment of time in which the various rules of that skill are mastered one by
one. Language is no exception to this principle. It may, however, be the most
complex system that people have to learn.
Not only do children often ignore explicit instruction about language but
also they are capable oflearning a language even if they are not exposed to any
language at all. Evidence for this fact comes from studies of deaf children of
speaking parents (approximately 90 percent of deaf children are born to speak-
ing parents). Goldin-Meadow, Butcher, Mylander, and Dodge (1994) studied a
deaf child whose parents chose to teach him by the oral method. Nonetheless,
as many deaf children do, he started to invent his own sign language to com-
municate with his parents. His sign language made a distinction between nouns
and verbs just as standard sign languages or natural languages do. Moreover,
some of his signs (e.g., hammer, brush, comb) could serve as either nouns or
verbs just like words in other languages. To distinguish noun uses from verb
uses he invented a series of syntactic markers. For instance, he tended to put
verbs at the end of his signing sequences. Thus, we see that to a certain extent
humans are born with an instinct to learn a language with certain features and
will construct such a language no matter what. Typically, the language they con-
struct corresponds to the one they hear, but much of their language learning
comes from the drive of this instinct and not from what they actually hear.
Similarly, it has been shown that birds have a strong instinct to learn birdsong,
but they will learn different dialects depending on the social context in which
they sing (Marler & Peters, 1982; West & King, 1980).
366
Language Acquisition
Even when children graduate from the two-word stage and start speaking
in longer utterances, their utterances preserve what might be regarded as a tele-
graphic property in that they tend to omit some of the less important words.
Table 10.5 shows some examples of such multiword utterances. Gradually, the
utterances begin to fill out, so that by the age of about 4 children speak essen-
tially in sentences. The sentences may be simple and limited by adult standards
and still contain grammatical errors, but they are recognizable as sentences.
This developmental sequence is unique to children. Adults learning a sec-
ond language try to speak in more complete sentences right from the begin-
ning—even if their sentences are limited and often not grammatical. It has been
conjectured that limited memory capacity may be a reason for the shortness of
children’s utterances (Anderson, 1983). Young children are not able to keep in
mind and plan longer utterances. It has been shown, for instance, that children
have severe limitations in their ability to repeat longer utterances (Brown &
Fraser, 1963). Chapter 5 noted that memory span is related to speed of articula-
tion. Since young children are still learning to speak, their articulatory rate is
much slower (Gathercole & Hitch, 1993), and so they are able to encode less of
the sentences spoken to them and can only plan shorter utterances. Newport
(1990) has argued that this limited processing capacity actually makes language
learning easier. Because young children do not process all the words of a com-
plex sentence, they avoid dealing with many of the most complex aspects of lan-
guage. They can concentrate on getting the core of the language right. This is
called the“less is more” hypothesis.
Another feature of language is that it contains many rules that often apply
to only some of the words in the language, for example, rules for past tense in
English. Most verbs are made into the past tense by adding ed or one of its
phonological variants. There are, however, clusters of exceptions—ring—rang,
sing-sang, and so on. Some words follow their own unique rules, such as eat—ate.
As children learn the complex rules and exceptions of past tense, they go through
a series of stages. First, they do not try to indicate past tense; then, they over-
generalize the dominant rules (e.g., singed); finally, they achieve basic mastery.
Children (and adults) are capable of applying such rules to novel words. So, for
instance, on being told that there is a verb gring (meaning, perhaps,“to splash in
the waves”), children spontaneously use either gringed or grang as the past tense.
367
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
368
Language Acquisition
Their bold claim has not gone unchallenged, however. Pinker and Prince (1988)
published an extensive criticism of the Rumelhart and McClelland study, focus-
ing on the details of the model. They pointed out that the ability to account for
the generalization stages depended on initially presenting the network with
many irregular verbs, whereas children do not encounter a special abundance of
irregular verbs early on. Pinker and Prince also pointed out that some of the
errors made by the model were quite unlike errors made by children. For
instance, the model generated membled as the past tense of mail.
Pinker and Prince argued that the English past-tense system is more rule-
governed than can be accounted for by a simple associative network. They used
the example that the same root word can have different past-tense realizations
depending on context. The word ring has two realizations as a verb—to make a
sound or to encircle. Although the root is the same, the past tense for the for-
mer meaning is rang, and for the latter meaning the past tense is ringed, as in:
369
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
resolved. The debate once again illustrates the tension between associative
models of inductive learning and rule-based, hypothesis-testing approaches.
370
Language Acquisition
Although older children are able to learn more rapidly initially, they tend
never to master certain fine points of the language as well as do their younger
siblings (Lieberman, 1984; Newport, 1986). One of the most characteristic fine
points is the ability to speak a second language without an accent, which is dif-
ficult if the language is learned after about age 12.
Newport (1990) reported a rare study on the effect of age of acquisition on
first language learning. She studied deaf children of speaking parents who often
did not learn sign language until quite late in their development and did not
master any language during their early years. She found a strong relationship
between the age at which these deaf people started to learn sign language and
their eventual level of mastery of sign language in adulthood. There appeared to
be a particularly large deficit if their learning was postponed until after the age
of 12. The existence of a critical period for language acquisition has been used to
argue for the special character of human language learning. However, as noted
earlier, Newport has argued that children learn better not because they have
special knowledge of language but precisely because they are less capable. This
is her less-is-more hypothesis—that the reduced information-processing
capacity of children actually reduces the complexity of the language hypotheses
that children have to consider.
371
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
372
Language Acquisition
373
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
mother was trained with involved artificial tokens called lexigrams. At age 3,
when he started spontaneously using lexigrams, investigators began to train
him as a subject. His language generations are not of the same repetitive vari-
ety as Nim’s. Also, it was discovered that he had acquired a considerable ability
to understand spoken language. When he was 5.5 years old, his ability to follow
spoken language was compared with that of a 2-year-old child. He was able to
outperform the 2-year-old child.
The accomplishment of outperforming a 2-year-old reflects the glass- halt-
full and glass-half-empty state of research on the language capacity of apes. It
remains unclear what should be the reasonable aspirations for these efforts to
374
Final Reflections
train apes. The expectation certainly should not be that they come to process
language identically to adult humans. It is not really a matter of their being infe-
rior to humans; they are different in many ways that have nothing to do with
linguistic ability. Therefore, one should not expect their linguistic learning (or,
indeed, any other learning) to be identical to human learning. One lesson from
the early chapters on animal learning is that learning manifests itself according
to the unique characteristics of each species. Still, the current state of the
research should make us cautious in our assumptions about how much of lan-
guage is unique to humans.
Final Reflections
Induction is the process by which we make inferences that go beyond our expe-
riences to make predictions about new situations—about whether a creature we
encounter is a dog and whether it is likely to bite, about whether having a high-
cholesterol diet will cause a patient to suffer heart disease, or about whether a
new linguistic utterance will be deemed grammatical. It is a critical aspect of
375
CHAPTER 10 Inductive Learning
Further Readings
Levine (1975) presents several reports on the hypothesis-testing approach to
concept learning. Smith (1989) provides a survey of research on induction and
concept learning. Shultz (1982) offers an overview of-causal learning, and
Wasserman (1990b) is particularly interested in the connections between causal
inference and animal conditioning. Klahr, Fay, and Dunbar (1993) report an
assessment of children’s skills at scientific experimentation. Pinker (1989, 1994)
provides reviews of research on language acquisition. Holland, Holyoak,
Nisbett, and Thagard (1986) wrote an influential monograph on the many vari-
eties of inductive learning.
376
Applications to Education
377
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
schools in Greece (sixth century B.C.) that taught music, reading, and gymnas-
tics (Boyd & King, 1975).
At least since ancient Greek times, some privileged children have received
formal education, but the concept of public education has only taken shape over
the last few hundred years. The current system of public elementary schools,
high schools, and universities in the United States was established in the nine-
teenth century (Good, 1962). The goal of universal education through high
school was articulated in the United States between the two world wars and in
many other modern countries only after World War II. The current curriculum
that occupies public education has been in place less than 100 years.
Higher education has always carried with it a sense of class privilege.
Much of education in previous centuries, such as training in the classics, was
conceived of as placing on students the mark of the upper class—that is, teach-
ing students to be”gentlemen.” Only in the last 100 years has education for all
been justified in terms of its utilitarian content—that is, teaching students
things that are useful to being good citizens (e.g., being able to read and judge
an article about public policy in a magazine) and productive workers (e.g., being
able to run an accounting system for a company). Even today there are serious
questions about how much of public education really is useful and how much
of it is actually devoted to establishing tokens of class privilege (e.g., Lave, 1988).
This chapter discusses some of these current criticisms in the section on math-
ematics education.
There is much debate over the success of the educational system, partic-
ularly in the United States. At one level it is a resounding success: almost all the
citizenry achieves at least a modest level of literacy. The United States has a
technologically sophisticated society that simply would not be possible without
modern education. On the other hand, the U.S. educational system is succeed-
ing much less well than the nation’s citizens would like. As Resnick and
Resnick (1977) documented with respect to literacy, this lack of success results
largely because people have ever higher aspirations as to what the education-
al system should achieve. Although there has always been a very literate elite,
in this century Americans have demanded that more and more citizens be able
to read more and more difficult material. An interesting question is whether or
not these expectations are realistic. One way to answer this question is to com-
pare the achievement of American children with that of children in other edu-
cational systems. If other countries are able to produce higher achievement, the
U.S. system also should be able to do so. This chapter focuses on what psy-
chology has to say about teaching (or learning) reading and mathematics, two
of the core skills targeted by modern education. It is worthwhile considering
the relative international standing of American students with respect to these
two topics.
378
The Goals of Education
Reading
It is difficult to compare the reading achievement levels of American students
to those of students of other nations because different nations have different
languages and orthographies. Differences in societies also pose a problem in
judging international performance. The United States aspires to keep all stu-
dents in school for 12 years and succeeds with over 80 percent (McKnight,
Crosswhite, Dossey, Kifer, Swafford, Travers, & Cooney, 1990). In other nations,
many students leave the school system earlier. It would not be fair to compare
the top 20 percent of one nation with the greater mix represented by the 80
percent of graduating American students. Societies also vary in terms of their
cultural and economic heterogeneity; the United States has a culturally diverse
society and increasing disparity in the economic standings of its citizenry.
Educational goals are generally easier to achieve in a culturally homogeneous
society, where education can be tailored to the specifics of the one group, than
in a diverse society, where different cultural groups may require different edu-
cational situations to optimize their learning. There is also a very strong corre-
lation between economic status and educational achievement (California
Assessment Program, 1980; Gamoran, 1987). This correlation suggests that the
growing underclass in the United States will be an increasing source of educa-
tional underachievement.
Despite these problems, there is reason to believe that U.S. schools suc-
ceed relatively well at teaching reading. In most international comparisons,
American students do as well as students of most other countries (Stevenson &
Stigler, 1992). When the reading achievements of non-Hispanic, white, middle-
class Americans are compared with those of the ethnically dominant, middle-
class children of other societies, Americans often outperform the other children.
This result suggests that a major mechanism for improving the reading scores of
American children as a group would be to improve the economic standing of the
underclass and to learn how to tailor reading education to minority ethnic
groups. In summary, the U.S. educational establishment does a relatively good
job at teaching reading; the problems that exist are as much societal as educa-
tional.
Figure 11.1 compares American and Chinese students and is representa-
tive of the international comparisons. It shows the number of students graduat-
ing from the first grade with reading scores at various grade levels (1:1 stands
for the first half of first grade and 1:2 for the second half). Note that a significant
number of first graders in the United States read one and two grade levels above
their age and a few read at even higher grade levels, whereas very few Chinese
students read above their grade level. On the other hand, almost 40 percent of
American first graders have not even mastered the lowest level of first-grade
reading, whereas almost all Chinese students have. This chart illustrates the
ereat disparity among reading performances within the United States. The stu-
dents with very low reading scores come disproportionately from economically
disadvantaged families.
B79
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
100
80
ES00
FIGURE 11.1 Histogram show- <5
ing relative proportion of Chinese §&
students (from Beijing) and 6 40
American students (from*Chicago) ie
at various reading levels. Source:
From A. S. Palinscsar and A. L. a6
Brown, Cognition and Instruction.
Copyright © 1984 by Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates, Inc., Mahwah, 6
NJ, pp. 138-139. Reprinted with 2 Td 1:2°0 211 9212 Sa Nae gaiieas2
permission. Reading level
PURER
There
States, with the better students doing at least as well as the top
students of most nations.
Mathematics
The international standing of U.S. students in terms of mathematics achieve-
ment is much worse. In international comparisons, American children enter the
first grade knowing a comparable amount of mathematics (Stevenson & Stigler,
1992) but steadily fall behind until they are one of the poorest-achieving groups
of students (McKnight et al., 1990). Figure 11.2 compares the performance of
U.S. twelfth graders with respect to algebra, geometry, and calculus with the
performance of students at comparable levels in other countries. For each topic,
~ the Americans are near the bottom of all countries surveyed, and Japan and
Hong Kong hold the top two positions. Unlike some of the other countries,
Japan aspires to give all its citizens 12 years of education and succeeds with
more than 90 percent. So this comparison is not an artifact of a relatively select
Japanese student population. Also, Japan and the United States are not very dif-
ferent in the level of reading achievement found in their schools. Several com-
parisons of Japanese and U.S. mathematics education have tried to identify the
cause of the difference in mathematics achievement. In one careful comparison
of fifth graders in Minneapolis and Sendai, Japan, two comparable cities, it was
found that no school in Minneapolis had an average mathematics score higher
than any school in Sendai (Stevenson & Stigler, 1992). This sample included
rich, suburban Minneapolis schools, indicating that the problems with mathe-
380
The Goals of Education
Algebra
URaI|
a109S
l=
100;—
Calculus
80 }-
Uka|\| 9409S
+ fe) Al
Geometry
rl L
URD|\|
3109S oe
381
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
matics achievement in the United States are not restricted to cultural minorities
or economically disadvantaged children.
McKnight et al. (1990) reviewed a number of popular explanations of the
difference in learning achievement in mathematics. One explanation involves
classroom size, but Japanese classrooms average 41 students and U.S. class-
rooms average only 26. A second explanation is the quality of the teachers.
Teachers in the two countries have relatively comparable training and back-
grounds, but Japanese teachers have more time for class preparation and do less
teaching (an average 23 class hours in the United States versus 17 in Japan).
Japanese teachers also teceive more mentoring and more state direction and
guidance on how to prepare their class presentations. American teachers often
complain that the curriculum is constantly changing, so that they never can
develop expertise in teaching it. Later, this chapter explores the reasons for fre-
quent changes in the U.S. mathematics curriculum.
Probably the major reason for the differences in achievement is the
amount of time actually spent on mathematics education. Large differences
exist at almost all grade levels. In Japan, elementary students spend twice as
much class time on mathematics as do elementary students in the United States
(White, 1987). Time is also used much more efficiently in the Japanese class-
room, and there are fewer distractions (such as announcements, special class
elections, or outings; Stevenson & Stigler, 1992). Many Japanese students go to
after-school Juku classes in which mathematics is the prime subject, especially
in the later grades. Juku classes (White, 1987) are special classes to help students
improve their performance in school and prepare for national exams. It is esti-
mated that the average Japanese parent spends $2000 per year on Juku.! Rohlen
(1998) calculated that the average Japanese student spends 3.2 times more time
on studying between grades 5 and 12 than the average U.S. student.
Interestingly, styles of instruction vary substantially among East Asian countries
like Taiwan and Japan (Stevenson & Lee, 1998) but all produce higher achieve-
ment. The common denominator to Asian success is that much more time is
spent on mathematics.
Societal attitudes probably magnify the basic differences (Stevenson &
Stigler, 1992). Japanese parents and children tend to believe that mathematics
achievement is primarily a result of effort, whereas American parents and chil-
dren tend to believe it is a talent that a person either has or does not have.
American parents, although they may deplore their nation’s achievement in
mathematics, tend to be satisfied with the achievement levels of their own chil-
dren. In contrast, Japanese parents, who may be proud of their nation’s achieve-
ment, tend to think that their own children could do better (Stevenson & Stigler,
“More than 50% of the 5 million lower secondary (7th to 9th grades) school students
attend a juku. In the last seven years, for instance, the amount spent by Japanese par- ~
ents on cram-schools and tutoring has doubled to $10.9 Billion ($109 oku).” From
“For Japanese, Cramming for Exams Starts Where the Cradle Leaves OFS
International Herald Tribune, April 28, 1992, pull!
382
Psychology and Education
1992). Japanese parents are inclined to help their children with mathematics at
home, whereas American parents think that such help is the province of the
school system. ;
There is always a suspicion that the differences in mathematics achieve-
ment between the United States and Asian countries may reflect some innate
racial differences. Although it cannot be proven conclusively that this is not the
case, there is good evidence that it is not a major factor. Stevenson and Stigler
(1992) reported no differences in general intelligence scores of the population.
The best American students typically do very well in international Math
Olympiad competitions. Invariably, such students are the few American children
who have devoted themselves to mathematics achievement and received exten-
sive support outside the classroom. Although there may well be innate mathe-
matical talent, the more critical variable is effort, as discussed in Chapter 9.
It surely should come as no surprise in the context of this book that time
spent learning has a major impact on learning outcome. In this regard, it should
also be noted that the amount of time spent on reading education is much more
comparable between Japan and the United States, and the outcomes are corre-
spondingly more comparable (Stevenson & Stigler, 1992; White, 1987).
However, although time spent learning has an important impact on learning
outcome, most of this book has been devoted to secondary variables, which
have an impact on how effective learning time is. This chapter focuses on how
learning time can be made more effective.
pieenti
383
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
4203
—728.-
Behavioral objectives include knowing simple subtraction facts (13 — 8 = 5), bor-
rowing, the special case of borrowing across zero, and subtracting when there is
only a top number. Each of these behavioral objectives was taught separately.
Gagné (1962) succinctly described what is involved in task analysis:
The basic principles of training design consist of: (a) identifying the
component tasks of a final performance; (b) insuring that each of
these component tasks is fully achieved; and (c) arranging the total
learning situation in a sequence that will insure optimal mediation-
al effects from one component to another. (1962, p. 88)
Each of the components identified by Gagné was essential to the success of the
behaviorist program in education:
384
Psychology and Education
385
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
Mastery Learning
One of the most significant outcomes of the behaviorist tradition is a set of
instructional strategies generally called mastery learning. Mastery learning is
based on two assumptions:
1. Almost all students should be able to learn almost all the material in a
standard school curriculum.
2. If students have not learned material early in a curriculum, they will have
more difficulty with material later in the curriculum.
With mastery learning techniques, students are given as much time as they need
to master early material before moving on to later material. This approach guar-
antees learning and makes the learning of later material easier. There are two
types of mastery curricula. One (Glaser, 1972; Keller, 1968; Suppes, 1964)
involves having each student follow an individual course of learning. The sec-
ond, associated with Bloom (1968, 1976), is more appropriate to standard
schoolroom classes and gets the whole class to mastery of a topic before the stu-
dents move on. The latter approach is much easier to manage than the individ-
ualized method, which requires tracking each student separately. The individu-
alized method has been used primarily with college or adult populations, where
individual students are more mature and more capable of managing their own
learning. Many psychology departments (including my own at Carnegie
Mellon) have self-paced introductory courses in which students have to achieve
a particular grade level on a chapter before they can go on to the next. It is up
to the student to know how to study and when to schedule the tests. Often
these are lectureless courses.
In general, mastery programs lead to higher achievement (Guskey &
Gates, 1986; Kulik, Kulik, & Bangert-Downs, 1986). However, it was also
claimed that mastery programs would result in reduced individual differences,
since all students master the prerequisite material (Bloom, 1976). That is, since
all students master the same material in the earlier units, they should take about
the same time to master the material in the later units that depend on these ear-
lier units. Evidence for this claim is weaker than that for the higher achievement
claim (Resnick, 1977), and large individual differences remain in the time to
learn material to reach the mastery level. Mastery learning’s failure to eliminate
individual differences should not obscure the fact that it results in higher edu-
cational achievement for all students. Despite the positive evidence, the educa-
tional establishment tends to view these efforts as failures. This is one of many
examples of how the educational establishment ignores empirical evidence in its
desire to follow fashion.
Many mastery programs introduced in schools have been dropped.
Maintaining a successful mastery program requires a lot of teacher commitment
and energy. The standard classroom is much easier to manage—this issue of
ease of classroom management is a significant issue that has caused many edu-
cational reform effects to fail (Grittner, 1975).
386
Reading Instruction
Reading Instruction
Compared to the situation in mathematics, there is relative agreement about what
the target of reading instruction should be. Society wants its citizens to be able to
read at a level that will allow them to process policy information so that they can
vote intelligently, to process information about commodities so that they can be
good consumers, to process technical information so that they can be good work-
387
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
ers, and in other ways to take in written information so that they can be effective
citizens. As already noted, the educational establishment can claim some success
at achieving these goals, at least for those who are not socially disadvantaged.
However, there has been one major controversy in the teaching of read-
ing. This is the conflict between the phonics method and the whole-word
method of instruction. The phonics method emphasizes training children in
how to go from letters and letter combinations to sound, and from sound to the
words and their meanings. The whole-word method emphasizes direct recogni-
tion of words and phrases and going directly from words to meaning.
In the United States reading instruction has been subject to many swings
of fashion. Until the 1800s, the principal emphasis was on the phonics method.
With the appearance of the McGuffey readers in the 1800s, emphasis switched
to the whole-word method. Emphasis has fluctuated back and forth since then.
Children learn to read under both methods, although studies tend to find that
the phonics approach is somewhat superior (Adams, 1990; Beck, 1981; Chall,
1967; Johnson & Baumann, 1984). Williams (1979) and Perfetti (1985) pondered
why greater use is not made of phonics-based instruction, given the positive
evidence. As Williams lamented,”Today as in the past, data do not carry a great
deal of weight in determining educational practice.” (p. 921). Both Williams and
Perfetti concluded that the whole-word approach, with its emphasis on mean-
ing, is more appealing in that it appears superficially to be in keeping with cog-
nitive trends in psychology, to be more fun, and to be a higher-status skill to
teach than low-level phonetic decoding skills.
The popular press has given a great deal of attention to dyslexia, which is
best defined as underachievement in reading performance. The most common
definition of a dyslexic is a person of normal or high IQ who reads at least two
grade levels below the expected reading level. In a review of dyslexia, Just and
Carpenter (1987) noted that in the United States and Great Britain 0.5 percent of
gitls and 3 percent of boys could be classified by this criterion as dyslexic. The
general public tends to believe that dyslexia is a visual problem involving confu-
sion of letters, but as Just and Carpenter noted, the major source of the deficit is
in making correspondences from symbols to sounds. The phonics method, which
focuses on this aspect of reading, may be particularly appropriate for dealing with
the problems of the dyslexic population (Lundberg, 1985; Perfetti, 1985).
388
Reading Instruction
Flywheels are one of the oldest mechanical devices known to man. Every
@ @ Ew@ @&
internal-combustion engine contains a small flywheel that converts the jerky
ss) G7)@ss)
motion of the piston into the smooth flow of energy that powers the drive shaft.
FIGURE 11.3 Eye fixation while reading a passage about flywheels. Reading is left-
to-right except for the one regression indicated with the arrows. The fixation times in
msec are given in circles. (Adapted from Just & Carpenter, 1980.) Source: From L.
Resnick et al. Addition and subtraction: a cognitive perspective. Copyright © 1982 by
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc., Mahwah, NJ, p. 140. Reprinted by permission.
Readers engage in a large number of jumps of eye fixation, called saccades. The
fixations between these quick jumps usually last at least a quarter of a second.
Figure 11.3 illustrates the eye movements of one college student while reading
a text. Readers tend to make one fixation on each word, sometimes skipping less
important words and sometimes making more than one fixation on long or dif-
ficult words. When a reader fixates on a word, that word is centered so that its
image falls on the fovea, which is the most sensitive part of the retina of the eye.
Normally, people are successful only in detecting letters that are close to the
fovea, and they perceive no more than 10 characters to the left or right of the
fovea (McConkie & Rayner, 1974). Thus, people can read at most a few words in
a particular fixation.
As the difficulty of the text increases, the length of fixations, number of fix-
ations per line, and number of regressions also increase. A regression is return-
ing to a previously read word. One minor regression is illustrated in Figure 11.3.
The average adult can read material of average difficulty at a rate between 200
and 400 words per minute; more adults read nearer the 200-word rate than the
400-word rate. The reading rate for adults is limited not by perceptual or ortho-
graphic skills, but by comprehension skills. Adults also cannot follow spoken
text at much faster than 200 to 400 words per minute. For adults, individual dif-
ferences in the comprehension of spoken material are the best predictors of
individual differences in the comprehension of written materials (Jackson &
McClelland, 1979; Sticht, 1972).
There are three logical steps to reading skill. One step is the perceptual
skill of identifying the individual graphemes (letters). For a language with an
alphabet, this skill is relatively easy; for example, English has only 26 graphemes
that need to be recognized. For a language with thousands of characters, such
as Japanese or Chinese, this identification is much more challenging, and chil-
dren spend many years mastering it. The second step of reading is the ortho-
graphic step. Orthography is concerned with going from symbol combinations
389
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
390
Reading Instruction
tified who can pronounce regular words and nonwords but have trouble with
exception words (Castles & Coltheart, 1993; Manis, Seidenberg, Doi, McBride-
Chang, and Peterson). .
An average successful adult reader has put an enormous amount of time
into mastering this skill—students may have spent 10,000 hours reading by the
time they reach college. The effort put into reading is commensurate with the
complexity of the skill. Over this period of learning, there is a pattern of skill
development such that measures of letter recognition best predict reading skill
in the first grade, measures of orthographic knowledge best predict reading per-
formance in the later elementary grades (Lesgold, Resnick, & Hammond, 1985),
and measures of comprehension of spoken text best predict reading skill in
adults (Sticht & James, 1984). This situation suggests that, as children grow up,
perceptual and then orthographic components become less important, leaving
the most difficult comprehension skills as the critical factor. Even in adulthood
phonetic decoding skills contribute to the prediction of reading level, although
general language comprehension skills contribute more Jackson & McClelland,
1979). Some adults appear to have reading difficulties at the orthographic level.
As noted, dyslexia is a condition associated with impaired ability to perform the
character-to-speech transition, although dyslexics form only a small fraction of
the overall population.
This pattern of development would be predicted from a componential
analysis of reading—letter recognition must be mastered before sound can be
assigned to letter combinations, and assigning sound to letter combinations
must be mastered before the words can be comprehended. The following sec-
tions focus on phonetic decoding skills and language comprehension skills,
which are the two critical components of reading English.
391
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
te
@ Less skilled
i
2
FIGURE 11.4 Timetoreadawordas £2
a function of grade level. (From Ehri & ie
Wilce, 1983). Source: Figure 11.4 from ‘ 1.0
D. A. Hinsley, J. R. Hayes, and H. A.
Simon in M. A. Just and P. A. More skilled
Carpenter, Eds. Cognitive processes in
comprehension. Copyright © 1977 by
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc., 0 | | | _
Mahwah, NJ, p. 140. Reprinted by per- 1 2 3 4
mission. Grade
at the speed with which high school students could read pronounceable non-
sense words, such as noke or pight. Figure 11.5 shows the results as a function of
the reading level: students with higher reading abilities were faster at identify-
ing the nonsense words.
Results such as those shown in Figures 11.4 and 11.5 only indicate a cor-
relation between phonetic decoding skills and reading ability; they do not actu-
ally establish that the reading differences are caused by these phonetic skill dif-
ferences. It could be the other way around; that is, better readers may read more
and so develop their decoding skills further. Lesgold et al. (1985) showed that a
student’s phonetic decoding skills in the previous grade predict current reading
comprehension better than reading comprehension ability in the previous grade
1200
Pseudoword
5 1100 decoding
o
E
>
S 1000
s
FIGURE 11.5 Mean speed to reada pro- § 900
nounceable nonsense word as a function &
of reading level. Source: From J. R. +=
Fredriksen in A. M. Lesgold and C. A. ee
Perfetti, Eds. Interactive processes in reading.
Copyright © 1981 by Lawrence Erlbaum re | Ff
Associates, Inc., Mahwah, NJ, p. 369. Re- Lo RES STAY 35 4
printed by permission. Reading ability level
392
Reading Instruction
predicts current decoding skills. This study implies that the decoding skills
developed in one year lay the groundwork for reading gains in the next year.
To strongly establish the direction of causality, it must be shown that
improving phonetic decoding skills directly improves reading skills. The fre-
quent success of phonics-based reading programs (Adams, 1990; Beck, 1981;
Chall, 1967; Johnson & Baumann, 1984) is one piece of evidence. More focused
studies show that phonemic training does help reading skills, at least in the
early grades. A study by Lundberg, Frost, and Petersen (1988) looked at the
effect of teaching Danish kindergarten children phonological skills to identify
the sounds that make words such as tom. This sound training involved no prac-
tice reading. Children were trained to identify beginning sounds, end sounds,
vowels, and the like. The training proved useful when the children entered a
regular reading program in the first grade. They were able to read more words
correctly, and they maintained this advantage into the second grade. Another
study, by Ehri and Wilce (1987), looked at the effect of spelling training on read-
ing. Spelling is a major exercise in understanding the orthography of the lan-
guage. Kindergarten children who were given spelling training showed better
ability to read new words.
Adams (1990) argued that successful reading depends on practicing these
phonetic decoding skills to the point at which they become automatic. Recall
from the discussion of automaticity in Chapter 9 that people are better able to
concentrate on high-level skills when the low-level components are automated.
In the case of reading, people can concentrate on comprehending the text when
they no longer have to worry about decoding the words.
Comprehension Skills
Comprehension skills play an increasingly important role in the later grades.
These skills can be analyzed and trained. One of the more successful training
programs was Palinscar and Brown’s (1984) reciprocal teaching program. They
identified four basic strategies that foster comprehension: summarizing, clarify-
ing of difficulties, asking a question that could appear on a test, and making a
prediction about upcoming content. They worked on a one-on-one basis with
seventh-grade students who were performing at the 20th percentile of their
class in reading scores. The researchers modeled how to perform these activities
and slowly encouraged the students to do the same. Table 11.1 illustrates the
modeling with one seventh grader of question-asking skills over a 15-day peri-
od. After this training program, the students were scoring at the 56th percentile,
and they maintained their improved achievement two months later.
The Palinscar and Brown method is simply a more extensive version of the
kinds of study-skill programs discussed in Chapter 6, which work by creating
393
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
5 < “NI
TEXT: Perhaps you are wondering where the lava and other volcanic products come from. Deep
within our earth there are pockets of molten rock called magma. Forced upward in part by
gas pressure, this molten rock continually tries to reach the surface. Eventually—by means
of cracks in the crustal rocks or some similar zone of weakness—the magma may break
out of the ground. It then flows from the vent as lava, or spews skyward as dense clouds
of lava particles.
22. S: How does the pressure from below push the mass of hot rock against the opening?
Is that it?
23. T: Not quite. Start your question with,“What happens when?”
24. S: What happens when the pressure from below pushes the mass of hot rock against the
opening?
25. T: Good for you! Good job.
Day 15:
TEXT: Scientists also come to the South Pole to study the strange lights that glow overhead dur-
ing the Antarctic night. (It’s a cold and lonely world for the few hardy people who“ winter
over” the polar night). These“southern lights” are caused by the Earth acting like a magnet
on electrical particles in the air. They are clues that may help understand the Earth’s core
and the upper edges of its blanket of air.
28. 5S: Why do scientists comes to the South Pole to study?
29. T: Excellent question! That is what this paragraph is all about.
LL
:
SSS
Source: From A. S. Palinscar and A. L. Brown, Cognition and instruction. Copyright © 1984 by
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc., Mahwah, NJ. Reprinted by permission.
394
Reading Instruction
more elaborative representations of the text. Palinscar and Brown’s effort was
more successful than most programs because it involved 15 days of training,
which is a good deal more than in most experimental studies. Their research
emphasizes two critical points about reading comprehension. First, an impor-
tant measure of reading comprehension is memory, and successful readers are
those who can remember more from what they read. Second, the kinds of skills
that go into achieving good memory performance are hardly automatic and
require extensive training, as does any other kind of skill.
When reading, it is important to be able to appreciate the main points of
paragraphs and how other points relate to the main points. So, for instance, the
points in this paragraph are all organized as evidence for the main point in the
preceding sentence (and what was that point?). Meyer, Brandt, and Bluth (1978)
found that many ninth graders were poor at recognizing the relationship of var-
ious points in a paragraph to one another. Poorer readers tended to be less
skilled in identifying the main points of a piece of text. In a companion study,
Bartlett (1978) found that a program to train students to identify the main points
of paragraphs and their relationships more than doubled their recall perfor-
mance. Once the students identified the main points, they could organize the
rest of the text with respect to these points.
Dansereau and his colleagues (Dansereau, 1978; Dansereau, Collins,
McDonald, Holley, Garland, Diekhoff, & Evans, 1979; Holley, Dansereau,
McDonald, Garland, & Collins, 1979) taught a networking strategy for identify-
ing the main points of a passage. This strategy involved identifying all the ideas
in a text and the relationships among them and then drawing a network show-
ing the relationships. The types of relationships included part of, type of, leads
to (causal), and characteristic of. Figure 11.6 shows a network representation of
a passage on wounds from a nursing textbook. The strategy led to about a 50
percent improvement in the recall of low-GPA students but did not benefit
high-GPA students. Apparently, high-GPA students already had effective strate-
gies for organizing text material.
The studies reviewed here were concerned with reading to extract factual
information from a text. Such a reading strategy is appropriate to texts such as
this, but extracting such information is just one purpose of reading. The purpose
of reading a mathematics or physics text can be different; for example, the goal
might be to extract information about problem-solving procedures. Chi,
Bassock, Lewis, Riemann, and Glaser (1989) showed that successful readers of
such texts spend a great deal of time trying to understand examples of problem-
solving procedures. When reading these examples, they try to imagine them-
selves going through the steps of the problem and compare what they do with
the example.
395
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
Scar tissue
is weak
Discussion
of wounds
Take steps to
p p c Aahe
minimize scars
Process of
ee wound healing
t t p p
t t p
c Cc c ql 7
peer ee
Soft, pink
and
friable
FIGURE 11.6 A network of a chapter from a nursing textbook, from Holley et al.,
1979). Note that p = part of, t = type of, 1 = leads to, and c = characteristic of. Source:
From C. D. Holley, D. F. Dansereau, B. A.McDonald, J. C. Garland, and K. W. Collins.
Contemporary Educational Psychology, Volume 4. Evaluation of a hierarchical mapping
technique as an aid to prose processing. Copyright © 1976 by Academic Press. Reprinted
by permission.
396
Mathematics Instruction
teaching method, reading skill requires learning and automating a lot of specif-
ic orthographic knowledge, which requires a great deal of time. In addition, a
major part of adult reading skill overlaps with adult listening skills; by practic-
ing listening to complex communications, people are also practicing skills rele-
vant to reading.
Not everything relevant to reading is being taught. The large effects pro-
duced by the training programs of Palinscar and Brown and of Bartlett are evi-
dence that schools are not doing everything they can to instruct reading. In par-
ticular, it seems that the goal of schools is to create students who have mastered
the orthographic component of reading. More effort needs to be given to read-
ing for special purposes, such as retention of concepts and facts and acquisition
of problem-solving procedures; more attention also needs to be given to train-
ing the cognitive components involved in reading for these special purposes.
Perhaps the lack of adequate training of reading skills for particular purposes
comes from an unfortunate tendency to align reading instruction with literature
instruction. The goal in reading a poem or a novel is literary appreciation.
Although undoubtedly an important ability, this is only one reason for reading.
A major flaw in most educational programs is the belief that reading for literary
appreciation prepares a student to read for other purposes. This belief reflects a
lack of task analysis, which would readily reveal the different goals of different
reading activities.
Mathematics Instruction
Controversy surrounds the subject of what the target of mathematics instruction
should be, and this controversy is reflected in the waves of curriculum reform
that have occurred in U.S. mathematics education. In the 1960s, the new math
movement attempted to conform to modern conceptions of mathematics and to
develop mathematics in school as a mathematician would. This movement was
followed by the back-to-basics movement in the 1970s and 1980s, which
emphasized developing perfection of traditional mathematical skills, such as
addition facts or the solution of linear equations. This approach has now large-
ly been replaced by what is termed the constructivist mathematics (called” fuzzy
math’ by its critics—e.g., Gardner, 1998), which focuses on having children dis-
cover mathematics for themselves and relate mathematics to their experiences
in everyday life. This newest movement is motivated in part by the observation
that many students do not value mathematics and do not see it as having any
practical role in their lives. Each of these movements has some intrinsic merit.
However, there was nothing about society in the 1960s that made formal math-
ematics more essential then, or about the 1980s that especially required basic
397.
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
skills, or about today that especially requires making mathematics practical and
relevant. The goals of formal appreciation, proficiency, and practicality are
always desirable. Each has its constituency, and the different fashions reflect
which constituency momentarily has the attention of mathematics education.
As noted earlier, the result for teachers is disaster. Teachers no sooner learn how
to teach to promote one goal than they find that the curriculum goals have
changed. Few nations undergo such rapid changes in the goals of their mathe-
matics curriculum as the United States.
Fad is not the only reason for curriculum change. The nature of mathe-
matics is changing. Mathematics is a developing subject, and there are new
domains that may be important to teach to children. The computer revolution is
requiring a major rethinking of the kind of skills that should be expected of chil-
dren. As much as a year of a child’s mathematics education may be spent learn-
ing the long-division algorithm. This seems rather wasteful in the era of calcu-
lators. Schools are abandoning teaching the long-division algorithm just as they
long ago gave up teaching children the algorithm for calculating square roots.
Algebraic skills that were formerly the domain of high school mathematics
classes and college calculus classes can also be embedded in a hand-held calcu-
lator. Calculators are available that can solve an equation with the push of a but-
ton, differentiate it, or integrate it. Everywhere educators must ask themselves
what is still important to teach. Also changing are the practical needs of the
nation. There is relatively little need to perform routine arithmetic calculations
and greater need to be able to use mathematically based computer software,
such as spreadsheets. The need for computer literacy has increased the need for
students to understand discrete mathematics. Developments in mathematics
and the social sciences require a citizenry that is much more sophisticated in
statistics. For instance, almost everyday the news contains claims about the
effectiveness of some social program; these claims cannot be evaluated without
a considerable understanding of the statistical basis for that claim.
Another problem in achieving consensus with respect to mathematics
education lies in the different conceptions of the nature of mathematical talent.
As mentioned earlier, Americans hold an unhealthy belief that mathematical
talent is a gift and not something developed through extensive practice. It is part
of the general Western illusion that genius is something that should come
effortlessly and in great flashes of insight. Since mathematical talent is so close-
ly tied to the Western conception of intelligence, it bears an unfortunately heavy
load of this misconception about the nature of talent. The worst part of this mis-
conception is a resistance to believing that mathematical talent can be analyzed
into its component skills and that these skills can be taught.
This section considers several mathematical skills that have been success-
fully analyzed into their components, including knowledge of basic arithmetic
facts, multicolumn subtraction skills, solution of algebraic word problems, and
proof skills in geometry. This section ends with a review of the debate about the
value of such mathematical skills.
398
Mathematics Instruction
399
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
tions create false facts, which can interfere with memory. Also, similar facts will
interfere with one another. Occasionally, children display evidence of these
interference problems; given a problem such as 3 x 4 = ?, they recall answers
such as 15 (giving a different answer from the multiplication table) or 7 (con-
fusing multiplication and addition). Siegler showed that children are sensitive to
their state of knowledge of specific facts and only begin to recall them when
they are fairly sure of producing a correct recall.
Siegler’s analysis is a triumph of the componential approach. Children’s
ability to reproduce the addition and multiplication facts rests on mastering spe-
cific strategies and memorizing specific facts, one at a time. Final mastery is
achieved when the child has built up enough strength for each correct fact to
overcome the interference inherent in the addition and multiplication tables.
Further practice brings automaticity, which facilitates using this knowledge in
more complex algorithms. For instance, Haverty (1999) has found that by
increasing students’ fluency in basic mathematics facts, she would improve their
ability to solve induction problems.
Multicolumn Subtraction
Multicolumn subtraction involves solving problems, such as:
3206
—1147
400
Mathematics Instruction
identify the student’s bugs. In one experiment, BUGGY processed the solutions
of 1300 students and found that 40 percent had systematic bugs. The program
has also been used to help train teachers to diagnose various bugs.
401
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
5g02 "foe
-3a7 -4586
aZas 306
4. Stop-borrow-at-zero. The student fails to decrement 0, although he or she adds 10 correctly to
the top digit of the active column.
70,3 60,4
-678 -~367
179 307
5. Don’t decrement-zero. When borrowing from a column in which the top digit is 0, the student
rewrites the 0 at 10 but does not change the 10 to 9 when incrementing the active column.
For 'L,0,5
- 368 9
344+ 1/06
6. Zero-instead-of-borrow. The student writes 0 as the answer in any column in which the bottom
digit is larger than the top.
326 S42
= ist “389
zIO zoo
7. Borrow-from-bottom-instead-of-zero. If the top digit in the column being borrowed from is 0,
the student borrows from the bottom digit instead.
TOr 50,6
-3 £8 -489
4354 03
Source: From L. Resnick in T. P. Carpenter, J. M. Moser, and T. A. Romberg, Eds. Addition and sub-
traction: a cognitive perspective. Copyright © 1982-by Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc., Mahwah,
NJ. Reprinted by permission.
is the cost of five lemons at 35 cruzeros apiece?) when they could not solve the
equivalent classroom problem (5 x 35 = ?). Perhaps more disturbing to mathe-
matics educators is evidence of children who can solve the formal mathematics
402
Mathematics Instruction
Source: D. A. Hinsley, J. R. Hayes, and H. A. Simon (1977). From words to equations: Meaning and
representation in algebra word problems. In M. A. Just and P. A. Carpenter (Eds.) Cognitive process-
es in comprehension. Copyright © 1977 by Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc., Mahwah, NJ, pages
93-94. Reprinted by permission.
problems but who cannot apply mathematics outside the classroom. This issue
has been studied using algebraic word problems, where students must use
knowledge of algebra to solve problems stated verbally.
Table 11.4 gives some of the examples of the algebraic word problems fre-
quently used in high school geometry texts. Many students who have mastered
the mechanics of algebra find such problems difficult. Mayer (1987) and Singley,
Anderson, Givens, and Hoffman (1989) conducted task analyses of what is
involved in solving such problems. These analyses identified four major stages:
comprehension, equation embellishment, combination of information, and
algebraic symbol manipulation.
1. Comprehension. Although their language comprehension abilities are gen-
erally adequate, many high school students lack the ability to process appropri-
ately the kinds of linguistic expressions that are used to communicate mathe-
matical relationships. A particularly notorious example was studied by Soloway,
Lochhead, and Clement (1982), who asked subjects to translate the following
assertion:”There are six times as many students as professors at this university.”
Many students translated this as 6S = P rather than 6P = S.
403
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
The reader might be helped by Figure 11.7, but such aids are typically not given
to the student. The output of comprehending this problem should include
assignments, such as:
a. Total length = 20
b. Total width = 14
c. Picture area = 160
This list represents some of the equations required to solve the problem, but, as
shown in the next stage, it does not include all the equations.
2. Equation embellishment. Problems like this picture-frame problem require
recognizing the type of situation and stating a set of equations to describe that
situation. For this problem, the additional equations include:*
d. Total area = Picture area + Frame area
e. Total area = Total width x Total length
f. Picture area = Picture width x Picture length
g. Total length = Picture length + 2 x Frame width
h. Total width = Picture width + 2 x Frame width
Since this information is not contained in the problem statement, students must
embellish the problem with an appropriate mathematical model, as shown.
Students often find it easier to come up with these relationships if they draw a
diagram such as that shown in Figure 11.7. The example given is a case of the pic-
ture-frame problem, but there are many other types of problems, and students
appear to master each separately. Table 11.4 includes some of the other types.
Mayer (1987) found approximately 100 problem types in typical algebra texts.
3. Combination of information. The information has to be combined to find
the desired quantity. If x is the width of the picture frame, these steps of combi-
nation might be
i. 20 = Picture length+ 2x (combining a and g)
j. 14 = Picture width + 2x (combining b and h)
k. 160 = (20 — 2x)(14 — 2x) (combining c, i, and j)
Students have great difficulty in seeing the appropriate combinations of equa-
tions to achieve the quantity they want.
* All these equations are required to solve this problem, but they do come up in other
picture-frame problems.
404
Mathematics Instruction
Frame
Picture Z width (x)
area (160)
(20)
length
Total
405
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
(a) X
4 M Z Prove YT= ZW
STATEMENT REASON
M is midpoint of YZ Given
YM = MZ Definition of midpoint
OY Given
LXV LON EXE Base angles of isosceles triangles
ZWMY = ZTMZ Given
AWMY = ATMZ Angle-side-angle (ASA)
WY =TZ Corresponding parts
WL 2 Reflexive
AWYZ = ATZY Side-angle-side (SAS)
YT =ZW Corresponding parts
(b) YT =ZW
Y
CORRESPONDING
PARTS
AWYZ = ATZY
Y
SAS
fies
ieee BING
VZ=VZ WY =TZ
REFLEXIVE CORRESPONDING
PARTS
AWMY = ATMZ
YM = MZ LXYZ = LXZY
Midpoint lsosceles
406
Mathematics Instruction
3 Where the letters A, B, C, and D are variables that can match to any letters in the
problem.
407
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
The first step in creating such a tutor is to work with educators to develop
a computer interface for the instruction of the skill. This interface will be a pow-
erful system for doing mathematical problem solving. Figure 11.9 illustrates a
system for solving problems in algebra. It consists of a spreadsheet, a graphing
facility, and a symbol manipulation facility. The tutor teaches students to use
these three types of mathematics software to solve real-world problems, such as
the one illustrated in Figure 11.9.
After designing the interface, the next step is to develop a cognitive model
of the knowledge that students must have to solve the problems posed in that
interface. Such a modelis created as a production system and is quite capable
of solving the problems given to students. This model serves two major instruc-
tional goals. First, the production rules are the instructional objectives. Second,
because the model is created as a working program, it can run along with the
student to help the computer tutor understand what the student is doing to
solve the problem.
Then the instructional component is prepared. This includes instruction
on the individual productions and a system of hints and corrections that the
computer tutor can provide during the problem solving. The tutor is able to
point out to students where they are making errors and steer them in the cor-
rect direction, avoiding much of the confusion and wasted time that normally
occurs as students practice a problem-solving skill.
Finally, a curriculum plan and a set of mastery criteria are prepared. These
are used to guide the students through the material in a way that ensures that
they reach mastery on the underlying production rules. Figure 11.9 shows a
408
Mathematics Instruction
?
4o3n{ aAniuba) | euqabry
Sahessayy
sytun BuKyquapy
k
) Busyjeus
quunu
sua
Buse)
suafajui puly
aayebau’)
adojs‘x
aAyebau
adojs
puly adojs
puly
“y%
aanisod
Wd
Buvaquy
edie
puly
“A
aanisod
adojs
40:9anf
juapnis
G2@S
Penqns
=X1¢0+S¢S
0S8 SZE
X10
=
FEUM
Aq
éj12S)
Op
0}
yI0q
SepIs
0]
386
X
Ue?
NOA
SIQeLIeA
jeu! jsoo
JOO)
LUOY
WO
‘Slay|IIM USdSn U4]
[EIU
00S 1! BulALUp 2q IIIA 2MJIZH Wow) 49N.Q Oy] JUS4 0} S091 PINOM YON MOH] “E
SIL
|IIM UAL
£ZHOH
ebseyo
Sa ASN
Ue
JO
saludo
‘ZLWaH
JSOD PUB
WY
“AuBduiod
Jeyjouy ‘Auedwios
SY] USALIP
YONA
FEUY
POU OS SEI/LU
/RQUaH
oMbUBDS
dja
ANY
JO
smopuLM
“ojiuied
“USALIPsug
S}4] JOqUUNU
SY]
HuAUSA
JSSYSHAOAA
“SSM
SALIP
94]
DSBS
0] sn Joy ¢7¢$ snid 120gsed “aij
Jo O]
YO!WS SjILU
JO)
BIUI9I She} JON.QJOY SUO
“SHE}OP PSSU
ydeig saalos
S[qeeA
WO) &ZUPH
e [Jo]JO
SM
payebpnq
coe
Ul
PIMOM
}S09Jo}
YSOo
peuoRIPpe
B
SULJSp
jEAIU! SBIILU sd¥7100
SH¥71100
SAA
Usd
I
“BINUUOS Z2143H
SATIN
N3AldC
“| J} ara eaey
Uy AUBLUMOH
31pz
SAPJY aM
PaoU
0]
SIIEUA,
Sy]
snjdue
YONA
aly
104
SA\
'Z “p
éSlay pinom
3q
élenbs
yoes
Aueduios84]
ZS}
0}
SLIM
SEIN
PUYON
S4y
ISO9
BuQUS!
Sy]
ISOO
Jo
BUNUSI
ou]
Yong
WOY
10) LUOY
“SLAY
PB
ajdwexy
jo
ay}
eigasye
prom
wia,qoid
AUNOL
6IL
‘Ioyn}
409
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
window that displays for students how well they are doing on the component
skills (production rules). Skills are associated with identifying the units of mea-
surement, determining appropriate bounds for the graph, and identifying the
points of intersection.
Table 11.5 presents a short interaction with the LISP tutor, which has been
teaching a course in LISP at Carnegie Mellon University since 1984. LISP has
been the main programming language of artificial intelligence. The student in
this example is writing a function to convert temperature from Celsius to
Fahrenheit. The table shows the tutor and the student interacting in a series of
cycles in which the student types some code, the tutor responds with a com-
ment, and the student writes some more code. Note that the tutor can monitor
what the student is doing on a symbol-by-symbol basis, judging each symbol as
it comes in. It can provide such articulate instruction because, behind the scenes,
it is solving the problem in a symbol-by-symbol basis just as the student is. The
tutor can provide cogent help and correction as needed. Students working with
the LISP tutor are able to reach the same level of achievement as students in a
conventional classroom in one-third the time (Corbett & Anderson, 1990).
A number of tutors, such as those for algebra and geometry, have achieved
similar successes in instruction. In each case, success depends on a careful
analysis that identifies the cognitive components (production rules) underlying
successful performance. With these components identified, the tutor is then able
to provide intelligent instruction directed to the underlying skill. As Table 11.5
410
Mathematics Instruction
illustrates, this instruction can be tailored to the particular student. The success
of the tutors is evidence that the learning of a complex skill is produced by the
learning processes reviewed in this book taking place on the individual compo-
nents of the skill. Today thousands of high school students throughout the
United States are learning their mathematics from such tutors (Koedinger,
Anderson, Hadley, & Mark, 1997). Evidence indicates that they are performing
about one standard deviation or a letter grade above students in comparable
control classrooms. I expect that some of the graduates of this program will go
on to college and read this text.
The approach taken by the tutors has a lot in common with the mastery
learning approaches reviewed earlier. Although the tutors typically result in
somewhat higher achievement gains, other mastery approaches also result in
achievement gains. Nonetheless, traditional mastery classrooms largely disap-
peared in part because such classrooms were difficult to manage. On this score
the tutoring approach has an advantage. Each computer tutor is in effect a
teaching assistant to the teacher, helping the teacher manage the learning of a
particular student.
Teachers in tutored classrooms report that their experiences are fulfilling
(e.g., Wertheimer, 1990). When students are learning with these tutors, the
teachers circulate around the class, providing instruction to the students for
whom the tutor’s explanations are not adequate. Teachers are the ultimate
domain experts, focusing on the difficult learning problems and leaving the sim-
ple learning problems to the computer.
411
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
412
Final Reflections
Lave went far beyond the evidence, although there may be some truth to
her conclusions. Since all her participants were expert at best-buy calculations,
there was no room for a relationship to be found between that skill and any-
thing else. Not all people perform all real-world tasks at uniformly high levels
of excellence. As any employer can testify, different workers vary widely in the
quality of their job performance. Numerous studies show modest to large cor-
relations between school achievement and work performance (e.g., Boissiere,
Knight & Sabot, 1985; Hunter & Hunter, 1984), even after partialing out the
effects of general ability measures (which are sometimes larger).
Whatever the final verdict on Lave’s arguments, they highlight the difficult
issues that society faces about the role of mathematics in everyday life and the role
it should have in the classroom. The lack of answers and consensus is part of what
fuels the never-ending reforms of the mathematics curriculum. As noted earlier,
the consequence of the reform-crazy movement in the United States is that math-
ematics educators never settle on a curriculum long enough to teach it well.
Final Reflections
The news media in the United States is full of proclamations on the failure of
the educational system. As discussed previously, these claims of failure are a bit
overstated. Part of the failure to reach levels of high achievement in the United
States reflects the lack of economic equity in the society. It is a serious mistake
to burden the school systems with trying to patch up a problem whose source
is elsewhere. Even with its diverse population, the United States does reason-
ably well in the instruction of reading but is failing dismally in international
comparisons of achievement in mathematics. The explanation for the disparity
in reading and mathematics achievement is largely in the amount of time spent
in mathematics instruction and in the pernicious belief in the United States that
mathematics achievement is a matter of talent rather than effort. Poor achieve-
ment is further exacerbated by the failure of the mathematics education com-
munity to stay committed to a specific curriculum.
Success in learning a subject, such as mathematics, is not just a function of
the amount of time spent in the classroom and doing homework. As this book
has shown in many ways, how the time is spent is critical. Some ways of repre-
senting the skill are more effective than others. In the case of reading instruction,
for example, although students can learn to read by both the phonics method
and the whole-word method, the phonics method appears to be more success-
ful, probably because it teaches a more efficient method for reading English.
Frequently, however, the problem is not that there are competing ways of
teaching a skill, but that there is no way of teaching the skill. With respect to
413
CHAPTER 11 Applications to Education
Further Readings
Several texts describe the application of the psychology of learning and cognition
to instruction, including those by Farnham-Diggory (1992), Gagné, Yekovich, and
Yekovich (1993), and Mayer (1987). Stevenson and Stigler (1992) wrote a popu-
lar and psychologically informed comparison of educational achievement in
Japan and the United States. Gagné, Briggs, and Wager (1988) present a series of
papers on instructional technology. Just and Carpenter (1987) provide a thorough
analysis of the reading process and apply that analysis to educational issues.
Adams (1990) offers a good discussion of reading and the phonics method.
Anderson, Corbett, Koedinger, and Pelletier (1995) describe their intelligent
tutoring work and its application to mathematics education. Two other major
efforts to bring cognitive psychology to the classroom are described in Brown &
Campione (1996) and Cognition and Technology Group and Vanderbilt (1997).
Westbury (1992) and Baker (1993) engage in an informed debate about the sig-
nificance of the differences in mathematical achievement between Japan and the
United States. Bruer (1993) describes a number of cognitively inspired applica-
tions for education. Some of the best informed general discussions of education
are found in a book edited by Ravitch (1998).
414
Glossary
415
Glossary
416
Glossary
417
Glossary
418
Glossary
free recall: A memory paradigm in which’ | iconic memory: Neisser’s term for visu-
items are presented one at a time and, al sensory memory.
then subjects can recall them in any order. © implicit-memories:—Memories that a
frontal cortex: The region at the front of person is not consciously aware of
the cerebral cortex that includes the retrieving.
motor cortex and the prefrontal cortex. induction: The process by which a sys-
frontal lobes: Frontal cortex. tem makes inferences about the structure
functional magnetic resonance imaging of the environment from its experience
({MRI): Measurement of metabolic with that environment.
activity by measuring the magnetic field inductive inference: An _ uncertain
produced by the iron in oxygenated blood. inference about the state of the world
based on experience with that world.
generalization: When a behavior is inductive learning: Learning by means
evoked by a stimulus other than the one of inductive inferences.
it was conditioned to. information-processing approach: “An
generalization gradient: Representa- approach in cognitive psychology that
tion of the tendency of various stimuli to theorizes about information in the
evoke a conditioned response. abstract and how it progresses through
generate-recognize theory: A theory of the cognitive system.
free recall that claims that subjects gen- inhibition: A response suppression
erate candidate items and then recognize caused by factors such as fatigue and
which ones they have studied. extinction.
generation effect: People tend to dis- inhibitory synapses: Synapses where
play better memory for material they the neurotransmitters decrease the
generate for themselves. potential difference across the mem-
global maximization: The theory that brane of a neuron.
an organism will choose a pattern of innerear: The part of Baddeley’s phono-
responding that will lead to optimal out- logical loop responsible for perceiving
come overall. inner speech.
goal: The desired state in solving a prob- inner voice: The part of Baddeley’s
lem. phonological loop responsible for gener-
ating inner speech.
habituation: Repeated presentation of instinctive drift: The tendency for ani-
the US can result in a reduced magnitude mals to revert to innate, species-specific
in the UR evoked by that US. response patterns in a learning experi-
hippocampus: The subcortical area that ment.
plays a critical role in the formation of instrumental conditioning: The proce-
permanent memories. dure in which a reinforcement is made
419
Glossary
420
Glossary
emotional tone of the material the sub- changes the frequency of a response type
ject is trying to recall. in the environment.
motor program: A __ prepackaged operator: An action that transforms one
sequence of actions that can be executed problem-solving state into another prob-
according to different parameters with- lem-solving state.
out central control. operator subgoaling: If an operator
cannot be applied to achieve a goal, the
natural categories: Categories of problem solver sets a subgoal to trans-
objects that are found in the real world, form the state so that the operator can be
such as“ dog” or“ tree.” applied.
negative acceleration: A property of opponent process: A mechanism that is
functions, such as learning curves or evoked when a stimulus evokes a strong
retention curves, whereby the rate of response in one direction; this mecha-
change becomes smaller and smaller. nism produces a compensatory response
in the opposite direction.
negative reinforcement: An _instru-
mental conditioning procedure in which optimal-foraging theory: The theory
an aversive stimulus is made contingent that organisms forage for food so as to
on omission of a response. maximize their net energy gain (food
intake minus energy spent foraging).
negative transfer: The phenomenon
that learning of earlier material impairs
the learning of later material. paired-associate learning: A memory
procedure in which the subject learns to
nerve impulse: Action potentials that
give a response when presented with a
move down axons.
stimulus.
neurons: The cells in the brain that are
parietal lobe: The region at the top of
most directly responsible for neural
the cerebral cortex that is involved in
information processing. higher level sensory functions.
neurotransmitters: Chemicals that partial-reinforcement extinction effect:
cross the synapse from the axon of one The phenomenon that animals show
neuron to alter the electrical potential of greater resistance to extinction when
the membrane of another neuron. trained under a partial reinforcement
schedule.
occipital lobe: The region at the back of partial-reinforcement schedule: A
the cerebral cortex that is devoted main- reinforcement schedule that reinforces
ly to vision. only some of the organism’s responses.
omission training: An instrumental peak shift: The phenomenon in discrim-
conditioning procedure in which a desir- ination learning that maximal response is
able stimulus is made contingent on gotten to stimuli shifted away from the
omission of a response. positive stimulus in a direction that is also
open-loop performance: A sequence of away from the negative stimulus.
actions performed without waiting for phonics method: A method of reading
feedback from the results of earlier instruction that emphasizes going from
actions before performing later actions. letter combinations to sound.
operant: A term Skinner used to describe phonological loop: The system pro-
an action, such as a lever press, that pro- posed by Baddeley for rehearsing verbal
duced some change in the environment. information by silently saying it over and
operant conditioning: Learning that over again.
421
Glossary
422
Glossary
423
Glossary
424
Glossary
425
Bibliography
426
Bibliography
427
Bibliography
Arkes, H. R., Hackett, C., & Boehm, L. (1989). The generality of the relation between
familiarity and judged validity. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 2, 81-94.
Atkinson, R. C., & Juola, J. F. (1973). Factors influencing speed and accuracy of word
recognition. In S. Kornblum (Ed.), Attention and performance (Vol. IV, pp. 583-612). New
York: Academic Press. :
Atkinson, R. C., & Juola, J. F. (1974). Search and decision processes in recognition
memory. In D. H. Krantz, R. C. Atkinson, R. D. Luce, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Contemporary
developments in mathematical psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 242-293). San Francisco: W. H.
Freeman.
Atkinson, R. C., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1968). Human memory: A proposed system and its
control processes. In K. W. Spence & J. T. Spence (Eds.), The psychology of learning and
motivation (Vol. 2). New York: Academic Press.
Atkinson, R. C., Bower, G. H., & Crothers, E. J. (1965). Introduction to mathematical learn-
ing theory. New York: Wiley.
Atkinson, R. L., Atkinson, R. C., & Hilgard, E. R. (1983). Introduction to psychology (8th
ed.). San Diego: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Ayres, T. J., Jonides, J., Reitman, J. S., Egan, J. C., & Howard, D. A. (1979). Differing suffix
effects for the same physical suffix. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning
and Memory, 5, 315-321.
Azrin, N. H., & Holz, W. C. (1966). Punishment. In W. K. Honig (Ed.), Operant behavior:
Areas of research and application. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Azrin, N. H., Holz, W. C., & Hake, D. F. (1963). Fixed-ratio punishment. Journal of the
Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 6, 141-148.
Baddeley, A. D. (1986). Working memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Baddeley, A. D. (1997). Human memory: Theory and practice. Boston: Allyn & Bacon.
Baddeley, A. D., & Lewis, V. J. (1981). Inner active processes in reading: The inner voice,
the inner ear, and the inner eye. In A. M. Lesgold and C. A. Perfetti (Eds.), Interactive
processes in reading (pp. 107-129). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Baddeley, A. D., Grant, S., Wight, E., & Thomson, N. (1975). Imagery and visual working
memory. In P. M. A. Rabbit & S. Dornic (Eds.), Attention and performance, (Vol. V, pp.
205-217). London: Academic Press.
Baddeley, A. D., Lewis,V.J., & Vallar, G. (1984). Exploring the articulatory loop. Quarterly
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36, 233-252.
Baddeley, A. D., Thomson, N., & Buchanan, M. (1975). Word length and the structure of
short-term memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 14, 575-589.
Bahrick, H. P. (1979). Maintenance of knowledge: Questions about memory we forget to
ask. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 108, 296-308.
Bahrick. H. P. (1984). Semantic memory content in permastore: Fifty years of memory for
Spanish learned in school. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 113, 1-24.
Bailey, C. H., & Chen, M. (1983). Morphological basis of long-term habituation and sen-
sitization in Aplysia. Science, 220, 91-93.
Baker, D. P. (1993). Compared to Japan, the U.S. is a low achiever...Really: New evidence
and comment on Westbury. Educational Researcher, 22, 18-21.
Balota, D., & Lorch, R. (1986). Depth of automatic spreading activation: Mediated prim-
428
Bibliography
ing effects in pronunciation but not in lexical decision. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 12, 336-345.
Balsam, P. D. (1988). Selection, representation and equivalence of controlling stimuli. In
R. C. Atkinson, R. J. Herrnstein, G. Lindzey, and R. D. Luce (Eds.), Stevens’ handbook of
experimental psychology, 2nd ed., (Vol. 2, pp. 111-166). New York: Wiley.
Banich, M. T. (1997). Neuropsychology: The neural bases of mental function. Boston, MA:
Houghton Mifflin Company.
Bannerman, D. M., Good, M. A., Butcher, S. P., Ramsay, M., & Morris, R. G. M. (1995).
Distinct components of spatial learning revealed by prior training and NMDA receptor
blockade. Nature, 378, 182-186.
Barbizet, J. (1970). Human memory and its pathology. San Francisco, CA: Freeman.
Barnes, C. A. (1979). Memory deficits associated with senescence: A neurophysiological
and behavioral study in the rat. Journal of Comparative Physiology, 43, 74-104.
Bartlett, B. J. (1978). Top-level structure as an organizational strategy for recall of class-
room text. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Arizona State University.
Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Baum, W. M. (1969). Extinction of avoidance response following response prevention:
Some parametric investigations. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 23, 1-10.
Beck, B. B. (1980). Animal tool behavior: The use and manufacture of tools by animals. New
York: Garland STPM Press.
Beck, I. L. (1981). Reading problems and instructional practices. In T. S. Waller & G. E.
MacKinnon (Eds.), Reading research: Advances in theory and practice (Vol. 2). New York:
Academic Press.
Bedford, J., & Anger, D. (1968). Flight as an avoidance response in pigeons. Paper presented
to the Psychonomic Society, St. Louis.
Beecroft, R. S. (1966). Classical conditioning. Goleta, CA: Psychonomic Press.
Begg, I., Snider, A., Foley, F, & Goddard, R. (1989). The generation effect is no artifact:
Generation makes words distinctive. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory,
and Cognition, 15, 977-989.
Bekerian, D. A., & Baddeley, A. D. (1980). Saturation advertising and the repetition effect.
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 19, 17-25.
Bernstein, I. L., & Borson, S. (1986). Learned food aversion: A component of anorexia
syndromes. Psychological Review, 93, 462-472.
Bernstein, I. L., Webster, M. M., & Bernstein, I. D. (1982). Food aversions in children
receiving chemotherapy for cancer. Cancer, 50, 2961-2963.
Best, M. R., Dunn, D. P, Batson, J. D, Meachum, C. L., & Nash, S. M. (1985).
Extinguishing conditioned inhibition in flavour-aversion learning: Effects of repeated
testing and extinction of the excitatory element. Quarterly Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 37B, 359-378.
Bilodeau, E. A., & Bilodeau, I. M. (1958). Variable frequency knowledge of results and the
learning of simple skill. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 55, 379-383.
Blackburn, J. M. (1936). Acquisition of skill: An analysis of learning curves (HRB Report No.
Tay
Blaney, P. H. (1986). Affect and memory: A review. Psychological Bulletin, 99, 229-246.
429
Bibliography
Blessing, S. B. (1996). The use of prior knowledge in learning from examples. Doctoral
dissertation, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA.
Bliss, T.V.P,, & Lomo, T. (1973). Long-lasting potentiation of synaptic transmission in the
dentate area of the anesthetized rabbit following stimulation of the preforant path.
Journal of Physiology, 232, 331-356.
Bliss, T.V.P., & Lynch, M. A. (1988). Long-term potentiation of synaptic transmission in
the hippocampus: Properties and mechanisms. In P. W. Landfield and S. A. Deadwyler
(Eds.), Neurology and neurobiology: Vol.35. Long-term potentiation: From biophysics to behav-
ior. New York: Alan R. Liss.
Bloom, B. S. (1968). Learning for mastery. Evaluation Comment, 1, 2.
Bloom, B. S. (1976). Human characteristics and school learning. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Bloom, B. S. (Ed.). (1985a). Developing talent in young people. New York: Ballantine Books.
Bloom, B. S. (1985b). Generalizations about talent development. In B. S. Bloom (Ed.),
Developing talent in young people (pp. 507-549). New York: Ballantine Books.
Bloom, L. C. & Mudd, S. A. (1991). Depth of processing approach to face recognition: A
test of two theories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition,
17, 556-565.
Blough, D. S. (1959). Delayed matching in the pigeon. Journal of the Experimental Analysis
of Behavior, 2, 151-160.
Blough, D. S. (1975). Steady state data and a quantitative model of operant generalization
and discrimination. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 1, 3-21.
Bobrow, D. G., & Bower, G. H. (1969). Comprehension and recall of sentences. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 80, 455-461.
Boissiere, M., Knight, J. B., & Sabot, R. H. (1985). Earnings, schooling, ability, and cogni-
tive skills. American Economic Review, 75, 1016-1030.
Bolles, R. C. (1970). Species-specific defense reactions and avoidance learning.
Psychological Review, 77, 32-48.
Boring, E. G. (1950). A history of experimental psychology. New York: Appleton-Century.
Boring, E. G. (1953). A history of introspection. Psychological Bulletin, 50, 169-189.
Bourne, L. E., Ekstrand, B. R., & Dominowski, R. L. (1971). The psychology of thinking.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bourne, L. E., Jr. (1974).An inference model of conceptual rule learning. In R. Solso (Ed.),
Theories in cognitive psychology. Washington, DC: Erlbaum.
Bovair, S., Kieras, D. E., & Polson, P. G. (1990). The acquisition and performance of text-
editing skill: A cognitive complexity analysis. Human Computer Interaction, 5, 1-48.
Bower, G. H. (1972). Mental imagery and associative learning. In L. Gregg (Ed.), Cognition
in learning and memory. New York: Wiley.
Bower, G. H., & Clark, M. C. (1969). Narrative stories as mediators for serial learning.
Psychonomic Science, 14, 181-182.
Bower, G. H., & Hilgard, E. R. (1981). Theories of learning (5th ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Bower, G. H., & Reitman, J. S. (1972). Mnemonic elaboration in multilist learning. Journal
of Learning and Verbal Behavior, 11, 478-485.
430
Bibliography
Bower, G. H., & Springston, F. (1970). Pauses as recoding points in letter series. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 83, 421-430.
Bower, G. H., & Trabasso, T. R. (1963). Reversals prior to solution in concept identifica-
tion. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 66, 409-418.
Bower, G. H., Karlin, M. B., & Dueck, A. (1975). Comprehension and memory for pic-
tures. Memory and Cognition, 3, 216-220.
Boyd, W., & King, E. J. (1975). The history of Western education (11th ed.). Totowa, NJ:
Barnes & Noble Books.
Bradshaw, G. L., & Anderson, J. R. (1982). Elaborative encoding as an explanation of lev-
els of processing. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 21, 165-174.
Braine, M.D.S. (1971). On two types of models of the internalization of grammars. In D.
I. Slobin (Ed.), The ontogenesis of grammar: A theoretical symposium. New York: Academic
Press.
Bransford, J. D., & Franks, J. J. (1971). The abstraction of linguistic ideas. Cognitive
Psychology, 2, 331-380.
Bransford, J. D., & Johnson, M. K. (1972). Contextual prerequisites for understanding:
Some investigations of comprehension and recall. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
Behavior, 11, 717-726.
Bransford, J. D., Franks, J. J., Morris, C. D., & Stein, B. S. (1979). Some general constraints
on learning and memory research. In L. S. Cermak & FILM. Craik (Eds.), Levels of pro-
cessing in human memory (pp. 331-354). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Breland, K., & Breland, M. (1951). A field of applied animal psychology. American
Psychologist, 6, 202-204.
Breland, K., & Breland, M. (1961). The misbehavior of organisms. American Psychologist,
16, 681-684.
Brigham, J. C. (1981, November). The accuracy of eyewitness evidence: How do attorneys
see it? The Florida Bar Journal, pp. 714-721.
Broadbent, D. E. (1957). A mechanical model for human attention and immediate mem-
ory. Psychological Review, 64, 205-215.
Brodgen, W. J. (1949). Acquisition and extinction of a conditioned avoidance response in
dogs. Journal of Comparative Physiological Psychology, 42, 296-302.
Brooks, L. R. (1967). The suppression of visualization by reading. Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 19, 289-299.
Brown, A. L., & Campione, J. C. (1996). Psychology theory and the design of innovative
learning environments: On procedures, principles, and systems. In L. Schauble & R.
Glaser (Eds.) Innovations in learning: New environments for education (pp. 289-325).
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Brown, J. (1958). Some tests of decay theory of immediate memory. Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 10, 12-21.
Brown, J. S., & Van Lehn, K. (1980). Repair theory: A generative theory of bugs in proce-
dural skills. Cognitive Science, 4, 397-426.
Brown, P. L., & Jenkins, H. M. (1968). Auto-shaping of the pigeon’s key-peck. Journal of
the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 11, 1-8.
Brown, R. (1973). A first language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
431
Bibliography
Brown, R., & Fraser, C. (1963). The acquisition of syntax. In C. N. Cofer and B. Musgrave
(Eds.), Verbal behavior and learning: Problems and processes (pp. 158-201). New York:
McGraw-Hill.
Brown, R., & Kulik, J. (1977). Flashbulb memories. Cognition, 5, 73-99.
Brown, R., & McNeill, D. (1966). The “tip of the tongue” phenomenon. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 5, 325-337.
Bruer, J. T. (1993). Schools for thought: A science of learning the classroom. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Bruner, J. S., Goodnow, J. I, & Austin, G. A. (1956). A study of thinking. New York: Wiley.
Bruner, J. S., Matter, J., & Papanek, M. L. (1955). Breadth of learning as a function of drive
level and mechanization. Psychological Review, 62, 1-10.
Bullock, M., Gelman, R., & Baillargeon, R. (1982). The development of causal reasoning.
In W. Friedman (Ed.), The developmental psychology of time (pp. 209-254). New York:
Academic Press.
Burns, D. J. (1990). The generation effect: A test between single- and multifactor theories.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 16, 1060-1067.
Burns, D. J. (1992). The consequences of generation. Journal of Memory and Language, 31,
615-633.
Burton, R. R. (1982). Diagnosing bugs in a simple procedural skill. In D. Sleeman & J. S.
Brown (Eds.), Intelligent tutoring systems. New York: Academic Press.
Butler, R. A. (1953). Discrimination learning by rhesus monkeys to visual-exploration
motivation. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 46, 95-98.
California Assessment Program. (1980). Student achievement in California schools: 1979-80
annual report. Sacramento: California State Department of Education.
Camp, D. S., Raymond, G. A., & Church, R. M. (1967). Temporal relationship between
response and punishment. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 74, 114-123.
Capaldi, E. J. (1967). A sequential hypothesis of instrumental learning. In K. W. Spence &
J.T. Spence (Eds.), The psychology of learning and motivation (Vol. 1). New York: Academic
Press.
Carew, T. J., Hawkins, R. D., & Kandel, E. R. (1983). Differential classical conditioning of
a defensive withdrawal reflex in Aplysia californica. Science, 219, 397-400.
Carey, S. (1978). The child as word learner. In M. Halle, J. Bresnan, & G. Miller (Eds.),
Linguistic theory and psychological reality., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Carraher, T. N., Carraher, D. W., & Schliemann, A. D. (1985). Mathematics in the streets
and in the schools. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 3, 21-29.
Castles, A., & Coltheart, M. (1993). Varieties of developmental dyslexia. Cognition, 47,
149-180.
Catalano, J. F,, & Kleiner, B. M.(1984). Distant transfer and practice variability. Perceptual
and Motor Skills, 58, 851-856.
Catania, A. C. (1992). Learning (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Cavanagh, J. P. (1972). Relation between the immediate memory span and the memory
search rate. Psychological Review, 79, 525-530.
Ceci, S. J., Loftus, E. F., Leichtman, M. D., & Bruck, M. (1994). The possible role of source
432
Bibliography
433
Bibliography
434
Bibliography
Dansereau, D. F., Collins, K. W., McDonald, B. A., Holley, C. D., Garland, J. C., Diekhoff,
G., & Evans, S. H. (1979). Development and evaluation of an effective learning strategy
program. Journal of Educational Psychology, 71, 64-73. :
Darwin, C. (1975). The origin of the species (P. Appleman, Ed.). New York: W. W. Norton
(original work published 1859).
Darwin, C. J., Turvey, M.T., & Crowder, R. G. (1972). The auditory analogue of the Sperling
partial report procedure: Evidence for brief auditory storage. Cognitive Psychology, 3, 255-267.
Daugherty, K. G., MacDonald, M. C., Petersen, A. S., & Seidenberg, M. S. (1993). Why no
mere mortal has ever flown out to center field but people often say they do. Proceedings
of the 15th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 383-388).
Davenport, D. G., & Olson, R. D. (1968). A reinterpretation of extinction in discriminat-
ed avoidance. Psychonomic Science, 13, 5-6.
de Beer, G. R. (1959). Paedomorphesis. Proceedings of the 15th International Congress of
Zoology (pp. 927-930).
de Groot, A. D. (1965). Thought and choice in chess. The Hague, Netherlands: Mouton.
DeKeyser, R. M. (1997). Beyond explicit rule learning: Automatizing second language
morphosyntax. SSLA, 19 pp. 195-221. (Studies in Second Language Acquisition).
Dempster, F. N. (1992). The rise and fall of the inhibitory mechanism: Toward a unified
theory of cognitive development and aging. Developmental Review, 12, 45-75.
Dennis, M. (1997). Acquired disorders of language in children. In T. E. Feinberg, and M.
J. Farah (Eds.), Behavioral neurology and neuropsychology. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Dewhurst, D. J. (1967). Neuromuscular control system. IEEE Transactions on Biomedical
Engineering, 14, 167-171.
Diamond, A. (1989). Developmental progression in human infants and infant monkeys,
and the neural bases of inhibitory control of reaching. In A. Diamond (Ed.), The develop-
ment and neural bases of higher cognitive functions. New York: Academy of Science Press.
Diamond, A. (1991). Frontal lobe involvement in cognitive changes during the first year
of life. In K. R. Gibson & A. C. Peterson (eds.), Brain maturation and cognitive development:
Comparative and cross-cultual perspectives (pp. 127-180). New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
Domjan, M. (1993). The principles of learning and behavior (3rd ed.). Pacific Grove, CA:
Brooks/Cole.
Dooling, D. J., & Christiansen, R. E. (1977). Episodic and semantic aspects of memory for
prose. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 3, 428-436.
Dweck, C. (1975). The role of expectations and attributions in the alleviation of learned
helplessness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 31, 674-685.
Eagle, M., & Leiter, E. (1964). Recall and recognition in intentional and incidental learn-
ing. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 68, 58-63.
Easterbrook, J. A. (1959). The effect of emotion on cue utilization and the organization of
behavior. Psychological Review, 66, 183-201.
Ebbinghaus, H. (1913). Memory: A contribution to experimental psychology (H. A. Ruger &
C. E. Bussenues, Trans.). New York: Teachers College, Columbia University. (Original
work published 1885)
Egan, D. E., & Schwartz, B. J. (1979). Chunking in recall of symbolic drawings. Memory
and Cognition, 7, 149-158.
435
Bibliography
Ehri, L. C., & Wilce, L. C. (1983). Development of word identification speed in skilled and
less skilled beginning readers. Journal of Educational Psychology, 75, 3-18.
Ehri, L. C., & Wilce, L. C. (1987, winter). Does learning to spell help beginners learn to
read words? Reading Research Quarterly, 22.
Eich, E. (1985). Context, memory, and integrated item/context imagery. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 11, 764-770.
Eich, E., & Metcalfe, J. (1989). Mood dependent memory for internal versus external
events. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 15, 443-455.
Eich, J. E., Weingartner, H., Stillman, R. C., & Gillin, J. C. (1975). State-dependent acces-
sibility of retrieval cues in the retention of a categorized list. Journal ofVerbal Learning and
Verbal Behavior, 14, 408-417.
Eichenbaum, H. (1997). Declarative memory: Insights from cognitive neurobiology.
Annual Review of Psychology, 48, 547-572.
Eichenbaum, H. & Bunsey, M. (1995). On the binding of associations in memory: clues
from studies on the role of the hippocampal region in paired-associate learning. Current
Directions in Psychological Science, 4, 19-23.
Eichenbaum, H., Stewart, C. & Morris, R.G.M. (1990). Hippocampal representation in
spatial learning. Journal of Neuroscience, 10, 331-339.
Einhorn, H. J., & Hogarth, R. M. (1986). Judging probable cause. Psychological Bulletin, 99,
mls
Eisenberger, R., Heerdt, W. A., Hamdi, M., Zimet, S. & Bruckmeir, G. (1979). Transfer of
persistence across behaviors. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and
Memory, 5, 522-530.
Ekstrand, B. R. (1972). To sleep, perchance to dream. In C. P. Duncan, L. Sechrest, & A. W.
Melton (Eds.), Human memory: Festschrift in honor of Benton J. Underwood (pp. 59-82). New
York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Ellis, N. C.,, & Hennelly, R. A. (1980). A bilingual word-length effect: Implications for
intelligence testing and the relative ease of mental calculation in Welsh and English.
British Journal of Psychology, 71, 43-52.
Engle, R. W., & Bukstel, L. (1978). Memory processes among bridge players of differing
expertise. American Journal of Psychology, 91, 673-689.
Epstein, S. (1967). Toward a unified theory of anxiety. In B. A. Maher (Ed.), Progress in
experimental personality research (Vol. 4). New York: Academic Press.
Erickson, M. A., & Kruschke, J. K. (1998). Rules and exemplars in category learning.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 127, 107-140.
Ericsson, K. A., & Lehmann, A. C. (1994). Marks of genius? Re-interpretation of excep-
tional feats by great musicians. In The Proceedings of the 35'* Annual Meeting of the
Psychonomics Society.
Ericsson, K. A., Krampe, R.T., & Tesch-Romer, C. (1993). The role of deliberate practice in
the acquisition of expert performance. Psychological Review, 100, 363-406.
Eron, L. D., Walder, L. O., Toigo, R., & Lefkowitz, M. M. (1963). Social class, parental pun-
ishment for aggression, and child aggression. Child Development, 34, 849-867.
Ervin-Tripp, S. M. (1974). Is second language learning like the first? TESOL Quarterly, 8,
111127;
436
Bibliography
437
Bibliography
438
Bibliography
Gluck, M. A., & Myers, C. E. (1995). Representation and association in memory: a neu-
rocomputational view of hippocampal function. Current Directions in Psychological Science,
4, 23-29.
Gluck, M. A., & Myers, C. E. (1997). Psychobiological models of hippocampal function in
learning and memory. Annual Review of Psychology, 48, 481-514.
Gluck, M. A., & Thompson, R. F. (1987). Modeling the neural substrates of associative
learning and memory: A computational approach. Psychological Review, 94, 176-191.
Glucksberg, S., & Cowan, G. N,, Jr. (1970). Memory for nonattended auditory material.
Cognitive Psychology, 1, 149-156.
Godden, D. R., & Baddeley, A. D. (1975). Context-dependent memory in two natural
environments: On land and under water. British Journal of Psychology, 66, 325-331.
Goldin-Meadow, S. Butcher, C., Mylander, C., & Dodge, M. (1994). Nouns and verbs in
a self-styled gesture system: What's in a name? Cognitive Psychology, 27, 259-319.
Goldman-Rakic, P. S. (1987). Circuitry of primate prefrontal cortex and regulation of
behavior by representational memory. In Handbook of physiology. The nervous system.
Higher functions of the brain (Vol. 5, pp. 373-417). Bethesda, MD: American Physiology
Society.
Goldman-Rakic, P. S. (1988). Topography of cognition: Parallel distributed networks in
primate association cortex. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 11, 137-156.
Goldman-Rakic, P. S. (1992). Working memory and mind. Scientific American, 267,
111-117.
Goldstein, A. G., & Chance, J. E. (1970). Visual recognition memory for complex config-
urations. Perception and Psychophysics, 9, 237-241.
Good, H. G. (1962). A history of American education. New York: Macmillan.
Goodwin, D. W., Powell, B., Bremer, D., Hoine, H., & Stern, J. (1969). Alcohol and recall:
State-dependent effects in man. Science, 163, 1358-1360.
Gordon, W. C. (1989). Learning and memory. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole.
Gormezano, I. (1965). Yoked comparisons of classical and instrumental conditioning of
the eyelid response; and an addendum on“Voluntary Responders.”InW. F. Prokasy (Ed.),
Classical conditioning (pp. 48-70). New York: Appleton-Century-
Crofts.
Gormezano, I., Kehoe, E. J., & Marshall, B. S. (1983). Twenty years of classical condition-
ing research with the rabbit. In J. M. Prague & A. N. Epstein (Eds.), Progress in psychobi-
ology and physiological psychology (Vol. 10). New York: Academic Press.
Gormezano, I., Prokasy, W. F., & Thompson, R. F. (Eds.). (1987). Classical conditioning (3rd
ed.). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Graf, P., Squire, L. R., & Mandler, G. (1984). The information that amnesic patients do not
forget. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 10, 164-178.
Graf, V., Bullock, D. H., & Bitterman, M. E. (1964). Further experiments on probability
matching in the pigeon. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 7, 151-157.
Grant, D. A. (1939a). The influence of attitude on the conditioned eyelid response. Journal
of Experimental Psychology, 25, 333-346.
Grant, D. A. (1939b). A study of patterning in the conditioned eyelid response. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 25, 455-461.
Grant, D. A. (1973). Cognitive factors in eyelid conditioning. Psychophysiology, 10, 75-81.
439
Bibliography
Grant, D. A., Hunter, H. G. & Patel, A. S. (1958). Spontaneous recovery of the conditioned
eyelid response. Journal of General Psychology, 59, 135-141.
Grant, D. A., & Norris, E. B. (1947). Eyelid conditioning as influenced by the presence of
sensitized beta-responses. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 37, 423-434.
Grant, D. S. (1976). Effect of sample presentation -time on long delay matching in the
pigeon. Learning and Motivation, 7, 580-590.
Grant, D. S. (1981). Short-term memory in the pigeon. In N. E. Spear & R. Miller (Eds.),
Information processing in animals: Memory mechanisms (pp. 227-256). Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Grant, D. S., & Roberts, W.’A. (1976). Sources of retroactive inhibition in pigeon short-
term memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 2, 1-16.
Greeno, J. G. (1974). Hobbits and orcs: Acquisition of a sequential concept. Cognitive
Psychology, 6, 270-292.
Grittner, F. M. (1975). Individualized instruction: An historical perspective. The Modern
Language Journal, 323-333.
Groves, P. M. & Thompson, R. F. (1970). Habituation: A dual-process theory. Psychological
Review, 77, 419-450.
Gruneberg, M. M., & Monks, J. (1974). Feeling of knowing and cued recall. Acta
Psychologica, 38, 257-265.
Gunn, D. L. (1937). The humidity reactions of the wood louse, Porcellio scaber (Latreille).
Journal of Experimental Biology, 14, 178-186.
Guskey, T. R., & Gates, S. (1986). Synthesis of research on the effects of mastery learning
in elementary and secondary classrooms. Educational Leadership, 43, 73-80.
Guthrie, E. R. (1952). The psychology of learning (rev. ed.). New York: Harper & Row.
Guttman, N., & Kalish, H. I. (1956). Discriminability and stimulus generalization. Journal
of Experimental Psychology, 51, 79-88.
Gynther, M. D. (1957). Differential eyelid conditioning as a function of stimulus similar-
ity and strength of response to the CS. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 53, 408-416.
Haber, R. N. (1983). The impending demise of the icon: A critique of the concept of icon-
ic storage in visual information processing. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6, 1-11.
Haig, K. A., Rawlins, J.N.P., Olton, D. S., Mead, A., & Taylor, B. (1983). Food searching
strategies of rats: Variables affecting the relative strength of stay and shift strategies.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 9, 337-348.
Hammond, L. J. (1980). The effect contingency upon the appetitive conditioning of free
operant behavior. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 34, 297-304.
Harley, W. F., Jr. (1965). The effect of monetary incentive in paired-associate learning
using a differential method. Psychonomic Science, 2, 377-378.
Hart, J.T. (1967). Memory and the memory-monitoring process. Journal ofVerbal Learning
and Verbal Behavior, 6, 685-691.
Hasher, L., Goldstein, D., & Toppino,T. (1977). Frequency and the conference of referen-
tial validity. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 16, 107-112.
Haverty, L. (1999). Mathematical problem solving requires the basics: Skill with sary
number knowledge improves inductive reasoning performance. Doctoral dissertation.
Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA.
440
Bibliography
Hawkins, R. D., & Bower, G. H. (Eds.). (1989). The Psychology of Learning and Motivation:
Vol. 23. Computational models of learning in simple neural systems. San Diego: Academic
Press.
Hawkins, R. D., Abrams, T. W., Carew, T.J., & Kandel, E. R. (1983). A cellular mechanism
of classical conditioning in Aplysia: Activity-dependent amplification of presynaptic
facilitation. Science, 219, 400-404.
Hayes, C. (1951). The ape in our house. New York: Harper.
Hayes, J. R. (1985). Three problems in teaching general skills. In J. Segal, S. Chipman, &
R. Glaser (Eds.), Thinking and learning (Vol. 2). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Hayes-Roth, F., Waterman, D. A., & Lenat, D. B. (1983). Building expert systems. Reading,
MA: Addison-Wesley.
Hearst, E. (1988). Fundamentals of learning and conditioning. In R. C. Atkinson, R. J.
Herrnstein, G. Lindzey, and R. D. Luce (Eds.), Stevens’ handbook of experimental psycholo-
gy: Vol. 2. Learning and cognition (pp. 3-110). New York: Wiley.
Heath, R. G. (1963). Electrical self-stimultion of the brain in man. American Journal of
Psychitry, 120, 571-577.
Heathcote, A. & Mewhort, D.J.K. (1995). The law of practice. Poster presented at the 36th
Annual Meeting of the Psychonomic Society, Los Angeles, CA.
Heathcote, A. & Mewhort, D.J.K. (1998). A survey of the law of practice. Poster presented
at the 39th Annual Meeting of the Psychonomic Society, Dallas, TX.
Hemmes, N. S., Eckerman, D. A., & Rubinsky, H. J. (1979). A functional analysis of col-
lateral behavior under differential-reinforcement-of-low-rate schedules. Journal of
Animal Learning and Behavior, 7, 328-332.
Henry, F. M. (1968). Specificity vs. generality in learning motor skill. In R. C. Brown & G.
S. Kenyon (Eds.), Classical studies on physical activity (pp. 331-340). Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall. (Original work published 1958)
Herrnstein, R. J. (1961). Relative and absolute strength of response as a function of fre-
quency of reinforcement. Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 4, 267-272.
Herrnstein, R. J. (1990). Rational choice theory. American Psychologist, 45, 356-367.
Herrnstein, R. J., & Vaughan, W. (1980). Melioration and behavioral allocation. In J.E.R.
Staddon (Ed.), Limits to action: The allocation of individual behavior. New York: Academic
Press,
Herrnstein, R. J., Loveland, D. H., & Cable, C. (1976). Natural concepts in pigeons. Journal
of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 2, 285-302.
Heyman, G. M., & Luce, R. D. (1979). Operant matching is not a logical consequence of
maximizing reinforcement rate. Animal Learning & Behavior, 7, 133-140.
Hillman, B., Hunter, W. S., & Kimble, G. A. (1953). The effect of drive level on the maze
performance of the white rat. Journal of Comparative Physiological Psychology, 46, 87-89.
Hineline, P. N., & Rachlin, H. (1969). Escape and avoidance of shock by pigeons pecking
a key. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 12, 533-538.
Hinton, G. E. (1992). How neural networks learn from experience. Scientific American,
267, 145-151.
Hintzman, D. L. (1992). Mathematical constraints and the Tulving-Wiseman law.
Psychological Review, 99, 536-542.
441
Bibliography
Hintzman, D. L., Block, R. A., & Summers, J. J. (1973). Modality tags and memory for repe-
titions: Locus of the spacing effect. Journal ofVerbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 12, 229-238.
Hiroto, D. S., & Seligman, M.E.P. (1975). Generality of learned helplessness in man.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 31, 311-327.
Hirshman, E., & Bjork, R. A. (1988). The generation effect: Support for a two-factor the-
ory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 14, 484-494.
Hirshman, E., Whelley, M. M., & Palu, M. (1989). An investigation of paradoxical memo-
ry effects. Journal of Memory and Language, 28, 594-609.
Hirst, W., Phelps, E. A., Johnson, M. K., & Volpe, B. T. (1988). Amnesia and second lan-
guage learning. Brain and Cognition, 8, 105-116.
Ho, L., & Shea, J. B. (1978). Effects of relative frequency of knowledge of results on reten-
tion of a motor skill. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 46, 859-866.
Hockey, G. R. J., Davies, S., & Gray, M. M. (1972). Forgetting a function of sleep at differ-
ent times of day. Experimental Psychology, 24, 386-393.
Hoffer, A. (1981). Geometry is more than proof. Mathematics Teacher, 11-18.
Holland, J. H. Holyoak, K., Nisbett, R. E., & Thagard, P. R. (1986). Induction: Processes of
inference, learning, and discovery. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Holland, P. C. (1985a). Element pretraining influences the content of appetitive serial
compound conditioning in rats. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Learning and
Behavior, 14, 111-120.
Holland, P. C. (1985b). The nature of conditioned inhibition in serial and simultaneous
feature negative discriminations. In R. R. Miller & N. E. Spear (Eds.), Information process-
ing in animals: Conditioned inhibition (pp. 267-297). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Holland, P. C., & Rescorla, R. A. (1975). The effects of two ways of devaluing the uncon-
ditioned stimulus after first- and second-order appetitive conditioning. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 1, 355-363.
Holley, C. D., Dansereau, D. F., McDonald, B. A., Garland, J. C., & Collins, K. W. (1979).
Evaluation of hierarchical mapping technique as an aid to prose processing.
Contemporary Educational Psychology, 4, 227-237.
Holyoak, K. J., Koh, K., & Nisbett, R. E. (1989). A theory of conditioning: Inductive learn-
ing within rule-based default hierarchies. Psychological Review, 96, 315-340.
Honig, W. K. (1981). Working memory and the temporal map. In N. E. Spear & R. Miller
(Eds.), Information processing in animals: Memory mechanisms (pp. 167-197). Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Hoosain, R., & Salili, F. (1988). Language differences, working memory, and mathemati-
cal ability. In M. M. Gruneberg, P. E. Morris, & R. N. Sykes (Eds.), Practical aspects of mem-
ory: Current research and issues: Vol. 2. Clinical and educational implications (pp. 512-517).
Chichester, England: Wiley.
Houston, J. P. (1965). Short-term retention of verbal units with equated degrees of learn-
ing. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 70, 75-78.
Houston, J. P. (1991). Fundamentals of learning and memory (4th ed.). Orlando, FL:
Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Hull, C. L. (1920). Quantitative aspects of the evolution of concepts. Psychological
Monographs (Whole No. 123).
442
Bibliography
443
Bibliography
Jenkins, J. G., & Dallenbach, K. M. (1924). Obliviscence during sleep and waking.
American Journal of Psychology, 35, 605-612.
Job, R.E.S. (1989). A test of proposed mechanisms underlying the interference effect pro-
duced by noncontingent food presentations. Learning and Motivation, 20, 153-177.
Johansson, R. S., & Westling, G. (1984). Roles of glabrous skin receptors and sensorimo-
tor memory in automatic control of precision grip when lifting rougher or more slippery
objects. Experimental Brain Research, 56, 560-564.
Johnson, D. D., & Baumann, J. F. (1984). Word identification. In P. D. Pearson, R. Barr, M.
Kamil, & P. Mosenthal (Eds.), Handbook of reading research. New York: Longman.
Johnson, D. M. (1972). A systematic introduction to the psychology of thinking. New York:
Harper & Row.
Johnson, E. E. (1952). The role of motivational strength in latent learning. Journal of
Comparative Physiological Psychology, 45, 526-530.
Johnson, N. F. (1970). The role of chunking and organization in process recall. In G. H.
Bower (Ed.), Psychology of language and motivation (Vol. 4). New York: Academic Press.
Jones, W. P,, & Anderson, J. R. (1987). Short- and long-term memory retrieval: A com-
parison of the effects of information load and relatedness. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: General, 116, 137-153.
Just, M. A., & Carpenter, P. A. (1987). The psychology of reading and language comprehen-
sion. Newton, MA: Allyn & Bacon.
Kaiser, M. K., McCloskey, M., & Proffitt, D. R. (1986). Development of intuitive theories
of motion: Curvilinear motion in the absence of external forces. Developmental Psychology,
ESM TIN
Kaiser, M. K., & Proffitt, D. R. (1984). The development of sensitivity to causally relevant
dynamic information. Child Development, 55, 1614-1624.
Kaiser, M. K., Proffitt, D. R., & McCloskey, M. (1985). The development of beliefs about
falling objects. Perception and Psychophysics, 38, 533-539.
Kamil, A. C. (1978). Systematic foraging by a nectar-feeding bird, the Amakihi (Loxops
virens). Journal of Comparative Physiological Psychology, 92, 388-396.
Kamil, A. C., Yoerg, S. I, & Clements, K. C. (1988). Rules to leave by: Patch departure in
foraging blue jays. Animal Behavior, 36, 843-853.
Kamin, L. J. (1968). “Attention-like” processes in classical conditioning. In M. R. Jones
(Ed.), Miami Symposium on the Prediction of Behavior: Aversive stimulation (pp. 9-31).
Miami, FL: University of Miami Press.
Kamin, L. J. (1969). Predictability, surprise, attention, and conditioning. In B. A. Campbell
& R. M Church (Eds.), Punishment and aversive behavior (pp. 279-296). New York:
Appleton-Century-
Crofts.
Kamin, L. J. (1956). The effects of termination of the CS and avoidance of the US on
avoidance learning. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 49 420-421.
Kamin, L. J., Brimer, C. J., & Black, A. H. (1963). Conditioned suppression as a monitor of
fear of the CS in the course of avoidance-training. Journal of Comparative and Physiological
Psychology, 56, 497-501.
Kandel, E. R. (1976). Cellular basis of behavior: An introduction to behavioral neurobiology.
New York: Freeman.
444
Bibliography
Kandel, E. R., & Hawkins, R. D. (1992). The biological basis of learning and individuality.
Scientific American, 267, 78-87.
Kandel, E. R., & Schwartz, J. H. (Eds.). (1985). Principles of neural science (2nd ed.). New
York: Elsevier.
Kandel, E. R., Schwartz, J. H., & Jessell, T. M. (Eds.). (1991). Principles of neural science.
New York: Elsevier.
Kaplan, C. A. (1989). Hatching a theory of incubation: Does putting a problem aside real-
ly help? If so, why? Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Carnegie Mellon University.
Pittsburgh, PA.
Katz, B. (1952). The nerve impulse. Scientific American, 187, 55-64.
Keele, S. W. (1987). Sequencing and timing in skilled perception and action: An overview.
In A. Allport, D. G. McKay, & W. Prinz (Eds.), Language perception and production:
Relationships between listening, speaking, reading, and writing (pp. 463-487). London:
Academic Press.
Keeton, W. T. (1980). Biological science. New York: W. W. Norton.
Kehoe, E. J., & Gormezano, I. (1980). Configuration and combination laws in condition-
ing with compound stimuli. Psychological Bulletin, 87, 351-387.
Keith, J. R., & Rudy, J. W. (1990). Why NMDA-receptor-dependent long-term potentia-
tion may not be a mechanism of learning and memory: Reappraisal of the NMDA-recep-
tor blockade strategy. Psychobiology, 18, 251-257.
Keller, F. S. (1968).“Good-bye teacher....” Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis, 1, 78-89.
Kellogg, W. N., & Kellogg, L. A. (1933). The ape and the child. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Kennelly, K. J., Dietz, D., & Benson, P. (1985). Reinforcement schedules, effort vs. ability
attributions, and persistence. Psychology in the Schools, 22, 459-464.
Keppel, G. (1964). Facilitation in short- and long-term retention of paired associates follow-
ing distributed practice in learning. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 3, 91-111.
Keppel, G., & Underwood, B. J. (1962). Proactive inhibition in short-term retention of
single items. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1, 153-161.
Keppel, G., Postman, L., & Zavortnik, B. (1968). Studies of learning to learn: VIII. The
influence of massive amounts of training upon the learning and retention of paired-asso-
ciate lists. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 7, 790-796.
Kieras, D. E., & Bovair, S. (1984). The role of mental model in learning to operate a device.
Cognitive Science, 8, 255-273.
Kimble, G. A. (1961). Conditioning and learning (2nd ed.). New York: Appleton-Century-
Crofts.
King, G. R., & Logue, A. W. (1987). Choice in a self-control paradigm with human sub-
jects: Effects of changeover delay duration. Learning and Motivation, 18, 421-438.
Kintsch, W. (1970a). Learning, memory, and conceptual processes. New York: Wiley.
Kintsch, W. (1970b). Models for free recall and recognition. In D. A. Norman (Ed.), Models
of human memory. New York: Academic Press.
Kintsch, W. (1974). The representation of meaning in memory. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Kintsch, W. (1998). Comprehension: A paradigm for cognition. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge
University Press.
445
Bibliography
Kintsch, W., & Buschke, H. (1969). Homophones and synonyms in short-term memory.
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 80, 403-407.
Kintsch, W., & van Dijk, T. A. (1978). Toward a model of text comprehension and repro-
duction. Psychological Review, 85, 363-394.
Klahr, D., & Dunbar, K. (1988). Dual space search.during scientific reasoning. Cognitive
Science, 12, 1-55. :
Klahr, D., Fay, A. L., & Dunbar, K. (1993). Heuristics for scientific experimentation: A
developmental study. Cognitive Psychology, 25, 111-146.
Klahr, D., Langley, P., & Neches, R. (Eds.). (1987). Production system models of learning and
development, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Klein, S. B., & Mowrer, R. R. (Eds.). (1989). Contemporary learning theories: Instrumental con-
ditioning theory and the impact of biological constraints on learning. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Kleinsmith, L. J., & Kaplan, S. (1963). Paired associate learning as a function of arousal
and interpolated interval. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 65, 190-193.
Koedinger, K. R., Anderson, J. R., Hadley, W. H., & Mark, M. (1997). Intelligent tutoring
goes to school in the big city. International Journal of Artificial Intelligence in Education, 8,
30-43.
Koh, K., & Meyer, D. E. (1991). Function learning: Induction of continuous stimulus-
response relations. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 17,
811-836.
KGhler, W. (1927). The mentality of apes. New York: Harcourt, Brace.
Kohler, W. (1955). Simple structural functions in the chimpanzee and in the chicken. In
W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A source book on Gestalt psychology. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Konarski, E. A., Jr. (1979). The necessary and sufficient conditions for increasing instru-
mental responding in the classroom: Response deprivation vs. probability differential.
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN.
Konarski, E. A., Jr., Johnson, M. R., Crowell, C., & Whitman, T. L. (1980). Response depri-
vation, reinforcement, and instrumental academic performance in an EMR classroom. Paper
presented at the 13th annual Gatlinburg Conference on Research in Mental Retardation
and Developmental Disabilities, Gatlinburg, TN.
Krueger, W.C.F. (1929). The effects of overlearning on retention. Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 12, 71-78.
Kulik, C., Kulik, J., & Bangert-Downs, R. (1986). Effects of testing for mastery on student
learning. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Educational Research
Association, San Francisco.
Laird, J. D., Wagner, J. J., Halal, M., & Szegda, M. (1982). Remembering what you feel:
Effects of emotion on memory. Journal of Personality of Social Psychology, 42, 646-657.
Landauer, T. K. (1975). Memory without organization: Properties of a model with random
storage and undirected retrieval. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 495-531.
Landfield, P. W., & Deadwyler, S. A. (Eds.) (1988). Neurology and neurobiology: Vol. 35.
Long-term potentiation: From biophysics to behavior. New York: Alan R. Liss, Inc.
Lashley, K. S. (1924). Studies of cerebral function in learning: V. The retention of motor
habit after destruction of the so-called motor area in primates. Arch, neuro. Psychiatry, 12,
249-276.
446
Bibliography
Lave, J. (1988). Cognition in practice: Mind, mathematics, and culture in everyday life. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Lawrence, D. H., & DeRivera, J. (1954). Evidence for relational transposition. Journal of
Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 47, 465-471.
Leaf, R. C. (1964). Avoidance response evocation as a function of prior discriminative fear
conditioning under curare. Journal of Comparative Physiological Psychology, 58, 446-449.
Leahey, T. H. (1992). A history of psychology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Lenneberg, E. H. (1967). Biological foundations of language. New York: Wiley.
Lesgold, A. M., Resnick, L. B., & Hammond, K. (1985). Learning to read: A longitudinal
study of word skill development in two curricula. In G. Waller, & E. MacKinnon (Eds.),
Reading research: Advances in theory and practice (Vol. 4). New York: Academic Press.
Levine, M. (1975). A cognitive theory of learning. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Levinger, G., & Clark, J. (1961). Emotional factors in the forgetting of word associations.
Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 62, 99-105.
Levonian, E. (1972). Retention over time in relation to arousal during learning: An expla-
nation of discrepant results. Acta Psychologica, 36, 290-321.
Lewis, C. H. (1978). Production system models of practice effects. Unpublished doctoral
dissertation, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor.
Lewis, C. H., & Anderson, J. R. (1976). Interference with real world knowledge. Cognitive
Psychology, 7, 311-335.
Lieberman, P. (1984). The biology and evolution of language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Light, J. S., & Gantt, W. H. (1936). Essential part of reflex arc for establishment of condi-
tioned reflex. Formation of conditioned reflex after exclusion of motor peripheral end.
Journal of Comparative Psychology, 21, 19-36.
Loftus, E. F., & Burns, T. E. (1982). Mental shock can produce retrograde amnesia.
Memory and Cognition, 10, 318-323.
Loftus, E. E., & Pickrell, J. (1995). The formation of false memories. Psychiatric Annals, 25,
720-725.
Loftus, E. F., Loftus, G. R. & Messo, J. (1987). Some facts about“weapon focus.” Law and
Human Behavior, 11, 55-62.
Loftus, G. R. (1972). Eye fixations and recognition memory for pictures. Cognitive
Psychology, 3, 525-551.
Loftus, G. R., & Patterson, K. K. (1975). Components of short-term proactive interference.
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 14, 105-121.
Logan, G. D. (1988). Toward an instance theory of automatization. Psychological Review,
96, 492-527.
Logan, G. D., & Klapp, S.T. (1991). Automatizing alphabet arithmetic: I. Is extended prac-
tice necessary to produce automaticity? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning,
Memory, and Cognition, 17, 179-195.
Lovett, M. (1998). Choice. In J. R. Anderson & C. Lebiere (Eds.), Atomic components of
thought. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Lundberg, I. (1985). Longitudinal studies of reading and reading difficulties in Sweden.
447
Bibliography
In G. E. MacKinnon & T. G. Waller (Eds.), Reading research: Advances in theory and prac-
tice (Vol. 4, pp. 65-105). Orlando, FL: Academic Press.
Lundberg, I., Frost, J., & Petersen, O. P. (1988). Effects of an extensive program for stim-
ulating phonological awareness in preschool children. Reading Research Quarterly, 23,
263-284. ;
MacCorquodale, K. O. (1970). On Chomsky’s review of Skinner's Verbal Behavior. Journal
of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 13, 83-99.
Macfarlane, D. A. (1930). The role of kinesthesis in maze learning. California University
Publication Psychology, 4, 277-305.
MacKay, D. G. (1982). The problem of flexibility, fluency, and speed-accuracy trade-off in
skilled behavior. Psychological Review, 89, 483-506.
Mackintosh, N. J. (1974). The psychology of animal learning. New York: Academic Press.
Mackintosh, N. J. (1975). A theory of attention: Variations in the associability of stimuli
with reinforcement. Psychological Review, 82, 276-298.
Mackintosh, N. J., & Little, L. (1969). Intradimensional and extradimensional shift learn-
ing by pigeons. Psychonomic Science, 14, 5-6.
MacPhail, E. M. (1968). Avoidance responding in pigeons. Journal of the Experimental
Analysis of Behavior, 11, 625-632.
MacWhinney, B. (1993). The (il)logical problem of language acquisition. Proceedings of the
15th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 61-70). University of Boulder,
CO. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
MacWhinney, B., & Leinbach, J. (1991). Implementations are not conceptualizations:
Revising the verb learning model. Cognition, 29, 121-157.
Maier, S. F., Jackson, R. L., & Tomie, A. (1987). Potentiation, overshadowing, and prior
exposure to inescapable shock. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior
Processes, 13, 260-270.
Maki, W. S. (1984). Some problems for a theory of working memory. In H. L. Roitblat, T.
G. Bever, & H. S.Terrace (Eds.), Animal cognition (pp. 117-133). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Maki, W. S., & Hegvik, D. K. (1980). Directed forgetting in pigeons. Animal Learning and
Behavior, 8, 567-574.
Mandler, G. (1967). Organization and memory. In K. W. Spence & J.T. Spence (Eds.), The
psychology of learning and motivation (Vol. 1, pp. 327-372). New York: Academic Press.
Mandler, J. M., & Ritchey, G. H. (1977). Long-term memory for pictures. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 3, 386-396.
Manis, F. R., Seidenberg, M. S., Doi, L. M., McBride-Chang, C. & Peterson, A. (1996). On
the bases of two subtypes of developmental dyslexia. Cognition, 58, 157-196.
Marcus, G. F., Brinkman, U., Clahsen, H., Wiese, R., Woest, A. & Pinker, S. (1995). German
inflection: The exception that proves the rule. Cognitive Psychology, 29, 189-256.
Marler, P, & Peters, S. (1982). Long-term storage of learned birdsongs prior to produc-
tion. Animal Behaviour, 30, 479-482.
Marr, D. (1971). Simple memory: A theory for archicortex. Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society of London, Series B, 262, 23-81.
Massaro, D. W. (1989). Experimental psychology: An information processing approach. San
Diego: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
448
Bibliography
449
Bibliography
450
Bibliography
Murdock, B. B., Jr. (1974). Human memory: Theory and data. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Myers, J. L., Fort, J. G., Katz, L., & Suydam, M. M. (1963). Differential monetary gains and
losses and event probability in a two-choice situation. Journal of Experimental Psychology,
66, 521-522.
Nathan, P. E. (1976). Alcoholism. In H. Leitenberg (Ed.), Handbook of behavior modification
and behavior therapy. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Neath, I., Surprenant, A. M. & Crowder, R. G. (1993). The context-dependnent stimulus-
suffix effect. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 19,
698-703:
Neely, J. H. (1977). Semantic priming and retrieval from lexical memory: Roles of inhibi-
tionless spreading activation and limited-capacity attention. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: General, 106, 226-254.
Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology. New York: Appleton.
Neisser, U. (1982). Memory observed. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
Nelson, T. O. (1971). Savings and forgetting from long-term memory. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 10, 568-576.
Nelson, T. O. (1976). Reinforcement and human memory. In W. K. Estes (Ed.), Handbook
of learning and cognitive processes (Vol. 3). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Nelson, T. O. (1977). Repetition and depth of processing. Journal of Verbal Learning and
Verbal Behavior, 16, 151-172.
Nelson, T. O. (1978). Detecting small amounts of information in memory: Savings for
nonrecognized items. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 4,
453-468.
Nelson, T. O., Gerber, D., & Narens, L. (1984). Accuracy of feeling-of-knowing judgments
for predicting perceptual identification and relearning. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
General, 113, 282-300.
Neves, D. M. (1977). An experimental analysis of strategies of the Tower of Hanoi puzzle (C.LP.
Working Paper No. 362). Pittsburgh, PA: Carnegie Mellon University.
Neves, D. M., & Anderson, J. R. (1981). Knowledge compilation: Mechanisms for the
automatization of cognitive skills. In J. R. Anderson (Ed.), Cognitive skills and their acqui-
sition. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Newell, A. (1991). Unified theories of cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Newell, A., & Rosenbloom, P. S. (1981). Mechanisms of skill acquisition and the law of
practice. In J. R. Anderson (Ed.), Cognitive skills and their acquisition. Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1961). GPS, a program that simulates human thought. In H.
Billing (Ed.), Lernende Automaten (pp. 109-124). Munich: R. Oldenbourg.
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Newport, E. L. (1986, October 17-19). The effect of maturational state on the acquisition of
language. Paper presented at the 11th Annual Boston University Conference on Language
Development.
Newport, E. L. (1990). Maturational constraints on language learning. Cognitive Science,
14, 11-28.
451
Bibliography
Norman, D. A., & Shallice, T. (1986). Attention to action: Willed and automatic control of
behavior. In R. J. Davidson, G. E. Schwartz, and D. Shapiro (Eds.), Consciousness and self-
regulation. Vol. 4 (pp. 1-18). New York: Plenum Press.
Nosofsky, R. (1988). Similarity, frequency, and category representation. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 10, 104-114.
Nosofsky, R. M. (1986). Attention, similarity, and the identification-categorization rela-
tionship. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 115, 39-57.
Nosofsky, R. M., Palmeri, T. J., & McKinley, S. C. (1994). Rule-plus-exception model of
classification learning. Psychological Review, 101, 53-79.
Nottebohm, F. (1970). The ohtogeny of birdsong. Science, 167, 950-956.
Noyd, D. E. (1965). Proactive and intra-stimulus interference in short-term memory for two-,
three- and five-word stimuli. Paper presented at the meeting of the Western Psychological
Association, Honolulu, HI.
O'Keefe, J. A., & Nadel, L. (1978). The hippocampus as a cognitive map. London: Oxford
University Press.
Obrist, P. A., Sutterer, J. R., & Howard, J. L. (1972). Preparatory cardiac changes: A psy-
chobiological approach. In A. H. Black & W. F. Prokasy (Eds.), Classical conditioning II.
New York: Appleton-Century- Crofts.
Ohlsson, S. (1992). The learning curve for writing books: Evidence from Professor
Asimov. Psychological Science, 3, 380-382.
Oldfield, R. C. (1937). Some recent experiments bearing on “internal inhibition.” British
Journal of Psychology, 28, 28-42.
Olds, J., & Milner, P. (1954). Positive reinforcement produced by electrical stimulation of
septal area and other regions of rat brain. Journal of Comparative Physiology and
Psychology, 47, 419-427.
Olton, D. S. (1978). Characteristics of spatial memory. In S. H. Hulse, H. Fowler, & W. K.
Honig (Eds.), Cognitive processes in animal behavior. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Olton, D. S., & Samuelson, R. J. (1976). Remembrance of places passed: Spatial memory
in rats. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 2, 97-116.
Olton, D. S., Becker, J. T., & Handelmann, G. E. (1979). Hippocampus, space and memo-
ry. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 2, 313-365.
Osherson, D. N., Kosslyn, S. M., & Hollerbach, J. M. (Eds.). (1990). Visual cognition and
action: An invitation to cognitive science (Vol. 2). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Otto, T. & Eichenbaum, H. (1992). Dissociable roles of the hippocampus and
orbitofrontal cortex in an odor-guided delayed nonmatch to sample task. Behavioral
Neuroscience, 105, 111-119.
Owen, A. M., Roberts, A. C., Hodges, J. R., Summers, B. A., Polkey, C. E., & Robbins, T. W.
(1993). Contrasting mechanisms of impaired attentional set-shifting in patients with
frontal lobe damage or Parkinson’s disease. Brain, 116, 1159-1175.
Owens, J., Bower, G. H., & Black, J. B. (1979). The “soap opera” effect in story recall.
Memory and Cognition, 7, 185-191.
Paivio, A. (1971). Imagery and verbal processes. New York: Holt, Rinehart, & Winston.
Palinscar, A. S., & Brown, A. L. (1984). Reciprocal teaching of comprehension-foster
ing
and comprehension-monitoring activities. Cognition and Instruction, 1, 117-175.
452
Bibliography
Palmer, S., Schreiber, G., & Fox, C. (1991, November 22-24). Remembering the earthquake:
“Flashbulb” memory of experienced versus reported events. Paper presented at the 32nd annu-
al meeting of the Psychonomic Society, San Francisco.
Parkin, A. J., Lewinsohn, J., & Folkard, S. (1982). The influence of emotion on serenbdlats
and delayed retention: Levinger and Clark reconsidered. British Journal of Psychology, 73,
389-393,
Pavlov, I. P. (1927). Conditoned reflexes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. (1988). Adaptive strategy selection in decision
making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 14, 534-552.
Pearce, J. M. (1994). Similarity and discrimination: A selective review and a connection-
istic model. Psychological Review, 101, 587-607.
Pearce, J. M., & Hall, G. (1980). A model for Pavlovian learning: Variations in the effec-
tiveness of conditioned but not unconditioned stimuli. Psychological Review, 87, 532-552.
Perfetti, C. A. (1985). Reading ability. New York: Oxford University Press.
Peters, D. P. (1988). Eyewitness memory and arousal in a natural setting. In M. M.
Gruneberg, P. E. Morris, & R. N. Sykes (Eds.), Practical aspects of memory: Current research
and issues: Vol. 1. Memory in everyday life (pp. 89-94). Chichester, England: Wiley.
Peterson, L. R., & Peterson, M. (1959). Short-term retention of individual items. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 58, 193-198.
Peterson, S. B., & Potts, G. R. (1982). Global and specific components of information inte-
gration. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 21, 403-420.
Petrides, M., Alivisatos, B, Evans, A. C., & Meyer, E. (1993). Dissociation of human mid-
dorsolateral from posterior dorsolateral frontal cortex in memory processing. Proceedings
of the National Academy of Science, USA, 90, 873-877.
Phelps, E. A. (1989). Cognitive skill learning in amnesics. Unpublished doctoral disserta-
tion, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ.
Pinker, S. (1989). Language acquisition. In M. I. Posner (Ed.), Foundations of cognitive sci-
ence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pinker, S. (1994). The language instinct. New York: William Morrow and Co.
Pinker, S., & Prince, A. (1988). On language and connectionism: Analysis of a parallel dis-
tributed processing model of language acquisition. Cognition, 28, 73-193.
Pirolli, P., & Card, S. (in press). Information foraging. Psychological Review.
Pirolli, P. L., & Anderson, J. R. (1985). The role of practice in fact retrieval. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 11, 136-153.
Polson, M., & Richardson, J. (Eds.). (1988). Handbook of intelligent training systems.
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Porter, D. (1961). An application of reinforcement principles to classroom teaching.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University, Graduate School of Education, Laboratory for
Research in Instruction.
Posner, M. (1994). Attention: The mechanisms of consciousness. Proceeding of the National
Academy of Science, USA, 91, 7398-7403.
Postman, L. (1964). Short-term memory and incidental learning. In A. W. Melton (Ed.),
Categories of human learning. New York: Academic Press.
453
Bibliography
454
Bibliography
Reder, L. M. (Ed.) (1996). Implicit Memory and Metacognition. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Reder, L. M., & Gordon, J. S. (1997) Subliminal Perception: Nothing Special, Cognitively
Speaking. In J. Cohen and J. Schooler (Eds.), Cognitive and Neuropsychological approaches
to the study of Consciousness (pp. 125-134). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Reder, L. M., & Schunn, C. D. (1996). Metacognition does not imply awareness: Strategy
choice is governed by implicit learning and memory. In L. M. Reder, (Ed.) Implicit Memory
and Metacognition. (pp. 45-77). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum, pp. 45-77.
Reder, L. M., Nhouyvansivong, A. Schunn, C. D., Ayers, M. S., Angstadt, P., & Hiraki, K.
(1997). Modeling the Mirror effect in a Continuous Remember/Know Paradigm.
Proceedings of the Cognitive Science Conference, 644-649.
Reed, S. K. (1972). Pattern recognition and categorization. Cognitive Psychology, 3,
382-407.
Reiss, S., & Wagner, A. R. (1972). CS habituation produces a“latent inhibition” effect but
no active conditioned inhibition. Learning and Motivation, 3, 237-245.
Reitman, J. (1976). Skilled perception in GO: Deducing memory structures from interre-
sponse times. Cognitive Psychology, 8, 336-356.
Reitman, W. (1965). Cognition and thought. New York: Wiley.
Rescorla, R. A. (1968a). Pavlovian conditioned fear in Sidman avoidance learning. Journal
of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 65, 55-60.
Rescorla, R. A. (1968b). Probability of shock in the presence and absence of CS in fear
conditioning. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 66, 1-5.
Rescorla, R. A. (1973). Effect of US habituation following conditioning. Journal of
Comparative Physiological Psychology, 82, 137-143.
Rescorla, R. A. (1988a). Facilitation based on inhibition. Animal Learning and Behavior, 16,
169-176.
Rescorla, R. A. (1988b). Pavlovian conditioning: It’s not what you think it is. American
Psychologist, 43, 151-160.
Rescorla, R. A., & Wagner, A. R. (1972). A theory of Pavlovian conditioning: Variations on
_ the effectiveness of reinforcement and nonreinforcement. In A. H. Black & W. F. Prokasy
(Eds.), Classical conditioning: II. Current research and theory (pp. 64-99). New York:
Appleton-Century- Crofts.
Resnick, D. P,, & Resnick, L. B. (1977). The nature of literacy: An historical exploration.
Harvard Educational Review, 47, 370-385.
Resnick, L. B. (1977). Assuming that everyone can learn everything, will some learn less?
School Review, 85, 445-452.
Restle, F. (1957). Discrimination of cues in mazes: A resolution of the “place-vs.-
response” question. Psychological Review, 64, 217-228.
Rilling, M. (1977). Stimulus control and inhibitory processes. In W. K. Honig & J.E.R.
Staddon (Eds.), Handbook of operant behavior. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Rizley, R. C., & Rescorla, R. A. (1972). Associations in higher order conditioning and sen-
sory preconditioning. Journal of Comparative Physiological Psychology, 81, 1-11.
Roberts, R. J., Hager, L. D., & Heron, C. (1994). Prefrontal cognitive processes: Working
memory and inhibition in the antisaccade task. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
General, 123, 374-393.
455
Bibliography
456
Bibliography
Sachs, J. S. (1967). Recognition memory for syntactic and semantic aspects of connected
discourse. Perception & Psychophysics, 2, 437-442.
Sakai, K. & Miyashita,Y.(1991). Neural organization for the long-term memory-of paired
associates. Nature, 354, 152-155.
Sakitt, B. (1976). Iconic memory. Psychological Review, 83, 257-276.
Salmoni, A. W., Schmidt, R. A., & Walter, C. B. (1984). Knowledge of results and motor
learning: A review and critical reappraisal. Psychological Bulletin, 95, 355-386.
Salthouse, T. A. (1985). Anticipatory processes in transcription typing. Journal of Applied
Psychology, 70, 264-271.
Salthouse, T. A. (1986). Perceptual, cognitive, and motoric aspects of transcription typing.
Psychological Bulletin, 99, 303-319.
Saltzman, I. J. (1949). Maze learning in the absence of primary reinforcement: A study of
secondary reinforcement. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 42, 161-173.
Santa, J. L. (1977). Spatial transformations of words and pictures. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 3, 418-427.
Saucier, D., & Cain, D. P. (1995). Spatial learning without NMDA receptor-dependent
long-term potentiation. Nature, 378, 186-189.
Saufley, W. H., Otaka, S. R., & Bavaresco, J. L. (1985). Context effects: Classroom tests and
context independence. Memory and Cognition, 13, 522-528.
Savage-Rumbaugh, E. S., Murphy, J., Sevik, R. A., Brakke, K. E., Williams, S. L., &
Rumbaugh, D. M. (1993). Language comprehension in ape and child. Monographs of the
Society for Research in Child Development, 58, Serial No. 233.
Schacter, D. L. (1987). Implicit memory: History and current status. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 13, 501-518.
Schacter, D. L., Cooper, L. A., Delaney, S. M., Peterson, M. A., & Tharan, M. (1991).
Implicit memory for possible and impossible objects: Constraints on the construction of
structural descriptions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and
Cognition, 17, 3-19.
Schmidt, R. A. (1988a). Motor and action perspectives on motor behavior. In O. G. Meijer
& K. Rother (Eds.), Complex movement behavior: The motor—action controversy (pp. 3-44).
Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Schmidt, R. A. (1988b). Motor control and learning: A behavioral emphasis. Champaign, IL:
Human Kinetics Publishers.
Schmidt, R. A. (1991). Motor skills acquisition. In R. Dulbecco (Ed.), Encyclopedia of human
biology (Vol. 5, pp. 121-129). Orlando, FL: Academic Press.
Schmidt, R. A., & Bjork, R. A. (1992). New conceptualizations of practice: Common prin-
ciples in three paradigms suggest new concepts for training. Psychological Science, 3,
207-217.
Schmidt, R. A., & Shapiro, D. C. (1986). Optimizing feedback utilization in motor skill train-
ing (Tech. Rep. No. 1/86). Motor Control Laboratory, UCLA. (ARI Contract No. MDA-
903-85-K-0225).
Schmidt, R. A., & White, J. L. (1972). Evidence for an error detection mechanism in motor
skills: A test of Adams’ closed-loop theory. Journal of Motor Behavior, 4, 143-154.
Schmidt, R. A., Shapiro, D. C., Winstein, C. J., Young, D. E., & Swinnen, S. (1987). Feedback
457
Bibliography
and motor skill training: Relative frequency of KR and summary KR (Tech. Rep. No 1/87).
Motor Control Laboratory, UCLA. (ARI Contract No. MDA903-85-K-0225).
Schneiderman, B. (1976). Exploratory experiments in programmer behavior. International
Journal of Computer and Information Sciences, 5, 123-143.
Schneiderman, N. (1973). Classical (Pavlovian) conditioning. Morristown, NJ: General
Learning Press.
Schofield, J. W., & Evans-Rhodes, D. (1989). Artificial intelligence in the classroom: The
impact of a computer-based tutor on teachers and students. Proceedings of the Fourth
International Conference on AI and Education (pp. 238-243). Amsterdam.
Schonberg, H. C. (1970). The lives of great composers. New York: W. W. Norton.
Schooler, L. J., & Anderson, J. R. (1990). The disruptive potential of immediate feedback.
Proceedings of the 12th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 702-708).
Cambridge, MA.
Schustack, M. W., & Sternberg, R. J. (1981). Evaluation of evidence in causal inference.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 110, 101-120.
Schwartz, B. (1973). Maintenance of keypecking in pigeons by a food avoidance but not
a shock avoidance contingency. Animal Learning and Behavior, 1, 164-165.
Schwartz, B. (1989). Psychology of learning and behavior (3rd ed.). New York: W. W. Norton.
Secretary's Commission on Achieving Necessary Skills. (1991, November). Scales for com-
petencies and foundation skills (Draft). Washington, DC: United States Department of
Labor.
Seligman, M. E. P. (1975). Helplessness: On depression, development and death. San
Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
Seligman, M.E.P,, & Johnson, J. C. (1973).A cognitive theory of avoidance learning. In F.
J. McGuigan & D. B. Lumsden (Eds.), Contemporary approaches to conditioning and learn-
ing (pp. 69-110). Washington, DC: V. H. Winston.
Seligman, M.E.P, & Maier, S. F. (1967). Failure to escape traumatic shock. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 74, 1-9.
Shaklee, H., & Tucker, D. (1980). A rule analysis of judgments of covariation between
events. Memory and Cognition, 8, 459-467.
Shapiro, D. C., & Schmidt, R. A. (1982). The schema theory: Recent evidence and devel-
opmental implications. In J.A.S. Kelso & J. E. Clark (Eds.), The development of movement
control and coordination (pp. 113-150). New York: Wiley.
Sheffield, F. D., Wulff, J. J., & Backer, R. (1951). Reward value of copulation without sex
drive reduction. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 44, 3-8.
Shepard, L. A. (1991). Psychometricians’ beliefs about learning. Educational Researcher, 20,
22163
Shephard, R. N. (1967). Recognition memory for words, sentence, and pictures. Journal of
Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 6, 156-163.
Shettleworth, S. J. (1975). Reinforcement and the organization of behavior in golden
hamsters: Hunger, environment, and food reinforcement. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 104, 56-87.
Shik, M. L., Severin, F.V., & Orlovskii, G. N. (1966). Control of walking and running by
means of electrical stimulation of the mid-brain. Biophysics, 11, 756-765.
458
Bibliography
459
Bibliography
Slamecka, N. J., & McElree, B. (1983). Normal forgetting of verbal lists as a function of
their degree of learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and
Cognition, 9, 384-397.
Slater-Hammel, A. T. (1960). Reliability, accuracy and refractoriness of a transit reaction.
Research Quarterly, 31, 217-228.
Smith, E. E. (1989). Concepts and induction. In M. I. Posner (Ed.), Foundations of cognitive
science (pp. 501-526). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Smith, E. E., Adams, N., & Schorr, D. (1978). Fact retrieval and the paradox of interfer-
ence. Cognitive Psychology, 10, 438-464.
Smith, E. E., & Jonides, J. (T995). Working memory in humans: Neurophychological evi-
dence. In M. S. Gazzinga (Ed.) The cognitive neurosciences, 1009-1020. Cambridge, MA
MIT Press.
Smith, E. E., Patalano, A. L., & Jonides, J. (1998). Alternative strategies of categorization.
Cognition, 65, 167-196.
Smith, S. M., Glenberg, A., & Bjork, R. A. (1978). Environmental context and human
memory. Memory and Cognition, 6, 342-353.
Solomon, R. L., & Corbit, J. D. (1974). An opponent-process theory of motivation: I. The
temporal dynamics of affect. Psychological Review, 81, 119-145.
Solomon, R. L., & Wynne, L. C. (1953). Traumatic avoidance learning: Acquisition in nor-
mal dogs. Psychological Monographs, 67 (Whole No. 354).
Solomon, R. L., Kamin, L. J., & Wynne, L. C. (1953). Traumatic avoidance learning: The
outcomes of several extinction procedures with dogs. Journal of Abnormal and Social
Psychology, 48, 291-302.
Soloway, E., Lochhead, J., & Clement, J. (1982). Does computer programming enhance
problem solving ability? Some positive evidence on algebra word problems. In J. Seidel,
R. E. Anderson, & B. Hunter (Eds.), Computer literacy. New York: Academic Press.
Sonuga-Barke, E.J.S., Lea, S.E.G., & Webley, P. (1989). The development of adaptive
choice in a self-control paradigm. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 51,
77-85.
Spear, N. E., & Miller, R. R. (1981). Information processing in animals: Memory mechanisms.
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Spelke, E., Hirst, W., & Neisser, U. (1976). Skills of divided attention. Cognition, 4,
215-230.
Spence, K. W. (1937). The differential response in animals to stimuli varying within a sin-
gle dimension. Psychological Review, 44, 430-444.
Spence, K. W. (1952). The nature of the response in discrimination learning. Psychological
Review, 59, 89-93.
Spence, K. W., & Ross, L. E. (1959). A methodological study of the form and latency of
eyelid responses in conditioning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 58, 376-381.
Sperling, G. A. (1960). The information available in brief visual presentation. Psychological
Monographs, 74 (Whole No. 498).
Sporer, S. L. (1991). Deep—deeper—deepest? Encoding strategies and the recognition of
human faces. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 17,
323-333.
460
Bibliography
Squire, L. R. (1987). Memory and brain. New York: Oxford University Press.
Squire, L. R. (1989). On the course of forgetting in very long-term memory. eles of
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 15, 241-245.
Squire, L. R. (1992). Memory and the hippocampus: A synthesis from findings with rats,
monkeys, and humans. Psychological Review, 99, 195-232.
St. Claire-Smith, R., & MacLaren, D. (1983). Response preconditioning effects. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 1, 41-48.
Staddon, J.E.R. (1983) Adaptive behavior and learning. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Staddon, J.E.R., & Ettinger, R. H. (1989). Learning: An introduction to the principles of adap-
tive behavior. San Diego: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Staddon, J.E.R., & Simmelhag, V. L. (1971). The“superstition” experiment: A reexamina-
tion of its implications for the principles of adaptive behavior. Psychological Review, 78,
3-43.
Standing, L. (1973). Learning 10,000 pictures. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology,
25, 207-222.
Staubli, U., Thibault, O., DiLorenzo, M., & Lynch, G. (1989). Antagonism of NMDA
receptors impairs acquisition but not retention of olfactory memory. Behavioral
Neuroscience, 103, 54-60.
Steele, D. R. (1994). Partial recall. Liberty, 37-47.
Stein, L. (1978). Reward transmitters: Catecholamines and opioid peptides. In M. A.
Lipton, A. DiMascio, & K. F. Killam (Eds.), Psychopharmacology: A generation of progress
(pp. 569-581). New York: Raven Press.
Steinberg, H., & Summerfield, A. (1957). Influence of a depressant drug on acquisition in
rote learning. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 9, 138-145.
Stephens, D. W., & Krebs, J. R. (1986). Foraging theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Sternberg, S. (1969). Memory scanning: Mental processes revealed by reaction time
experiments. American Scientist, 57, 421-457.
Stevenson, H. W., & Lee, S. (198). An examination of American student achievement
from an international perspective. In D. Ravitch (Ed.) Brookings papers on Education Policy:
1998, pp. 7-52. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press.
Stevenson, H. W., & Stigler, J. W. (1992). The learning gap: Why our schools are failing and
what we can learn from Japanese and Chinese education. New York: Summit Books.
Sticht, T. G. (1972). Learning by listening. In R. O. Freedle & J. B. Carroll (Eds.), Language
comprehension and the acquisition of knowledge. Washington, DC: Winston.
Sticht, T. G., & James, J. H. (1984). Listening and reading. In P. D. Pearson, R. Barr, M. L.
Kamil, & P. Mosenthal (Eds.), Handbook of reading research. New York: Longman.
Straub, R. O., Seidenberg, M. S., Bever, T. G., & Terrace, H. S. (1979). Serial learning in the
pigeon. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 32, 137-148.
Sulin, R. A., & Dooling, D. J. (1974). Intrusion of a thematic idea in retention of prose.
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 103, 255-262.
Suppes, P. (1964). Modern learning theory and the elementary school curriculum.
American Educational Research Journal, 2, 79-93.
461
Bibliography
462
Bibliography
Timberlake, W., & Grant, D. S. (1975). Auto-shaping in rats to the presentation of anoth-
er rat predicting food. Science, 190, 690-692.
Tinklepaugh, O. L. (1928). An experimental study of representative factors in monkeys.
Journal of Comparative Psychology, 8, 197-236.
Tobin, H., Logue, A. W., Chelonis, J. J. Ackerman, K.T., & May, J. G., III (1996). Self-con-
trol in the monkey Macaca fascicularis. Animal Learning and Behavior, 24, 168-174.
Tolman, E. C., & Honzik, C. H. (1930a). “Insight” in rats. University of California Publ.
Psychology, 4, 215-232.
Tolman, E. C., & Honzik, C. H. (1930b). Introduction and removal of reward, and maze
performance in rats. University of California Publ. Psychology, 36, 221-229.
Tolman, E. C., Ritchie, B. F., & Kalish, D. (1946). Studies in spatial learning: II. Place learn-
ing versus response learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36, 221-229.
Tolman, E. C., Ritchie, B. F., & Kalish, D. (1947). Studies in spatial learning: VResponse
learning vs. place learning by the non-correction method. Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 37, 285-292.
Trowbridge, M. H., & Cason, H. (1932). An experimental study of Thorndike’s theory of
learning. Journal of General Psychology, 7, 245-258.
Tulving, E. (1975). Ecphoric processing in recall and recognition. In J. Brown (Ed.), Recall
and recognition. London: Wiley.
Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tulving, E., & Flexser, A. J. (1992). On the nature of the Tulving-Wiseman function.
Psychological Review, 99, 543-546.
Tulving, E., & Osler, S. (1968). Effectiveness of retrieval cues in memory for words. Journal
of Experimental Psychology, 77, 593-601.
Tulving, E., & Pearlstone, Z. (1966). Availability versus accessibility of information in
memory for words. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 5, 381-391.
Tulving, E., & Psotka, J. (1971). Retroactive inhibition in free-recall: Inaccessibility of
information available in the memory store. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 87, 1-8.
Tulving, E., & Schacter, D. L. (1990). Priming and human memory systems. Science, 247,
301-306.
Tulving, E., & Thomson, D. M. (1973). Encoding specificity and retrieval processes in
episodic memory. Psychological Review, 80, 352-373.
Tulving, E., & Wiseman, S. (1975). Relation between recognition and recognition failure
of recallable words. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 6, 79-82.
Tversky, A. (1972). Elimination by aspects: A theory of choice. Psychological Review, 79,
281=299.
Ulrich, R. E., & Azrin, N. H. (1962). Reflexive fighting in response to aversive stimulation.
Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 5, 511-520.
Underwood, B. J., & Freund, J. S. (1968). Errors in recognition learning and retention.
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 78, 55-63.
Underwood, B. J., & Freund, J. S. (1970). Relative frequency judgments and verbal dis-
crimination learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 83, 279-285.
Vaccarino, F. J., Schiff, B. B., & Glickman, S. E. (1989). Biological view of reinforcement. In
463
Bibliography
464
Bibliography
Watts, F. N., & Sharrock, R. (1987). Cued recall in depression. British Journal of Clinical
Psychology, 61, 1-12.
Watts, F. N., MacLeod, A., & Morris, L. (1988). A remedial strategy for memory and con-
centration problems in depressed patients. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 12, 185-193.
Watts, F. N., Morris, L., & MacLeod,A. (1987). Recognition memory in depression. Journal
of Abnormal Psychology, 96, 273-275.
Waugh, N. C., & Norman, D. A. (1965). Primary memory. Psychological Review, 72, 89-104.
Weisberg, P., & Waldrop, P. B. (1972). Fixed-interval work habits of congress. Journal of
Applied Behavior Analysis, 5, 93-97.
Weisman, R. G., & Premack, D. (1966). Reinforcement and punishment produced by the
same response depending upon the probability relation between the instrumental and
contingent responses. Paper presented at the Psychonomic Society Meeting, St. Louis.
Weisman, R. G., Wasserman, E. A., Dodd, P. W., & Lunew, M. B. (1980). Representation
and retention of two-event sequences in pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
Animal Behavior Processes, 6, 312-325.
Wenger, E. (1987). Artificial intelligence and tutoring systems: Computational and cognitive
approaches to the communication of knowledge. Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.
Wertheimer, M. (1979). A brief history of psychology (2nd ed.). New York: Holt, Rinehart, &
Winston.
Wertheimer, R. (1990). The Geometry Proof Tutor: An“Intelligent” Computer-based tutor
in the classroom. Mathematics Teacher, 308-313.
West, M. J., & King, A. P. (1980). Enriching cowbird song by social deprivation. Journal of
Comparative Physiological Psychology, 94, 263-270.
Westbury, I. (1992). Comparing American and Japanese achievement: Is the United
States really a low achiever? Educational Researcher, 21, 18-24.
Westbury, I. (1993). American and Japanese achievement...again: A response to Baker.
Educational Researcher, 22, 21-25.
White, M. (1987). The Japanese education challenge: A commitment to children. New York:
Free Press.
Wickelgren, W. A. (1974). How to solve problems. New York: W. H. Freeman.
Wickelgren, W. A. (1975). Alcoholic intoxication and memory storage dynamics. Memory
& Cognition, 3, 385-389.
Wickelgren, W. A. (1976). Memory storage dynamics. In W. K. Estes (Ed.), Handbook of
learning and cognitive processes (Vol. 4). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Wickelgren, W. A. (1977). Learning and memory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Wilcoxon, H. C., Dragoin, W. B., & Kral, P. A. (1971). IlIness-induced aversions in rat and
quail: Relative salience of visual and gustatory cues. Science, 171, 826-828.
Williams, B. (1988). Reinforcement, choice, and response strength. In R. C. Atkinson, R. J.
Herrnstein, G. Lindzey, and R. D. Luce (Eds.), Stevens’ handbook of experimental psycholo-
gy: Vol. 2. Learning and cognition (pp. 167-244). New York: Wiley.
Williams, J. P. (1979). Reading instruction today. American Psychologist, 34, 917-922.
Wixted, J. T., & Ebbesen, E. B. (1991). On the form of forgetting. Psychological Science, 2,
409-415.
465
Bibliography
466
Photo Credits
Chapter 1
Page 10: Sovfoto/Eastfoto. Page 13: Courtesy Robert Yerkes Papers, Manuscripts and
Archives, Yale University Library Page 21 (left): Courtesy Pfizer, Inc. Page 21 (right):
Courtesy The B. F. Skinner Foundation. Page 31: From Comparative Psychology; A
Modern Survey by Donald A. Dewsbury, 1973 by McGraw-Hill, Inc.
Chapter 3
Page 93: From R.J. Herrnstein, D.H. Loveland and C. Cable“Natural Concepts in Pigeons,”
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior and Processes, Vol. 2, No. 4 (1976).
Page 99: From”The Form of the Auto-shaped Response with Food or H,0 Reinforcers” by
Jenkins, H.M. and Moore B.R., Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1973, vol. 20,
page 175, fig. 2. ©1973 by the Society for the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, Inc.
Page 110: From “The Hippocampal Formation of the Primate Brain: A Review of Some
Comparative Aspects of Cytoarchitecture and Connections” in Cerebral Cortex, Vol. 6, p.
348, by D. L. Rosene and G. W. Van Hoesen, ©1987 by Plenum Press.
Chapter4
Page 124: Courtesy Yerkes Primate Research Center. Page 145: Thomas D.
Mangelsen/Images of Nature.
Chapter 6
Page 212: Courtesy Psychonomic Society. Page 224: From The Mind of an Ape by David
Premack and Ann James Premack, ©1983 by Ann J. Premack and David Premack.
Reprinted by permission of W. W. Norton & Company, Inc.
Chapter 7
Page 263: Forden/Sygma Photo News. Page 269: AP/Wide World Photos.
Chapter 9
Page 315: From The Mentality of Apes by W. Kohler, 1926 © by Harcourt, Brace & Co,,
Routeledge. Page 336: Courtesy Gabriele Wulf, Max Planck Institute of Psychology
Research.
467
Photo Credits
Chapter 10
Page 374: From The Mind of an Ape by David Premack and Ann James Premack, ©1983
by Ann J. Premack and David Premack. Reprinted by permission of W. W. Norton &
Company, Inc. Page 375: Courtesy Duane Rumbaugh, Language Research Center,
Georgia State University.
Chapter 11
Page 408: © John Heller.
468
Author Index
469
Author Index
470
Author Index
471
Author Index
472
Author Index
473
Author Index
474
Author Index
475
Author Index
476
Author Index
477
Author Index
Spence, K, W., 16, 88-89 Thorndike, E. L., 6, 12-16, 17, 18, 26, 78, 80, 118, 125,
Sperling, G. A., 156, 157, 158 209, 383, 384
Sporer, S. L., 161 Timberlake, W., 98, 99, 135, 136
Springston, F., 163 Tinklepaugh, O. L., 81
Squire, L. R., 229, 230, 301, 303 Tobin, H., 147
Staddon, J. E. R., 83, 102, 117, 134, 138, 141, 151 Toigo, R., 128
Standing, L., 211 Tolman, E. C., 15, 17-20, 26, 82, 95, 118, 121, 124, 305
Stark, K., 248 Tomie, A., 103
Staubli, U., 115 Toppino, T., 294
Steele, D. R., 259 Toth, J. P, 294
Stein, L., 134 Trabasso, T. R., 344, 345
Steinberg, H., 258 ~ Travers, K. J., 379, 381
Stephens, D. W., 143 Trowbridge, M. H., 15
Stephens, R., 61 Tucker, D., 356
Stern, J., 281 Tulving, E., 161, 162, 267, 271, 274, 275, 283, 291, 303
Sternberg, R. J., 356 Turvey, M.T., 157, 168
Sternberg, S., 172, 173, 174 Tversky, A., 149
Stevenson, H. W., 379, 380, 382, 383, 414
Stewart, C., 113 U
Sticht, T. G., 389, 391 Ulrich, R. E., 128
Stigler, J.W., 379, 380, 382, 383, 414 Underwood, B. J., 165, 240, 278
Stillman, R. C., 281
Stinkman, P. G., 115 Vv
Straub, R, O., 221 Vaccarino, F. J., 134
Sulin, R. A., 287 Vallar, G., 168
Summerfield, A., 258 van Dijk, T. A., 218
Summers, B. A., 91 Van Lehn, K., 337, 400
Summers, J. J., 238 Vidden, T. O., 321
Suppes, P, 386 Volpe, B.T., 302
Surprenant, A. M., 159
Sutherland, N. S., 143 Ww
Sutherland, R. J., 113 Waddill, P. J., 198n6
Sutterer, J. R., 56 Wager, W. W., 414
Suydam, M. M., 142 Wagner, A., 16, 44, 50, 56, 64, 65-75, 70, 77, 91, 107-
Swafford, J. O., 379, 381 108, 114, 116, 176, 177, 178, 187, 196n3, 245-246,
Swanson, L. W., 114 349, 350, 356, 357, 368
Swinnen, S., 334 Wagner, J. J., 283
Szegda, M., 283 Walder, L. O., 128
Waldrop, P. B., 22
T Walter, C. B., 334
Taub, E., 327 Ward, W. C., 355-356
Taylor, B., 96, 97 Wasserman, E. A., 60, 77, 94, 106, 107, 108, 221,
Teasdale, J. D., 283 356n3, 376
Terrace, H. S., 85, 184, 221, 222, 223, 373 Waterman, D. A., 325
Tesch-Romer, C,, 324 Watkins, M. J., 161, 240n1
Teyler, T. J., 114 Watkins, O. C., 240n1, 274
Thagard, P. R., 376 Watson, J., 5, 15, 16
Tharan, M., 296, 297 Watts, F. N., 283
Thibault, O,, 115 Waugh, N. C., 165
Thomas, E. L., 203 Weber, A., 214, 215
Thompson, R. F., 42, 47, 48, 56n2, 77, 114 Webley, P., 147
Thomson, D, M., 274 Webster, M. M., 62
Thomson, N., 167, 170 Weingartner, H., 281
478
Author Index
479
- tt si wale
~ a ort2 3
a, ee
(
: OF, TF ae
‘i a L1H 2 Siow a 2 ‘"
A ee 1 sme
eemuy *
iy ~ oe PRLe ae
b bab AD abr 7 apt 6, ae aS
ship 20i3
thoy i eo b.. V™_ 2
} A NP eet “ho
five } af 1S geee
pciecaerae
*, é ’ } rad 7.) yattaur? iegt. wi ee TLE
lie Ti i. Du ’ £2.16 grow en LET AN atAW
sheep fy iy The The Ob Syrian
bhewmmnaain, 1 AP PIS. “, SER DRA ais
eos C afi3 - u ay ard
anent, 4 Let 5 ovionantell
Seiden, |W TN, WA, 2 339, aye a MS
“1p prdatiy hf on TA ree BrAdostS
pee Fa. | : £Q) .® penis
pata FA. am, 02 t Dea’
Pdi, RA 38) . > fei ph
Conewien A, Se lk
daoters WA, i = e
senna, |ha :
feakiae By:
Mae rant 4a sy i
‘Ratinlatel, hy Fae F es
bitter’ Ko 3 S
Satins, ’ x. an P
—_ hana 4, Me ia): ‘ ee
nh iw z 7? «iy Tk ASSn rea
Serarcees.1.W. 1 le 9, 6 OT OR si
i <a 7
vagrviny, 3 ls = Wages. |. eH
28 i
Ses 1D Wile 1 Ue ten e
vo
vere
if aan 7 er
Wabtiigs Edis
Wola (Sh
ae
GeibeR, 33%, of tak © oti
Tayler, fh,OA REY? hg me. 4" ane: ee
Tesh’ 0. 2 ee : ial Ye i
- Tasrand, 62 aL be SIL Oe a F thieving, LAS as
ir ior Lt =-70 5 ‘. Pothics BL an
p> be a it ’ © a¢
Thapant # ais
Thi. Uo, De HRS no
ry aul, oO INS
em 7 J
LM oy - 4 we ' Pea ~m
ine
Ld *
he,
’ 4
37. 48,
j
BERS oh aM
Sy ‘Se és
tty Ta) Om ; =
Tt. «e<.'6
be * 7
7%
Subject Index
481
Subject Index
482
Subject Index
483
Subject Index
484
Subject Index
485
Subject Index
486
Subject Index
487
maAnee 20 wht hee?
sa ce Dials er -
4 ot) 19S tet seqgnotetl- gt ee
‘ on We npetthl gnitltcing peat ewncsiitas
i vitck, METfesere
720, Sy ener wdepae
iat 5ote hg te AMM °F LER seeanif oh shay alr
awed ba nia hatalaro>
RED ES Bes MET Gitkeroung sere rryqe ter
akceai « @ WORLR2 err ieee deay, TS
inept idcieget ened sesh Nea Me wag lin, rom Wat ove
yr ll
“phe amedig e Tarot arene aie Ofcael SS54-055,
vistaced Bet (ud 1 Pee werote Cn: wired eh,
ae an. iiey ary, Sa oe ’ Murr 0 ~ ingen pe a
Reine ye er Oat) sacar Sew eititonrnn tee io PR DR ered 2
heen. )) TRE} sulci beeebibral? Dati, 965-28 bbenaldan:
bi aesdien of er Vitnasi dose sleerncinld - rae: Rncaegea’
ome. ~ esis 7.
| be LM
pave. 4
— ix . vo , a “As
he bdedsaast
»
Vaan, 29g 1h. ™ ake i hel iy
megs ehcp. po ee YK mitts te BOERNE,
7 ‘ aa
in dee me SS. aw erule/] entra 2k)” etevigna ed
Pryvietia c, Gey ceelperm, 22 wee EACH he we Laer oo i904
EAST UY Sieh, “ d “Sereiey eerie ty plea.
vere iosiaae, ler 21-29) bares icc, ae 2 me
WA KoA De TL) Bxb yt eye a aeny = a
Sie de |dhe phetiwe Dette yecsicey . rh pa i) eral ie, ae
Cc Geen. if ; y Sa eh 7
ae Ga Vs ial Aty MEET oh 7A
Soe sins Dos Ma Se :
Carat! ieee: [NTE Sep Hee
é a ° ‘ — al .
aye o'r ‘ 7