The Entrepreneur - An Economic Theory, 2nd Ed
The Entrepreneur - An Economic Theory, 2nd Ed
The Entrepreneur - An Economic Theory, 2nd Ed
Team FOS
The Entrepreneur
An Economic Theory, Second Edition
Mark Casson
Professor of Economics, University of Reading, UK
Edward Elgar
Cheltenham, UK Northampton, MA, USA
Mark Casson 1982, 2003 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical or photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Published by Edward Elgar Publishing Limited Glensanda House Montpellier Parade Cheltenham Glos GL50 1UA UK Edward Elgar Publishing, Inc. 136 West Street Suite 202 Northampton Massachusetts 01060 USA First published 1982 Second edition 2003 A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication Data Casson, Mark, 1945 The entrepreneur : an economic theory / Mark Casson. 2nd ed. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Entrepreneurship. I. Title. HB615 .C37 2003 338'.04dc21 2002037937 ISBN 1 85898 910 8 (cased) Typeset by Manton Typesetters, Louth, Lincolnshire, UK. Printed and bound in Great Britain by MPG Books Ltd, Bodmin, Cornwall.
Contents
List of gures List of tables Preface to the second edition Introduction PART I THEORETICAL FOUNDATIONS 9 19 34 43 56 vi vii viii 1
1 The signicance of the entrepreneur 2 Basic concepts of the theory 3 The entrepreneur as intermediator 4 The competitive threat to the entrepreneur 5 Partial coordination: the case of innovation PART II THE MARKET-MAKING FIRM
6 Making a market 7 Internal and external markets 8 The market for information 9 Speculative intermediation and the role of inventory management 10 Organizing the supply of market-making services PART III SYNTHESIS 11 12 13 14 15 Growth and dynamics of the rm The market for entrepreneurs Social mobility and the entrepreneur Alternative theories of the entrepreneur Conclusions
Bibliography Index
Figures
3.1 3.2 4.1 4.2 5.1 5.2 5.3 5.4 6.1(a) 6.1(b) 6.1(c) 6.2 11.1 11.2 11.3 12.1 The Edgeworth box Offer curves in the Edgeworth box Competition between two entrepreneurs in intermediating an exchange of goods using a multi-part tariff Competition between two entrepreneurs in intermediating an exchange of goods using a one-part tariff Technological innovation: a partial analysis Product innovation: a partial analysis Arbitrage: a partial analysis Arbitraging stocks: a partial analysis Total cost functions for the rst market-making activity Total cost functions for the second market-making activity Total cost function for market making Determination of the quantity of trade with market-making costs Diffusion curves with and without advertising Dynamics of demand for a new durable product Information feedbacks on product quality improvement: their internalization within the rm Steady state of the market for entrepreneurs 37 40 45 47 61 63 66 68 101 101 101 103 173 175 177 196
vi
Tables
2.1 2.2 Decision-making activities and the qualities they require Additional activities required when there is functional specialization within decision making, and the qualities they require An analysis of entrepreneurial qualities Classication of obstacles to trade, and the corresponding market-making activities Market-making activities and their most suitable contractual arrangements Alternative forms of entrepreneurship Alternative methods of advancement and their requirements Personal abilities and the way they are acquired 25
vii
ix
who obtained the relevant information rst. This in turn led me to the work of Frank Knight, Friedrich von Hayek, Israel Kirzner and Joseph Schumpeter. Reading these classic writings on entrepreneurship proved immensely stimulating, but it also produced some intellectual indigestion. The ideas of each author seemed quite different, and it was not clear how they all tted together. I therefore wrote the rst draft of this book simply to sort out my own ideas to cure my indigestion, in other words. Some authors claim that writing is a form of therapy, and from what has been said above it is clear that therapy was a motive in the present case. The disadvantage of therapy as a motive for authorship, however, is that the book is written for the benet of the author and not the reader. If the author has no clear concept of the intended audience, other than people like themselves, then the book is likely to fail in commercial terms. The rst edition of this book almost fell into this trap but not quite. The danger was averted because, through giving seminars to colleagues at Reading and elsewhere, I began to appreciate the wide variety of motives that stimulate interest in the entrepreneur. For many people the major motive for studying entrepreneurship is not pure intellectual curiosity, but rather an admiration for entrepreneurs as successful and wealthy people. In recognition of this, I began the book with a mythical biography of Jack Brash the stereotypical entrepreneur. If there is one thing that readers of this book seem to remember, it is the story of Jack Brash, which is reassuring in some ways, but rather depressing in others. The most enthusiastic reviewer of the rst edition was Karen Vaughn, who was very supportive of the notion of building a bridge between conventional economic theory on the one hand and the study of real-world entrepreneurship and market processes on the other. Not all reviewers shared her enthusiasm, however. A mathematical economist considered my reliance on diagrams, supported by verbal argument, to be an old-fashioned method of exposition. A specialist on small business economics considered the book too philosophical. Another reviewer confessed that that they could nd nothing at all of any substance that was original in the book. The most perceptive criticisms of the book, in my view, were those which drew a parallel between entrepreneurship and leadership. As already noted, much of the popular appeal of the entrepreneur rests upon the entrepreneur as role model. People admire the way that a successful entrepreneur inspires their employees to dedicate themselves to the business, and converts their customers into enthusiastic believers in the product. Entrepreneurs benet society, from this perspective, not only in material terms, but in raising morale, and in doing so they benet themselves as well. By focusing, as its sub-title suggests, on the strictly economic aspects of entrepreneurship, the book failed to address the social aspects of the subject in sufcient depth.
The entrepreneur
I was particular sympathetic to these criticisms because I had already come to the same conclusion myself, but only at the end of the book, and without appreciating the full implications of this view. The rst edition of this book concluded by looking forward to the emergence of an integrated social science a social science that could do justice to the social as well as the economic aspects of the entrepreneur. This has provided me with a research agenda which I have pursued steadily over the last 20 years. Readers who enjoyed the book, and are looking for a sequel, could consult The Economics of Business Culture (1991), Entrepreneurship and Business Culture (1995), Information and Organization (1997) and Enterprise and Leadership (2000). All of these books attempt to build upon the foundations set out in this book in order to generate a more balanced approach to leadership and to the role of the entrepreneur. Within the eld of entrepreneurship, the ideas presented in this book have been taken up quite widely. The concept of entrepreneurship set out in the opening chapters is the basis for the denition of the entrepreneur used in The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, The International Encyclopaedia of Social Science, the Fortune Encyclopaedia of Business, the Penguin Dictionary of Economics and the Oxford Encyclopaedia of Economic History. However, the eld of entrepreneurship still remains somewhat divorced from mainstream economics. Ever since this book was written, it has seemed obvious to me that entrepreneurship is at the heart of the market process, which is, in turn, supposed to be at the heart of mainstream economics. Entrepreneurs are the personication of the market process: without them, the market system as we know it would barely exist. Some markets might operate as auctions, but the familiar market in which entrepreneurs advertise products they have developed, and quote prices at which they are committed to trade with the public, would not exist without them. It seems equally obvious that ows of information, and not just ows of product, are crucial to economic activity, for without a ow of information no-one would know what products are for sale. Indeed, it could be argued that, in a metaphysical sense, ows of intangible information are more real, in the modern economy, than the tangible product ows which they coordinate. Yet mainstream economists continue to emphasize ows of product, and ows of payment, as if they were the core of the economic system. It is not only mainstream economists that continue to ignore the economic theory of the entrepreneur. Ironically, some researchers on small business do so too. Considerable confusion has been generated over the last 20 years by the mistaken habit of regarding the owners of small businesses as the only true entrepreneurs. Entrepreneurship, as dened in this book, is concerned with the exercise of judgment in all sorts of different business situations, including large-scale technological innovations undertaken by multinational
xi
manufacturing rms and large-scale nancial speculations undertaken by international banks. It also includes political entrepreneurship such as the founding of a new political movement and criminal entrepreneurship, such as drug-dealing. Some small rms are certainly very entrepreneurial, but others are not. The notion that entrepreneurship is only to be found in small business is a myth, although quite a useful myth for those who wish to subsidize small business, or to win the small business vote. It is unfortunate that this myth has been perpetuated because researchers have taken too little note of the economic theory of the entrepreneur. When revising a book that is more than 20 years old, a number of issues arise regarding the changes that should be made. To begin with, should the book be thoroughly rewritten and updated? If it were a textbook that had been regularly updated before then it would certainly be sensible to update it again. Recently published work would be cited and discussed, and issues raised by the latest thinking on the subject would be addressed. This book is not a textbook, however, but is intended to be an original contribution to theory. Furthermore, there has been a phenomenal growth in the literature on entrepreneurship in the last 20 years particularly on the empirical side and two different edited collections of major writings on the subject have recently been published. To incorporate all of this literature into the new edition would have meant writing a new book rather than producing a new edition of an existing book. I have therefore decided to leave the literature review and references as they were. This will help the reader to appreciate the context in which the book was originally written, and in particular to appreciate the relatively limited resources available to students of entrepreneurship some 20 years ago. Economic theory has advanced signicantly in the last 20 years, notably in the analysis of asymmetric information, which has an important bearing on the theme of this book. However, these advances have been broadly in line with the developments anticipated in the rst edition, and so it has not been necessary to amend or correct any of the text in the light of recent work. Because the concept of asymmetric information is now more widely understood, however, it has been possible to abbreviate or omit certain sections of the text in which these ideas were elaborated. Growing recognition of the coordination problems created by asymmetric information means that general equilibrium theory is no longer such a dominant force in conventional neoclassical economics as it was at the time this book was written. To reect this change, criticisms of neoclassical theory in the rst edition have been replaced by criticisms of simple neoclassical theory in this new edition, since sophisticated neoclassical theory is now immune to some of the criticisms advanced in the rst edition of this book. In the light of these remarks, the main changes in this new edition are designed to clarify the arguments which were advanced in the original edition
xii
The entrepreneur
of the book. The nal draft of the rst edition was completed in some haste, over a summer vacation. There was no time to put the draft manuscript to one side and return to it later for a nal revision. As a result, some rather turgid sections of prose remained in the nal version, together with some peripheral material which distracted from the main argument of the book. These problems were recognized in the opening sentence of the original Preface, which began, rather ominously, Inside every long book there is a good short book trying to get out. In response to this problem, the present draft has been slimmed down by one-third mainly just by eliminating repetition and peripheral material. The benet to the reader is considerable, as the chapters now hang together much better than they did before. There is one important part of the book where no changes need to be made, and that is in thanking those friends and colleagues who helped me with the rst edition of this book. I should like to reiterate my thanks to Peter Buckley, Paul Geroski, Charles Sutcliffe and Mike Utton for their detailed criticisms of the manuscript, and to Phil Rosson for his advice on the economics of marketing. Nicole Collis typed the manuscript, and my wife Janet helped me to improve the style. Michael Hay (now of London Business School) and Sue Corbett saw the book through the press. Lauraine Newcombe provided secretarial support during the recent revision of the book. There are two people I should like to thank in particular because they have been involved with both the rst edition and the revised edition. The rst is Edward Elgar, who originally commissioned this book some 24 years ago when he was an editor with Martin Robertson (a division of Blackwells). I am very pleased that this new edition is appearing under his own imprint. The second is Jill Turner, Executive Assistant in the School of Business at the University of Reading, who has always been on hand to provide advice and support throughout the time in which this book has been in print. MARK CASSON UNIVERSITY OF READING
Introduction
We all of us know someone who is an entrepreneur. He may be a property developer, a small businessman, or just someone who knows how to turn a fast buck. Perhaps he buys secondhand Jaguar cars that are destined for the scrapheap, does them up and sells them to the Japanese. Or he buys unwanted books from publishers and sells them at unrepeatable bargain prices from a high-street shop. Nowadays it is quite fashionable to be an entrepreneur. Suburban front rooms are stacked high with pocket calculators to be sold through mail-order advertisements in the local paper. Commuters wives run nearly new boutiques in their local village. It was not always so. A French sociologist, challenged to give a denition of the entrepreneur, is reputed to have said The entrepreneur is a pig. This book attempts to give a more balanced view, but in doing so it faces the same problem as did the French sociologist: the most difcult part of studying entrepreneurship is to dene who or what is an entrepreneur. Most studies of the entrepreneur make no attempt at denition. They rely instead on a stereotype, that of the swashbuckling business adventurer. Anyone who conforms loosely to this stereotype is dubbed an entrepreneur. An examination of the folklore of entrepreneurship enables us to sketch the following portrait.
The entrepreneur
an item for which their wage was tuppence was priced at two guineas or more in the West End shops. John did not do well at school; he was quiet and withdrawn. Leaving school at the earliest opportunity, he became an errand boy and then shopassistant, but was sacked on his eighteenth birthday when he became entitled to higher wages. Finding another steady job hard to obtain, he resolved to go into business on his own account. He chose house clearance and secondhand furniture dealing. It was a time of high unemployment, and many of the unemployed were so poor that they nanced themselves by selling off family heirlooms, and many choice items were going for a song. Jacks experience with fashion garments had taught him that, while many people were poor, there were still those rich enough to afford expensive goods, if you knew where to nd them. His idea was to buy in bulk from the local neighbourhood and sell to West End dealers. What the dealers would not take he stored in the front room at home and sold from a market stall at the weekend. Before he could begin he needed to buy a handcart. He did not have the ready cash but, nding a cart locally that was rather overpriced, he offered to give the asking price if he could be allowed six months to pay. The owner was delighted to nd a buyer, and the cart was Jacks. Jack was selective in what he bought. He always promised his sellers that their effects would be disposed of discreetly. By this he meant that they would be sold on the other side of town for a high price instead of locally for a lower price. He often worked unusual hours, so that he could call when the husband was out of the house. Wives were more willing to sell old things that were just gathering dust. If they thought their husbands would miss it they might buy a cheaper item to replace it with; Jack often had something handy that would do. He soon learnt by experience what sort of things the West End dealers were looking for, but eventually these became more scarce as potential supplies were depleted by his own activities, and by competitors moving in on his eld. Jack realized that supplies were so tight that he would have to stimulate them articially. In particular there was a strong demand for fancy gilt-framed mirrors, and to satisfy this demand he entered the reproduction market. He obtained a couple of quotations in nearby Whitechapel for a batch of 50 reproduction items, and set the retail price by quadrupling his unit cost. He took the mirror which was to be copied and hawked it round the dealers he knew, offering a basic trade discount of 40 per cent, with an extra 10 per cent for an order of ve or more, and a further 5 per cent for cash in advance. In this way he collected enough cash to nance production of the rst batch of 50. The business took off in a big way. The dealers sold out the rst batch very quickly and re-ordered in bigger quantities. However, Jacks prot on the rst
Introduction
batch only allowed him to nance another batch of 50 right away, though by the time the fourth batch was under way, ploughed back prots together with prepayments allowed the production run to increase to 250. Unit costs fell as batch size increased, and Jack found that he was doing very well indeed. He began to look around for something to do with the cash. He realized that what sold the mirror was the design of the frame, and that the same sort of frame could be used for pictures, prints and photographs as well, so these products were added to his range. About this time it occurred to Jack that he could cut out some of the dealers and sell direct to the public. Without the dealers margin he could set a lower price and sell more units. The logical place to sell was where the market was biggest, and so when the premises next to his largest trade customer became vacant he rented them, and set up in competition. By cutting his price he devalued his competitors existing stock, and shortly the rm was forced into liquidation. However, Jack helped his old friend by taking over the lease and buying up the stock, on what Jack considered very generous terms. When war broke out in 1939 Jack realized that, as a rst-generation Briton, he was in a rather vulnerable position. As a youngster he had been aware of Cockney antipathy to the aliens who settled in East London. He sold his business while it was still doing well, and invested the proceeds in jewellery. This was the form in which he kept his savings throughout the war. Very patriotically he enlisted, and soon found his niche running the stores on an aireld. As a quartermaster his methods were somewhat unconventional, and the stores often contained some things they shouldnt and were short of a few things they should have held. However, Jack never made anything personally out of his deals, though by the end of the war quite a few people owed Jack a favour. After the war Jack kept in touch with them, and some of them repaid the favour by investing in his business ventures, or introducing Jack to useful contacts. By the time he was demobilized Jacks experience in the stores had given him a good idea of the sort of surplus goods that would be coming onto the market, and for some years after the war he made a living buying up motor spares and selling them to people who were trying to keep their pre-war vehicles on the road. However, his big opportunity did not come until restrictions on the production of domestic furniture were lifted. Immediately after the war the rate of household formation had been very high on account of marriages deferred because of the war. All these households had been furnished with utility items, built to government specication, but public provision had resulted in too low a degree of product differentiation for most consumers tastes. As a wartime economy measure this was fully justied, but it was ill-adapted to the emerging post-war afuent soci-
The entrepreneur
ety. Jack decided to go back into fancy frames and mirrors, but to give his products a futuristic look. He sunk his own savings in an initial batch of frames and was fortunate to sell them outright to a buyer for a chain of high-street stores. The frames sold well, but to Jacks surprise the buyer suggested that an antique-look frame might also sell, provided that the frames were in better taste than Jacks prewar product. As the chain expanded so did Jacks own business; however, the store managers always insisted on putting the frames at the back of the store, instead of at the front, as Jack would have preferred. Jack resolved to set up his own outlets in order to keep the chain store on its toes, and to improve his bargaining power. He rented a number of shops and sold prints, antique maps and mirrors as well as frames. However, although his sales were high, his costs were even higher, and very soon he was in nancial difculties. He approached his bank manager to ask for an overdraft to nance his working capital. The manager was sympathetic, but cautious. He introduced him to an accountant who drew up a proper balance sheet and made projections of income and expenditure. The accountant made a number of recommendations for turning round the business. 1. 2. 3. 4. The shops should sell a wider range of merchandise and not just Jacks own products. Stock control should be improved, using more formal procedures. Jack should stop trying to run everything himself, and managers should be given more discretion. Higher wages should be paid to attract better-quality staff. He should stop recruiting yes men and hire people with some air of their own instead. Jack should form a limited company and put some professional people on the board to advise him.
5.
The bank manager indicated that the money would be available if these changes were made. It seemed to Jack that the establishment had nally gained the upper hand. But he needed the money and so he agreed; and this is how the Flash Furniture Company was born. Very soon Jacks stores were stocking a complete range of furniture and glossy household goods, and Flash Homes were pictured in full-page advertisements in the womens weeklies. They could also be seen in the show houses on the big new estates. A special feature was that items were coordinated to form a complete range of room furnishing in a particular style. You could buy Tudor or Spanish as well as the budget-price Superluxe range. You chose the items you wanted using the special Adjustable Room Planner. Later a Nordic range was introduced, nished in brightly coloured plastic for easy
Introduction
cleaning, but this dated rather quickly. Much of it was sold off for ofce use; the remainder was lost when a mysterious re gutted a warehouse, but fortunately it was fully insured. About this time unpleasant rumours began to circulate about Jacks personal life. He featured in the gossip columns, particularly in the at-racing season, when he hosted frequent parties for other racehorse owners. It was said, however, that he neglected his mother, who still lived in a at in East London. Jack strenuously denied the charge, and said that his mother was given everything she wanted including a television and that she was too old to get about anyway. In 1936, he had married Georgina, only daughter of Brigadier Mount of Monks Court, Oxfordshire, and an heiress to a small fortune. They had no children, and after the war Jack had begun to groom his young cousin Robert to take over the business. Soon after Robert came of age Jack retired from active management of the business, and began devoting himself to the pursuits of a country gentleman. He became well known for his views on free education as the key to equality of opportunity. He lavishly endowed one of the newer universities, and re-equipped its common rooms in the Nordic style. The business began to go down hill, but Jack did not seem to notice, being preoccupied with the honours heaped upon him by the establishment. Shortly before his death he was knighted for his services to education and industry, and was awarded an honorary doctorate from one of the newer universities. At the degree congregation he was described as a great public benefactor and a man of the people. He always tried to give the public what it wants and believed passionately in the housewife voting with the pennies in her purse. It was generally agreed that, if there were a few more people like Jack Brash, then the country would not be in the state it is in today.
The existence of this stereotype has undoubtedly impeded the economic analysis of the entrepreneur. There is a tendency to evaluate theories solely on the basis of their ability to rationalize this preconceived view. This procedure is the very antithesis of proper research methodology. Many of the qualities with which the heroic stereotype is imbued are simply a reection of contemporary cultural attitudes. Nevertheless, the stereotype is useful in that it provides various hypotheses regarding the family background, personal qualities and the business methods of the entrepreneur. The fact that these hypotheses are value-loaded does not matter, so long as they are regarded only as working hypotheses and not as statements of empirical regularity. The stereotype is useful as an articulation
The entrepreneur
of the view that there is a correlation between various personal characteristics and entrepreneurial activity. It serves to direct the theorists attention to the need to derive, if possible, relations between observable personal characteristics and the level of entrepreneurial activity. It is one of the objects of this book to deduce from very simple assumptions testable hypotheses of this kind.
PART I
Theoretical Foundations
The stimulus for writing the rst edition of this book was a perception that, at the time, there was no established economic theory of the entrepreneur. The subject area had been surrendered by economists to sociologists, psychologists and political scientists. Indeed, it seemed that all the social sciences, except economics, had a theory of the entrepreneur. There were two main reasons why there was no economic theory of the entrepreneur. These were connected with the limitations of the two main schools of economic thought at the time. First, the neoclassical school of economics made very extreme assumptions about access to information. Simple neoclassical models assume that everyone has free access to all the information they require for taking decisions. This assumption reduces decision making to the mechanical application of mathematical rules for optimization. It trivializes decision making, and makes it impossible to analyse the role of entrepreneurs in taking decisions of a particular kind. Secondly, the Austrian school of economics, which takes the entrepreneur more seriously, is committed to extreme subjectivism a philosophical standpoint which makes a predictive theory of the entrepreneur impossible. Austrians argue that anyone who has the sort of information necessary to predict the behaviour of entrepreneurs has a strong incentive to stop theorizing and become an entrepreneur himself. They suggest, furthermore, that by entering the system himself, the theorist might well generate a behavioural response which would falsify his own prediction. This argument, however, really applies only to the prediction of entrepreneurial success; it may be much easier to predict entrepreneurial failures. The argument also fails to recognize that many economic laws refer to the aggregate behaviour of populations of individuals, and that it may be possible to predict the behaviour of a population of entrepreneurs even if it is impossible to predict the individual behaviour of any one of them. In any case, the inability to predict individual behaviour depends crucially on the absence of barriers to entry into entrepreneurship. As we shall see, there are often signicant barriers and in this case the successful theorist has no opportunity to endogenize his predictions. As a consequence it may even be possible to predict the exploitation of specic
9
10
Theoretical foundations
entrepreneurial opportunities. Finally, even where prediction is impossible, it may still be feasible to develop a retrodictive theory of entrepreneurship that is, a theory that can be tested, with the benet of hindsight, on historical data. Thus even if a predictive theory cannot be developed, it is still possible to have a testable one.
1.2
The prevalence of the negative attitudes outlined above might have reected a situation in which there was little demand for a theory of the entrepreneur. But that was the very opposite of the truth. In many elds of economics, existing theories were demonstrably inadequate, and writers in these elds frequently pointed to the need for a theory of the entrepreneur. This need was most apparent when analysing the reasons for economic success and failure. The problem of explaining why some succeed while others fail is crucial to the study of economic development, the growth of the rm and the distribution of income. The spread of subjects is so broad because success can be analysed at a number of different levels: the individual, the institution (for example the rm), the region, the nation-state and the empire. Orthodox economic theory attributes success and failure almost entirely to material factors. For example, it attributes international differences in living standards to differences in national endowments of labour, capital and natural resources, which in turn stem from differences over time in rates of population growth, saving and natural resource depletion. Statistical evidence, however, indicates a signicant residual factor which is connected with differences in the quality rather than the quantity of resources, and also with differences in the efciency with which these resources are utilized. In recent statistical analysis of growth, differences in the quality of labour and in the efciency of resource use have been attributed to differences in the endowment of human capital. Human capital is often assumed to reect technical skills acquired through education and training, but it may also reect the underlying entrepreneurial abilities of the population. In this case, to fully eliminate the residual from the explanation it is necessary to have a theory of the entrepreneur. When economic growth and development is considered in a historical perspective, the role of the entrepreneur comes into sharper focus. Entrepreneurship appears as a personal quality which enables certain individuals to make decisions with far-reaching consequences. With the benet of hindsight the historian can see that certain people were right at a time when practically everyone else was wrong. By acting differently from other people, and achiev-
11
ing success in doing so, their example caused other people to change their mind, and thereby altered the course of history. The signicance of the entrepreneur, on this view, lies in the fact, rst, that he is atypical and, secondly, that though in a minority of one it is he that is right and the majority that is wrong. What is needed therefore is not so much a theory of the success of the entrepreneur as a theory of the failure of those around him. The essence of the theory of the entrepreneur is not so much the rationalization of success as the explanation of failure. Returning to the issue of international disparities in development, what needs to be explained is why the unsuccessful nation cannot allocate resources as efciently as the successful nation. An obvious hypothesis is that achieving efciency in resource allocation is a difcult and costly business, and that there are barriers to communicating the information and the attitudes that underlie the most efcient allocation system. Entrepreneurial effort is required to develop an improved allocation of resources and to transfer the relevant know-how to other countries. If two countries differ in their endowments of entrepreneurship then there will be a tendency for improvements to originate in the country with the most abundant endowment of entrepreneurs. A corollary of this is that, where indigenous entrepreneurs are scarce, it will be left to foreign entrepreneurs from the economically successful country to enter the backward country and improve the allocation of resources. An efciency gap will emerge, with one country consistently allocating resources better than the other. One country moves further ahead just as the other one is catching up. Moreover, as the catching up process depends upon the efforts of foreign entrepreneurs, the dependency of the backward country upon the successful country increases all the time. At the microeconomic level, the entrepreneur is obviously an important gure in the foundation and development of rms. Although economic theory has little to say on the matter, intuition suggests that there is a close connection between the personal qualities of the entrepreneur and the economic success of the rm, as measured by its growth and protability. This highly personalized view of the rm is very common in the writing of business history, and has been pursued extensively in the sociological literature. The personal qualities found within a society will be inuenced by the latent abilities of the ethnic groups that comprise the population, their level of education and the prevailing culture and morality. The extent to which these qualities are exercised in business will be affected by the relative status of different occupations and careers, and the legal freedoms that are enjoyed in commerce. One of the most interesting features of successful entrepreneurs is that they are frequently drawn from minority groups in society groups that nd alternative avenues of social advancement closed to them. It is therefore apparent that society and its institutions have an important inuence on the
12
Theoretical foundations
development and selection of entrepreneurs. Given that entrepreneurs are an important inuence on national economic success, it is clearly desirable to know what sorts of social institution provide a favourable climate for developing qualities of entrepreneurship. The theory of the entrepreneur has an important role in the eld of economic dynamics. Orthodox theory provides an unsatisfactory account of the way in which individuals and economic systems adjust to change. Simple neoclassical theory is inherently static in its approach, and is usually rendered dynamic simply by introducing ad hoc assumptions about adjustment lags. It offers very little insight into the ways in which different economic systems adjust to change. It trivializes the comparison of market economies and centrally planned economies by focusing on the case of perfect information in which resources are reallocated simply by applying two different versions of the conditions for the same mathematical optimum. This problem is a manifestation of a deeper problem, which is that neoclassical economics has no adequate theory of the competitive process. Competitive equilibrium is analysed in detail, but the process by which this equilibrium is reached is discussed in a highly articial way. Neoclassical theory presents a view of the market which has no room for the entrepreneur. In neoclassical theory the closest parallel to the entrepreneur is the Walrasian auctioneer. The Walrasian auctioneer calls out trial prices, and adjusts these prices until supply is equal to demand. This process of calling out prices is similar to the role of entrepreneurs in announcing price quotations. In the articial world of the Walrasian auctioneer, price setting costs nothing to carry out, and the auctioneers services are provided free. In the real world of the entrepreneur, on the other hand, price setting is costly and the entrepreneur is rewarded for his effort by a margin between the price at which he buys and the price at which he sells. This margin covers the costs of the price setting and provides a prot to the entrepreneur as well. The entrepreneur requires a prot because, unlike the auctioneer, he undertakes to trade at the prices he quotes, whether there is an equilibrium or not. Thus entrepreneurs may trade at disequilibrium prices whereas the Walrasian auctioneer does not. Trading at disequilibrium prices exposes the entrepreneur to risks for which he must be compensated in the form of prot. When explaining the trade cycle, the amplitude and frequency of uctuations depends crucially on the lengths of the various adjustment lags. These lags depend partly upon the willingness of people to adjust by relinquishing habitual modes of behaviour, and also upon technological constraints on adjustment. Adjustment is much easier the longer the time allowed, and the time available is greater the sooner the need to adjust is foreseen. If a few individuals have the foresight to recognize the impending need for change, then their example may encourage others to adjust as well. In this way the
13
existence of a few people with an entrepreneurial outlook may contribute to reducing adjustment lags and so help to improve the stability of the economy over the trade cycle. Thus, without a theory of the entrepreneur, it is impossible to provide a complete account of the lags which govern the dynamics of the trade cycle. The basic problem is that as yet there is no satisfactory account of the economic function of the entrepreneur. It is apparent both to the historian and to the modern observer that entrepreneurs have an important role in the market economy. Yet orthodox theory provides no room for the entrepreneur, for all the economic functions that need to be performed are already performed by someone else. This gives a certain implausibility to the neoclassical account of economic behaviour. To remedy this problem it is necessary to make far-reaching changes in economic theory.
1.3
Criticisms of neoclassical theory are very common, but the theory remains inuential because most of its critics can offer little to put in its place. Because they are unable to focus their criticisms properly, the problem of meeting their criticisms is quite unmanageable. It is therefore incumbent upon a new author to summarize concisely his main criticisms and to indicate how he intends to meet them. At an intuitive level, the basic objection to neoclassical economics is that it depersonalizes the market process. Transactors are faceless economic agents; the only personal characteristics that really matter are their tastes for consumer goods. The transactors are linked by an equally impersonal mechanism the invisible hand of Adam Smith, which neoclassical economics translates into an assumption of perfectly competitive market equilibrium. On the few occasions when market adjustment is personied it is in terms of the Walrasian auctioneer, as described above. It is essential to resolve the tension that exists between the invisible hand of Adam Smith and the all-too-visible hand of the entrepreneur, or alternatively between the very real entrepreneur and his ctional counterpart, the Walrasian auctioneer. In this book the theoretical reconstruction proceeds on two fronts. The rst is to recognize that individuals differ not only in their tastes but in their access to information. Individuals with similar tastes, acting under similar circumstances, but with different information at their disposal, may well make different decisions. The entrepreneur exhibits an extreme form of this. The entrepreneur believes that the totality of the information available to him, in respect of some decision, is unique. On account of this, he will decide one way when everyone else would decide another. The entrepreneur believes
14
Theoretical foundations
that he is right, while everyone else is wrong. Thus the essence of entrepreneurship is being different being different because one has a different perception of the situation. It is this that makes the entrepreneur so important. Were he not present, things would have been done very differently. In this way the entrepreneurs perception of the situation exerts a material inuence on the allocation of resources. The entrepreneur hopes to prot from this difference in perception by taking a position vis--vis other people. He may take up a position by contracting with them, or merely by adjusting his own behaviour in the light of his expectations about how they will behave. Suppose that the entrepreneur chooses the contractual route. Intuitively, he places bets with those who dissent from his view, in the hope that he will be rewarded when his beliefs turn out to be correct. Many of the predictions of the economic theory of entrepreneurship come from considering the tactical aspects of this strategy. The most important tactical problem is that the entrepreneur can only contract with other people on favourable terms if he can protect the information on which (he believes) his superior judgment is based. If he fails to maintain secrecy then he will be faced with competition from other people who share his views, and the terms on which he can contract will become less favourable as a result. He must also recognize that the people with whom he contracts will require assurances that he can pay up if he is proved wrong a constraint which may prove difcult, and quite irritating, for someone who has little wealth but is certain that he is right. The obvious strategy is to seek someone to underwrite the risk that he (the entrepreneur) is wrong. But since everyone else believes he is wrong, to whom can be turn? He can only obtain underwriting by persuading someone else that he is right. And therein lies the catch, for anyone else who believes the entrepreneur is right is ipso facto a potential competitor. As we shall see, it may be possible to establish special institutions to resolve this problem. But it should be apparent that, in the absence of such institutions, access to capital may prove a substantial barrier to entry into entrepreneurship. The second area of reconstruction stems from recognition of the difculties that are inherent in organizing a market. Simple neoclassical theory assumes that there are no costs of organizing a market, but in practice setting up a transaction involves a signicant resource cost. The buyer has to be put in contact with the seller, price has to be negotiated, physical custody of the goods has to be exchanged, their quality checked and default penalized. Since it is the entrepreneur that rst perceives the opportunity to contract, it is he that normally takes the initiative in approaching the other party. Consequently, it is he that incurs the cost of setting up the trade. In particular, the entrepreneur incurs the brokerage cost of making contact with the other party and communicating his offer to trade. The allocation of some of the other
15
costs may be determined by the provisions of the contract. But at the time the contract is negotiated the brokerage costs are sunk costs, and so there is no guarantee that they can be recovered from the other party. The entrepreneur must allow for these costs before initiating the transaction, and rely on his bargaining skill to recover the costs from the negotiated price. Thus, once transaction costs are recognized, it is apparent that the entrepreneurs bargaining skills are crucial in enabling him to appropriate the prots of his superior judgment through the contractual route. It is also important for the entrepreneurs success that he minimizes the transaction cost incurred in establishing any given volume of trade. This transaction cost embraces both the cost incurred directly by the entrepreneur and also any costs incurred by the other party that will be reected in the negotiated price. Transaction costs represent the opportunity costs of the market-making services that are required to overcome obstacles to trade. Most obstacles to trade stem from ignorance of one kind or another that is, from a lack of information. As a result, market-making services typically involve information processing; this is certainly true of brokerage, negotiation, metering and quality control. We have seen that most market-making costs are incurred in the rst instance by the entrepreneur, since he usually initiates the trade. In principle the entrepreneur could hire all the market-making services he requires, but in practice this is not always possible, for there are costs of making markets in market-making services and in many cases these costs are prohibitively high. This is because it is extremely difcult to check the quality of the market-making services supplied. The only effective way of checking quality is to supervise production of them, since only supervision gives access to the kind of information necessary for an absolute guarantee of quality. To effect this supervision it is necessary to create an institution in which the production of market-making services can be supervised. This institution is the market-making rm. The rationale of the market-making rm is that it produces trade at minimum cost. Implicit in this is a much broader concept of production than is used in neoclassical theory. Unlike the neoclassical theory, production involves not just the transformation of material inputs into outputs, but also the creation of trade from inputs of market-making services. These services are in turn generated by the utilization of assets. Two types of asset are particularly important: human assets such as administrative workers, and purpose-built infrastructures, such as transport and communication systems. Compared with the material-transforming rm, the market-making rm is of much greater economic signicance. The process of material transformation may interest the scientist and engineer, but economists prefer to regard as a black box whatever lies behind the production frontier. By contrast, the
16
Theoretical foundations
activity of making a market is of central interest to the economist. Indeed, we shall argue that the material-transforming rm is really of interest only in so far as its activities become integrated with market making, that is only in so far as it takes the initiative in hiring its own inputs and selling its own output. We suggest, furthermore, that the initiative for this integration normally comes from the market-making activities, and not from material transformation, which from an economic point of view is a quite trivial activity. The activities of the market-making rm are probably best understood by considering the relations between the rm and the household. Households supply factor services to rms and buy consumer products from them. We are all familiar with the fact that in setting up these transactions it is usually the rm that takes the initiative in approaching the household. In consumer product markets, for example, the rm seeks out the household by advertising its product, displaying it in convenient locations (shops) and offering to supply the product on demand at a publicly quoted non-negotiable price. The rm guarantees the quality, and provides households with a sanction to ensure that this is enforced namely a brand name with a valuable reputation which can be lost as a result of complaints. Similarly, in the labour market, rms typically advertise vacancies, quote wage rates and also take the initiative in evaluating product quality; for example, they assess the workers performance while he is in probationary employment. As a consequence, the worker needs to take only a fairly passive role in placing himself in employment. The fact that the entrepreneur has often to create an institution to make markets between himself and other transactors extends the range of issues about which the entrepreneur has to make judgments. Although he does not have to perform all the activities within the institution himself, he is responsible for the structure of the institution and, in particular, for the way in which specic tasks are delegated, and the way that the delegates are supervised. As a consequence, the theory of the market-making rm feeds back upon the original conceptualization of the entrepreneur. It describes a specic range of issues with which many entrepreneurs are heavily preoccupied, and upon which entrepreneurial judgment has to be continuously exercised.
1.4
The next chapter denes the role of the entrepreneur and introduces the basic concepts which are required to analyse it. One of the most important of these concepts is coordination. Chapters 3 to 5 are devoted exclusively to this concept. They show how the entrepreneurs assessment of a situation is crucial in affecting where, when and how coordination occurs.
17
Chapters 6 to 10 relate the theory of the entrepreneur to the theory of the rm. The rm is the institution through which the entrepreneur operates in a market economy; indeed, the entrepreneur is often identied as the founder, or as the owner or manager, of a rm. One of the main objects of this part of the book is to locate the entrepreneur within the rm, and in particular to identify the circumstances under which he is the employer and the circumstances under which he becomes an employee. The nal part of the book, comprising Chapters 11 to 15, weaves together the different threads of the argument which have appeared in the main body of the book. Entrepreneurship is related to wider issues such as social mobility and the distribution of income. The book ends where it begins, by using the theory to re-evaluate the stereotype of the entrepreneur.
SUMMARY
This chapter has identied one of the main issues in entrepreneurship to be the explanation of success and failure in individuals, organizations and nations. It has been argued that radical change is called for if the entrepreneur is to be integrated into mainstream economic theory.
18
Theoretical foundations
It is inevitable that the neoclassical theory that we are attacking should be something of a straw man. The attack on orthodox theory is chiey an expository device, though if the reader wishes to identify a particular target, then Debreu (1959) will sufce. The classic statement of the gap in economic theory is Baumol (1968). Theoretical interest in the entrepreneur has recently been renewed, both from the subjectivist standpoint, for example Buchanan and Pierro (1980), and the neoclassical one, for example Kihlstrom and Laffont (1979). The gap has proved particularly serious in the study of economic development. Denison has measured the residual component in the economic growth of rich nations (Denison 1962, 1967), though the existence of this component was recognized long before (Cole, 1954); the entrepreneurial factor in the development of poorer countries is emphasized by Broehl (1978), Gerschenkron (1953), Hagen (1962), Harbison (1956) and Hirschman (1958). Recent progress in the study of entrepreneurship and economic development is reviewed by Leff (1979). For an overview of the literature on entrepreneurship, see Cochran (1968), Cole (1959), Hoselitz (1951) and Schreier and Komives (1973); other useful references include Becker and Whisler (1967), Bruce (1976). Glade (1967), Gurzynski (1976), Kingston (1977), Miller (1962), Sawyer (1951) and Schultz (1975). The seminal paper on market behaviour when individuals have limited access to information is Stigler (1961), though subsequent developments of Stiglers approach have been somewhat tangential to entrepreneurship; for a survey see Rothschild (1973). Somewhat similar issues are considered from a different perspective in a volume edited by Cox (1967). Richardson (1960) presents an interesting analysis of the allocation problems that are raised when information is restricted. Manne (1966) has considered the role of privileged access to information in the context of insider-trading on the stock market. Assumptions about the distribution of information between transactors underlie the stock market philosophies reported by Smith (1981). Finally, mention should be made of a very interesting study of access to information in cereals trading by Stewart (1970). The most dramatic examples of success and failure are to be found in the histories of rms and their product innovations; high points in the literature of success and failure include Brooks (1963), Bylinsky (1976) and Robertson (1974). For an interesting account of success and failure from a more academic perspective, see, for example Church (1969).
20
Theoretical foundations
theory. It is therefore natural to work with denitions which relate directly to observables, and which distinguish the major types of economic agent observed in practice. The problem with the theory of entrepreneurship is that these two approaches have never been integrated. The functional approach should predict the emergence of a particular group of people embodying a unique complex of characteristics characteristics which enable them to carry out their function most efciently. Given that at least some of the characteristics are observable, they could then form the basis for an indicative denition of the entrepreneur. It is one of the main objects of this book to achieve a convergence of the two approaches along these lines. Since this is a theoretical work, we begin with a functional denition, and then move towards an indicative one.
2.2
The entire structure of the theory developed below rests upon the following denition: an entrepreneur is someone who specializes in taking judgmental decisions about the coordination of scarce resources. It is instructive to consider this denition as one would a text, almost word by word. An entrepreneur is someone; in other words the entrepreneur is a person, not a team, or a committee, or an organization. Only individuals can take decisions; corporate bodies only arrive at decisions by aggregating votes. Individuals in committee make strategic decisions on how to inuence other peoples voting and on how to vote themselves; it is these decisions that are entrepreneurial, not the decision of the committee as a whole. This does not mean that the role of teams and committees is excluded; it means only that the denition commits us to a detailed examination of how such teams and committees operate internally. who specializes; everyone is involved in taking judgmental decisions at one time or another, but this does not make them a specialist at it. A specialist carries out his function not only on his own behalf but on behalf of other people. In a market economy specialist services may be offered for hire, and individuals can decide which services to supply in accordance with their personal comparative advantage. Decision making may be hired out on this principle, as when consultants or managers act as delegates to take decisions on an owners behalf. Alternatively, decision makers may prefer to hire in resources, so that while on hire to them these resources are effectively under their control. Though they do not own the resources (in any permanent sense) they have control over them (as least temporarily) and can therefore exercise decision making with regard to their utilization. Thus the market for decision
21
making can operate in two ways, with the decision-making service being hired by the owners of resources, or with the decision makers hiring resources from their owners. In either case the market effects a separation between decision making and other activities, and so facilitates specialization in decision making according to comparative advantage. in taking judgmental decisions; the concept of choice, and hence of decision making, is central to economic theory. A judgmental decision is one where different individuals, sharing the same objectives and acting under similar circumstances, would make different decisions. The difference arises because they have different perceptions of the situation arising from different access to information, or different interpretations of it. The difference between them is not only a quantitative one, in the sense that it takes a longer time, or involves a greater expenditure of resources, in making the same decision, but a qualitative one, namely that the decision made is actually different. about the coordination; coordination may be dened as a benecial reallocation of resources. Coordination is thus a dynamic concept, as opposed to allocation, which is a static one. The concept of coordination captures the fact that the entrepreneur is an agent of change: he is not concerned merely with the perpetuation of the existing allocation of resources, but with improving upon it. of scarce resources; the restriction to scarce resources limits the eld of study to that usually identied as economic. It must be emphasized that this denition is institution-free. It makes no reference to the type of economic system within which the entrepreneur operates, or to the particular kind of organization or institution with which he is associated. The entrepreneurial function can be performed by very different kinds of people under different economic systems. In principle, the entrepreneur could be a planner in a socialist economy, or even a priest or king in a traditional society. In practice, though, entrepreneurship is closely identied with private enterprise in a market economy. This book follows convention in conning the analysis to the operations of the private sector in a market economy. It is assumed, furthermore, that entrepreneurs are motivated by self-interest. Their objectives relate to their consumption of goods and leisure, and to their status, as reected, for example, in the amount of deference and respect they receive from other people. Consumption and status can, however, be bought using the income generated by entrepreneurial activity. To simplify the theory it is assumed that entrepreneurs operate their business purely with a view to maximizing the prot they obtain from a given amount of effort. They rely on the prot to buy the consumption and the status they require; they do not seek to increase their status by methods which would reduce the protability of the business.
22
Theoretical foundations
Although these assumptions are clearly counterfactual, the resulting theory goes a long way towards explaining entrepreneurial behaviour. The relaxation of these very strict assumptions has been a major preoccupation of the authors own recent work since the publication of the rst edition of this book.
2.3
Having dened the function of the entrepreneur, it must now be established that this function is not completely trivial. This section shows that entrepreneurship is a continuing function rather than a once-for-all, or possibly intermittent, activity. There will be a demand for entrepreneurial services so long as opportunities for coordination exist. Opportunities will exist as long as new information is becoming available, in the light of which the existing allocation of resources appears inefcient. The new information may be a net addition to the stock of knowledge, in the sense of a discovery of something about which people were previously ignorant, or a replacement for obsolete knowledge. The former case is exemplied by scientic breakthroughs, successful prospecting for minerals and so on. The latter case, which is far more common, is exemplied by the updating of knowledge in the light of a recent event, that is by information that the state of the world has changed. It is unlikely that the number of new opportunities will run down over time. Discoveries will continue so long as people remain inquisitive. Updating of knowledge will occur so long as unpredictable disturbances affect the state of the world. It is not necessary to assume that the appearance of new opportunities is exogenous. The modeller may postulate various historical laws determining the occurrence of new opportunities. It is, however, important that the actual opportunities which occur should be unpredictable to the economic agents themselves. Otherwise agents could plan ahead with just as much certainty as if things were to remain unchanged. All coordination could be organized in the present to be implemented automatically in the future. Thus, while there would be intense entrepreneurial activity in the current period, there would be none at all in future periods. In principle, even the exploitation of unpredictable opportunities can be organized in the present for execution in the future using contingent plans. Contingency planning is analytically a very powerful concept. It is familiar to most economists through the time-state theory of general equilibrium. It is familiar to management scientists through the concept of scenario planning. Contingency planning involves identifying all probable future states, devising plans now for each of them, and triggering the relevant plan automatically
23
once the future state has been realized. If contingency planning were implemented over an innite time horizon then decision making would become a once-for-all event. All decisions about the future would be telescoped into the present. The reason why contingency planning is never fully implemented is that it is not efcient to do so. It is not efcient because information processing is so costly. Planning involves information processing, and the further ahead one plans the more the contingencies multiply, and the greater the information costs become. Because contingencies evolve through a branching process, the number of contingencies typically increases exponentially with respect to the planners time horizon. Thus as the planning horizon moves forward in time, so information costs increase at an increasing rate. Information costs are minimized by planning only for the current period. However, such a strategy forgoes altogether the benets of planning ahead. The main benet of planning ahead is that it enables adjustment to anticipated events to commence earlier and so reduces costs of adjustment. For example, using a two-period plan it is possible to maximize the expected value of the objective conditional upon subjective probabilities attaching to second-period states of the world. The solution to this problem gives an efcient strategy for the current period (and a provisional strategy for the future period) conditional upon these probabilities. The expected outcome of the two-period plan may be compared with the expected outcome of two sequential one-period plans, in which the decisions made in the rst period constrain the options available in the second-period plan. The expected value of the objective under sequential planning will normally be lower by an amount which reects the increased costs of adjusting at short notice to second-period conditions. This shows that the expected cost of adjustment is dependent upon the time horizon. Total planning cost is given by the sum of information costs and adjustment costs. It is minimized by setting the planning horizon at the margin where the increase in information costs incurred by putting back the horizon is just equal to the expected reduction in adjustment costs that would be effected. Normally this point corresponds to a nite multi-period planning horizon. When multi-period planning is used, a plan must be revised with a frequency at least as great as the term for which it has been drawn up. It is often advantageous, though, to roll over a plan, that is to revise a plan before the existing plan has expired. The frequency with which a plan is revised will be strongly inuenced by the rate at which new relevant information becomes available to the planner. Each period a decision has to be made whether to continue with the existing plan or to revise it. The rst policy is essentially a passive one; it requires no initiative on the part of the planner. The second
24
Theoretical foundations
policy is an active one, and incurs information costs when it is initiated. The planner must assess whether the efciency gains from a revised plan will outweigh the costs of revision. If they do so then the plan will be revised; if not then the provisional arrangements specied in the existing plan will be implemented. To a certain extent this distinction between active and passive planning encapsulates an important difference between entrepreneurs and other people. Consider for example a simple type of plan in which the same strategy is repeated one period after the next; in other words the plan involves the adoption of a habit. In this case the passive decision not to revise the plan is equivalent to a conservative no change strategy. An active decision, on the other hand, involves a reappraisal of the habit, which possibly (though not necessarily) leads to a change. An entrepreneur may be characterized as an active planner, and a non-entrepreneur as a passive planner. Because entrepreneurs are active planners they invest heavily in decision making, while passive planners allow their decisions to be taken by default. As we have seen, the rationale for active planning is that new information has become available which leads entrepreneurs to question the efciency of their existing plans. Also two kinds of information have been distinguished, namely discoveries and updates. The kind of information to which the entrepreneur responds will determine whether he is seen as an instigator of change, or as someone who reacts to it. An entrepreneur who revises his plans when there has been no change in the state of the world is not responding to an objective change in the state of the world, but to a subjective change in his state of knowledge. But as a result of his plan revision, the state of the world may well be changed. In objective terms, therefore, he is an initiator of change. On the other hand, the entrepreneur responding to an information update is responding, indirectly, to an objective change in the state of the world, which rendered his original information obsolete. In objective terms, therefore, he is reacting to change rather than initiating it. Although supercially it seems important to know whether entrepreneurs are initiators or reactors to change, it is apparent that for analytical purposes the distinction between these roles is of relatively little consequence.
2.4
Decision-making services are scarce because decision making involves the use of resources which have a positive opportunity cost. This section analyses these costs and briey considers the ways in which entrepreneurs can economize on them.
25
The logic of a decision suggests that there are three main stages of decision making, each involving several activities (see the left-hand column of Table 2.1). The rst stage in any decision is to formulate the problem. This involves specifying the objective, the potential strategies and the constraints, and deriving from them a decision rule. The objective is dened upon a set of targets, or goals. When there is more than one target the objective indicates the way that different targets should be traded off against each other. Each potential strategy involves setting particular values for each of the available instruments, that is for the variables under the decision makers control. Typically one of the strategies will be a null strategy, which involves preserving the status quo. In the context of entrepreneurship this means that the allocation of resources will remain unchanged. The other strategies represent alternative methods of exploiting an opportunity for coordination. The optimal strategy is the one that maximizes the value of the objective. Table 2.1 Activities First stage: formulation of the decision problem Specication of the objective Specication of the potential strategies Specication of the constraints Derivation of the decision rule Second stage: generating the data Data collection Data estimation Third stage: execution of the decision Application of the data to the decision rule Initiation of the implementation process Decision-making activities and the qualities they require Qualities
Self-knowledge (or knowledge of the principals objectives) Imagination Practical knowledge Analytical ability Search skill Foresight Computational skill Communication skill (in formulating instructions)
The constraints restrict the degree of freedom available when choosing the instruments. The formulation of the constraints is derived, either implicitly or explicitly, from a theory about the way the world works (or the part of the world directly relevant to the decision problem). In some cases the theory may be expressed in terms of a formal model in which the constraints are derived mathematically.
26
Theoretical foundations
Combining the objective, the strategies and the constraints makes it possible to derive a decision rule. This rule is obtained by solving the rst-order marginal conditions for the maximum of the objective subject to the constraints. A well-behaved decision rule establishes a one-to-one relationship between the values of certain state variables and the set of optimal strategies. The state variables correspond to the variables which appear in the specication of the objectives and the constraints. The next stage in the decision is to generate the data. The data establish numerical values for the state variables. The data may already be available from secondary sources, or they may have to be gathered from primary sources on the initiative of the entrepreneur. When all available data sources have been tapped, the data set may still remain incomplete. The decision maker must then supply his own estimates of the unknown variables. In doing so he may wish to exploit correlations between the unknown variables and the known values of other variables. As a result, he may need to tap more varied sources of information than those from which his direct observations were obtained. The nal stage is the execution of the decision. This involves the application of the decision rule to the completed data set, and the initiation of the implementation process. It is evident that the decision-making function consists almost entirely of information processing of one kind or another. In this context information processing includes the collection, analysis, communication and storage of information. Mental labour (as opposed to physical labour) is an important input in each case. Considering the human being as an information-processing unit, the senses are used for data collection, the brain for analysis and storage, and the body (voice, hands and so on) for communication. However, in each case there is some possibility of substituting non-human assets for labour. Instrumentation can be used to monitor physical events and so generate updated information on states of the world. Documentary les can be substituted for human memory in the storage of information. Computers economize on labour in both the analysis and storage of information. Finally, transport and communication infrastructures economize on the labour used for communication: for example, post and telecommunications are a substitute for face-to-face communication. The fact that mental labour is a key input to decision making indicates that decision making has an opportunity cost in terms of leisure or manual labour services forgone. The fact that there is substantial investment in assets designed specically to economize on mental labour indicates that the opportunity costs of mental labour are quite substantial. The entrepreneur can reduce the time he spends on each decision through delegation. However, some activities are much more easily delegated than others. In principle the specication of the objectives and the options cannot
27
be delegated; they have to be communicated by the principal to the delegate so that the delegate understands the nature of the problem. In practice, though, only the outline may be specied by the principal; the delegate may be left to ll in the details for himself. The other activities can all be delegated; indeed, in principle each activity could be delegated to a different person. There are two main obstacles to delegation. The rst is the difculty of communication between principal and delegate. Communication involves encoding a message, transmitting it and decoding it, all of which takes up time for each party. Moreover, language is never completely unambiguous, so that there is always a risk that misunderstanding may result. The second difculty relates to the organization of delegation. A major problem in delegation is default. Default may occur either because the delegate is incompetent or because he deliberately pursues his own interests at the expense of those of his principal. The risk of incompetence is controlled mainly by screening delegates for ability. Deliberate default may be controlled both by screening for honesty and by devising an appropriate system of incentives. The problem of default in decision making is greatest when the delegate is given discretion to exercise his own judgment. In this case the delegate himself is a potential entrepreneur. The most efcient criterion by which the delegates performance can be assessed is whether in retrospect his decision was reasonable, given the information he could have been expected to have at the time. However, the application of this criterion is likely to be expensive as it involves a difcult subjective assessment of what might have been. Furthermore, the principal may have to wait a long time before deciding whether the delegate has been in default, and this diminishes the effectiveness of any incentives offered to him. On the other hand, assessing the decision prematurely is an unsatisfactory solution, at least in the long run, because if the delegate expects to be assessed arbitrarily he will take little account of the correctness of his decision. It may even bias his decision so that he chooses a strategy which appears favourable on a short-run assessment, but is unfavourable to his principal in the long run. The risk of default can be reduced over time by repeatedly delegating to the same reliable people. The risk borne by the principal is partly subjective, reecting his ignorance of the personal qualities of the delegate. Repeated delegation to the same person, if it is successful, reduces this ignorance and enables the delegate to establish a reputation with the principal. As a result, the principal recognizes that, by his continuing this strategy, the risk of default will be much lower than the risk he originally perceived. The alternative is to delegate without discretion. This means that the delegate is given precise instructions on how to proceed; that is, which information to collect from where, what decision rule to apply, and so on. The question of default here reduces to whether the delegate obeyed orders: did he record the
28
Theoretical foundations
information accurately, apply the decision rule correctly, and so on? This kind of question can be answered in two main ways: either by checking the work as it is done, through supervision, or checking it after it has been done by replicating the procedure. Supervision has the advantage that the work is only done once, but also has the disadvantage that the supervisor and delegate have to be close together, so that the supervisor can make spot checks on the delegate. This normally means that they must work at the same location. If each decision occupies the delegate for only a short time, then the average cost per decision of setting up the supervisory arrangement may be quite high. However, given that decision making is a continuing process, average cost can be reduced by offering continuity of work to the delegate. This arrangement also has the advantage of establishing mutual condence between principal (or supervisor) and delegate, in the manner described above. The commitment to continuity of work is likely to be of far greater signicance to both parties than the nature of the individual decisions to which the delegate is to be assigned. The costs of contractual specication and negotiation may therefore be reduced if the delegate is hired and paid, not for each separate decision, but simply by the time he spends in decision making. This arrangement also provides the principal with the exibility to reassign the delegate to another decision should unforeseen circumstances require it, without having to renegotiate the price for the job. The delegate does not lose by this arrangement so long as he is indifferent between the various decision problems to which he may be assigned. Contractual costs may be further reduced by providing for automatic renewal of the contract each period, that is by negotiating a contract for an open term. The non-discretionary delegate decision maker may therefore be offered an open-term contract for continuous employment at a time rate in return for following specic decision procedures under supervision. In other words, the delegate acquires the contractual status of the typical employee. Discretionary decision makers too may take open-term contracts on time rates, but because discretion is allowed the case for detailed supervision is much weaker. Although contractually they may still be employees, their employer will typically control the quality of decision making not by daily supervision but by longer-term retrospective assessments of performance.
2.5
A decision does not need to be delegated in its entirety to a single person. Different decision-making activities can be specialized with different people. Nor does each delegate need to stand in the same contractual relation to the principal. The choice of decision rule might be delegated to a consultant for a
29
xed fee, and the information to be fed into the decision rule might be purchased in the form of a reference book, while the remaining functions might be performed by employees. When there is specialization among employees in different facets of decision making, it is important to structure the information ows between them appropriately. In theory each delegate might communicate only with the principal, but in practice it is normally efcient for the delegates to communicate directly with each other. Each delegate then needs to know from whom he will receive communications, and to whom he should send them. Where delegates communicate directly with each other in the service of the same principal they are said to operate as a team. The rules governing the information ow determine the organization of the team. It is tempting to suggest that the team itself can function as an entrepreneur but, as noted earlier, this is not strictly correct. The team coordinates the activities of individual decision makers. In so far as individual team members have discretionary powers, they may themselves be entrepreneurs. Also it is likely that the person establishing the organization is an entrepreneur, in the sense that he has to take judgmental decisions about which is the most suitable form of organization. But the team itself is not an entrepreneur.
2.6
ENTREPRENEURIAL QUALITIES
The qualities essential for successful decision making are listed in the righthand column of Table 2.1. The diversity of the qualities required suggests that the entrepreneur needs to be a generalist rather than a specialist. In other words, it is important for the entrepreneur to be reasonably procient in all aspects of decision making, rather than very procient in some aspects but inadequate in others. However, the fact that all the qualities are normally necessary does not mean that they are all of equal economic signicance. Some qualities are possessed by practically everyone, so that the possession of them is not necessarily peculiar to the entrepreneur. It is those qualities that are most scarce which are of the most economic signicance. A scarcity of personal qualities usually occurs, not because everyone has only a little of the quality, but because only a few people have the quality and many people do not have it all. In other words, scarcity is associated with skewness in the distribution of qualities between people. It is the possession of scarce qualities which confers an advantage on some people in becoming an entrepreneur. It has already been established that functional specialization in decision making is possible. This implies that the entrepreneur who is decient in
30
Theoretical foundations
Table 2.2
Additional activities required when there is functional specialization within decision making, and the qualities they require Qualities Delegation skill Organizational skill
some qualities can in principle hire delegates who have these qualities. The entrepreneur and the delegate complement each other and can take decisions successfully as a unit. The difculty with functional specialization is, rstly, that it is necessary to screen delegates and to devise appropriate incentives for them to pursue their principals objectives, and secondly, that if the delegates operate as a team then it is necessary to devise an organizational structure too. This means that, in order to hire complementary qualities, the entrepreneur needs additional qualities of his own, namely delegation skills and organizational skills (see Table 2.2). The difculty of screening and devising incentives is far greater for some qualities than for others. Among the scarce qualities, the most difcult to screen for are imagination and foresight. It is doubtful if anyone without these qualities can succeed in recruiting people with them. It follows that these two qualities are essential to the successful entrepreneur. Besides these qualities, however, the entrepreneur also needs either to be himself a generalist, so that he can discharge his function without delegation, or to possess delegation and organizational skills. All entrepreneurial qualities are to some extent innate. However, not all of them are entirely innate. Some can be enhanced by training, or simply by experience. For example, analytical ability and computational skill can be enhanced by education at school and university, while practical knowledge and search skills can be enhanced by general experience of everyday life. Entrepreneurial careers will be strongly inuenced by the desire to enhance qualities which are scarce and difcult to acquire from delegates because of the problems involved in screening. Of the two indispensable qualities mentioned above, imagination is almost entirely innate, while foresight, though to some extent innate, can be enhanced by a varied experience. Delegation skill and organization skill, though not essential, are highly desirable whenever large-scale decision making is contemplated. These too are qualities which can be enhanced through experience. The analysis is summarized in Table 2.3. It suggests that there are four main qualities which are crucial to the success of the entrepreneur. One of the
Table 2.3
An analysis of entrepreneurial qualities Essential to all non-trivial decisions Scarce and unequally distributed Essential, scarce Scarce, difcult to and difcult to screen for and screen for capable of enhancement
Quality Self-knowledge Imagination Practical knowledge Analytical ability Search skill Foresight Computational skill Communication skill Delegation skill Organizational skill
31
32
Theoretical foundations
qualities imagination is almost entirely innate. The other three qualities are all capable of enhancement. The problems encountered in screening for these qualities, and in enhancing the ones that are decient, have a number of important implications for the development of a successful entrepreneurial career. The analysis of these implications constitutes one of the main themes of this book.
SUMMARY
This chapter has presented a functional denition of the entrepreneur and has considered why the entrepreneurial function is so valuable. It emphasizes that the demand for entrepreneurship stems from the need to adjust to change, and that the supply of entrepreneurship is limited, rst by the scarcity of the requisite personal qualities, and secondly by the difculty of identifying them when they are available.
33
Nicosia, 1966), organization theory (Marschak, 1968, 1971, 1972; Marschak and Radner, 1972; Simon, 1959, 1976, 1980) and the theory of the rm (Loasby, 1976; Williamson, 1975). Shackle (1961, 1970, 1979) has laid great stress on the role of imagination as part of his theme that decision making is a creative process. It is worth pointing out, however, that the concept of imagination used in this book is very mundane compared with the concept that Shackle seems at times to have in mind. Our imaginative entrepreneur is not a budding Leonardo or Newton, but is simply someone who is able to visualize the probable consequences of a fairly marginal change in resource allocation. The question of the innateness of entrepreneurial ability is considered by Kierulff (1975).
The entrepreneur has been dened as someone whose judgment differs from that of other people. He believes that, without his intervention, a wrong decision would be made. The decision may be wrong because it is made passively, with the appropriate policy not even being given active consideration. Or it may be wrong because the appropriate policy has been considered and dismissed because of misinformation or faulty logic. Because of this wrong decision, resources will not be allocated as efciently as they might be. Thus an opportunity for coordination exists. The entrepreneur intervenes in order to exploit his superior judgment. There are several ways in which the entrepreneur could intervene, and these are considered in detail later (see Chapter 8). For the moment it is assumed that the entrepreneur intervenes by buying up the resources that would have been misallocated. By becoming the owner of the resources he can ensure that they are put to better use. It cannot be too strongly emphasized that this motive for acquiring ownership of resources is quite different from the motive usually assumed in economics. The usual reason given for the acquisition of resources is the desire to consume them. When everyones judgment is the same, the desire to consume is the ultimate reason for owning resources. When judgments differ, a second and probably more powerful reason for the acquisition of resources comes into play. Change of ownership is the rst stage in the reallocation of a resource to an alternative use. The second stage is for the new owner to utilize the resource in a way its previous owner would not. This change of ownership becomes one of the elements in a twostage process by which differences in judgment are translated into the reallocation of resources. If the entrepreneur wishes to acquire ownership of resources from other people by voluntary means, then he is committed to the contractual route. He is obliged to trade the ownership of another resource for the one that he wishes to acquire. Any private reward that the entrepreneur obtains from his superior judgment will be the result of negotiating favourable terms for these trades. Thus so far as the entrepreneur is concerned, superior judgment is
34
35
turned to good account only when the exercise of judgment is combined with the exercise of bargaining power. To simplify the analysis, it is assumed in this chapter that the entrepreneur attempts to exploit his bargaining power to its absolute maximum, by obliging other people to trade with him on terms which leave them no better off than they would otherwise be. In practice, of course, he must allow them a perceptible increase in their welfare in order for his proposals to prove acceptable. Subject to this qualication, however, the entrepreneur adopts a hard-line approach in which he appropriates all the potential economic rents for himself.
3.2
As noted earlier, coordination is a principal function of the entrepreneur. It is important, however, to distinguish between the private and social aspects of coordination. It is assumed that every individual is motivated to achieve private coordination. Private coordination occurs when the individual concerned is made better off as a result of a reallocation of resources. Social coordination occurs when someone is made better off without anyone else being made worse off; in other words, when there is a Paretoimprovement in resource allocation. One of the key issues in economics, and in the study of entrepreneurship in particular, is the extent to which the pursuit of private coordination indirectly leads to social coordination as well. In this context it is useful to introduce a weaker concept of social coordination. This asserts that coordination occurs when those who benet from a reallocation could in principle compensate those who lose. In other words, there is a potential for Pareto-improvement, although, because compensation is not actually paid, the improvement does not occur. Coordination can be analysed from either a general or a partial point of view. A general analysis considers coordination within the context of the economy as a whole: it is concerned with a change in the economy-wide allocation of resources. A partial analysis considers coordination in the context of a small part of the economy. It is assumed that a change in resource allocation within a given sector will exert a negligible inuence upon the rest of the economy, so that the feedback on that sector from the rest of the economy can be ignored. General analysis has the advantage that it provides a completely selfcontained view of coordination. Unlike partial analysis, it has no loose ends where the effects of the coordination spill over onto parts of the economy outside the model. On the other hand, the structure of a general model is far more complex than a partial one: for example, it involves many more differ-
36
Theoretical foundations
ent types of resource. To compensate for this it is necessary to simplify by making very strong behavioural assumptions. Because partial analysis has intrinsically a much simpler structure, there is scope to make much more realistic assumptions about individual behaviour. This chapter focuses upon the general analysis of coordination. Although the model presented is highly abstract, it illustrates some important aspects of coordination which might not otherwise be apparent. It has an important place within the logical structure of the book because it provides the foundations for the transition to the more relevant partial analysis which begins in Chapter 5.
3.3
In conventional economics the most fundamental example of coordination is the process of exchange. Consider an economy with a xed endowment of two goods, good 1 and good 2. The more of each good that is consumed by one individual the less there is available for the other. The initial allocation of the goods is such that each individual is endowed with relatively little of the good that he most prefers. Suppose, for example, that individual A likes good 1 much more than good 2, while individual B likes good 2 more than good 1. If individual A is initially allocated most of good 2, and B most of good 1, then each would be happy to sacrice some of his own endowment for some of the other. Both individuals could be made better off by an exchange of goods. Now suppose that there is a third party, C, who is an entrepreneur. In the absence of C, no exchange can take place. A and B either are unaware of each others existence or misperceive one anothers preferences. Another possibility is that they expect one another to default upon the contract, and so are unwilling to trade except through an intermediary. For the moment, ignorance or misperception is assumed; discussion of dishonesty is postponed until Chapter 6. The entrepreneur C knows the preferences of both A and B, but his preferences are not known to them. C can offer to trade with A and B using any combination of price and quantity he desires. C does not have any endowments of his own. He can only offer A what he intends to buy from B, and vice versa. This example can be analysed easily using an Edgeworth box. It is assumed that the economy has a xed endowment of the two goods. The total endowments are represented by the dimensions of the box KLMN in Figure 3.1. The allocation of goods to individual A is measured from the origin K and the allocation of goods to individual B from the origin M. Individual As
37
Figure 3.1
consumption of good 1 is measured upwards along the left-hand vertical axis, whilst their consumption of good 2 is measured to the right along the lower horizontal axis. Individual Bs consumption of good 1 is measured downwards along the right-hand vertical axis, whilst their consumption of good 2 is measured to the left along the upper horizontal axis. It is convenient to assume that initially each individual holds the entire endowment of one of the commodities. Thus the initial allocation of consumption is represented by a corner point in the gure, L, where all of good 1 is owned by A and all of good 2 is owned by B. It is assumed that each individual regards the two goods as to some extent complementary in consumption. More precisely, if he is offered two equally desirable combinations of the goods, then he would rather consume some positively weighted average of the combinations for example half of one and half of the other than either of the combinations themselves. This property is indicated geometrically by the convexity of the indifference map to the origin. Individual As indifference map emanates from the origin K and is exemplied by the indifference curve LA. Individual Bs indifference map
38
Theoretical foundations
emanates from the origin M and is exemplied by the indifference curve LB. The two sample indifference curves have been chosen so that they each pass through the point representing the initial allocation, L. In the absence of the entrepreneur, consumption will be conned to L. Yet any point within the shaded area LEGF between the indifference curves would place each individual upon a higher indifference curve. In other words, both individuals would be made better off by a movement to a point such as H in the interior of LEGF. It is useful to distinguish two cases, in one of which the entrepreneur has full information about preferences, and in the other of which he has more limited information, which is actually collected as part of the negotiation process. When the entrepreneur has full information about preferences he has no difculty in mapping out the trading possibility set LEGF. Using hard-line negotiating tactics, he can move individual A along the indifference curve LA and at the same time move individual B along the indifference curve LB. It follows that the entrepreneurs own consumption possibilities lie on or within the boundaries of the trading possibility set. The entrepreneurs own preferences are indicated by the sample indifference curve CC drawn with respect to the origin E. The entrepreneurs optimal strategy is determined by moving the origin E along the boundary LEG until the tangent QQ is parallel to the tangent PP which is common to both the upper boundary of the trading possibility set and the entrepreneurs indifference map. The entrepreneur offers individual A the bundle E and individual B the bundle F. As a result, the entrepreneur is able to appropriate a surplus, comprising EH units of the rst good and EJ units of the second. This consumption represents the real prot of intermediation. It is readily established that the new allocation of consumption is not only privately efcient for the entrepreneur, but socially efcient as well. This follows from the tangency conditions at E and F, which imply that the marginal rates of substitution in consumption for all three individuals are equalized. Since both A and B have been constrained to their original indifference curves, all the gains from trade are appropriated by the entrepreneur. The tangents PP and QQ can be used to analyse the pricing strategy of the entrepreneur. The simplest strategy is for the entrepreneur to use a twopart tariff. A different tariff is offered to each party. The rst part of each tariff is a lump sum payable for the right to trade with the entrepreneur; the second part consists of a xed rate of exchange equal to the equilibrium marginal rate of substitution between the goods. The entrepreneurs reward for intermediation is obtained entirely from the lump sum payments. Individual A pays a lump sum equivalent to QL units of the rst good and individual B pays a lump sum equivalent to PL units of the second good (as
39
valued by the price set in the second part of the tariff). This indicates that, because of the entrepreneurs monopoly of the trading opportunity, his reward consists essentially of lump sum payments from transactors for the right to trade with him.
3.4
It is somewhat implausible to assume that the entrepreneur has the kind of information on preferences assumed above. He may still be able to spot a trading opportunity even though he has quite limited information. The key factor is that he has more information than the others or at least a better combination of information; complete information is not necessary. In the case above the entrepreneur could, in theory, obtain full information if he were prepared to ask the transactors about all the points on their current indifference curve. However, although individuals may behave as though they have indifference curves, they do not necessarily think in terms of them. The entrepreneur may therefore have to obtain the information he requires by presenting people with a series of binary choices between alternative consumption bundles. There are many problems with this, one of which is that the number of separate choices required to determine the form of the indifference curve could be enormous. A more practical alternative is to quote trial prices to consumers and monitor their quantity response. To control the number of different prices quoted it is desirable to use only a one-part tariff. By offering different trial prices to each transactor, and noting the quantity he is willing to trade, the entrepreneur maps out the transactors offer curve. This is different from the individuals indifference curve, although the two are, of course, related. Suppose, therefore, that the entrepreneur now has information not on indifference curves but on offer curves. The trading possibility set is represented in Figure 3.2 by the shaded area LSPT between the offer curves LA and LB. The new possibility set lies entirely within the old possibility set, indicating the reduced opportunities for the entrepreneur consequent upon his more limited information. The entrepreneurs optimal strategy is determined by the points S and T, at which points the slopes of both the offer curves and of the entrepreneurs indifference map are equal. The slopes of the chords LS and LT indicate the relative prices at which the entrepreneur trades with the two parties. The angle SLT between the chords is related to the entrepreneurs margin, that is, to the difference between the buying price and the selling price for each commodity.
40
Theoretical foundations
Figure 3.2
It is readily established that the outcome of entrepreneurial intermediation using a one-part tariff is not socially efcient. The reason is that the slope of an offer curve does not represent a pure substitution effect in consumption, but a mixture of income and substitution effects. The entrepreneur creates trade with each individual up to the point where his own marginal rate of substitution between the two goods is equal to their marginal rate of transformation through trade. This marginal rate of transformation is measured by the slope of the trading partners offer curve. It therefore differs from the trading partners marginal rate of substitution, so that the two rates of substitution are not equalized. It can be shown that social efciency would be achieved by increasing the entrepreneurs volume of trade with each individual. The entrepreneurs exploitation of his monopoly using a one-part tariff produces too low a volume of trade. This does not, of course, imply that the entrepreneurs trading partners would be better off without him. Without the entrepreneur, no trade would occur. The allocation of resources produced by the entrepreneur is a Pareto-improvement on the no-trade situation, for it makes the entrepreneur
41
better off without making either of his trading partners worse off; indeed, it makes his partners better off as well. It is just that it is possible to visualize an even better allocation. Even so, this better allocation is of purely academic interest, for no-one including the entrepreneur has the information required to achieve it.
3.5
The preceding analysis demonstrates just how crucial bargaining tactics are for entrepreneurial success. Success does not just depend upon the entrepreneur having superior judgment to other people. While superior judgment is a necessary condition for success, it is not a sufcient condition. It is also necessary that the entrepreneur be able to turn his judgment to good account by contracting with parties of inferior judgment on terms favourable to himself. To negotiate favourable terms it is normally necessary to have information about the preferences and beliefs of the other party. Even more important, it is necessary to prevent ones superior judgment being communicated to the other party during the negotiation process. To begin with, the entrepreneur must avoid the other party recognizing that he values a resource more highly than they do. He must create an expectation that he cannot afford to pay more than the amount currently offered. He does this using a hard-line bargaining strategy in which no concession is ever made to the other party. Consequently, no indication is ever given of what is the most that the entrepreneur would actually be willing to pay. When intermediating an exchange, it is also important for the entrepreneur to prevent the two parties negotiating directly with each other. Once such negotiations have been established, the two parties are unlikely to need the entrepreneur. The main exception is when negotiations break down and the entrepreneur has to be called in as an arbitrator. It is very difcult, however, for the entrepreneur to appropriate a signicant reward from such arbitration. To prevent the two parties making contact with each other, it is necessary to negotiate with each separately. Establishing round-the-table multilateral negotiations would ipso facto make the entrepreneur redundant. He would have performed a valuable social service in getting the other parties together, but, because he would no longer have a monopoly in bargaining with each of them, he would have no means of obtaining a private reward for this service.
42
Theoretical foundations
SUMMARY
The chapter analyses the role of the entrepreneur in achieving coordination by promoting exchange. In each case the entrepreneurs superior judgment enables him to identify an opportunity for coordination which he exploits through intermediation. In order to protect his superior judgment he has to keep apart the people between whom he is intermediating. He also has to ensure that he does not weaken his bargaining position by giving away too much information in the course of negotiating with each party.
The preceding analysis of coordination has assumed that each opportunity is exploited by a single entrepreneur. It has been shown that the entrepreneur can appropriate a private reward which, under certain conditions, is equal to the value of the improvement in resource allocation which he effects. In some cases his reward exceeds this value and in other cases it is less. In the long run, the existence of such potential rewards will bring entrepreneurs into competition with each other in seeking them out. This raises the possibility that a given opportunity could be discovered simultaneously by several entrepreneurs. There is no reason why any of the entrepreneurs should know that others have made the same discovery at least not until they all seek to exploit the opportunity at the same time. At this point each entrepreneur will become aware of competition through his inability to negotiate a favourable price. He is unlikely to know from precisely where this competition originates. It is possible, of course, that he could identify the source of competition and arrange to eliminate it through collusion. In practice this is likely to prove difcult; for, even if the source of competition could be identied, a collusive agreement would prove difcult to enforce. The simultaneous discovery of an opportunity for coordination is not, however, the only threat to the entrepreneur. A more serious threat comes from the presence of people seeking to acquire knowledge of opportunities at second hand from the entrepreneur. These people are not true entrepreneurs themselves for they rely upon the entrepreneur to provide their information for them. In effect they back the entrepreneurs judgment rather than their own by seeking to replicate whatever the entrepreneur does. They hope by doing so to obtain a free ride upon the entrepreneurs judgment. Alternatively, they may be entrepreneurs, but misguided ones. They believe, erroneously, that the entrepreneur will fail to exploit the opportunity properly. As a result, they think that they can exploit the opportunity themselves without facing any effective competition from the entrepreneur from whom they have taken the idea. These imitators, of whatever sort, may be termed follower-entrepreneurs to distinguish them from the leader-entrepreneurs who discover opportunities at rst hand.
43
44
Theoretical foundations
The rst part of this chapter examines the consequences for the entrepreneur of competition in the exploitation of a given opportunity. It shows that, not surprisingly, competition reduces the reward to entrepreneurship and more signicantly that in most cases it completely eliminates it. The relation between leaders and followers is then examined and the conditions under which competition from followers can be eliminated are discussed. Finally, it is shown that, if followers can be deterred, then in the long run the leaders may be able to achieve an equilibrium in which each obtains a positive reward. Adjustment to equilibrium is, however, likely to be slow and uncertain even at the best of times.
4.2
COMPETITION IN EXPLOITATION
The main result is easily stated: if two or more entrepreneurs compete to exploit the same opportunity, then normally neither of them will obtain any reward. This result needs to be modied slightly when there is uncertainty about the situation. In this case, competition from the more risk-averse entrepreneur constrains the reward that the less risk-averse entrepreneur can obtain. Only when the degree of risk aversion is the same for both does neither obtain any reward. The reason why competition eliminates rewards is that the information exploited by the entrepreneur is an indivisible good. Once the information has been acquired, the additional cost involved in its exploitation is zero. Thus, so long as a positive reward accrues to the information, it pays each entrepreneur to bid away from his competitor the resources required to exploit it. Consequently, competition between entrepreneurs bids down the reward for information to zero. The operation of this principle may be illustrated by an example based upon the model of exchange presented in the previous chapter. Consider two entrepreneurs, C and D, attempting to intermediate an exchange between two consumers A and B. Suppose that C is the rst to approach A and B. His optimal strategy in the absence of any constraints imposed by D is to negotiate with A and B separately and to move A and B along their indifference curves until the marginal rates of substitution of A, B and C have been equalized. The situation is illustrated in Figure 4.1, which is based upon Figure 3.1. As before, individual As consumption of the two goods is measured from the origin K and individual Bs consumption from the origin M. The initial allocation of the goods is represented by L, with all of the rst good being allocated to A and all of the second good to B. Individual A is on the indifference curve LA and individual B on the indifference curve LB. Entre-
45
Figure 4.1
Competition between two entrepreneurs in intermediating an exchange of goods using a multi-part tariff
preneur Cs consumption is measured from the origin E and his initial strategy is to consume at F, where his indifference curve CC is tangent to Bs indifference curve LB. E and F are jointly determined by this condition, together with the condition that the tangent to LA at E is parallel to the tangent to LB at F. It is planned to consume the prots of intermediation in the form of EH units of the rst good and EJ units of the second good. Suppose that entrepreneur D now enters the picture. To bid away trade from C he must offer both A and B an improvement in their welfare. For illustrative purposes it is useful to assume that the increment in welfare is fairly substantial in each case. Entrepreneur Ds counter-offer to A is indicated by the point E which lies on a higher indifference curve than E, and his offer to B by F, which lies on a higher indifference curve than F. Ds consumption is measured from the origin E and his planned consumption is at F on his indifference curve DD. He plans to consume EH units of the rst good and EJ units of the second good.
46
Theoretical foundations
To regain trade, entrepreneur C must now improve upon Ds offer. For example, he may offer A consumption at E, which lies on a higher indifference curve than E, and simultaneously offer B consumption at F which lies on a higher indifference curve than F. It is apparent from the gure that Cs prots from intermediation have shrunk considerably, as his own consumption of both goods is lower than before. As offer follows counter-offer so prots are squeezed further until the process terminates at a point such as Z. Z represents the common limit of the sequence E, E, E, and the sequence F, F, F, When referred to the origin K, it indicates individual As consumption and when referred to the origin M it indicates Bs consumption. Prots have been completely eliminated and so neither C nor D consumes anything. The point Z cannot be uniquely determined unless the negotiation process is modelled more fully, which is beyond the scope of this chapter. The only restriction upon Z is that it lies upon the contract curve XX. The contract curve is the locus of points within the trading possibility set LEGF at which the indifference maps of individuals A and B are tangent to each other. Any point on the contract curve apportions the total stock of the two goods between the individuals A and B in a manner which equalizes their marginal rates of substitution. Because there is total apportionment of the stock between A and B, there is no margin of prot for C and D; and because the marginal rates of substitution are equal, there is no potential for prot from the intermediation of exchange. There is no guarantee that a point such as Z, once attained, will be a stable equilibrium. For one entrepreneur can always undermine the other entrepreneurs offer, by proposing trade at another point on the contract curve. This offer is bound to seem preferable to one of the transactors, and worse to the other. If two such offers are on the table at the same time, then neither offer will be acceptable to both of the parties and trade will be unable to proceed. To guarantee a stable outcome it is necessary to assume that, once the prot of intermediation has been eliminated, one of the entrepreneurs quits and leaves the other to settle the nal allocation of consumption between the two individuals. This does not eliminate the constraint on the other entrepreneur so long as the threat of re-entry remains.
4.3
Implicit in the preceding analysis is the assumption that both entrepreneurs have at their disposal a multi-part tariff. It is often more plausible to assume that they are both restricted to a one-part tariff. This case is also of particular
47
Figure 4.2
Competition between two entrepreneurs in intermediating an exchange of goods using a one-part tariff
theoretical interest as it leads to a very simple result which links the theory of entrepreneurship to the elementary theory of supply and demand. With a one-part tariff, both entrepreneurs are restricted to trading possibilities determined by As and Bs offer curves. The trading possibility set is indicated in Figure 4.2 by the area LSPT lying between As offer curve LA and Bs offer curve LB. The analysis depends crucially upon two properties of the offer curves. The rst is that they intersect at a point, such as P, on the contract curve XX. The second is that each individuals welfare increases as he moves along his offer curve away from the no-trade position. Thus as individual A moves along LA from L to S and then to P and A his welfare increases, and similarly as B moves along LB from L to T to P and B his welfare increases too. Suppose that entrepreneur C begins by ignoring competition from D. His optimal strategy is to set a price for A so that A consumes at S and to set a price for B so that B consumes at T. His own consumption is measured from
48
Theoretical foundations
the origin S and, given S, his optimal strategy is to consume at T where his indifference curve CC is tangent to the frontier of the trading possibility set, as given by the offer curve LB. S is determined by the condition that the tangent to LA at S is parallel to the tangent to LB at T. When entrepreneur D enters the picture, he seeks to bid away trade from C. To do this he must offer both A and B a higher welfare than before. He must therefore move A to a point such as S to the right of S and move B to a point such as T to the right of T. Thus both individuals move further away from the no-trade position L. To counter D, C must now offer to trade at points such as S, to the right of S, and T, to the right of T. The process of offer and counter-offer continues until one of the entrepreneurs arrives at the intersection P. There is no point in continuing beyond P because the entrepreneur would then be incurring debts which will make him worse off than he would be by quitting the market and which, in any case, he would be unable to pay. Neither is there any point in the other entrepreneur challenging the allocation P, and so that is where equilibrium will be achieved. The actual mechanism of adjustment is, of course, price competition. Another property of the offer curves is that the terms of trade improve as the individual moves along his offer curve away from the no-trade position. The terms of trade are the price at which the individual obtains his purchase, expressed in terms of the good in which he makes his payment. Competition takes the form of offering each individual trade at a more favourable price: for each good a lower price is quoted to the buyer and a higher price to the seller. The process ends when the margin between the buying price and selling price has been eliminated. Because of the nature of the process, at this price supply and demand for each good will be equal. It is necessary to qualify this analysis in one respect. It has been assumed that the offer curves intersect only once, and there is no guarantee that this condition will be satised. Relaxing this condition leads to indeterminacy in the outcome. Equilibrium will still be achieved at an intersection and one of the intersections will still lie upon the contract curve. But the equilibrium itself is no longer unique and so the price and quantity traded cannot be predicted with certainty. It is worth noting that, where entrepreneurial competition leads to an equilibrium on the contract curve, social efciency is achieved. This applies whether a single- or multi-part tariff is used. When a multi-part tariff is used, social efciency is achieved even in the absence of competition, as shown in Section 3.3. The most interesting result, therefore, is that competition is a sufcient condition for entrepreneurial intermediation to lead to social efciency when a one-part tariff is used.
49
4.4
BARRIERS TO ENTRY
As we have seen, the essence of entrepreneurship is superior judgment, and the reward to this judgment depends critically upon the entrepreneur enjoying monopoly power. It is important, however, to distinguish between a monopoly of the information on which the judgment is based, and a monopoly of the situation to which the judgment relates. To achieve a monopoly of information, two conditions must normally be satised. The information must be discovered before anyone else discovers it, and when it has been discovered other people must be excluded from it. The rst condition involves getting to the source of the information before anyone else does. If several people arrive at the same source simultaneously, then noone can gain a monopoly. Competition will be present right at the outset. The second condition is that the information, when discovered, is kept secret. Secrecy means that the information is not communicated to anyone else. But there is more to secrecy than just this. People must be prevented from independently gaining access to the source. The risk of subsequent discovery must be reduced by putting other people off the scent. A basic requirement is that the discoverer of the information should act as though he has not discovered anything. A more sophisticated strategy is for him to make out that he has discovered something else, and so divert peoples efforts to making contact with quite different sources instead. It must be recognized, however, that as soon as privileged information is exploited for personal gain, the very act of exploitation is likely to draw peoples attention to it. Secrecy is usually only a temporary expedient. This does not imply, though, that the entrepreneurs monopoly power must be dissipated. Although the monopoly of information may be lost, the monopoly of its exploitation may be retained. Even if the information becomes public knowledge, competition from other entrepreneurs can be prevented if there is a barrier which deters them from doing anything with it. Two possible situations can be envisaged. In the rst case the discoverer can do nothing to prevent people who share the information from exploiting it. In the second case, the discoverer can use a temporary monopoly of the information to erect barriers to competition which confer a monopoly of exploitation. In this case secrecy becomes a means to an end. Secrecy buys the discoverer sufcient time for him to consolidate his advantage. He uses his temporary lead to erect a permanent barrier to competition. Barriers to competition are only important where the exploitation of the opportunity is a continuous process. If the opportunity can be pre-empted entirely by a once-for-all initiative, then nothing remains for potential competitors to exploit. This indicates an important distinction between coordination involving stocks, and coordination involving ows. The reallocation of a
50
Theoretical foundations
stock is a once-for-all activity which appropriates the gains from coordination in perpetuity. The reallocation of a ow is a continuing activity; imitators who notice it once it has begun can move in and bid away the activity from the innovator. In the latter case the innovator could, in principle, translate his activity from the ow to the stock dimension: he could capitalize the ow by establishing long-term contracts with the other transactors involved. The existence of long-term contracts ties up the sources of supply and demand upon which a potential competitor would depend. The difculty with this strategy is twofold. First, for reasons explained in Chapter 7, long-term contracts are difcult to negotiate and to enforce. Secondly, they can only be negotiated on terms favourable to the entrepreneur if transactors believe that future competition is unlikely to occur anyway. If transactors expect prices to become more competitive, then they will be unwilling to trade now on terms which capitalize the entrepreneurs monopoly prot. The strategy will only work if the entrepreneur can use his negotiating skill to persuade transactors that competition is unlikely whether or not they contract with him on a long-term basis. This suggests that, while long-term contracts may be a useful adjunct to another barrier, they are unlikely to be an effective barrier in themselves unless the entrepreneur has exceptional negotiating skill. Suppose then that the entrepreneur is coordinating in the ow dimension, that his activity cannot be kept secret, and that long-term contracts cannot be negotiated unless some independent barrier to competition exists. The entrepreneur has a choice of four main strategies to deter competition: 1. 2. He can apply for a statutory monopoly, for example a licence, patent or charter. He can identify a resource which is indispensable for the exploitation of his opportunity, and which is in inelastic supply. By buying up this resource he can monopolize exploitation indirectly by monopolizing an indispensable input. He can commit himself at the outset to exploitation on such a scale that the entry of a competitor would lead to overexpansion, and so incur losses for the competitor as well as for the entrepreneur. This is particularly important if there is a substantial minimal scale on which the competitor must enter. He can build up goodwill towards himself in the early stages of exploitation, and thereby hope to make his trading partners suspicious of any competitors who appear. In other words, he can increase customers switching costs.
3.
4.
51
The choice of strategy depends crucially upon the kind of activity in which the entrepreneur is involved. It is desirable to postpone further discussion until the partial analysis of coordination is introduced in the following chapter. Partial analysis provides practical examples of coordination at the industry level. Using these examples it is possible to identify the factors which inuence the entrepreneurs choice of a barrier to competition in each particular case.
4.5
The remainder of this chapter is concerned with long-run competition between entrepreneurs in identifying opportunities for coordination. This is analysed in terms of a competitive process of search for information. It was suggested earlier that the successful entrepreneur requires a monopoly of some item of information. Strictly speaking, however, the only item that has to be monopolized is the information that a particular prot opportunity exists. Information about the existence of a prot opportunity may be called commercial information. It is shown in the following chapter that commercial information is typically a synthesis of other information, which may be called raw information. Items of raw information are like the pieces of a jigsaw that have to be tted together to get the overall picture. This picture tells a story, and a story it tells is the commercial information. It is assumed that each entrepreneur enters the search process with fairly wide-ranging background information, as a result of both incidental experiences and purposive search in the past. Not all entrepreneurs have the same background information by any means, but all are searching for the last few items of raw information in other words, for the last few pieces of the jigsaw. Entrepreneurs have a choice as to where they direct their search. Information sources are localized and searching one area will lead to one type of commercial information, while searching in a different area will lead to another kind of commercial information. Here the jigsaw analogy rather breaks down. A better analogy would be searching for pieces of a Meccano set. Different types of synthesis can be effected with different combinations of pieces, and people with imagination may be able to achieve a synthesis with a given combination that other people would be unable to visualize. It is the imagination that dictates what kinds of synthesis are believed to be possible, and so lends direction to the search process. By and large, entrepreneurs wish to avoid searching areas of information that other entrepreneurs are searching in too. Because of differences in background information, a considerable degree of overlap can be tolerated, but if too many people search in too narrow an area then the prospective reward to
52
Theoretical foundations
each is reduced. The greater the number of entrepreneurs searching in a given area, the lower the probability that any given one of them will be the rst to make a discovery. If each entrepreneur is basically as well equipped for search as the others, then his probability of obtaining a reward from search varies inversely with the number of entrepreneurs in the eld. Suppose that there is a xed number of different areas of search. An area is distinguished by the subject matter of the information, though it also has a geographical dimension to the extent that sources of information on particular subjects tend to be concentrated in particular locations. Suppose also that there is a xed number of able entrepreneurs, each of whom has an actuarially fair chance of achieving priority in any area. This chance depends, of course, on the number of other entrepreneurs also searching in the area. All areas of search are freely accessible to any entrepreneur, but each entrepreneur can search in only one area at a time. There are also some other entrepreneurs who are not so able. They do not realize that they are not as able as the other group, though they are in the process of nding out. They nd out the hard way, by striving for success and not nding it. The less able entrepreneurs, when in competition with the more able entrepreneurs, stand no chance of achieving priority in discovery. In competition with each other they stand an actuarially fair chance of achieving priority. Their main chance of reward lies in areas which offer gains to priority, but provide too little opportunity to attract any of the more able entrepreneurs. Here less able entrepreneurs may be found sheltering under the lack of interest of the more able entrepreneurs. This possibility is ignored in the analysis below. Each entrepreneur plans his search over a unit period and is condent that during this period there will be just one discovery in each area. All the able entrepreneurs share the same perception of the potential reward available in each area. Finally, all the entrepreneurs are risk-neutral, and there is no area offering pre-emption by priority which affords too small a reward to attract at least one able entrepreneur. Under these conditions there exists an equilibrium in which the expected reward to search in each area is equalized across all areas. In fact the equality is only approximate because, by assumption, the entrepreneurs are indivisible in allocation, and so there has to be an integer number of entrepreneurs in each location. The equilibrium condition applies, of course, to the able entrepreneurs. The less able entrepreneurs also receive the same expected reward in each area but that is lower than the reward to the able entrepreneurs; indeed, it is zero. This zero reward applies independently of the allocation of less able entrepreneurs among the different areas. The allocation of the less able entrepreneurs depends upon their own misguided perceptions of the opportunities and rewards.
53
The equilibrium condition determines a unique allocation of able entrepreneurs between the different areas (except for possible problems at the margin caused by indivisibility). Under the equilibrium allocation, the number of able entrepreneurs in each area is directly proportional to the potential reward available. This means, of course, that in areas where preemption by priority is impossible, no able entrepreneurs will be found at all. This simple result accords with the view that entrepreneurs are attracted to areas where the highest rewards are to be found. It also accords with the view that the ability to pre-empt by priority a principle enshrined in the patent system, for example is crucial in attracting entrepreneurial activity. Thus, other things being equal, able entrepreneurs will be attracted to areas where patent and other forms of barrier to entry are available, and will avoid areas where patent protection is not available or where, in general, followers can undermine a leaders position.
4.6
The previous section described an equilibrium in entrepreneurial search, but it did not describe the process of adjustment to it. One possibility is that each entrepreneur is aware of the provisional plans of the other entrepreneurs and so can assess the number of entrepreneurs tentatively allocated to each area. Using this information each entrepreneur can assess the probability of his achieving priority of discovery in each area, and thereby allocate himself to the area which offers the greatest expected reward. But if all entrepreneurs are simultaneously reallocating themselves in the light of the others provisional allocations, what guarantee is there that the process will converge upon the equilibrium allocation? More generally, what grounds are there for believing that entrepreneurs can know each others provisional allocations when deciding upon their own strategy anyway? The short answer is that no formal mechanism for harmonizing entrepreneurs plans exists. Entrepreneurs must rely upon conjectures about the others plans in order to coordinate their own strategy with those of others. A possible alternative to coordination of search by conjecture is coordination by contract. Two variants may be considered. In the rst, the entrepreneurs who are engaged in search contract directly with each other. However, a consistent economy-wide search plan could only be arrived at either by a multilateral negotiation bringing all the entrepreneurs simultaneously round the table, or by an extremely prolonged series of bilateral negotiations. Multilateral negotiations would be prohibitively costly to organize, while different bilateral negotiations would take so long to harmonize that unac-
54
Theoretical foundations
ceptable delays would result. Moreover, even if the contracts could be negotiated, they would be extremely difcult to enforce. An alternative is to establish a statutory body to license search in different areas. The licensing body would not necessarily confer a monopoly of search on particular entrepreneurs, but would merely regulate entry to avoid overcrowding in particular areas. In effect the right to search would be transferred from common ownership to public ownership, by virtue of the latent right of state regulation being activated. Under a regime of public ownership contracts would be established, not between one entrepreneur and another, but between entrepreneurs on the one hand and the state on the other. Since the state would be a party to all the contracts, the contracts would tend to be easier to set up and to enforce. The state could realize the competitive equilibrium described earlier by the simple expedient of selling licences to entrepreneurs. It would issue a sufcient number of licences to achieve approximate equality in the price of licences for each area. The state would of course have to x the number of licences of each type before auctioning them, as entrepreneurs would be reluctant to bid for licences whose value could be subsequently diluted. Since information is a public good with innite capacity, social efciency requires that there be no replication of its production. It was assumed earlier that there was only one discovery to be made in each area, and that this discovery would be made even if there was just one entrepreneur searching in the area. If interpreted literally, this implies that when entrepreneurial effort has a positive opportunity cost only one entrepreneur should be allocated to each area. Social efciency also requires, of course, that the less able entrepreneurs should be excluded from search altogether. On this basis social efciency is achieved if the licensing authority establishes a single licence for each area and then auctions each licence to the highest bidder. In cases where the area of search can be identied fairly easily this principle has been applied with some success. In some cases the areas of search do actually correspond with geographical areas, as when prospecting for mineral deposits, for example, but it has to be admitted that there are many other cases in which it is simply impossible to specify precisely what the subject of the information is until you have it. For reasons which are fully explained in Chapter 8, any form of coordination by contract is out of the question in such cases. There is no alternative but to rely upon coordination by conjecture, and the very vague tendency to converge to the competitive equilibrium described in Section 4.5. The economy simply does not have the kind of information or the facility for exchanging it which is necessary to provide proper guidance to the entrepreneur who is deciding upon his area of search.
55
SUMMARY
This chapter has shown that the private reward to the exercise of entrepreneurial judgment depends crucially upon the absence of competition from like-minded individuals. Since the information on which judgment is based is a public good in common ownership, the successful entrepreneur is always vulnerable to threat of imitation. The erection of a barrier to entry is important in consolidating the entrepreneurs temporary lead over his competitors. If barriers to entry are difcult to erect, then entrepreneurial search for information will be deterred. It is difcult in any case for entrepreneurs to consolidate their search effort because the fact that information is in common ownership means that unintentional congestion in some areas of search is difcult to avoid.
The preceding chapters have been concerned with very fundamental issues. Much of the discussion has been highly abstract. The main formal model employed was based upon an economy comprising just two people and two goods. To generate practical testable hypotheses it is necessary to recognize that the real world is much more complicated than this. In practice, entrepreneurship involves many millions of people interacting with each other, and for this purpose a range of institutions, such as rms, and trading mechanisms, such as markets, must be employed. These mechanisms and institutions emerge as a means of addressing the problems created by the complexity of real-world phenomena. This chapter examines some of the basic issues raised by the fact that many different entrepreneurs are at work in a particular economy at any given point in time. In a market economy, individual entrepreneurs do not formulate proposals to reallocate all the resources in the economy as part of a single plan. They formulate partial proposals concerned with reallocation in some small sector: forming a new production plant, arbitraging between two segments of a market, and so on. The reason why proposals are partial is not difcult to see. To formulate a partial proposal the entrepreneur requires only very limited information which may be quite close to hand. A more wide-ranging proposal requires a great deal of extra information, much of which may only be obtainable from distant and diverse sources. Thus, as the scale of the proposal increases, the entrepreneur has to widen his area of search to tap additional sources which are much more costly to reach. As a result, information costs increase with the scale of the proposal at an increasing rate. Even if the entrepreneur did formulate a far-reaching proposal it would be difcult to nance it. His own personal wealth would almost certainly prove inadequate. He would have to borrow the funds. But, as noted earlier, it is a characteristic of the entrepreneur that people are reluctant to lend to him because his assessment of the situation differs from their own. How much more reluctant they are likely to be if the proposal is a far-reaching one! To begin with, the larger the scale of the proposal, the more different backers the
56
57
entrepreneur will require. Some potential backers will be naturally more optimistic than others. A small-scale proposal can attract sufcient funds just from the most optimistic backers, but a large-scale proposal must obtain funds from the less optimistic backers too. On these grounds alone, the largescale proposals will prove more difcult to nance. But in addition, even the most optimistic backers are likely to be less optimistic about a large-scale proposal than they would be about a small-scale proposal made by the same entrepreneur. For, once they realize that the entrepreneur is extending his skill and competence to the limits by tapping distant and unfamiliar sources of information, their own perception of the risks is bound to increase. Both of these factors mean that as the scale of a proposal increases, so the cost of borrowed capital increases at an increasing rate.
5.2
In a large economy there will be a number of different proposals being made by different entrepreneurs at any one time. Each proposal will normally be formulated on the assumption of no change elsewhere in the economy. But because of the other proposals in hand this assumption will be incorrect. What guarantee, therefore, is there that the different proposals will be consistent with each other? Suppose that two proposals place conicting demands upon the same resource. In this case it is the owners responsibility to avoid congestion in the use of the resource. He must sell a right of access to one entrepreneur and deny it to the other. This effectively vetoes the other entrepreneurs proposal; unless he can nd a substitute resource he must abandon his proposal, and try to reformulate it so that it imposes no demand upon the resource concerned. In this way the exercise of the right of ownership ensures the compatibility of the demands upon the resource. If all resources with nite user capacity have owners, and all the rights of ownership are exercised, the proposals which are actually implemented are bound to be consistent with each other. Given that inconsistencies are eliminated in this way, is there any guarantee that the best of the proposals are chosen and the worst abandoned? This condition could, in principle, be satised by simultaneous negotiations over all the proposals. Each entrepreneur would haggle simultaneously with all the owners of the resources that he required. Each resource owner would haggle simultaneously with all the entrepreneurs who demanded his resource. Haggling would continue until no-one thought that they could achieve a better outcome: no resource owner could expect to get a better offer from the entrepreneurs, and no entrepreneur could expect to obtain better terms from any of the resource owners. In the process, entrepreneurs with good proposals
58
Theoretical foundations
would bid away resources from entrepreneurs with worse proposals. As resource prices rose, so proposals which conicted with better ones would become loss makers and their entrepreneurs would abandon them. At the end only the best proposals would remain. Unfortunately, simultaneous negotiation of this kind is likely to prove prohibitively costly. It involves keeping open the channels of communication between everyone concerned for the duration of the negotiations. It puts people under psychological strain by obliging them to participate in several different negotiations at once. The alternative is sequential negotiation, in which each individual negotiates with only one person at a time. The advantages of sequential negotiation are obvious. The main disadvantage is that no-one is sure whether, by accepting an offer now, it may become necessary to refuse a better offer later. This has two main implications for behaviour. First, all negotiations have to be based upon expectations of what alternative future negotiations would yield. It is expectations of these future outcomes which determine what the outcome of the current negotiations will be. Unless the current negotiations break down, the alternative future outcome is completely hypothetical. Given this subjectivity of expectations, it is open to each negotiator to inuence the other negotiators expectations so that he will make concessions in his favour. This tactical aspect of bargaining was emphasized in Chapter 3 where bargaining tactics were shown to be an integral factor in successful entrepreneurship. The second and perhaps most signicant implication of sequential negotiation is that it encourages transactors to hold idle resources. If a transactor completely commits all his resources in a current negotiation then, as noted above, this negotiation is concluded at the expense of any alternative opportunity for negotiation which could present itself immediately afterwards. But if the transactor has a deliberate policy of undercommitting his resources now, then a future opportunity for trade can still be negotiated. Thus, to avoid the risk of having to forgo future trading opportunities, transactors may systematically undercommit themselves in current negotiations. Each transactor holds an uncommitted inventory of resources which he can draw upon when a future opportunity for negotiation arises at short notice. The economy outlined above is very much like the economy as it really is. It is certainly a more realistic model of the economy than that of general equilibrium. It is this realistic model that provides the background to the following analysis of individual entrepreneurs partial plans. Three examples of coordination are given: technological innovation, product innovation and arbitrage. The analysis is based upon the familiar supply and demand curves. As in conventional theory, these curves are drawn on the assumption that the coordinating activity to which they relate is only a small part of the total
59
economy. As a result the activity exerts a negligible inuence upon the rest of the economy, and so there is no feedback from the rest of the economy onto the entrepreneur. Reactions from the rest of the economy could easily be accommodated within our framework of analysis, but a discussion of this would involve digressing from the main line of the argument into the theory of, for example, oligopolistic reaction curves. There is one important difference, however, between the demand and supply curves used below and those which appear in orthodox analysis. The demand and supply curves used in orthodox analysis are drawn conditional upon a state of general equilibrium in the rest of the economy. The curves below are drawn, instead, conditional upon current entrepreneurial activity in the rest of the economy. The individual entrepreneur is temporarily insulated from the spillover effects of entrepreneurial activity in the rest of the economy by the slack that is built into the system. This slack allows potential spillovers to be absorbed by unplanned inventory adjustment that is, by variations in the quantity of uncommitted resources.
5.3
TECHNOLOGICAL INNOVATION
This section presents the rst, and perhaps most inuential, example of partial coordination, which is due to Schumpeter. Schumpeter emphasizes the role of the entrepreneur as a technological innovator. He distinguishes between invention, which is a scientic activity not necessarily motivated by economic advancement, and innovation. The inventor develops a technique which the innovator seeks to exploit for the creation of wealth. Innovation involves a judgmental decision whether to commit scarce resources to the application of the invention. The introduction of a new technique often results in a new design and specication of the product. For example, new techniques often have important implications for product quality. For analytical purposes, however, it is often useful to separate these two aspects of innovation. In the present section it is assumed that the new technique merely reduces the cost of production, and leaves product quality unchanged. In the next section it is assumed that the technique facilitates the development of a new variant of the product which is regarded by buyers as a close substitute for the old variant. It is assumed that the new technique is a proprietary technique, but that the old technique is not. The entrepreneur has a temporary monopoly of the new technique stemming from the superiority of his judgment. In certain cases he may be able to convert this temporary monopoly into a long-term monopoly. The old technique may at one time have been a proprietary technique too, but
60
Theoretical foundations
now there is free access to it. As a result there are now many producers using the old technique, and so product price is competitively determined. It is assumed that production under both the old technique and the new one incurs constant long-run marginal cost. This is either because efcient production requires a single plant which exhibits constant returns to scale or because the optimum scale of each plant is very small relative to total output, so that production is adjusted by varying the number of plants in use, and not by varying production in each. If in addition all factor inputs are variable and in perfectly elastic supply to the rm, then the long-run marginal cost curve is horizontal. The innovation of any technique incurs a set-up cost which is a xed cost independent of rm output. For the old technique this set-up cost is a sunk cost incurred a long time ago by the innovator of the technique. Subsequently, other rms have entered the industry gaining a free ride on the innovator by beneting from his experience. For the innovator of the new technique, however, the set-up cost is an opportunity cost. It may be translated from a set-up cost into a recurrent cost by assuming that it is nanced by a bond whose maturity equals the time span of the innovators monopoly. Using this convention, the innovators long-run average variable cost exceeds his long-run marginal cost, but approaches it asymptotically as rm output increases. Product demand is a decreasing function of price, assuming incomes and all other prices to be constant. This is illustrated by the downward-sloping demand curve DD in Figure 5.1, whose slope measures the degree of substitutability between the product and a composite bundle of all other goods. In the absence of any competition, DD would be the demand curve facing the entrepreneur. However, the entrepreneur faces competition from other rms using the old high-cost technique. This competition will force industry price down to OP, the price which just covers the long-run marginal costs of existing producers, as indicated by the horizontal long-run marginal cost curve PP. This price constitutes a limit price for the entrepreneur. If he charges above this price he is liable to be undercut by users of the old technique, and so will be unable to sell anything. If he charges below this price then users of the old technique will shut down to avoid losses and he will acquire a monopoly of the industry. Thus the rm demand curve is innitely elastic at the price OP and coincides with the industry demand curve at below this price. It is indicated in the gure by the kinked demand curve PED. The prot-maximizing strategy for the entrepreneur is to produce where marginal revenue equals marginal cost. If the entrepreneur can charge discriminatory prices, such that each unit can be sold separately at the maximum that the market will bear, then the marginal revenue curve coincides with
61
Figure 5.1
demand curve PED. Equilibrium for the rm is at F where PED intersects the marginal cost curve of the new technique MM. It follows that rm and industry output is ON, all produced using the new technique, and the price of output varies between a minimum of OM, the marginal cost, and OP, the limit price. It may however be difcult for the entrepreneur to discriminate in price. He may not have the requisite information on the demand curve (as suggested in Chapter 3) or he may not be able to prevent resale between buyers. If he is conned to uniform pricing, then his marginal revenue curve differs from the demand curve: it is shown in the gure by the curve PEHJ which has a discontinuity EH at the output OK at which the demand curve has a kink. The discontinuity is caused by the fact that below the output OK an additional unit of output can always be sold without any reduction in price, whilst above OK an additional unit of output can only be sold by reducing the price, thereby reducing the revenue obtained from the units which could have been sold anyway at the higher price. The marginal revenue and marginal cost curves intersect at G, giving an output OK and a price OP. Average cost of production is OR and so prot is given by the area of the rectangle PESR. With a uniform price, price is on average higher and output is correspondingly lower (a trade-off indicated by the downward-sloping portion ED of the demand curve). Prot is also lower under uniform pricing. It is readily
62
Theoretical foundations
established that the prot forgone is measured by the area of the triangle EFG. The protability of the innovation ensures that private coordination is achieved by the entrepreneur. It is readily established that innovation achieves social coordination as well. None of the original buyers of the product is any worse off, for no-one has to pay more than the price they were paying before. None of the original producers is any worse off, for under competition they were only operating at break-even point away, so the fact that they have to shut down does not mean a loss for them, so long as they shut down immediately the innovation occurs. None of the factor owners is any worse off, since by assumption the price of factors of production is unaffected by the innovation because the industry is so small a part of the entire economy. The entrepreneur, on the other hand, is better off on account of the prot he earns. Since the entrepreneur is better off and no-one else is worse off, social coordination has been achieved. It does not follow that the allocation of resources is socially efcient. To demonstrate efciency it is necessary to show that no further opportunities for social coordination exist. In this respect the pricing strategy of the entrepreneur is crucial. Under uniform pricing the entrepreneur refuses to supply output in excess of OK even though the value of this output to buyers (indicated by the height of the demand curve) exceeds the value of the inputs used to produce it. If the entrepreneur could sell the additional output at below the price of the rest of the output, then the buyers would be no worse off, while the entrepreneur would be better off. It follows that social coordination may be achieved by replacing uniform prices with discriminatory prices. Thus, while discriminatory pricing may lead to social efciency in innovation, uniform pricing normally does not. It should be emphasized that social coordination in the full sense is achieved by innovation only when there are no xed factors involved in the exploitation of the old production technique. Since by assumption these factors have no alternative use, their value will be annihilated by the innovation. This is an aspect of what Schumpeter called creative destruction. More generally, if the innovating industry were a large one, so that factors were in less than perfectly elastic supply, then innovation would tend to reduce the value of the factors used relatively intensively in the old technique, and increase the value of factors used relatively intensively in the new technique. These possibilities were excluded by assumption from the discussion above. If the assumption is relaxed, then it is apparent that, because there is a group of factor owners adversely affected by the innovation, social coordination in the strong sense cannot occur. However, social coordination is still possible in the weak sense that those who benet from the innovation could in principle compensate those who lose from it and still leave themselves better off.
63
5.4
PRODUCT INNOVATION
Consider the innovation of a new product which is a differentiated version of an existing product, and so is a close substitute for it. It is assumed that the market for the new variant is small compared to the market for the existing variant, so that the price of the existing variant remains xed independently of the innovators pricing and output strategies. Some buyers have a positive preference for the new variant and are willing to pay more for it than they are for the existing variant. Others prefer the existing variant and will buy the new variant only if its price stands at a discount to the existing one. Thus, notwithstanding the substitutability between the two variants, there is a demand for the new variant in its own right. Substitutability simply means that the demand for the new variant at any price is governed by the price of the existing variant. In Figure 5.2 the price of the old variant is OL and demand for the new variant is indicated by the downward-sloping demand curve DD. The entrepreneur monopolizes the supply of the new variant, so that DD is his demand curve too. The cost structure of the innovator is assumed to be the same as before: production is under constant returns to scale, so that with factors of production in innitely elastic supply, there is a constant long-run marginal cost. Innovation incurs a set-up cost which is independent of output, so that long-run average cost exceeds long-run marginal cost, but is asymptotic to it at high levels of output.
Figure 5.2
64
Theoretical foundations
The geometric analysis of prot maximization closely parallels that of the previous section. To avoid too much repetition, it is appropriate to consider just one of the possible pricing strategies, namely uniform pricing. With uniform pricing the marginal revenue curve is DB, which lies below the demand curve DD for all positive levels of output. It intersects the horizontal marginal cost curve MM at C, giving an equilibrium output OQ and an equilibrium price OP. As shown, OP > OL so that the new variant sells at a premium with respect to the old one. This outcome is probably typical, though it is by no means inevitable. Average cost is OR, and prot is given by the area of the rectangle PXSR. To analyse social coordination it is necessary to specify the conditions under which the old variant of the product is produced. If the old variant is produced competitively by rms with no xed factors, then the results parallel exactly those of the previous section. Producers of the old variant are no worse off because, although they have lost sales to the new variant, these sales afforded them no prot. Factor owners are no worse off because factor prices are unaffected. None of the buyers is any worse off, and most are much better off because they are able to buy the new product for less than they would actually be willing to pay. The entrepreneur is better off too, by an amount equal to his prot. Thus no-one is worse off, many people are better off and so social coordination has occurred. The allocation of resources is not socially efcient, however, and for exactly the same reason as before. Both the entrepreneur and his customers could be made better off if additional units were produced for sale at discriminatory prices below the price of existing output. Thus while product innovation with discriminatory pricing may be socially efcient, product innovation with uniform pricing is not.
5.5
ARBITRAGE
Kirzner is the major modern exponent of the arbitrage theory of the entrepreneur. Kirzner takes his methodology from von Mises, and so places himself rmly within the Austrian tradition. This makes him sceptical of any attempt to create a positive theory of the entrepreneur based upon the neoclassical analysis of arbitrage. As noted in Chapter 1, and as emphasized again in Chapter 6, the neoclassical theory has weaknesses in analysing many aspects of market behaviour, including arbitrage. Equally, however, the Austrian methodological position has its weaknesses, since so much of it depends upon the absence of barriers to entry, which in entrepreneurship are very much a fact of life. This book seeks to show that the insights of the neoclassical and Austrian theories can be synthesized within a broader framework, once the extreme
65
methodological positions underlying the theories are abandoned. It is therefore entirely appropriate to examine to what extent the neoclassical theory of arbitrage can be used to elucidate an important special case of entrepreneurial activity. Consider two perfectly competitive markets for the same product which are operating in isolation. For example, they may be two agricultural markets operating in different towns. Figure 5.3 illustrates a case in which the rst market (on the left) has very limited demand and abundant supply, while the second market (in the middle) is in the opposite position with buoyant demand and relatively small supply. As a result the price in the second market is much higher than in the rst. No-one perceives this apart from the entrepreneur. The Austrian economist Krner, pursuing the spatial analogy, supposes the entrepreneur to have built a watchtower which enables him to recognize a much wider market than anyone else. The man on the watchtower realizes that the two segments of the market can be integrated, and that integration affords prots of arbitrage. Arbitrage behaviour is governed by the interplay of the excess demand schedule for the high-price market and the excess supply schedule for the low-price market. The excess demand schedule for a market shows the excess of demand over supply at any given price. The excess demand schedule for the high-price market is indicated by the schedule DD in Figure 5.3(c). It is derived from the horizontal discrepancy between the demand schedule D2D 2 and the supply schedule S2S in Figure 5.3(b). It shows the net demand in the 2 high-price market that the entrepreneur can ll by redirecting supplies from the low-price market. The excess supply schedule for a market shows the excess of supply over demand at any given price. The excess supply schedule for the low-price market is indicated by the schedule SS in Figure 5.3(c). It is derived from the horizontal discrepancy between the supply schedule S1Sl and the demand schedule D1D in Figure 5.3(a). It shows the net supply from 1 the low-price market that the entrepreneur can requisition for resale in the high-price market. The potential for arbitrage is indicated in Figure 5.3(c) by the intersection J of the excess demand and excess supply schedules DD and SS. The corresponding quantity OK indicates the amount of output forthcoming from the low-price market at a supply price less than or equal to its demand price in the high-price market. In the absence of transport costs this is the socially efcient volume of trade. The effect of transport costs is to shift up the excess supply curve SS to TT. If transport services are competitively supplied under constant costs, then there will be a xed charge per unit traded and the excess supply curve will shift up in parallel fashion, as indicated in the gure. In this case the socially efcient volume of trade is OQ, determined by the intersection E of DD and TT.
Figure 5.3
66
67
The imposition of a tariff would induce a similar shift in the excess supply curve. If the tariff were based upon quantity, the excess supply curve would shift upward in parallel fashion as before, but in the more likely case of an ad valorem tariff the shift would be an equiproportional one, so that the new excess supply curve TT would be more steeply sloped than before. The introduction of a tariff does not of course change the efcient volume of trade, but it does change the actual volume traded. Assuming that there are no distortions elsewhere in the economy for which the tariff is designed to correct, the tariff will create social inefciency by inhibiting trade. In the case of arbitrage between two competitive markets the entrepreneur cannot normally impose price discrimination (though see Section 5.6 below). If the entrepreneur is unable to effect price discrimination in the high-price market, then his marginal revenue curve becomes P2M. If he is unable to effect price discrimination in the low-price market, then his marginal cost curve becomes P3N. If price discrimination is impossible in either market, then the entrepreneurs prot-maximizing strategy is to trade at F, importing OG units into the high-price market, which have been bought at a price OP6 and are resold at a price OP4. Payments for transport or tariffs are measured by the area of the rectangle P5VWP6. Prot is measured by the area of the rectangle P4UVP5. Because the entrepreneur bids away supplies from the low-price market, buyers in this market now have to pay a higher price than before, and so are worse off. Similarly, because the entrepreneur increases supplies to the highprice market some sellers in this market receive a lower price than before, and so are worse off as well. Since some people are made worse off, arbitrage does not effect social coordination in the strong sense. However, it may be shown that it does effect social coordination in the weak sense, for the losses of the buyers in the low-price market and the sellers in the high-price market are exactly offset by the gains to buyers in the high-price market and sellers in the low-price market. Thus the buyers and sellers who gain are able to compensate the buyers and sellers who lose. The entrepreneur has to compensate no-one, and so his prot is a pure social gain. Against this must be set the fact that the volume of trade is not socially efcient. The coordination that has been achieved does not go far enough because the volume of trade OG is below the socially efcient level, which is OQ when there are transport costs and OK when there are not. Thus, as before, uniform pricing leads to social inefciency through the restriction of the volume of trade.
68
Theoretical foundations
5.6
It was noted above that an arbitrager cannot normally impose discriminatory prices. There is, however, one important case in which price discrimination may well be feasible. This is the case in which the entrepreneur is arbitraging stocks instead of ows. Consider for example a xed stock of some resource, say land. Suppose that there are two uses for this resource, say agriculture and housing, and that the market for agricultural land is organized separately from the market in housing land. An entrepreneur who specializes in reallocating land between agriculture and housing may be able to arbitrage between these two markets using price discrimination. Price discrimination is effected by transferring small units of land sequentially. In between each transfer both markets readjust to a new uniform price for the stock of land. Because each new transfer is effected only after the markets have adjusted to the previous transfer, each transfer takes place at different prices. Thus, by regulating the rate of ow of land between the two markets, the entrepreneur can achieve a maximum reward from the reallocation of the stock. The situation is illustrated in Figure 5.4. The stock of land in use for housing is measured horizontally from the left-hand origin O1, and the stock of land in agricultural use is measured from the right-hand origin O2. Price is measured vertically: the price of housing is measured along the left-hand axis and the price of agricultural land along the right-hand axis. The total stock of land is measured by the length of the horizontal axis O1O2, with O1K units
Figure 5.4
69
being initially allocated to housing and O2K to agriculture. The demand for housing land is measured from the origin Ol and is given by the demand curve D1D , while the demand for agricultural land is measured from the 1 origin O2 and is given by the demand curve D2D . Competition sets the initial 2 price of housing land at OlPl and the initial price of agricultural land at O2P2 < OlPl. The entrepreneur spots the opportunity for transforming agricultural land into housing land. He begins by buying just one unit of agricultural land, forcing up the price marginally to O2P , and reselling it for O1P, marginally 2 l below the initial price of housing land. This reallocation provides O1K > O1K units of housing land and O2K > O2K units of agricultural land. The entrepreneur repeats this unit arbitrage until the price discrepancy in the two markets has been completely eliminated. This is achieved when KL units of land have been reallocated from agriculture to housing, and the prices of land have been equalized at O1P = O2P. Because he never arbitrages more than one unit at a time, he is able to obtain each unit at its demand price in the low-price (agricultural) market and resell it at its demand price in the high-price (housing) market. His total prot is made up of the areas of rectangles of unit width, as indicated by the shaded area within the triangle ABC. As the indivisibility of the units is decreased, so this area tends towards the area of the triangle ABC. The prot earned by sequential unit arbitrage is thus equivalent to the prot obtained by price discrimination. The initial users of intramarginal agricultural land lose as a result of the arbitrage, as do the owners of the initial stock of housing land. This is because the rise in the price of agricultural land transfers wealth from the users to the owners, while the fall in the price of housing land transfers wealth from the owners to the users. Those who gain are the owners of the land remaining in agricultural use, the initial users of housing land and, of course, the entrepreneur. It is readily established that those who gain can compensate those who lose and still have additional wealth left over. The owners of agricultural land can exactly compensate the users of it, and the users of housing land can exactly compensate the owners of it. The entrepreneur therefore has no need to compensate anyone. Thus the economy-wide increase in real wealth, measured by the area ABC, is equal to the prot of the entrepreneur and, although social coordination has not been achieved in the full sense, it has been achieved in the weak sense. There is no scope for any further reallocation of land, and so the allocation is socially efcient.
70
Theoretical foundations
5.7
A feature common to all the previous examples is that the entrepreneurs recognition of an opportunity for coordination rests upon a synthesis of information. These examples therefore serve to highlight the point about the synthesis of information which has been made earlier in the book. In the case of technological innovation, the entrepreneur needs to synthesize technical information on the new method of production with information about the scarcity of factors of production in order to assess whether the new technique, besides its technical virtues, will also reduce costs of production. In the case of product innovation, the entrepreneur needs to synthesize information about buyers preferences for product quality with information about the production costs of the new design of good. In the case of arbitrage the entrepreneur needs to synthesize information about the balance of supply and demand at one location with information about the balance of supply and demand at the other location. This information must in turn be synthesized with information about the supply of transport services and about potential scal intervention in the ow of goods (for example tariffs). In the nal example involving arbitrage in stocks, the entrepreneur needs to synthesize information about the balance of supply and demand in the market for one type of user service with information about the balance of supply and demand for another type of user service. The entrepreneur will also need to be aware of social and legal restrictions involving the reallocation of the stock from one use to the other. In each of these cases the entrepreneur does not necessarily possess any single item of information that no-one else does. His advantage lies in the fact that some items of information are complementary, and that his combination of complementary items of information is different from everyone elses. This suggests that the key to successful entrepreneurship is not to have more specialized or detailed knowledge than anyone else, but simply to have the right sort of coverage of information. Another point to emphasize is the diversity of the information synthesized by the entrepreneur. Many different types of information have to be synthesized, including information on preferences, technology, factor supply, transport services, tariffs and any other forms of restriction upon the reallocation of resources. This diversity of information means that the entrepreneur must be a generalist, capable of assimilating information of many different kinds. He must know enough about each subject area to know what it is he needs to know and to recognize and interpret relevant information when it is offered to him. He does not need to be a specialist at each of those subjects, but he needs to know enough to be able to delegate to specialists and to utilize them efciently.
71
A further point is that primary sources of information are geographically dispersed. If channels of communication were perfect, then this would be of little consequence for the entrepreneur, for he could gather his information quite satisfactorily at second or third hand. In practice, however, channels of communication are imperfect and this suggest that there are at least two advantages to the entrepreneur in gathering information at rst hand wherever possible. To begin with, the successful entrepreneur is the one who is rst to achieve the synthesis of information, and so no entrepreneur can afford to be slow in gaining access to new information. Imperfections in communication cause lags to information ltering through to secondary and tertiary sources. To maintain his information up to date, the entrepreneur needs to be in contact with primary sources wherever possible. The second advantage stems from quality control. As emphasized in Chapter 8, acting upon wrong information can lead to heavy losses. Information can often be distorted in communication. In particular, each communicator tends to be selective in what he passes on, and often stresses some aspects of information at the expense of others. In some cases information may even be concealed in order deliberately to mislead. Thus information obtained at second or third hand will not only be selective (which could in principle be a good thing), but will incorporate some of the attitudes and beliefs of the intermediators (which may well be a bad thing). To avoid distortion it is therefore best to go direct to the primary source. In order to maintain contact with a diverse collection of primary sources, the entrepreneur needs to be geographically mobile. He must scan each of the key sources fairly regularly, which will tend to give him an itinerant lifestyle. Where he does rely upon intermediators, he needs to have some idea of the nature and the extent of the distortions they are liable to create: in particular, he needs to the able to check that they are not concealing anything important. In such cases there is no real substitute for face-to-face contact in communication. This imposes a further commitment to mobility on the entrepreneur unless of course he can organize things so that the intermediators visit him, instead of him having to visit them.
5.8
The examples discussed in this chapter also provide a convenient framework for analysing the kinds of barriers to entry that can be created in practice. Barriers to entry provide a de facto right of exclusion for the entrepreneur. Only so long as he holds this right can the entrepreneur normally obtain a private reward from the exploitation of information. As the previous chapter has shown, once entry becomes possible, competi-
72
Theoretical foundations
tion from other entrepreneurs will reduce and eventually eliminate his prot. Barriers to entry are sometimes regarded as exogenous industry characteristics, but it is more appropriate to regard them as being endogenously determined by the entrepreneur. The entrepreneur has a temporary monopoly of information about an opportunity for coordination and while this monopoly lasts he can invest in building barriers which will enable him to consolidate his monopoly position over a longer period. So far as technological innovation is concerned, the most obvious barrier to competition is the patent. Historically, patents were developed to protect inventors from the predatory activities of innovators. However, to the extent that the innovator can exploit the inventors ignorance of the market place to acquire patent rights cheaply, the innovator can prot as much, if not more, from the patent as the inventor. The patent system has a rather limited scope. It applies mainly to inventions embodied in machinery or some other durable form; it does not apply, for example, to management systems or to marketing techniques. It can be used to protect new designs of products such as consumer and producer durables, but cannot be used to protect new types of service such as vehicle hire or insurance. The patent system is also conned geographically to the developed market economies and the countries within their sphere of political inuence. The weaknesses of the patent system are to some extent made good by the application of similar principles to copyright in original literary and artistic work, and to the registration of trade marks. This means, for example, that while a management system may not be patentable, the documents describing it, and perhaps even the forms which are used when operating it, may be copyright. This, however, protects only against exact imitations; those who copy the principle, but make modications in detail, can claim that no copyright has been infringed. The same problem has arisen in the defence of patent rights themselves: the judiciary has tended to take the view that minor modications of patented designs constitute new designs which are patentable in their own right. Thus, while the innovator may be protected against the appearance of perfect substitutes, he is not protected against the development of very close substitutes which exploit the principles that he has pioneered himself. A disadvantage of patenting anything is that it draws attention to it. Patent registrations are widely used as a source of information by entrepreneurs seeking new ideas. This has two disadvantages to the patentee: rst, it increases the probability that close substitutes will be developed and, secondly, it encourages other people to spin off derivative ideas before the innovator himself has had time to do so. If patent protection were perfect, of course, the rst problem would not arise. The second problem would be avoided too
73
because a perfect patent system would, in theory, require people who developed derivative ideas to pay a fee for each of the ideas that they drew upon. An alternative to patenting is to try to perpetuate secrecy about the technology even when the innovation has occurred. There are two main threats to secrecy. One comes from imitation of the product design through reverse engineering. Where the technology is entirely embodied in the design this threat is a very serious one. Some innovators have disguised their designs in order to deter reverse engineering (for example in the design of microelectronic circuits). The other threat is that employees may steal the technology for their own use. If the entrepreneur delegates the supervision of production, he places the supervisor in an ideal position to acquaint himself with the technology. One way round this difculty is to spread out responsibilities so that each delegate is aware of only one aspect of the relevant technology. Thus, if any single delegate quits, he takes away very little information of commercial relevance with him. This principle applies to the structuring of any organization for example a spy network which handles condential information and is vulnerable to defection. In effect, it puts the argument about the synthesis of information into reverse. Once the entrepreneur has achieved his synthesis of commercially relevant information, he delegates its implementation by breaking up the information again into its constituent parts. Another strategy is to lock in the delegate by offering cheap mortgages and generous pension rights which he has to repay if he quits. This obligation may not prevent him from moving to another employer who has sufcient capital to offer similar perks, but it may be sufcient to deter him from becoming self-employed. Certainly, it increases the net capital requirement associated with going into business on his own account. Another barrier to entry involves the entrepreneur acquiring a monopoly of some key resource which is in totally inelastic supply. This barrier to entry too mainly applies to technological innovation. A new technology may require intensive inputs of a raw material whose deposits are geographically concentrated in certain areas. The innovator can buy up mining rights in these areas and so secure future supplies for himself, while at the same time preventing other people gaining access to them except on his terms. In this way the innovator creates a barrier to entry by backward integration into the mining and extraction of raw materials. He defends his monopoly of the technology by acquiring a monopoly of the inputs required to exploit it. In industries where the minimum efcient scale of production is fairly high, the initial scale of innovation may create a substantial barrier to entry. The minimum efcient scale of production is usually identied as the lowest level of output at which minimum average cost is attained. Suppose that minimum efcient scale is fairly large relative to the overall size of the
74
Theoretical foundations
market and the price elasticity of industry demand is fairly low. If the innovator commits himself to building sufcient capacity to almost saturate the market, then a potential competitor will perceive considerable risk in entering the industry and adding to its capacity. Assuming that the innovator does not voluntarily contract his output to accommodate his competitor, the additional supply from the entrant will lead to a lower industry price. The large scale of entry that is required, coupled with the inelasticity of demand, means that price may be very much lower than before. If the innovator chooses a suitable limit price to begin with, he can ensure that the post-entry price will fail to cover average costs. Under these conditions the entrant can anticipate that his entry will eliminate all the prots that he is trying to share. The deterrent effect depends crucially upon the entrants expectations of how the innovator will react to his entry. It was assumed above that the entrant expected the innovator to react by cutting his price and leaving his output unchanged. It is possible, however, that the innovator may be able to inuence the entrants expectations by suggesting, for example, that the innovator would cut his price by even more than the entrant might expect. This effect on expectations could be achieved, for example, by the threat of a price war. If the threat is credible, then the expected costs of entry are increased further. Alternatively, the innovator may attempt to capitalize the value of the threat by setting a higher industry price in the rst place. Given that entrants often nd the availability of capital a signicant barrier, a particularly effective threat may be to bankrupt the entrant by making the price war particularly short and sharp. In effect the innovator, who is assumed to be already adequately capitalized, threatens the entrant, who is potentially undercapitalized, with the loss of all his capital. This increases the risks perceived by the entrants potential backers. The innovator hopes that as a result the entrants cost of capital will become prohibitively high. A nal barrier is for the innovator to build up goodwill among his customers, and perhaps among key members of his labour force as well. Goodwill may be dened as a propensity to trade repeatedly with the same rm. It is particularly relevant to the innovator of a new product. Advertising is often cited as a method of building up goodwill in the form of brand loyalty; this is considered further in Chapter 11. There are many other devices which can be employed by an entrepreneur with marketing expertise. He can sell his product with a coupon giving a discount on the next item purchased. Of course, if the entrepreneurs revenue is not to be impaired, then the cost of the discount must be included in the price of the current purchase. The potential entrant can only compete with the coupon by launching his own product at the discounted price. But if customers suffer from coupon illusion and assume that it must be advantageous to use the coupon, then they may not even attempt to evaluate the entrants price. Another device for building up good-
75
will is to provide regular customers with privileges. The innovator has a head start in recruiting regulars so that, by the time the entrant appears, the innovator and his customers may have established a close working relationship. Customers will be reluctant to incur the set-up costs of establishing a similar relationship with another rm. The entrant must offer a substantial subsidy to new customers to compensate them for these costs. He may even have to sell his product at a loss in order to build up his demand. This not only reduces the protability of entry generally, but increases the capital requirements because of the need to fund initial losses.
SUMMARY
This chapter has sought to explain why the coordination effected by entrepreneurs is partial, in the sense of being concerned with only a small sector of the economy, rather than general, in the sense of reallocating all resources according to some economy-wide plan. The answer lies in the increasing cost of synthesizing knowledge from very diverse sources. It is shown that partial coordination is a continuous process and that as a result the overall consistency of the different partial plans being implemented at any one time cannot be guaranteed. Slack has to be built into the system by holding idle inventories to accommodate unforeseen excess demands for resources. Inventories are economized by applying the principles of banking. Three examples of partial coordination are given. Two of these examples integrate the theory of the entrepreneur with the conventional theory of industrial organization, whilst the third integrates the theory of the entrepreneur with the theory of arbitrage.
PART II
6. Making a market
6.1 INTRODUCTION
It is appropriate at this point to take stock of the development of the theory. The analysis so far has been based upon a rejection of the simple neoclassical view that everyone has access to the same information. It has been shown that the relaxation of this assumption provides an economic rationale for the entrepreneur. Essentially, the rationale is that the entrepreneur has better or at least more relevant information than other people. It must be admitted, however, that in modelling the entrepreneurs behaviour certain assumptions have been made which in themselves are decidedly neoclassical. In particular, it has been assumed that, while other people are disadvantaged in terms of access to information, the entrepreneur has all the information that he requires to set up a transaction. Because information about the market is freely available to the entrepreneur, the opportunity cost to him of setting up a trade is zero. It is this assumption of zero opportunity cost that makes the preceding analysis of the entrepreneur so neoclassical. In neoclassical theory no-one incurs any costs in setting up a trade. In the theory of entrepreneurship developed above, everyone except the entrepreneur encounters prohibitive costs of setting up a trade. The entrepreneur encounters costs which are not only lower, but are actually zero. That is why the entrepreneurs behaviour is so neoclassical. Other peoples costs make for a non-neoclassical environment, but the absence of costs for the entrepreneur make his response to that environment thoroughly neoclassical. The assumption that setting up a trade is a costless activity stems ultimately from the neoclassical view about the way that markets work. Because of the way that markets are supposed to work, transactors require very little information in order to set up a trade. Most of the information they require is provided in an impersonal way by the market itself. It is for this reason that the introduction of the entrepreneur into a basically neoclassical economy often seems implausible. Given the very limited information that is required to establish trade, it is difcult to believe that transactors may not have this information and so may have to rely upon the entrepreneur instead.
79
80
The market-making rm
In fact, however, the neoclassical view of the way that markets work is quite implausible. Some of the problems with the neoclassical views were indicated in the discussion of partial coordination in Chapter 5. A more extensive critique is given in Section 6.2 below. Markets work quite differently from the way that neoclassical theory suggests. Transactors require a great deal of information in order to effect a trade. This information is very costly to the average transactor and somewhat less costly to the entrepreneur. The entrepreneur requires information not only about the contract of trade itself, but about the specication of the product and the personal characteristics of those with whom he trades. Even with this information he may have to provide additional services to his trading partners so that trade can proceed. The entrepreneur therefore encounters signicant costs of his own. It is the entrepreneurs efforts to minimize these costs that determine the characteristic way in which he behaves.
Making a market
81
nounces a trial price in each market and aggregates the quantity responses that the transactors provide. In markets where demand exceeds supply, he raises the price and in markets where supply exceeds demand he reduces the price. If supply and demand are equal he leaves the price unchanged. Under suitable conditions this process converges to a general equilibrium across all markets. The logic of the Walrasian process is unassailable, but equally, its practical irrelevance is undeniable. The pattern of behaviour which it describes is hardly ever observed in practice. According to Walras, price is uniform simply because the auctioneer says that it will be so. It is parametric to transactors because only the auctioneer can conduct trade. It is an equilibrium price because all the computation of demand and supply balances is centralized with the auctioneer, and he does not allow trade to proceed until his computations are complete and economy-wide balance has been achieved. The Walrasian process could possibly be advanced as a theory of decentralized planning within a state-controlled economy or within a rm, but it cannot be used to model a private ownership market economy. The Walrasian process applies to any number of transactors: even to as few as two. However, there is a tradition in economics that seeks a rationale for perfect competition in the existence of a very large number of transactors. It is assumed that many traders participate in each market, and each wishes to trade an amount that is small relative to the overall size of the market. It is argued that, because there are a large number of different traders, it is difcult to identify individual people and to prevent resale between them. Any attempt to charge different prices for different units will create an incentive for arbitrage. Suppose, for example, that sellers attempt to discriminate between buyers. Buyers who can purchase at the lowest price will increase their demand in order to resell to buyers faced with a higher price. As a result, all demand will eventually be concentrated on the low-price units and demand for the high-price units will be eliminated. Competition between arbitragers will eliminate any margin between buying and selling prices. Thus throughout the market the law of one price will prevail. Given that no transactor constitutes a signicant part of the market for any good, a threat by him to withdraw from the market will have negligible consequences for the overall balance of supply and demand. It is likely that only a negligible variation in price will be required to restore the balance by inducing someone else to enter the market to take his place. Consequently, no-one can reasonably expect that their own quantity response to price can have any signicant inuence at all upon the prevailing price. Price adjusts to equilibrium in each market through the response of frustrated buyers or sellers to a shortage or surplus of goods. If there is a shortage of supply, then buyers attempt to bid away supplies from other people by
82
The market-making rm
raising the price. The higher price causes some buyers to withdraw from the market, and encourages some suppliers to enter it. This reduces demand, increases supply and so adjusts the market to equilibrium. Conversely, if there is a surplus of goods, then suppliers bid down the price; this stimulates demand, discourages supply and so restores equilibrium. In this model, price is uniform on each side of the market because of the threat of arbitrage, it is parametric because there are many insignicant traders, and it is maintained in equilibrium because transactors react instantaneously to any frustration of their trading plans. On closer examination, however, these propositions rest upon three important implicit assumptions. First, it is assumed that there are no barriers to entry into markets and, in particular, that there are no barriers to entry into arbitrage activities within a market. The idea that there are no barriers to entry is implicit in the view that markets will involve a large number of traders. It is still more evident in the view that prot opportunities from arbitrage will be competed away. Secondly, it makes very strict assumptions about the availability, and the relevance, of non-price information. It assumes, for example, that everyone has perfect knowledge of the specication of each product. Thus no buyer is ever in any doubt about whether or not the product will meet his requirements. Anything that people do not know is assumed to be irrelevant to their needs. Thus if transactors do not know one anothers names and addresses, then it is only because such information is irrelevant. It is irrelevant because the economy has no spatial dimension: all transactors reside at the same place where simultaneous auctions are held perpetually. If transactors do not know one anothers personal characteristics, then it is because such characteristics are common to everyone; for example, everyone is totally honest and as a result there is no chance of default. The only personal information which is really relevant is about preferences. In the perfect competition model, all relevant information about preferences is communicated to other transactors through the price mechanism. Thus the only relevant information is price information; non-price information about personal characteristics is of no value at all. Finally, neoclassical theory assumes not only that markets adjust quickly, but that they adjust completely before any trade at all takes place. This is recognized explicitly in the Walrasian model, where no trade is permitted by the auctioneer until all markets are in equilibrium. In the absence of an auctioneer it implies that buyers and sellers whose trading plans are frustrated can initiate a complete renegotiation of contracts before anyone else can go ahead with their trades. Furthermore this recontracting between transactors will continue until all plans are fully harmonized, and only then will trade occur. The same assumption is implicit in monopolistic competition
Making a market
83
theory and in the preceding analysis of the entrepreneur. The monopolistic competitor is always in equilibrium in the sense that he always produces exactly what he can sell, and no more. The intermediating entrepreneur is always in equilibrium because he only buys what he knows he can sell, and only sells what he knows he can buy. Neither of them is ever left with unsold inventory, or is forced to default owing to shortage of supply, for trade is never allowed to proceed until all such potential discrepancies have been eliminated. If interpreted literally, this assumption implies that, every time a market is subjected to disturbance, trading is suspended until recontracting has been completed, and only then is the market activated again. In an economy continuously subjected to change, it is doubtful if trading would ever be able to occur! The analysis of entrepreneurship in the preceding chapters has been chiey concerned with relaxing the rst assumption about barriers to entry. It has assumed barriers to entry where neoclassical competition theory supposes none to exist. The entrepreneur is modelled as a monopolist enjoying privileged access to commercial information. Only once this monopoly is destroyed by the entry of another entrepreneur does the market tend towards the competitive equilibrium. The second implicit assumption of neoclassical theory is that the organization of transactions is a costless activity. This assumption is not applied only to competitive markets; it is also a feature of the analysis of monopolistic competition, in which the monopolist always has complete information about the environment in which he operates, and transactors can easily familiarize themselves with the price and quality of the product. It is also implicit in the earlier analysis of entrepreneurial coordination, in which the entrepreneur has no difculty in identifying and making contact with his trading partners because he has perfect information about them. As noted above, the acquisition of information, and the other activities involved in setting up a transaction, incur a positive opportunity cost. This cost may be considered as analogous to a tax upon the transaction. Taxes on transactions, for example tariffs, lead to a separation of buying price and selling price. Prima facie transaction costs may be expected to have a similar consequence. The implications of transaction costs are analysed in detail in this chapter and the next. The counterfactual nature of the third assumption has already been noted in Chapter 5. Recontracting involves economy-wide multilateral negotiation, and it is prohibitively time-consuming to carry out. The alternative to recontracting is to use sequential negotiation and to contain the spillovers between negotiations by holding inventories of idle resources. As a result, entrepreneurs need to hold inventories in order to facilitate the setting up of
84
The market-making rm
transactions. The consequences of inventory management for entrepreneurship are quite complex, and so discussion of this is deferred until Chapter 9.
6.3
Transaction costs are costs incurred in overcoming obstacles to trade. It is sometimes asserted that transaction costs are a cause of market failure, but this is not strictly correct. The existence of transaction costs necessitates a modication of the perfect competition model. In this sense transaction costs appear as the immediate cause of the failure of the model. But it is obstacles to trade that are the ultimate cause of the failure of the market. A rational individual only incurs transaction costs in order to avoid a breakdown of trade. From this point of view transaction costs improve the efciency of the market, they do not reduce it. Six main obstacles to trade may be distinguished: they are summarized in the left-hand column of Table 6.1. This column should be studied in detail. Following the discussion above, the entries may be interpreted in two different ways. The conventional interpretation is that of an inventory of possible deviations from perfect competition. On this view it is appropriate to analyse Table 6.1 Classication of obstacles to trade, and the corresponding market-making activities Market-making activity Contact making via search or advertisment Specication of the trade and communication of the details to each party Negotiation Transport and administration
Obstacle to Trade No contact between buyer and seller No knowledge of reciprocal wants
No agreement over price Need to exchange custody of goods and pay any taxes or tariffs due on the transaction No condence that goods correspond to specication
Monitoring, that is screening of quality, metering of quantity, timing of instalments, observation of contingent events Enforcement
Making a market
85
each obstacle to trade as though it were the only deviation present. The objections to this are twofold. First, it is unrealistic, for in practice many markets exhibit several simultaneous obstacles to trade. Secondly, and much more fundamental, is that the effectiveness of a policy designed to overcome one obstacle may be strongly inuenced by the presence of other obstacles. For example, if each buyer nds it difcult to make contact with more than one seller, and vice versa, then the market will become fragmented, transactors will tend to be bilateral monopolists, and so it may be difcult to obtain agreement over price. Thus the existence of one obstacle to making contact gives rise to another obstacle in obtaining agreement on price. A more satisfactory interpretation of the table is that the entries describe the logical sequence of steps necessary to take transactors from mutual isolation, through anarchy (for example, a Hobbesian state of nature) by way of strategic haggling towards successful completion of a trade. Logically, the rst step in a trade is for transactors to make contact, and then to communicate reciprocal wants which are embodied in the contractual specication. It is assumed that they exchange two types of good, one of which may be designated the product and the other the payment. The contractual specication may allow for product supply and/or payment to take place in various instalments at different dates, for the arrangements to be contingent upon particular events on or before these dates, and for various penalties or compensations to be paid in the event of default. After negotiating a price, the two parties exchange custody of the goods and pay any taxes or tariffs due on the transaction. Each party monitors the exchange: he screens the quality and meters the quantity of the good he offers, and checks that the other partys screening and metering of the good he receives is correct. (In certain cases it may be possible to eliminate this duplication of screening and metering: see Chapter 9 below.) Failure of the quantity or quality to comply with the specication constitutes default. In the nal stage the penalties and compensations due in respect of default are enforced.
6.4
To overcome each of the obstacles to trade, market-making activities are required; these are listed in the right-hand column of the table. The cost structure of these market-making activities is a major inuence upon the prices and the quantities traded in different kinds of market, and upon the role of intermediation within them. When analysing cost structure it is important to distinguish between set-up costs and recurrent costs, and between xed costs and variable costs. A set-up cost is essentially a once-for-all cost; it represents an investment which is
86
The market-making rm
normally justied on the grounds that it reduces subsequent recurrent costs. A variable cost is a cost related to the number of transactions effected by the market maker, or to some other relevant factor. A xed cost is a cost independent of these factors. A xed cost usually reects an indivisibility in a resource: cost is independent of the rate of utilization of the resource until its capacity limit is reached; thereafter a further indivisible unit has to be used. It should be emphasized, however, that the use of indivisible resources generates xed costs of market making only if use of the resource cannot be shared by different market-making activities or by the makers of different markets. Most, though not all, market-making activities involve handling considerable amounts of information. The properties of information are an important inuence on the structure of market-making costs. An item of information is an indivisible asset. It is also a potentially durable asset. So far as an individual is concerned, information once received can be memorized: it is therefore durable in the sense that it effects a oncefor-all change in his state of mind. So far as an organization is concerned, information can be stored in les to which members of the organization both present and future can gain access. Since the lifetime of an organization can exceed the lifetime of an individual, the potential durability of information is even greater from the organizations point of view. Many assets are indivisible, but information is unusual in being one of the few assets which is totally indivisible in demand. No-one ever demands more than one unit of an item of information. While it is possible to replicate the supply of an item of information, an individual or organization gains nothing from being supplied with an additional unit. Moreover, since an item of information is durable, demand is restricted not just to one unit at a time but to one unit in a lifetime. It appears, therefore, that an item of information is an indivisible good for which each customer only ever demands one unit. This may be summarized by saying that information is a satiation good. The information required by a transactor may be classied by the object to which it pertains, namely the product, the trading partner, or the contract itself. The transactor needs to acquire knowledge of relevant characteristics of these objects in order to complete a trade successfully. The relevant characteristics of a product constitute its specication. Products can be specied both functionally and indicatively. A functional specication describes what the product does, while an indicative specication describes what it is and how it can be recognized. So far as the buyer is concerned, the functional specication is of paramount interest. For example, a person who buys a motor car expects to acquire a vehicle for the transport of passengers and irrespective of what the product looks like, if it does not perform this function then it does not qualify as a motor car. Given this functional approach, the relevant characteristics of the motor car include carrying capacity for passen-
Making a market
87
gers and their luggage, speed, fuel consumption, and so on. Once the functional characteristics have been assessed, the indicative characteristics come into play; these are mainly concerned with the appearance of the car: styling, colour, trim, and so on. The relevant characteristics of a transactor include his name and address, his honesty, competence and his liquidity, and also his attitude to negotiations. Name and address are important for making contact (or for maintaining a contact made by chance). His address may also provide an indication of how easy it will be to enforce a contract with him; for example, the social sanctions and the legal system to which he is subject will depend upon his normal place of residence. If he lives in an area where social sanctions are severe, and in a country where the legal system is comprehensive and cheap to use, then costs of enforcement will tend to be low. The need for enforcement only arises, of course, in the event of default. The supplier of a product can default on either quantity, or quality, or both. Default on quantity involves short supply (or possibly delay in supply, if time is of the essence in the contract). Default on quality signies a failure to meet the specication. As noted above, the functional aspect of the specication is the most crucial, and it is here that default is most likely to arise. The product may not be t for the purpose intended, or it may fail to achieve the standard of performance specied. Default in the indicative aspect is usually fairly easy to detect, and for this reason the supplier is much less likely to perpetrate it. Default may be unintentional or deliberate. The risk of deliberate default is governed by the honesty of the person concerned. Unintentional default on quantity is liable to occur if the supplier holds inadequate stocks of the product. Default on quantity is usually considered with respect to payment rather than the supply of the product, though the principle is the same in either case: holding too little stock of the item that one is committed to provide. This may be identied as a liquidity problem, where liquidity is understood in its broadest sense. Unintentional default on quality is liable to occur if the supplier is incompetent in the manufacture of the product, or if there are inherent natural variations in the production process. Default arises when checks are too costly to carry out, or when the supplier lacks the skill to carry them out properly. To some extent there is a grey area between unintentional and deliberate default in which the supplier is simply negligent. Default due to negligence is deliberate in the sense that the decision to be negligent is deliberate and the eventual consequences of negligence are foreseeable. On the other hand, it is unintentional in the sense that none of the defaults that follow is specically willed. Where negligence is important, the preceding remarks need to be modied slightly, though the principles remain the same.
88
The market-making rm
Finally, the trading partners attitude to negotiation is important because it inuences the amount of time that needs to be spent on reaching agreement. There are three main aspects to the time costs of negotiation. The rst is that, if the trading partner uses very subtle tactics, then considerable time may need to be spent planning for each round of the negotiations. The second is that, if the trading partner is willing to make concessions, but will only make very small concessions at one time, then many rounds of negotiations may be involved before a satisfactory price is obtained. Both of these factors increase the amount of mental labour used in negotiation. The third aspect is concerned with the speed with which agreement is reached. This is clearly related to the rst two factors: the amount of preparation needed for each round of the negotiations and the number of rounds involved. However, it is not uniquely determined by them because there is usually a certain amount of slack in the timetable of negotiations to allow the two parties to do other jobs at the same time (to participate in other negotiations, perhaps). It is often the case that one of the parties is anxious to complete the negotiations because further delay to the transaction will spill over and disrupt other plans. In this case slack in the other partys negotiation schedule may impose heavy costs on the impatient transactor. To a certain extent this externality can be internalized by offering the other party more favourable terms conditional upon a quick completion of the transaction, but, given the tactical nature of negotiation and the fact that agreement is uncertain anyway, there is no guarantee of success. A simpler strategy is to make a preliminary assessment of whether the other party is himself interested in swift completion, and only to initiate negotiations if he is. It is in this context that the trading partners attitude to negotiations is important. The most important characteristics of a contract are quite simply the price and the quantity traded. Also relevant are the penalties stipulated for default and the arrangements made for the settlement of disputes. The latter are usually standing arrangements dictated by social convention and law, and are not explicitly stated in the contract. Each of the three types of information distinguished above (product information, transactor information and contract information) qualies as a satiation good. When entering a market for the rst time, an individual needs product information: he needs to know exactly what is on offer. Once he has acquired this information he can trade as little or as much as he likes. It follows that the acquisition of product information is a xed cost independent of the number of subsequent transactions and their value. Having acquired product information, the individual needs to nd someone with whom to trade. Once he has acquired information about a trading partner he can, in principle, trade with them as much or as little as he likes. However, if he decides to investigate another trading partner, then additional information is required before
Making a market
89
trade can take place. It follows that the acquisition of transactor information is a xed cost independent of the number and value of subsequent transactions with that person, though it varies directly with the number of alternative transactors investigated. Provisional contract information is made available through the negotiation process, though denite information is available only once agreement has been reached. Contract information is necessary whatever the nal price and quantity agreed. It is therefore a xed cost independent of the value of the transaction, though obviously it varies directly with the number of transactions effected. The existence of xed costs of entering a market, taking on a new trading partner and negotiating a contract have important implications for the behaviour of rational transactors. Other things being equal, it is better for a transactor to continue trading in a market with which he is already familiar than to enter a new market where there is a different product specication and in all probability a new trading partner must be sought out. Once he has found a satisfactory partner with whom to trade, there is a strong incentive for him to continue trading with the same partner rather than to seek out a new one. If his trade in the product is just a once-for-all event, then this is of little signicance, but if he plans to trade repeatedly in the same product it will be advantageous to repeat-trade with the same partner. Finally, when repeattrading is involved it may be cheaper to make occasional bulk transactions than to make frequent small transactions. This is because, each time a new contract is negotiated, a xed cost is incurred, so that the average cost per unit amount traded is reduced if the average size of the transaction is increased in order to keep the frequency of transaction low. These consequences of xed costs, together with others, are examined in greater detail below. The main line of argument is taken up again in Section 6.9.
6.5
This section considers some of the factors which may explain why marketmaking costs vary between different markets. Six main factors are isolated: the complexity of the product specication, the time elapsing between making and completing the contract, the synchronization (or lack of it) between payment and supply, and the ease with which custody of the product can be exchanged, its quantity metered and its quality checked. It is suggested that markets can be rated on each of these grounds without too much difculty, and that markets with low overall scores will normally have prohibitive costs of operation. When discussing the rst factor product specication the term product is used in its broadest sense, to refer not necessarily to a commodity but
90
The market-making rm
to a service or indeed to any kind of transferable property right. The more complex the specication, the more difcult it is for transactors to familiarize themselves with it. Someone has to devise the specication, and the greater the complexity the more time this will take. Messages about the specication will be long and therefore expensive to transmit between trading partners. Furthermore, it will take the recipient a long time to digest the content of the message. Thus a complex specication is not only expensive to devise, but increases the cost of informing people about the product. The longer the time elapsing between making and completing the contract, the longer the contract has to be kept on le. If the nal delivery of the product (or the nal payment for it) occurs a long time after the contract is made, then there is a risk that the commitment may be forgotten. Both parties must remember the commitment: one to honour it, and the other to guard against default. Memorizing commitments ties up mental resources (or ling space) and so has a positive opportunity cost. The cost is greater the longer is the time span involved. In this way a time lag in completion of a contract increases memory costs. The existence of a time lag also increases the risk that one or other of the parties will default by going bankrupt in the meantime. Bankruptcy is usually signalled by default in some other market. The law of bankruptcy allows this default to spill over into the remaining markets, and provides an easy way for those who have overcommitted themselves to renege on a large number of commitments simultaneously. The law of bankruptcy poses a serious hazard to those who rely upon deferred completion of a contract. The existence of a time lag also means that circumstances may change in the meantime, so that the trade is no longer as attractive as it was. In principle this risk can be avoided using a contingent contract, though as shown in the following section this solution is often unsatisfactory on other grounds. In fact there is a double risk, for if the trade appears more attractive than it did, then it probably appears less attractive to the other party, and this provides the other party with an incentive to default. Thus deferred completion offers the worst of both worlds: the possibility of either trading on unfavourable terms or having the other party default. The incentive for a person to default on a contract depends crucially upon whether the other party has already discharged his reciprocal obligations. The incentive to default on the supply of a product is much greater for someone who has already been paid than for someone who has not, for, in the rst case, default effects a unilateral transfer of the payment, while in the second case the defaulter can expect the other party to repudiate the contract, so that his prospective payment is lost. It follows that the incentive to default is much greater when there is a failure to synchronize payment and supply. This is a quite separate issue from that of time lags in completion. A contract may
Making a market
91
take a long time to complete, and possibly involve many instalments as well; but so long as payment and supply are synchronized on all instalments throughout the contract period, the opportunity to effect a unilateral transfer does not exist. Underlying this analysis of default is the idea that physical possession is a more important factor than legal title in determining who has the benet of the product. The crucial aspect of supply and payment is not usually the transfer of a title but the transfer of physical custody of the product (or in some cases the resource from which the product is obtained). The transfer of custody is therefore an essential part of most transactions. However, the ease with which it can be effected varies considerably between products. Furthermore, where the product is cumbersome or unwieldy, it may be very difcult to achieve complete synchronization between the transfer of custody over the payment and the transfer of custody over the product. In this context the physical attributes of the product its dimensions, weight, and so on, as given in its indicative specication may crucially affect both the cost of exchanging custody and the consequent risk of default on the transaction. Where the product is a straightforward commodity, the metering of quantity is unlikely to pose serious problems, though the costs may be non-trivial where gases, liquids, electric currents and so on are concerned. The metering of services may be more problematic, particularly if the source of the services tends to be somewhat unreliable, as with labour services. Some of the problems involved are considerable, as shown in Chapter 10 below. Screening for quality is usually much more difcult. As noted earlier, quality is dened relative to product specication. Where natural variations in quality are inevitable, quality control is usually effected by grading. Where variations are avoidable, a simple dichotomy between perfect and faulty items is most often used. However, the dichotomous view is compatible with grading if it is assumed that the market being studied is for a specic grade and that any item of a lower grade is faulty while any item of the specied grade or above is perfect. Where quality control is concerned, there is a crucial distinction between inspection goods and experience goods. An inspection good is a good whose quality can be assessed before use, while an experience good is a good whose quality can only be assessed by use. The distinction, of course, is not necessarily an absolute one, but may be a relative one, based upon whether the cost of inspection is low, or prohibitively high. Inspection before use does not avoid the disruption caused by having to nd a replacement item, but it does avoid the costs associated with the possibly permanent damage that can be caused by utilization of a faulty item. Of all the product characteristics discussed above, it is probably ease of inspection that is the most signicant inuence on market-making costs.
92
The market-making rm
6.6
This section considers one particular type of market and demonstrates the extreme difculties encountered in organizing it. This is the market in contingent forward claims. As noted earlier, a contingent claim is a claim which has to be honoured if and only if a particular state of the world materializes. A forward claim is a claim which matures at a future date; it must be distinguished from a spot claim which is a claim that has to be honoured immediately. Although contingent forward markets exist in practice, there are remarkably few instances of them. Relative to other types of market, the number actually in operation is minute compared to the number which would, in theory, exist if there were no market-making costs. The cost of specifying a contingent claim is bound to be greater than the cost of specifying a corresponding unconditional claim because of the need to describe the event upon which the claim is contingent. To reduce the scope for disagreement it is necessary to specify the event very accurately. The need to devise the specication and to communicate it to all potential transactors adds to the xed cost of creating the market. Moreover, when contracts have been exchanged, it is necessary for the parties to monitor the state of the world to check whether the event has occurred. Particular difculty will be encountered with events which are partially subjective. For example, a trader who believes his preferences are liable to change may wish to express a demand for future consumption which is contingent upon the state of his preferences at the time of consumption. But unless some objective method of ascertaining preferences is available, there is no way in which such a claim can be translated into operational terms. If the consumer knew that there was some objective event which would induce the change in his preferences, then the claim could be made contingent upon that event instead, but there is no guarantee that the consumer does know what the event would be. There is a further difculty if the claim is contingent upon an endogenous event, for then there is the possibility that one or other of the parties could inuence the event to make it turn out in his favour. Such tactical manipulation of events could be considered as a form of default on the spirit (if not the letter) of the contract. This aspect of moral hazard is well known to insurers and is a major reason why in practice more forms of insurance are not available. Most contingent claims are also forward claims, for most uncertain events lie in the future. Forward claims have problems of their own, whether or not they are contingent. By denition, forward claims involve a lag between
Making a market
93
contract and completion and so incur memory costs. These costs are greater the more remote is the date at which the claim matures. Moreover, if the forward claim is purchased with a spot payment, then the lack of synchronization provides the issuer of the claim with a major incentive to default. On the other hand, if payment is synchronized with supply, then the nature of the reciprocal claims is so tentative, given that either party may be bankrupted in the meantime, that neither is likely to have much condence in the contract. Thus, unless the issuer of the claim has a rst-class reputation, it is highly unlikely that the claim will be acceptable to anyone. It is because of this that very few forward markets operate, and many of those that do so involve claims either issued by governments or underwritten by them.
6.7
This section considers some strategies of a general nature for reducing marketmaking costs in a given market. They are general in the sense that they contribute to surmounting several different obstacles to trade at once, rather than being designed to overcome just one particular obstacle. They are also general in the sense of being applicable, in some degree, to almost every market. Bulk trading affords three main advantages. First, it exploits the fact that contact making is a xed cost independent of the size or value of the transaction. This means that infrequent bulk trades incur fewer contact-making costs per unit traded than frequent small trades. Secondly, it exploits the fact that, while negotiation costs may increase with respect to the value of a transaction, they normally increase less than proportionately. Consequently, infrequent bulk trades incur fewer negotiation costs than frequent small trades. Finally, bulk trading exploits the fact that there are often signicant economies of scale in the physical distribution of goods, that is in the transport of the good from the sellers custody to the buyers custody. It should be noted, however, that as the size of a bulk trade increases, certain disadvantages become apparent. To begin with, bulk distribution of a good makes sense only if either there is a major geographical concentration of demand at one point and a major geographical concentration of supply at another, or the product is durable, so that bulk consignments can be accumulated at the point of supply, transported to the point of demand, and then gradually decumulated through use. Thus, to exploit bulk distribution, it may be necessary to agglomerate demanders and suppliers spatially and/or invest in substantial storage facilities. Beyond a certain point, the additional costs incurred by this strategy may outweigh the saving in distribution costs, and so a limit to bulk distribution will be set.
94
The market-making rm
However, a limit on bulk distribution does not limit the bulk of the transaction in so far as the transaction may provide for distribution in a number of different instalments spread over a specied period of time. Savings in the administrative costs of contact making and negotiation can still be achieved provided contracts are made long-term. In fact, long-term contracts have the additional advantage that they offer the supplier security of demand, and the buyer security of supply. However, as the term of the contract is extended, what is secure in the short or medium term may become risky in the long term. Changes in tastes, technology and resource endowments may call for substantial changes in the pattern of trade, which may be inhibited by a longterm contract. To take account of this, the contract needs to be made contingent on future states of the world, but, for reasons explained above, it is only when transactors have an exceptional degree of condence in each other that contingent long-term contracts are likely to be feasible. The implication of this is that, while bulk trading does indeed offer scope for reducing transaction costs, the scope is limited because of the need for geographic agglomeration and additional investment in storage, and because of the costs associated with organizing multiple-instalment transactions. Repeat-trading involves transacting time and again with the same person. It differs from multiple-instalment trading in that contact is renewed each time. The advantage of repeat-trading is threefold. First, the cost of renewing a contact is less than the cost of making a contact for the rst time, since each transactor already knows where to nd his trading partner. Secondly, experience of earlier trades will have given the transactor information about his trading partners personal characteristics. Provided the overall experience was satisfactory, he can place reasonable condence in his partners competence and integrity, so that the subjective risk of default which he perceives is lower. In those respects where previous experience was unsatisfactory (for example, supply of an occasional faulty item) he knows more about the kind of problem likely to be encountered, so that he can prepare in advance to deal with it. Finally, repeat-trading affords an opportunity for improving the quality of service. A history of satisfactory repeat-trading may encourage each party to extend certain privileges to the other which will lead to a mutual reduction of transaction costs. For example, negotiation costs could be reduced by an informal agreement not to initiate renegotiation unless market conditions have changed signicantly. Alternatively, one of the parties might offer some element of service (for example, very prompt replacement of a faulty unit) which is strictly outside the provisions of the contract, but could be deemed a reasonable expectation given the unforeseen circumstances that prevail. The prospect of further trades, coupled with condence in the integrity of the other party, creates an expectation that the other party will feel obliged to reciprocate with a similar kind of gesture when the occasion
Making a market
95
arises. Thus an implicit contract is created which avoids the specication costs which would be incurred by taking account of these contingencies in a formal manner. Establishment of a reputation affects the status that a transactor enjoys among those with whom he trades. A transactor has a reputation when many of his potential trading partners believe they are well-informed about his personal characteristics. Only a good reputation reduces transaction costs a bad reputation actually increases them. From the trading partners point of view, the important characteristics of a transactor are ease of contact, negotiating skill, screening ability and dependability. Ease of contact means that it is cheap to communicate with the transactor, for example because he has retail premises open long hours and reasonably close at hand, a telephone number which is easy to remember, a 24-hour answering service, and so on. Negotiating skill means that the transactor is easy to bargain with; either he quotes a realistic price which he sticks to, or he adapts his price readily if his initial quotation is out of line with the market. Screening ability ensures that the quality of the product he offers is reliable, and dependability means that there is little risk of default on quantity or timing. A reputation for any of these personal qualities reduces the cost that other transactors perceive in trading with the party concerned. Reputation benets the trading partners, because they are able to make trades which might otherwise seem to be too risky, and it also benets the reputable party, for he is able to trade at a more favourable price than his less reputable competitors (indeed, his potential competitors may not even be able to trade at all). The gains from reputation are analogous to the gains from repeat trading, to the extent that both are achieved by increasing transactors condence. However, there are some important differences. First, repeat trading generates mutual condence, whereas reputation refers to a unidirectional condence, because the reputable person does not necessarily reciprocate the condence that other people place in him. Secondly, reputation involves a transactor having the condence of many people rather than just the condence of those with whom he trades regularly. Reputation is particularly important in attracting new trading partners, or those who trade only intermittently or on a casual basis. Finally, reputation does not need to be based solely upon past trading experience; it can also be built up by advertising, that is by publicizing claims on ones own behalf about ones personal qualities (or those of the product).
96
The market-making rm
6.8
This section considers two strategies specically designed to reduce the risk of default or at least to eliminate any exaggerated perception of this risk by the parties involved. External monitoring occurs when one party allows his trading partner to monitor his own activity. For example, a seller may allow the buyer to monitor production of the good he intends to buy, or the buyer of a good may allow the seller to monitor the way he uses it. The monitoring of production by the buyer reduces the buyers screening costs: intuitively, the buyer can see how the product is made, and so he does not need to take it apart when he has bought it to see that it is made properly. The rationale for the monitoring of use by the seller is at rst sight not so obvious. It applies when the seller is parting with custody of a product in order that the buyer can utilize it, before returning it to the seller, that is it applies to a service supplied by the seller but rendered, as it were, on the buyers premises. Monitoring by the seller may be important where the buyer hires a very valuable and fragile piece of equipment, or where the buyer is hiring the use of know-how which is the sellers property. In each case the seller may be afraid that the value of his asset may be impaired by the buyers improper use of it. Additional sanctions can be brought into play when the sanctions available through the legal system are believed to be inadequate. In fact it is not so much the sanctions themselves, but the threat of the sanctions, that is important in discouraging default. The typical extralegal sanction involves doing something which is harmful to all the parties involved not just to the defaulter but to oneself as well. The fact that it is harmful to oneself explains why it will only be done as a last resort. It also means that there may be a credibility problem with the threat to apply the sanction. However, if the sanction is applied just once, it may be worthwhile if it raises the other partys expectation that it will also be applied in subsequent trades. Furthermore, if the application of the sanction is publicized it may also reduce the risk of default in subsequent trades with other parties. So long as the other party perceives this, the sanction itself will be perfectly credible. The acquisition of a sanction can be effected by extending the range of possible transactions with the other party. The outcome of one transaction is made contingent upon the successful completion of the other. The system works so long as there is always another transaction in the pipeline, for default on one transaction then means that the potential gains from the next transaction are lost. This provides a powerful argument for repeat-trading, in addition to those already presented above. More precisely, it provides an argument for offering the prospect of repeat trades to a party so that one is
Making a market
97
less likely to be treated as a one-off partner who can make no reprisal in case of default. The argument extends, of course, beyond repeat trades to any subsequent transaction between the two parties, whether in the same market or not. It also applies to any outstanding transaction negotiated earlier but not yet completed. A classic type of sanction involves extending short-term credit to a trading partner (usually a supplier) which can be withdrawn at short notice should he default on a transaction. While default on the transaction may be difcult to penalize legally, default on payment may be much easier to punish in law. In this case the legal sanction available in one market (for credit) is used to substitute for an ineffective legal sanction in another market (for the product). The power of sanctions also extends to diminishing the defaulters standing with other transactors by publicizing his default. The partners who are most vulnerable in this respect are those who have the greatest reputation for probity to begin with. This illustrates the fact that reputation provides assurance to trading partners in two quite different ways. First, it reduces the risks that they perceive to begin with, and secondly it increases the sanction that they have should the risk materialize and default occur. It is apparent that sanctions can take many forms and, given sufcient ingenuity, they are not difcult to invent and to apply. The simplest sanctions are refusal to repeat the trade and to damage the defaulters reputation. The important thing is not that the sanctions should be feasible (though that is desirable) but merely that they should be credible to the other party.
6.9
It was emphasized in Section 6.4 that market making involves processing a considerable amount of information. The ease with which information can be handled depends crucially upon how well the information ow is structured. Two of the main inuences upon information ow are social convention and organization (see Chapter 11). For information ows as complex as those required for the operation of a market, social convention is usually unable to provide the degree of structure required. Greater sophistication is called for and this necessitates the use of purpose-built organizations. Among these purpose-built organizations are market-making rms. These rms act as specialized intermediaries. Their principal function is to reduce obstacles to trade by improving information ow. The efcient market-making rm overcomes these obstacles with minimum transaction cost. Because of the complexity of the information ows involved in a market, the determination of an optimal structure of information ow is a difcult
98
The market-making rm
task. Many different structures are possible and the factors governing a rational choice are not always measurable, or even properly understood. The choice of structure is therefore a judgmental decision and is liable to occupy skilled mental labour for some considerable time. Once the structure has been determined, however, few judgmental decisions of similar importance are called for. Subsequent decisions can therefore be delegated to people with more limited powers of judgment. Furthermore, an efcient structure will ensure that these decision makers are provided with much of the information they need through routine procedures which involve no exercise of judgment at all. The implementation of these procedures can be delegated to unskilled mental labour (that is, clerical workers) or to computers. The logical structure of information ow has its adjunct in the layout of the physical infrastructure for communication. The infrastructure comprises resources for encoding, transmitting, receiving and decoding messages and for ling records; it also includes the channels required for face-to-face communication, and for telecommunication as well. To minimize communication costs, these elements all need to be brought into the appropriate spatial relation with each other. Assembling the elements in this way may involve considerable manual labour; if some of the elements have to be relocated from a considerable distance, then a signicant input of transport services may be required as well. The direct consequence of all this is that the set-up cost of a market organization is likely to be quite high compared with its recurrent costs. The initial decision on structure involves intensive use of a scarce input skilled mental labour while subsequent operation uses much more abundant inputs, such as semi-skilled and unskilled mental labour. The communication infrastructure also involves a set-up cost, though, because it involves more abundant inputs, it is unlikely to be as large. Both set-up costs are largely xed costs independent of the number of transactions subsequently effected. This is because the organization and its infrastructure are essentially indivisible assets with a large capacity. Some of the recurrent costs are also xed costs. Information handling relies heavily on the use of labour and of specialized ofce machinery, both of which tend to be supplied in indivisible units. This means that, where small variations in utilization are concerned, many recurrent costs are xed costs. Only where large variations are concerned do recurrent costs vary a great deal, and then in lumpy amounts. A further consequence of the indivisibility of inputs into information handling is that the minimum efcient scale on which a market-making activity can be conducted may be quite high. This relies upon a well-known argument that, where an activity involves the use of several indivisible inputs, all of the inputs are used to capacity only when the scale of the activity is equal to the
Making a market
99
lowest common multiple of the capacities of the separate inputs. When this condition is satised the activity can be conducted using an integer number of units of each of the inputs and all of the units are fully utilized. It follows that, even if the degree of indivisibility in the individual inputs is quite small, the minimum efcient scale of the activity may be quite large, particularly where many different inputs are involved. The inescapable conclusion is that the xed costs of an information-based market-making activity are likely to be very high. If the organization and the infrastructure both specialize in performing a particular activity in a particular market, then it follows that the level of transactions which warrants the operation of that market may be quite high. The implications of marketmaking costs for the volume of trade are examined in detail in the following section.
6.10
There have been two main schools of thought regarding the impact of market-making costs on market price and the volume of trade. The rst takes the very negative view that market-making costs complicate the analysis of markets so much that nothing very denite can be said: in other words, once the neoclassical paradigm is abandoned, anything goes. The second exploits an analogy between market-making costs and tariffs (or transport costs) to argue that a determinate price and volume of trade will still exist, characterized in the usual way by marginal conditions. It is predicted that, when there are market-making costs buying price will be higher, selling price lower, and the quantity traded will be lower too. The analysis below follows the second approach, though it differs from the conventional formulation in one important respect. It is assumed that each market is organized by a single entrepreneur who specializes in providing market-making services. Thus market-making costs are incurred in the rst instance by the entrepreneur and not by the transactors themselves. However, the costs are ultimately borne by the transactors because the entrepreneur recovers his costs by setting a margin between his buying price and his selling price. This margin is equivalent to a tax upon transactions imposed by the entrepreneur. The assumption that there is only one entrepreneur may seem very strict, but it merely reects the fact that, when information is costly, markets tend to be segmented, and each segment tends to be formed around a particular entrepreneur. Thus the concept of a market used here involves not merely trade in a single good, but trade in a single good in a single geographical area
100
The market-making rm
between a given group of transactors who are in contact with the same entrepreneur. The analysis begins with the derivation of the market-making cost function. It is assumed for simplicity that there are just two market-making activities which incur positive opportunity costs. These may be visualized as contact making (activity 1) and quality control (activity 2). For each activity there are two possible techniques. Without loss of generality it may be assumed that one technique has a higher xed cost and a lower variable cost than the other (if both xed cost and variable cost were higher it would never be efcient to use the technique concerned). In deriving variable cost as a function of quantity traded, it is assumed that variable cost is directly proportional to the number of transactions and that the average volume per transaction is xed. It follows that with each technique the market-making cost, C, is a linear function of the quantity traded, Q. The cost function Cij for the ith activity and the jth technique (i, j = 1, 2) is illustrated in Figures 6.1(a) and (b). The quantity traded is measured horizontally and the cost vertically. A prot-maximizing entrepreneur necessarily minimizes the market-making cost of establishing any given volume of trade. This determines the cost function for each activity as the envelope, taken from below, of the cost functions for the two alternative techniques. The slope of each cost function is discontinuous at the point where the costs of the two techniques are equal. This point, A1 in Figure 6.1(a), A2 in Figure 6.1(b), is a switch point. Below the corresponding volume of trade, Q1 in Figure 6.1(a), Q2 in Figure 6.1(b), it is efcient to use the rst technique, which has the lower xed cost. This may be visualized as a primitive technique, such as making contact by attending a public market place, or testing quality by examining every item purchased. Above the critical volume of trade it is efcient to use the second technique which has the higher xed cost. This may be visualized as a sophisticated technique such as making contact through media advertising or the operation of permanent retail premises. In the context of quality control, it could be a formalized test procedure, implemented on a sample basis. It is readily deduced from the gures that market making exhibits decreasing average and marginal cost with respect to the quantity traded: in other words, there are increasing returns to scale in market making. It can also be deduced that returns to scale increase because of a switch from primitive techniques of market making to more sophisticated ones as the volume of trade increases. When the results for the two activities are aggregated, the result is a cost function which is similar in all respects to its component functions, except that it no longer has just one switch point, but two. In a sense, therefore, the aggregate cost function is slightly smoother than the functions from which it is constructed see Figure 6.1(c).
Making a market
101
Figure 6.1(a)
Figure 6.1(b)
Figure 6.1(c)
102
The market-making rm
The impact of market-making costs upon price and quantity is illustrated in Figure 6.2, which presents a partial equilibrium of a single market created by a single entrepreneur. Two cases are distinguished, according to whether or not the entrepreneur can implement price discrimination. The familiar supply and demand curves DD, SS are shown in the top half of the gure. With price discrimination see Figure 6.2(a) these also correspond to the entrepreneurs marginal revenue and marginal supply cost schedules. From these schedules it is possible to derive the entrepreneurs gross prot function OH1 in Figure 6.2(b). This shows how the entrepreneurs prot varies with respect to the volume of trade in the absence of market-making costs. It reaches a maximum at Zl, where the quantity traded is OK, which is the perfectly competitive volume of trade, corresponding to the point J in Figure 6.2(a). Introducing the aggregate market-making cost function CC into Figure 6.2(b) shows that net prot is maximized at X1 where the slope of the net prot function OH1 indicated by the slope of the tangent V1V is equal to 1 the slope of the cost function. The relevant segment of the cost function is B1B2, indicating that the volume of trade is above the critical level Q1 but below the critical level Q2. It follows that the entrepreneur will operate a sophisticated system of contact making, but only a primitive system of quality control. Equilibrium output is OYl, which is less than the competitive output OK. Maximum buying price and minimum selling price are read off from the demand and supply schedules DD and SS. The entrepreneur buys at a maximum price OP1 and sells at a minimum price OP , earning a gross prot 1 X1Yl and a net prot X1X. The maximum buying price is higher than it would l be without market-making costs, and the minimum selling price is lower. Gross prot, as well as net prot, is lower too. When the entrepreneur is restricted to uniform pricing, then his marginal revenue is given by DM, below DD, and his marginal supply cost by SN above SS: see Figure 6.2(c). The entrepreneurs gross prot is now given by the curve OK in Figure 6.2(d). This curve peaks at the output OG, which corresponds to the prot-maximizing output in the absence of market-making costs. Apart from this, the analysis exactly parallels the analysis of discriminatory pricing. Net prot is maximized at X2 in Figure 6.2(d). At X2 the slope of the gross prot function OZ2K, as measured by the slope of the tangent V2V , is equal to the slope of the aggregate market-making cost function CC. 2 The volume of trade OY2 is much lower than before. In particular it is now below OQl, so that contact making as well as quality control is effected using a primitive technique. Buying price is OP2, below the maximum buying price before, and selling price is OP , above the minimum selling price before, 2 gross prot is reduced to X2Y2, and net prot is down to only X2X . The 2
Figure 6.2
104
The market-making rm
impact of market-making costs on the volume of trade is to reduce it from OG, which corresponds to the intersection F2 of DM and SN, to OY2. As a result, the entrepreneurs buying price is reduced, and his selling price increased. It should be obvious that this analysis can be extended in many different ways. By imposing various restrictions upon the demand, supply and marketmaking cost functions, it is possible to predict not just the price and quantity traded in the presence of market-making costs, but also to predict how the choice of market-making technique will respond to parametric changes in demand and supply conditions through their impact on the equilibrium volume of trade. By extending the number of market-making activities included in the aggregate cost function, it is possible to provide still more detail about the way in which the entrepreneur will organize his market-making activities. The theory has tremendous potential and so far very little of that potential has been realized. The following chapter provides some more hints about the direction in which the theory of market making can be developed.
SUMMARY
This chapter has emphasized that intermediation, or making a market is not the relatively trivial exercise that the analysis in Part I might suggest. It is shown that signicant transaction costs are incurred in overcoming obstacles to trade. Many of these obstacles are due to ignorance and so the marketmaking activities required to overcome them involve the acquisition and processing of information. The rational entrepreneur will endeavour to minimize the transaction cost of conducting any given volume of trade, and will trade up to the margin where the private gain from an additional trade is just equal to the additional cost involved. Market-making information relates to product characteristics and transactor characteristics as well as to the terms of the contract itself. Most information costs are xed costs, independent of the volume of trade, and this exerts a major inuence upon the strategies pursued by entrepreneurs to minimize transaction costs. The most important strategies are reviewed, but discussion of their implications is deferred until later chapters.
Making a market
105
considered by McNulty (1967, 1968) and Stigler (1957). Many writers have emphasized that the perfect competition model is not really about the process of competition at all: see, for example, Andrews (1964), Clark, J.M. (1955, 1961) and Hayek (1949). On the other hand, it has to be recognized that some of the predictions of the perfect competition model still apply even if a much more general concept of competition is used, see, for example, Alchian (1950). The seminal paper on transaction costs is Demsetz (1968). Very little has been written by economists on the actual structure of transaction costs and upon the mechanisms for reducing them; most of the relevant material is to be found in the marketing literature, as reviewed by Kotler (1976). The conceptual framework, however, is already well established and in this respect the analysis above relies heavily upon Williamson (1975).
The previous chapter discussed, amongst other things, the methods available to an entrepreneur for reducing his market-making costs. The focus was on methods of improving the organization of trade within a particular market. This chapter analyses a quite different approach to the reduction of marketmaking costs. The focus is on achieving a reduction of market-making costs within the economy as a whole through a reduction in the number of markets that operate. Because of the xed costs incurred in making a market, conducting a roughly similar volume of trade through fewer markets reduces aggregate market-making costs. But how exactly is the number of markets reduced? And what are the criteria which determine which markets should be eliminated and which preserved? The basic strategy is to absorb several different markets into a single market by devising a single composite good (or property right) to replace several distinct goods (or property rights) which would otherwise be traded separately. The principles underlying this approach are examined in Section 7.2 below. Efciency demands that it should be relatively easy to make a market in the composite good. Ceteris paribus, goods which have low marketmaking costs should be chosen as composite goods, and the goods displaced should be those with high market-making costs. The economic forces which induce this result are examined in Section 7.3. But what is the effect of the disappearance of some particular market on the freedom of the individual to allocate resources in the way he wants? The individual can respond in one of two ways. He can decide to abandon any attempt to inuence the allocation of goods in the way that would have been possible had all markets been in operation. Alternatively, he can develop his own internal market to allocate the composite good to a use to which the more specic good would have been exclusively dedicated. To illustrate with a trivial example: if the market in purpose-made taxi cabs were to disappear, a taxi driver could respond either by switching to alternative work or by purchasing an ordinary motor car and using it as a taxi when required. In the rst case the allocation of goods is constrained because taxi services are no
106
107
longer supplied; in the second case an internal market is established by which a motor car is allocated to use as a taxi. The institutional structure of markets is different, but the allocation of resources is very similar to what it was before. The internal market is not, however, merely a last resort for people who cannot obtain what they want in an external market. If the costs of gaining access to an external market are high, then some individuals may positively prefer to use an internal market even though the external one is available. This does not mean that they do not make use of an external market at all. It means that they use a different external market from the one that they would otherwise have used. They gain access to the market for a composite good instead of the market for the specic or purpose-dedicated good; they then deploy the composite good for the purpose they require. They gain to the extent that the net cost of the composite good (after allowing for the cost of access to the market) is lower than the net cost of the purpose-dedicated good (after allowing, also, for the cost of access to the market). If these gains outweigh the cost of operating the internal market, then internalization is positively preferred. The coexistence of internal and external markets indicates that in practice coordination is a two-stage process. It is by no means the simple matter of market intermediation that was suggested earlier. The rst step for an entrepreneur who believes that resources are misallocated is to acquire control of the goods concerned. The second step is for him to reallocate the goods to their appropriate use. Market intermediation is important because it allows these two steps to be performed by different people. For example an entrepreneur, C, may believe that individual B would make better use of a given resource than individual A. If he is correct, then he can prot by intermediating trade between A and B. This is true even if he does not know to what use B will put the resource. B himself performs the second stage of the coordination by buying the resource from C and allocating it to its proper use. In this example two different people perform the two different stages of coordination; the rst stage involving intermediation in an external market is carried out by C and the second stage involving allocation through an internal market is carried out by B.
7.2
This section considers ways of reducing market-making costs in the aggregate by reducing the number of different markets. The basic principle is to package different goods together to form a single composite good. The xed cost of the market for the composite good need be no greater than the xed
108
The market-making rm
cost of any one of the markets for a constituent good. Two separate cases need to be distinguished according to whether the constituent goods are complements or substitutes. Packaging complements works best when the constituent goods are complementary in both supply and demand. The main application of the principle is to durable assets. A durable asset may be regarded as the equivalent of a bundle of dated services. Each service consists of the right to utilize the asset at a particular time. The different services are strictly complementary in supply because, when the durable is produced, each dated service is produced in a one-to-one relation with all the other services that can be rendered throughout the assets life. The services are usually complementary in demand, though they are not necessarily so. Because of the xed cost of exchanging custody of a good in order to utilize it, few people will wish to acquire just a single dated service. They will normally demand several consecutive dated services in order to recover the xed cost of acquiring custody. In many cases they will demand all the dated services throughout the assets life. In principle, each dated service could be sold separately through a contract of hire. The owner of the asset would offer for sale all the services rendered on the different dates spanned by the life of the asset. He would be responsible for organizing the hiring so that the good is never double-booked (or, in the case of a public good, for ensuring that the number of simultaneous bookings does not exceed capacity). If there were no market-making costs, an efcient allocation of asset use could be achieved using only the markets for dated durable services, and without recourse to the market for the durable good itself. There are two problems with this strategy. The rst concerns the multiplicity of different markets that would have to be operated, and the consequent difculty of covering the aggregate xed cost of market-making. The second concerns the peculiar problems of enforcing claims on future supplies, which were noted earlier (Section 6.6). Because the different dated services are joint products of the process which produces the durable commodity, and there are often economies of continuity in the process which utilizes the durable services, the principle of complementarity indicates that it is appropriate to package the dated services into a right of ownership of the durable asset itself. The durable asset is then traded in a spot market. The owner of the asset has physical custody of it and thereby ensures his own supplies of whatever future services of the asset he requires. The minority demand for individual dated services can be satised by the purchase and resale of the asset. Instead of hiring the asset for a specic period, the user buys the asset at the beginning of the period and resells it at
109
the end of the period. Although this involves two transactions where one would do, it is still efcient, given that the market for hire is so small that the total saving to hirers would be less than the xed cost of operating the market. Packaging substitutes is decidedly the most signicant way of reducing aggregate market-making costs. It works best when the constituent goods are substitutes in both supply and demand. The embodiment of the principle is the multi-purpose good: the good is capable of being put to a number of alternative uses (so that the uses are substitutes in supply) and it is unlikely that more than one of these uses will be required at any one time (so that the uses are substitutes in demand). It would be possible to establish a market for each of the separate user services that the good is capable of producing. The owner of the good would sell specic user rights, and so would allocate the good to whatever kind of use commanded the highest price. In the absence of market-making costs, an efcient allocation of each good between alternative uses could be achieved using only the markets for specic user services; the existence of a separate market in the good itself would contribute nothing to efciency. In practice, however, there are so many different user services that the number of different markets required would be enormous. Trading in many of these markets would be very thin and it would be difcult to recover the xed cost of market making from each of them. Thus when marketmaking costs exist, it is normally efcient to suppress the markets for specic user services and to operate just the market for the multi-purpose good instead.
7.3
This section analyses the role of the entrepreneur in promoting the development of a multi-purpose good. It is assumed that the entrepreneur recognizes the high market-making costs that are being incurred in the provision of specialized products to people with specialized requirements. These costs are incurred in the rst instance by intermediators who are making the markets in these specialized products. But the costs are being passed on to the customers in the form of a high selling price. Some of the costs are also passed on to the producers because the intermediator sets a low buying price as well. Each specialist market therefore operates with a large margin between buying price and selling price and a small volume of trade. Each market can continue operating only so long as the total margin earned is sufcient to meet the (mainly xed) costs of operating it. The entrepreneur seeks to introduce a multi-purpose good which will meet a number of different specialized needs. The typical multi-purpose good is
110
The market-making rm
formed by assembling a mixture of components. By activating one subset of these components, the good can be put to one specialized use; by activating another subset of components it can be put to a different specialized use. A good example of a multi-purpose good is a music centre which can be used as radio, tape-recorder, record-player, CD player, and so on. The user simply presses a button to select the preferred mode of operation. A personal computer may also be regarded as a multi-purpose good, in so far as it can run different types of software games, word-processing, mathematical computing, and so on. It is sometimes suggested that products can be identied in terms of characteristics over which consumer preferences are dened. In the present context, it could be suggested that the characteristics of a multi-purpose good correspond to the different functions that it can perform, while the different functions are generated from different permutations of the components that comprise the good. One of the objectives of the entrepreneur is to nd the combination of components which gives as many different desirable characteristics (that is, specialized uses) for a given total component cost. The multi-purpose good substitutes for all the specialist goods which previously performed these separate functions. However, being designed as a versatile good, it may not be able to achieve, in all cases, the same standard of performance as the specialist good it substitutes for. Demand for the specialist good may shrink, but not be eliminated. However, the xed costs of market making may mean that the specialist markets can no longer operate protably at a reduced level of demand. As a result, the specialist products may disappear from the market place altogether. The limited markets in high-performance specialized goods are superseded by a larger market in a versatile good offering a mediocre standard of performance instead. It must be recognized that the introduction of multi-purpose goods does not reduce every single component of market cost. For example, the specication cost of a multi-purpose good may be no less than the total specication costs of the specialized goods it displaces. This is because goods are normally specied by function rather than appearance (as noted earlier). The versatility of the multi-purpose good makes for a very complex functional specication. Furthermore, the different functions of the good may not be immediately apparent from its appearance, unlike its more specialized counterparts. For this reason, verbal communication of the functional specication may be very important in attracting customers. Furthermore, the complexity of the specication means that diffusion of information about the specication must be carefully controlled: messages passed on at second or third hand may easily get distorted. All of this obliges the entrepreneur to invest heavily in advertising his product specication to customers, to the extent that adver-
111
tising may become by far the largest cost in making a market for a multipurpose product. The burden of advertising costs may, however, be offset by economies in production which can be achieved in component manufacture. If the product is built up from components, then production switches from a low-volume output of specialized goods to high-volume outputs of components. There may even be more different components than there were specialized goods; this simply means that the average value of a component is relatively low. It is still true that each component has a high-volume output so that the producer can fully exploit economies of scale. It does mean, however, that additional markets have to be created for the components. The more components there are, the more markets are required, and the lower are the potential gains from introducing the multi-component good. Fortunately for the entrepreneur, it is much easier to organize markets between a component producer and the producer of a multi-purpose good than it is to organize a market between the producer of a specialized good and the nal users of it. One obvious reason is that fewer transactors are involved in buying the component than are involved in buying the nal product. But perhaps the main reason is that it is far easier to internalize a market in a component than in a nal product. Internalization signicantly reduces the cost of operating a component market and means that, even if the number of components is large relative to the number of specialized goods that are displaced, the introduction of a multi-purpose good may still, overall, achieve signicant economies in market-making costs.
7.4 INTERNALIZATION
Internalization of a market occurs when a transactor buys a good from himself or sells a good to himself. Internalization involves limiting the eld of trading partners so narrowly that the only trading partner is oneself. The advantages of this are fairly obvious. There is no problem in making contact, there is no need to haggle over price (since payment effects a purely notional transfer of income), there is no need to exchange custody, there is no incentive deliberately to default on either quantity or quality and while unintentional default cannot entirely be ruled out, at least the transactor has a good knowledge of his trading partners capabilities! Moreover, by internalizing a transaction it is often possible to keep the details of it secret and so bypass scal intervention and avoid paying taxes or tariffs. The disadvantages are equally obvious. In fact there is really only one: narrowing the eld of trading partners reduces the opportunity to benet from specialization. It means that in effect the buyer (or seller) cannot get as
112
The market-making rm
good a price for the good as he might. Internalization is only justied if the reduction in the gains from trade as reected in the poorer price is more than offset by the saving of market-making costs. The principle of internalization at its most basic is illustrated by the do-ityourself system of supplying household services. The gains from specialization forgone are measured by the additional time it takes the householder to perform the task relative to the time it would take the specialist (assuming both have the same opportunity cost of time). The reduction in market-making cost is measured by the saving of the specialists charges for operating the market in his own services. The rational householder supplies do-it-yourself services if the saving of the specialists market-making charges exceed the gains from specialization forgone. The most important aspect of internalization, however, is concerned not with households but with rms. Specialization in production induced, for example, by the division of labour leads to a large volume of intermediate product trade. Intermediate products are goods produced in one plant which are passed on to another plant for further processing. Components used in the production of a multi-purpose good are intermediate products. Economies of specialization encourage the production of a component in one plant and the assembly of the multi-purpose good in another plant. Internalization of the intermediate product market means that both the component-producing plant and the assembly plant are brought under common ownership. The intermediate product can then be transferred from one plant to the other without any change of ownership, and therefore without any haggling or risk of default. Internalization of intermediate product markets increases the scale and diversity of a rms operations. The more markets that are internalized by a given rm, the greater is the number of activities that are brought under its control. This increases the extent to which coordination is effected through operations internal to the rm. The rm is still involved in external markets. To set up the rm to begin with, it is necessary for the entrepreneur to acquire the different plants through external markets. He can acquire the plants second hand by purchasing them from their previous owners; this is equivalent to creating the internal market through a takeover or merger of hitherto independent rms. Alternatively, he can acquire plants by commissioning their construction. In either case the external market is used in order to establish the internal market. Even when the internal market is set up, the rm is still involved in external markets, hiring labour and other factor services for the plants and selling the nal product they produce. Internalization merely reduces the rms dependence on external markets; it does not eliminate the use of external markets altogether. It is apparent, therefore, that internalization is a major inuence on the size and structure of the rm. The scope of the internal markets relative to the
113
external markets determines the boundary between coordination by negotiation and coordination by control. The implications of internalization for the entrepreneur are examined in greater detail in Chapters 8 and 10. The different strands of the discussion are brought together in Chapter 11, which shows, amongst other things, how internalization inuences the dynamics of the growth of the rm. This chapter concludes with some observations upon the way that the peculiar problems of the external market in labour create a form of dual internalization. The problems of organizing external markets in specic labour services lead to these markets being internalized through a contract of employment in which the entrepreneurs acquire rights of control and supervision over employees. Secondly, the problems of recruiting and retaining employees encourage the entrepreneur to internalize his supply of labour within the family, or within any other kind of economic grouping to which he belongs. The consequences of this dual internalization of the labour market will become apparent as the argument proceeds.
7.5
Labour is probably the most versatile multi-purpose good, particularly when mental as well as manual labour services are taken into account. Within the labour market as a whole, various submarkets exist for particular skills. However, the allocation of labour to specic tasks is hardly ever effected by the labour market alone. Typically, the labour market allocates people to employers, or more precisely to a particular post with a particular employer. Each post has a job specication, which may be explicit in some cases, but less than explicit in others. The job specication determines the kind of tasks that the employee can be expected to perform. It also states who will issue the instructions about which task is to be performed at any given time. In some cases the instructor will be named (for example, if it is the employer himself), while in other cases the instructor will be identied by the post that he holds. If the post is with the same employer, then the employee is effectively operating within the hierarchy of an employing organization. It is characteristic of employment that the employer has control of the employee within the terms of the contract of employment: that is, within the scope of the agreed job specication. It is the employer that determines the precise task to which an employee is allocated. In principle, though, the allocation of labour to specic tasks need not be effected in this way. In theory there could be a market for every labour service required for the performance of every possible task. Once a contract had been made in the
114
The market-making rm
labour market, the buyer of the labour service would have no need to give the seller further information about the task that he was to perform. The seller would know exactly what he was required to do as soon as the contract was agreed. Thus the buyer would have no control over the seller. He would be bound by a contract which specied exactly what the seller was to do. Under a regime of this kind there would be no employers as such: only buyers and sellers of specic labour services. The rationale of the employment contract is that labour is a multi-purpose good and that, because of the xed cost of making a market in each specic labour service, it is more efcient to work with fewer markets in more general labour services. Each of these general markets has a larger volume of trade and it is therefore easier to recoup the xed cost of making the market. Although workers are endowed with particular skills, even a specialist or craftsman may nd that there are a number of different tasks in which his comparative advantage is roughly the same and between which he is largely indifferent as regards the non-income attributes of the work to be done. A worker in this position has nothing to lose from contracting to supply general labour services within his area of specialism rather than a single specic service. The costs of market making are signicantly reduced if the complexity of the specication that has to be announced to potential suppliers of the labour service is kept as low as possible. This is achieved if a market in general labour services is created and all demands for specic labour services are channelled into this market. The market for specic labour services does not disappear altogether: it is merely internalized by the employer. Thus employers hire general labour services and instruct the person they hire about the specic services to be supplied. This does not, of course, reduce the cost of communication between employer and employee, but it does reduce the cost of communication between the employer and all those potential suppliers of labour services who do not nally work for him. In common with many other multi-purpose goods, labour is a durable asset. The durability of labour is also an inuence upon the employment contract. There are set-up costs associated with switching labour from one place of work to another. The cost of travel to and from the job means that it is efcient for the worker to work at just a single place each day. Travel to work is an important part of daily routine. Economies of habit formation make it desirable to work at the same place day after day. Also where labour is concerned the roles of transactor and resource are unied. Economies of repeat-trading, which relate to the advantage of trading with the same transactor, imply that there are economies of repeatedly using the same labour resource. This provides an argument for continuity of employment in the longer term, that is, over several months or years.
115
In principle the allocation of labour over time could be determined through forward markets in dated labour services. However, the difculty of enforcing forward contracts suggests that the market-making costs would be prohibitive. Logic dictates that the employer should make an outright purchase of the resource: that is, he should buy out the employee. It is one of the peculiarities of the labour market that an outright purchase of this kind is unenforceable, because of constraints imposed by social convention. The result is that the employer nds it difcult to secure a future supply of labour and the employee nds it difcult to secure a future supply of work. In an attempt to resolve this problem, a fairly complex system of customs has developed within the spot market for labour services. One of these customs is the open-ended labour contract. This provides for the automatic renewal of daily employment until one or other of the parties takes active steps to separate, by giving notice of either quitting or redundancy. This eliminates the need for each party actively to conrm renewal of the contract on a day-to-day basis. Negotiation costs are reduced by restricting the frequency of negotiation: convention dictates that wage rates are normally renegotiated not more than once a year. Given the economics of repeat-trading, each party can impose a substantial cost upon the other by initiating a premature separation. The cost of separation is normally greater the shorter the notice that is given. Premature separation is deterred by incentives embodied in implicit contracts. An implicit contract is a contract which is not enforceable in law, but is backed by sanctions of a more general nature, such as those described in Section 6.8. The terms of an implicit contract are not always precisely dened, so it is the spirit of the contract, rather than the letter, that is enforced. Implicit contracts have many roles besides deterring separation (see, for example, Section 9.3). In the context of separation, employers may threaten to give bad references to premature quitters, or to foreclose on personal loans advanced to them. Employees may deter redundancy by threatening to strike (backed by colleagues) or to instigate political action hostile to the employer.
7.6
It is well known that the costs of organizing the labour market are very high. This partly reects the heterogeneity of both workers and jobs and the consequent difculties of matching the worker to the job. Partly it is due to social convention which imposes constraints on the contract of employment and the sanctions that can be applied to enforce it. The problem is exacerbated by the fact that it is difcult to organize private intermediation which, if it could be effected, would help to reduce transaction costs. For reasons already ex-
116
The market-making rm
plained, an intermediator cannot buy and sell labour just like any other commodity. It is true that in some sectors of the labour market there are private agencies who employ labour specically for rehire to other rms, but, because the agencies cannot enforce long-term contracts with their employees, they are always vulnerable to being bypassed. Once the agency has placed the worker with a rm, the rm can offer the worker a job directly, and so both rm and worker will terminate their contract with the agency. The difculties of intermediation in the labour market create an incentive to internalize the supply of labour services to rms. The most basic form of labour market internalization is self-employment. Instead of selling his labour services to an employer, the worker integrates forward and establishes a rm to employ himself. If he works in a service industry, he may be doing no more than marketing his own labour services to the public instead of relying upon an employer to do the marketing for him. But if he works in a manufacturing industry then he bypasses the market for labour services altogether, and becomes involved directly in the product market. He may rely upon an intermediator in the product market to put him in contact with his customers, or he may integrate further forward into market making, and market his own product directly to the customers. Self-employment is, on the face of it, a very attractive way of bypassing labour market imperfections. The main constraint is that, if the self-employed person is successful, then he will need to take on extra labour and, in order to recruit it, he will be forced back into the market that he has tried to avoid. The only difference is that he will now enter the market as an employer rather than as an employee. A possible solution to this problem is suggested by an extension of the concept of internalization from the individual worker to his family, and perhaps even to his friends. Instead of internalizing the labour market around an individual it is internalized around a social unit instead. Social ties are normally closest within the family (though exceptions have been noted in certain cultures). A self-employed person may expand his business by rst taking on other members of his household, then non-resident members of his family, and then members of his extended family for example those related at once or twice remove by marriage. Within the family, he may prefer to take on rst those who are most dependent upon him, for example his children, as sanctions against them are relatively easy to enforce. The last to be taken on will be those who because of their family status hold sanctions over him. It is worth noting that the family is capable of internalizing not only the labour market, but the capital market too. The family may even internalize the product market, in the manner explained earlier (Section 7.4), but this has little direct relevance to the entrepreneur.
117
A self-employed person who needs risk capital will often go to his family rst. Ostensibly, he is hoping to exploit the goodwill of his family towards him. But goodwill often runs out when people are asked to part with their money even within families. There is, however, an economic rationale to this strategy. First, the borrower can have condence that his relatives though they might refuse him a loan would not stoop to stealing his ideas and putting them into practice on their own account instead. Second, the borrower is already well-known to the lenders; if the lenders are of an older generation they may have known him from his birth. They are therefore in a good position to assess his relevant personal qualities such as integrity and competence. Third, as members of his family, they are in a good position to monitor the way he uses their capital and to bring pressure to bear upon him should things not turn out as well as expected. Finally, if the borrower stands to inherit the lenders estate, then he is in effect being given no more than a mortgage upon his own inheritance. The lender is in a privileged position to provide the mortgage, because a third party might be unwilling to accept the prospect of an inheritance as security for a loan. It has been suggested that some families actually operate an internal capital market in which nancial resources are pooled under the management of the head of the family and are then allocated among family entrepreneurs on the basis of a strictly economic assessment of their prospects. Individual projects are screened by the head of the family, in much the same way as they would be screened by the board of a large company, or by the management of a merchant bank. The advantage of the family organization is that it captures all the information that family members have about each other and puts it to an economic use. Firms enjoy a similar advantage but to a much more limited extent. They can use the information gained from monitoring individual employees to assess the projects they present for consideration by the board, but they do not enjoy the same depth of information as does the family rm which draws upon personal knowledge that is not available to the typical employer.
SUMMARY
This chapter has stressed the role of internalization in the reduction of transaction costs. It is shown that internalization is intimately connected with control over the utilization of multi-purpose goods. Internal and external markets typically exist side by side, with coordination being achieved by a two-stage process in which multipurpose goods are rst allocated through external markets to people who believe they can put them to a better use, and are then allocated internally by their new owners to their appropriate use. The
118
The market-making rm
cost advantages of internal markets constitute the basic rationale for the rm. They explain why it is that entrepreneurs seeking to intermediate transactions need to establish a unit of control within which the assets required to generate market-making services can be brought together. This unit of control is examined in greater detail in Chapter 10.
An important application of the theory of market-making costs is to the market for information. It can be shown that there is a strong incentive for an entrepreneur to internalize the exploitation of the commercial information upon which his superior judgment is based. It is the internalization of commercial information that leads the entrepreneur to acquire control of assets, and hence links the entrepreneur to the management of a rm. In analysing this, it will be assumed that the entrepreneur is certain of the accuracy of the information at his disposal. There are ve main ways in which an entrepreneur can exploit commercial information: 1. 2. 3. He can license the information. He can enter into bets with those who do not have the information and whose judgment as a result differs from his own. He can buy up assets which, given his information, are currently undervalued, with a view to reselling later. Once the information becomes public, other transactors will revalue the assets and he will make a capital gain. This strategy relies upon other people coordinating the use of resources once the information becomes public. It also depends upon other entrepreneurs creating the market for the assets. He can initiate the coordination himself. He can intermediate any additional transactions which the information indicates are required. He can also acquire control of any multi-purpose goods which need to be reallocated to another use. He can act as coordinator, but as delegate rather than principal. He can offer his services as a delegate to someone who is liable to make the wrong decision or whose existing delegate is inept and rely upon the incentive system of his employer to reward a correct decision.
4.
5.
119
120
The market-making rm
8.2
Consider an entrepreneur who believes that he has privileged information. He is absolutely convinced of its accuracy. He also believes that it is relevant to other people. If made available to them it will change their decisions and as a result improve their welfare. Under these conditions it seems perfectly reasonable to regard the item of information as a commodity which should command a positive price, and to market it as such. Given a perfect market in information, the entrepreneur should be able to sell his information for an amount equal to the capitalized value of its use. However, information is not just like any other good and its market, far from being perfect, is in many cases prohibitively costly to organize. To sell any good it is necessary to be able to exclude people from it. Because information is a public good with practically innite capacity it is difcult to enforce custody of it. Partly because of this difculty, the law regards most information as being in common ownership. With the exception of certain items of information which are patentable, and others which are covered by the right to personal privacy, exclusion from information is not legally enforceable. Thus the problems of de facto exclusion are compounded by the absence of legal sanctions. In these circumstances the right of exclusion can only be upheld by secrecy. It is an unfortunate fact that the very act of marketing information is likely to undermine its secrecy. The reason is that, where information is concerned, it is difcult to separate the product itself from its specication. As a result the information is given away as soon as the specication is announced. Separation of specication and product can be achieved in a few cases: newspaper vendors have developed the art of separating the description of news from the news itself. Famous lm star dies or Shock election result describes what the news is about without describing precisely what it is. Even in these cases, though, people who have read the description may be able to make a reasonable guess at what the news item is. It follows that a vendor of information always runs a risk of giving his product away through the very act of specifying it to buyers. This in itself would not matter if information were not a satiation good. In some markets, sellers regularly give away samples of their product to stimulate future demand. But, because information is a satiation good, fullling demand just once destroys all subsequent demand from the same source. If the seller decides to enforce exclusion by keeping the specication secret, then he creates uncertainty in the mind of the buyer. As a result the buyer cannot appraise the value of the information properly. His demand price will reect a strong subjective probability that the information is worthless to him: he may know it already or it may simply be irrelevant to his
121
needs. This makes it likely that the buyer will be unable to offer anything like what the seller believes the information to be worth. If the seller fails to recognize the buyers uncertainty problem, then he may hold out for too a high price, and negotiations may break down. Given the asymmetry in the perception of the situation between buyer and seller, it would be mutually advantageous for the seller to insure the value of the information to the buyer. The buyer would pay the seller only if the information was novel and relevant to him. The buyer would be willing to pay more if the payment were contingent upon the novelty and relevance of the information being proven, and the seller, being condent of this, would regard this payment as being just as assured as an unconditional payment. Unfortunately, this arrangement runs into the difculties described in Section 7.3; for it is essentially a contingent contract, and one contingent upon factors (novelty and relevance) which are to some extent subjective. Unless the contract is very carefully specied, there will be ample opportunity for the buyer to default, by dishonestly claiming that he already had the information or that he could have done just as well without it. If in addition the information relates to a future state of the world, then the problem of default is magnied, for the contingent contract then becomes a forward contract too. Information also poses severe problems of quality control. With most products a defect simply means that the buyer has wasted his payment. But with some products defects in quality can impose severe penalties on the buyer. Information typically comes into the latter category. This is because information is commonly used in decision making and mistaken decisions can result in severe losses due to resource misallocation. Just as correct information leads to coordination, so the use of incorrect information may lead to dislocation. It has already been noted that the use of guarantees to insure the buyer is not usually reliable when severe losses are possible. Neither can the buyer satisfy himself of the quality by supervising the researching of the information, for this would destroy the sellers secrecy, and so eliminate the basis for the market. The best that can probably be hoped for is that the seller can offer to provide the buyer with corroborative evidence before the information is used. Effectively, this transforms the information from an experience good into an inspection good and so makes it easier for the buyer to control the risk that the information will actually prove a liability. Finally, it is necessary to return to the problem of enforcing exclusion from a public good. It is apparent that, if two or more people already have access to a public good, then they are both in a weak position when selling access to a third party. If each can offer access, then neither can ensure exclusion unless they collude. Competition between them will drive down the price of access to zero. So far as information is concerned, this means that it normally
122
The market-making rm
has to be sold with restrictions upon resale by the buyer. If the buyer attempts to resell the information in competition with the original seller, then together they will bid away any reward from a subsequent sale. Restrictions on resale are notoriously difcult to police, and so the risk of default by the buyer is considerable. Furthermore, it is doubtful whether such restrictions would be enforceable in law. Given the widespread view that information is in common ownership, restrictions on resale are liable to be regarded as illegal restraints of trade. Thus, even if offenders could be detected, penalties could not be enforced in law.
8.3
If an entrepreneur cannot sell his information to other people, then the obvious alternative is to exploit it himself. This is equivalent to internalizing the market for information. As exploiter of the information, he buys it from himself; as the possessor of the information, he sells it to himself. In a world of perfect markets, betting would be the best way of exploiting information. The entrepreneur offers to bet with other people upon the event whose occurrence is uncertain, or upon the state of the world or the aspect of it which is in doubt. Betting can operate in cases where licensing cannot. It can generate a private reward even to information which is quite irrelevant to personal welfare. All that is necessary for betting to succeed is that the parties with whom the entrepreneur seeks to bet are not totally risk-averse. Since the entrepreneur is by assumption convinced of the accuracy of his information he perceives no risk, and is therefore restricted in his bets mainly by the risk aversion of other parties. The other constraint is his wealth, which restricts the payments he can offer to make if he is wrong. However, betting is not without its problems. One of them is that offering to bet with people may actually change their beliefs. This problem is particularly acute when betting upon events which are known to be irrelevant. If an event is irrelevant to the entrepreneur then his motive for betting cannot be insurance. It must be speculation. This signals to other people that the entrepreneur believes he has superior information. If he offers very large bets this suggests, furthermore, that he feels certain of his information. This in turn may persuade other people that he is probably right. The fact that the entrepreneur offers a bet may therefore change the mind of the people with whom he plans to bet. As a result, there may be nobody with whom he can bet on favourable terms. Note that this problem is the reverse of the problem with licensing. Licensing rests upon the assumption that other people will believe the
123
information when they are told it, and encounters problems because they may not. More precisely, licensing relies upon people believing the claims that are made for the information, and not challenging them once it has been supplied. Betting rests on the principle that people would not believe the information on which the entrepreneur acts even if they were told it. Indeed, the nature of the bet virtually tells them what it is the entrepreneur believes. Problems arise when other people actually believe that the entrepreneurs information is correct! This problem with betting is somewhat reduced if the information relates to a relevant event or to a future one. When the entrepreneur bets upon a relevant event, it is conceivable that his motive is insurance. It is therefore possible that he does not have privileged information, and so it is less likely that other people will change their beliefs. Almost by denition, the entrepreneur cannot know the outcome of a future event, however strong his beliefs about it. Consequently, it is always possible that he is wrong. Furthermore, if the event lies in the future, it is more difcult for people to check the entrepreneurs information for themselves, and so there is less likelihood of his privileged access to it being eliminated. However, betting on a future event involves a forward contract and so incurs a risk of default. This implies, amongst other things, that the entrepreneur must have a reputation for integrity if his bets on future events are to prove acceptable to others. Finally, betting shares a problem with licensing in respect of the multiplicity of markets that are required. Information is a very heterogeneous good, and so each item of information, and each bet, incurs its own market-making costs. Even if contact making, monitoring and enforcement costs can be shared between them, each item, and each bet, incurs its own specication and negotiation costs. The gains from exploiting some items of information may be sufciently large to warrant the establishment of a special market, but generally this will not be so. On the whole, the market-making costs for information and bets are so high, and the possibilities of sharing them so limited, that it is uneconomic for specic items of information to be sold and specic bets to be placed.
8.4
PORTFOLIO SPECULATION
The problems of betting are largely overcome by portfolio speculation. Portfolio speculation, like licensing, applies only to the exploitation of information about relevant events. Also like licensing, it applies to information which will be believed once people gain access to it. The principle of portfolio speculation is that, because the information is relevant, resources will be reallocated once the information becomes public. In a market sys-
124
The market-making rm
tem this reallocation will be guided by prices. The entrepreneur can back his judgment by making spot purchases of assets which he believes will appreciate once prices change. An asset is of course just a forward claim, or a bundle of such claims. It might be argued, therefore, that the method is similar to betting. However, there is one crucial difference, which is that portfolio speculation relies upon the revaluation of claims that already exist rather than upon the creation of purpose-made claims. This has several advantages. First, there is the obvious advantage that no additional markets need to be created. The speculator enters markets that already exist for other purposes. The market-making costs incurred are marginal costs only: the xed costs of market making are avoided altogether. Secondly, the information upon which the entrepreneur is acting is masked by the remaining volume of trade in the market. This will be governed by other, possibly quite different, motives. Even in a purely speculative market there may be many people present, each speculating upon some different item of information. This makes it very difcult for those with whom the entrepreneur is trading to ascertain upon which event he is speculating, and to modify their own beliefs accordingly. Thus the condentiality of the information is maintained by trading in a market where price is determined by other factors besides beliefs about the particular event concerned. Finally, it is possible for the entrepreneur to trade in markets where forward claims are relatively secure. For example, it was noted earlier that durable goods may be regarded as an embodiment of forward claims on user services. Custody of a durable good especially a private good provides a very secure forward claim on a user service. If user services are liable to be revalued when the information becomes public, then an entrepreneur can take a speculative position in the spot market for durable goods. By working out which user services will become scarcer, he can determine which durables are liable to appreciate. If he concentrates his portfolio upon these, then he can anticipate a capital gain. Of course, portfolio speculation has its disadvantages too. First it is necessary for the entrepreneur to think through the implications of the event concerned before he can speculate upon it. This means that he must have considerable background knowledge about the way the economy works. Unless he invests time and effort in analysing its implications, lack of background information, or simply faulty logic, may lead him to the wrong conclusion. Thus his information about the event may be right, but his speculative position wrong. Rather ironically, it is possible that in this situation two wrongs could make a right. If his information is misleading, and his interpretation of it incorrect, then his speculation may turn out successful. Obviously, though, it is impossible to rely upon such coincidence when undertaking speculation.
125
The main problem with portfolio speculation is that it relies upon other people responding to the information when it becomes public. It is other people that actually reallocate resources: the entrepreneur just sits back and takes a capital gain. If publication of the information is delayed, then coordination will be postponed and the potential reward from the information will be reduced. If information were costless to transmit there would be no problem. The entrepreneur would transmit the information right away, as soon as he had formed his speculative portfolio. Everyone would interpret the information in the same way as the entrepreneur, and his conjectures would be completely validated. Resources would be reallocated immediately. But, in practice, information is costly to transmit, particularly if the message has to be forceful and clear. This is very important in the present instance because the entrepreneur is relying upon his conjectures about how other people will respond to the information to achieve his capital gain. If they misunderstand the message, or fail to recognize its implications, then coordination will be delayed and some of the value of the information lost. If the cost of reliable publication is very high, the only alternative is to rely upon the accidental rediscovery of the information by other people. For the entrepreneur this means uncertainty about exactly when, and by whom, implementation will be initiated. Under these circumstances portfolio speculation becomes a much less attractive option.
8.5
The problem of predicting other peoples discovery of information, and their reaction to it, is avoided if the entrepreneur implements coordination himself. The entrepreneur still needs some background information to ensure that he does not miss any of the implications for coordination, but he does not need to make detailed predictions about other peoples collective response to its announcement. Indeed, the boot is now very much on the other foot. Given his commitment to effect coordination himself, the entrepreneur desires protection against competition. He therefore wishes to inhibit the diffusion of information rather than to promote it. The signicance of the competitive threat depends upon whether there is a once-for-all opportunity for coordination, or a continuing one. Typically, a once-for-all opportunity involves stock adjustment, while a continuing opportunity involves the adjustment of ows (see Chapter 5). A once-for-all opportunity is easy to pre-empt simply by being the rst in the eld. The fact that the entrepreneur has a temporary lead in the implementation of the information guarantees his success.
126
The market-making rm
Where a continuing opportunity is concerned, the entrepreneur must reconcile himself to the fact that eventually his successful exploitation of it will attract the attention of others. Even if they would not normally have discovered the information for themselves, they can do so now simply by studying his method of operation. There are two main strategies available to the entrepreneur for preventing the erosion of his prot. One is to use his temporary lead to invest in creating barriers to entry. This has already been analysed in detail in Section 5.8. The other is to supplement coordination with portfolio speculation. The principle underlying this strategy is as follows. The entry of competitors will cause selling prices to be bid down and buying prices to be bid up as the entrepreneurs monopoly is destroyed. The benets will accrue not to the competitors but to those with whom they trade. If, for example, the entrepreneur is buying user services which are in less than perfectly elastic supply, then the price of these services will be bid up. As a result the durable goods which generate them will appreciate in value. If the entrepreneur owns the durable goods whose services he uses, then, as an owner, he stands to gain from the entry of competitors. To exploit this opportunity fully, the entrepreneur will wish to own as many units of the durables as he can, and not just the units whose services he uses. In this way the entrepreneur can recover some of his losses by speculating upon the entry of his competitors. Even if the entrepreneur does not anticipate competition, the ownership of inputs is a method of minimizing risk. It offers partial insurance not only against competition but against any other factor which could raise the price of inputs and reduce the gains from coordination. The principle applies most strongly to inputs which are in inelastic supply, since it is these inputs whose prices are most sensitive to disturbances. It is apparent that forward integration into coordination is as much a complement to portfolio speculation as it is a substitute for it. Nevertheless, forward integration is not without its problems, the chief of which is that it requires a diversity of skills to be exercised by the entrepreneur. The two main forms of coordination are production in which choice of technique has to be coordinated with the state of nature and the creation of trade, in which the plans of one individual have to be coordinated with the plans of another. Successful production requires not only privileged information about the state of nature, but detailed knowledge of how to implement the appropriate technique. Successful trade creation requires not only privileged information about transactors willingness to trade, but also knowledge of market-making techniques. The entrepreneur must either have this knowhow himself, or he must know where to hire it. But hiring know-how is difcult for the very reasons considered above. The same problems the entrepreneur encounters in selling his information to others will cause problems
127
for an entrepreneur who wishes to buy information from others. If the entrepreneur cannot hire the know-how, he must supply it himself. It is this excessive demand upon the entrepreneurs knowledge and ability that constitutes the main disadvantage of forward integration.
8.6
The exploitation of information in the ways discussed above is liable to be constrained by the wealth of the entrepreneur. An exception may have to be made for licensing, but that option is usually excluded on other grounds. Betting is constrained by the entrepreneurs ability to pay up if he is proved wrong. Unless those who bet against him are irrational, they will not accept bets that could not be honoured. Portfolio speculation requires capital in order to buy up the appropriate assets. As noted above, forward integration into coordination is often an adjunct to portfolio speculation rather than an alternative to it. It also imposes its own capital requirements. Because of market-making costs, a producer may have to buy outright a producer durable whose services he would like to hire. For reasons explained in Chapter 9, to create trade efciently, an entrepreneur may have to hold an inventory of the goods in which he trades, and an inventory of the means of payment to go with it. Furthermore, there are often economies of integrating production and market making, so that the entrepreneur is obliged to nance not only the purchase of producer durables but the creation of inventory as well. It is tempting to suggest that if there were a perfect market in capital, then the wealth constraint would disappear and the entrepreneur could borrow as much as he wished at the prevailing rate of interest. But this is false, and only illustrates the dangers of carrying over the logic of perfect competition into the realm of the entrepreneur. Entrepreneurship has its own logic, which is equally simple. The entrepreneur who believes that he has relevant information believes that other people have got the allocation of resources wrong. If he cannot license the information, then he exploits it by backing his own judgment against theirs. This entire policy rests on the fact that other people think differently to him. He cannot expect people who think differently to lend him money to back his judgment against theirs, when if their judgment is proved correct he will be unable to repay the loan. It might appear that to lend any money to an entrepreneur is a denial of the logic of the situation. But this is an overstatement. Certainly, the lender perceives greater risks than does the entrepreneur. These risks would be reduced if the lender were better informed. To obtain a loan the entrepreneur must make his information available to the lender, together with any corrobo-
128
The market-making rm
rative evidence that is available. The danger is that in doing so the entrepreneur builds up a competitor. Indeed, it is worse than that, for it is likely that the potential lender has far more capital than does the entrepreneur. The entrepreneur needs the lender, but once the lender has the information he no longer needs the entrepreneur. He can cut out the entrepreneur and exploit the opportunity himself. Wherever there is an obstacle to trade, people will seek to develop marketmaking institutions to overcome it. That is the moral of entrepreneurship. Loans are a form of intertemporal trade, and the information asymmetry between borrower and lender is an obstacle to trade. The obstacle can be overcome if there is a market-making institution which has a reputation for integrity and condentiality. The institution invites applications for loans and considers them in condence using information supplied by the proposer (the entrepreneur). The institution voluntarily commits itself not to undertake on its own behalf projects of the kind for which loan applications are submitted. It also debars itself from approaching other people with proposals based upon those that have been submitted. It honours these commitments because it nds the loan business it can attract using its reputation for integrity is more valuable in the long term than any gains it could make in the short term by breaching this commitment. The type of institution which normally assumes this role is of course, the bank in particular, the merchant bank. This is in fact a special case of a more general phenomenon, namely the contribution that reputation makes to the creation of markets. An alternative to the banks reputation for integrity is the entrepreneurs reputation for accuracy. If the entrepreneur has a record of successful judgment in similar projects, then the lender may be willing to accept that the entrepreneur is correct without knowing precisely what his information is. This preserves the entrepreneurs condentiality while keeping down the lenders perception of risk. It provides privileged access to capital for the experienced and successful entrepreneur. But it does nothing to solve the strategic problems faced by the rst-time entrepreneur. Finally, it is important to consider the case in which there are several likeminded individuals, each of whom has insufcient wealth to exploit the information properly. If the individuals can establish contact with one another, then they can pool their resources. Effectively, they agree not to compete, but to collude, in backing their collective judgment against that of everyone else. The fact that each party has limited wealth affords security to the others that he will not drop out of the group and go it alone in competition with them. This concept of pooling entrepreneurial wealth is of course the basis of the joint-stock company. It is of particular importance when the implementation of coordination involves economies of scale.
129
8.7
There are various ways in which a lender can reduce the risks involved in backing an entrepreneur. The rst is to assess the entrepreneurs general knowledge and his basic business skills. If the entrepreneur is ignorant of even basic information, then it is likely that his difference of judgment emanates not from knowing more than others but from knowing less. If he does not possess basic business skills, then, whether or not his information is correct, he is unlikely to translate it successfully into prot. Other relevant attributes of the entrepreneur include his ability to reason, to communicate and to cross-check information. It has even been claimed that qualities such as imagination and foresight can be assessed by studying behaviour in the simulated situations which appear in business games. If this claim were entirely correct, then many of the problems characteristic of nancing entrepreneurship could be easily solved. In practice, it is quite likely that entrepreneurs have more imagination than the people who devise the games. On the other hand, the potential reward to devising a successful method of screening for entrepreneurship is so great that continual improvement of technique is likely even if complete success cannot ever be attained. Another method of controlling risk is to exploit the fact that the implementation of any activity always generates information as a by-product. Where the activity is designed to exploit privileged information, the information thrown up by the activity can be used to validate the initial claim. The sooner the information becomes available, the sooner errors can be detected and corrective action taken. So far as the lender is concerned, full and accurate reporting of the information is crucial in minimizing the risk of loss. A lender is not automatically entitled to information of this kind. Even if he were to contract to receive such information, he would still need to check that there was no concealment, or deliberate distortion. Nor can the lender rely upon the entrepreneur agreeing to the correction of errors in the way that he would desire. To check that the entrepreneur is not concealing information, the lender needs to be able to monitor the implementation of the activity himself. He must have unrestricted access to the premises where the activity is carried on. As new information becomes available he must have the right to consult the entrepreneur and, if things turn out badly, the right to overrule the entrepreneur in the interests of reducing the loss and protecting the repayment of his loan. This suggests that the lender should participate in the project as one of its principals, with the entrepreneur assuming the role of delegate. Naturally, the arrangement must provide for the entrepreneur to be rewarded if his judgment is correct. This can be achieved by the entrepreneur acting as joint principal with the lender and receiving a xed reward for his work as del-
130
The market-making rm
egate, or by the entrepreneur acting as delegate under an incentive system which pays delegates by their results. Finally, it is possible for the lender to use the fact that collateral for his loan may be available in the form of durable goods and inventory owned by the entrepreneur. Given the additional risks perceived by the lender it is unlikely that his valuation of the collateral will be as high as the entrepreneurs. Nevertheless, the lender can reduce his risk either by purchasing the assets himself and renting them on a long-term basis to the entrepreneur or by acquiring a rst charge on the assets so that, should the project fail, the lender can obtain custody of them. If the assets can be mortgaged to the lender, then his potential loss is limited to the excess of the loan over a conservative, or pessimistic, valuation of the assets.
8.8
The simplest way for the entrepreneur to act as delegate is to become an employee. The entrepreneurs principal provides him with the necessary nance. The entrepreneur continues to bear some of the risks because he is paid by results. But the risks that he cannot afford to bear are borne by somebody else. Employment, however, is implicitly a long-term arrangement. Although an entrepreneur may become an employee in order to obtain nancial backing for a project, can he continue as an entrepreneur and originate subsequent projects while remaining employed? This depends very much upon the nature of the post to which the entrepreneur is appointed. Who would wish to hire an entrepreneur specically to act in that capacity? The answer is another entrepreneur who believes that there is a gap in the market for entrepreneurship. An entrepreneur may believe that there is an entire eld of economic activity in which there are many unexploited opportunities for coordination, and will continue to be so for some time. His judgment is that, if only the right people were directed to these areas, then very large prots could be made. He does not have the depth of information required to recognize and exploit these opportunities himself. What he does have is information which, if made available to people with more specialized knowledge, would enable them to exploit them. Given the problems of licensing information of this sort, it is probably easier to advertise for prospective entrepreneurs to come forward. The entrepreneurs are screened for ability in the manner indicated above and offered employment under an incentive system. The incentive system may be a formal one in which each employee is constituted as a separate prot centre and receives a proportion of his prots as salary. Or it may be an informal
131
system in which the employees decisions are monitored and those who are most successful relative to the others are promoted, while those who are least successful are demoted or red. The delegate entrepreneurs are provided with information by their employer. They may also be expected to pool information among themselves. Typically, each delegate is expected to put forward proposals for comments by the other delegates and, after suitable revision, for assessment by his employer. At each stage the proposal goes before a panel, or committee, in which the delegate advocates the implementation of his proposal. If he can persuade the others of its value, then it proceeds to the next stage. If he cannot persuade them, then his proposals will be vetoed. A proposal is implemented when it receives the nal assent of the employer or, in the case of small proposals, the assent of those delegated to give approval. The arrangement described above effectively makes a market in entrepreneurship itself. It is an entrepreneurial response to the problems of quality control in the market for entrepreneurs. In fact it has a dual role in improving quality and in checking it. It improves the quality of judgment by giving delegate entrepreneurs free access to the judgments and skills of other delegates as well as those of the employer. It checks quality both by assessing the delegates personal qualities before he is hired and by probing the proposals he puts up from the many different angles adopted by his fellow-entrepreneurs. The logic of linking the improvement of quality to the checking of it is quite simple. It exploits the fact that information gained from investigating one proposal may be useful in developing some other proposal. Thus having one entrepreneur screen another entrepreneurs proposals allows information to be captured and put to further use. Another way of explaining this is to say that the employerentrepreneur internalizes the capital market. He performs a function similar to the banks, and other honest brokers in the capital market, in allocating funds between alternative risky projects. But he lends to his own delegates rather than to independent borrowers. Because he can supervise and if necessary overrule his delegates, the risk of large losses is reduced. Furthermore, because his reward is directly related to the performance of the projects, he has a strong incentive to provide his delegates with information that will not only help to avoid losses but will help to make large prots on their projects even larger. The advantages of this system cannot really be questioned. The only question is how the employerentrepreneur can get it to work. From whom does he get his own funds in the rst place? How does he prevent his delegates from quitting once they have learnt their employers secrets? How does he ensure that the different delegates cooperate with each other rather than compete?
132
The market-making rm
The short answer is that the employerentrepreneur can do these things only with difculty. He must have an exceptional reputation in the capital market. He must be extremely good at organizing delegation. He can prevent delegates from learning too many of his secrets by compartmentalizing the system so that no delegate has access to all compartments at once. Thus at any one time each delegate may know a few secrets, but not sufcient to provide him with the overall perspective of the situation, which must remain unique to his employer. To retain his most able delegates, he must reward their judgment appropriately. This involves making a careful assessment of what they could expect to earn by exercising their judgment elsewhere. Finally, he must devise incentives which, while rewarding individual success, also reward cooperative contributions to the success of other peoples projects, and penalize success which is achieved at their expense.
8.9
The contractual arrangements discussed above between entrepreneurs and lenders, and between one entrepreneur and another, are typically institutionalized in the rm. The rm is a legal ction. The rm can own resources on its own behalf, and is in turn owned by other people (or by other rms). The capital structure of the rm, together with its contracts with employees, determines the allocation of risk. In principle, the rm could issue many different kinds of contingent forward claims upon its output, and hold many different contingent forward claims upon its inputs. In practice, because of market-making costs, rms typically buy their inputs in spot markets and issue just two main kinds of forward claim. One is an unconditional claim, promising repayment of principal with interest, and the other is a residual claim on the prots of the rm. Within these two categories a number of variations occur. Some claims are transferable between lenders and some are not. Some claims are short-term, others long-term, and some perpetual. Some short-term claims may be renewable on demand, and some may not. Within the term of the loan, interest rates may be xed or variable. The most common forms of claim are equity, which is a transferable perpetual residual claim; debenture, which is a transferable long-term or perpetual xed interest unconditional claim; a mortgage, which is a non-transferable long-term unconditional claim (normally at variable interest); and a bank loan, which is a non-transferable short-term unconditional claim, sometimes renewable on demand and normally at variable interest. Transferable claims are normally divided into shares so that each unit can be traded independently. The existence of different types of claim enables lenders to specialize in insuring different types of risk. Holders of unconditional claims are exposed
133
mainly to a risk of default, while holders of residual claims are exposed to the risk that prot will be less than the amount anticipated. By and large a more limited range of factors inuence default than inuence protability, so that less judgment is involved in the valuation of unconditional claims than in the valuation of residual claims. Those who are best at assessing the factors which inuence default will specialize in holding unconditional claims, while those who have the wider knowledge required to assess the factors which inuence prot will specialize in holding residual claims. Similarly, lenders who believe themselves to be far-sighted will specialize in holding long-term non-transferable claims while those who are relatively near-sighted will specialize in holding short-term or transferable claims. The holders of risk capital provide insurance to the employees. In particular, where an employee has discretion, the owners of capital will bear some of the loss incurred if the employee makes the wrong decision. The employee will bear some of the loss too, as he will be penalized by the incentive system. It does not follow, though, that the employee is necessarily seeking insurance. He may be risking as much through the incentive system as he could afford to risk if he were self-employed. In this case he chooses to be an employee only because the incentive system offers a bigger potential reward for the same degree of risk. The existence of different types of rm whose risks are inuenced by different factors facilitates both insurance and portfolio speculation. In the absence of markets in specic contingent claims, individual investors can substitute into markets for corporate equity. An individual insuring against, or speculating upon, a particular event can work out which types of corporate equity are most likely to appreciate relative to the others when the event occurs, and concentrate his portfolio upon them in the expectation of a capital gain. Small-scale insurance and speculation is promoted by the availability of transferable shares in small denominations. It has already been established that share ownership allows like-minded entrepreneurs to cooperate in funding large-scale projects. As originally formulated, the argument does not depend upon the shares being transferable. But transferability and small denominations allow the principle to be applied more widely.
SUMMARY
This chapter has brought together a number of different strands of the preceding analysis to show that the entrepreneur who has gained privileged access to information must normally internalize its exploitation. For example, the entrepreneur may integrate forward into market making, or into production.
134
The market-making rm
He may become the owner of a rm, or one of its employees. The internalization of the market for information explains why entrepreneurship is rarely observed in a completely pure form; it is usually integrated with other functions as well. If external trade in information were common, then the institutional structure of the economy would be quite different from what it is in practice. It is difcult to visualize an economy of this kind because the advantages of internalizing information are so overwhelming that almost every facet of economic organization takes this internalization for granted.
In Chapter 6 recontracting was identied as one of the important characteristics of perfect competition. Recontracting means that buyers and sellers continue negotiating until their plans have been completely harmonized, and only then does trade proceed. However, negotiation takes time, and it is unreasonable to assume that the economy can remain in suspended animation following a disturbance until all trading plans have been renegotiated. If trading continues after the disturbance and before renegotiation can be completed, then disequilibrium will ensue. Transactors on one side or other of the market will face quantity rationing; either buyers will be unable to purchase as much as they demand or sellers will be unable to dispose of all their supplies. Transactors inability to full trading plans in one market will force them to modify their plans in other markets. Indeed, because a rational individual formulates an integrated trading plan covering all markets, failure to full the plan in one market is likely to have repurcussions in all other markets in which he is involved. The consequences of continuing to trade without renegotiation are perfectly foreseeable. It is to be expected that an entrepreneurial response will be forthcoming. The obvious response is for a market-making rm to hold an inventory of the good in order to buffer uctuations in demand and supply. An exogenous increase in demand, or a reduction in supply, is accommodated by running down the inventory. A reduction in demand or an increase in supply leads to a build-up of inventory. While inventory is benecial in buffering uctuations in trade, it is not without its costs to the rm. These include the opportunity cost of the storage facilities required to keep the inventory in good condition and the additional cost incurred in moving the inventory to and from the store rather than directly from the buyer to the seller. These costs are likely to be higher the more perishable is the good and the more difcult it is to transport. Another major component of cost is the opportunity cost of postponing demand. Inventory normally has to be kept idle because only then is it immediately available for supply. Putting a good into inventory therefore
135
136
The market-making rm
delays the use of it. This incurs a cost to buyers who are impatient to consume it and to people who could use it in the meantime to produce something of greater value. This is reected in the interest cost of nancing inventory. As the size of inventory is increased, so the benet conferred by the marginal unit of inventory diminishes and its cost increases; the point of equality between benet and cost determines the optimal inventory level. Two kinds of inventory investment may now be distinguished. Unplanned inventory investment is the net investment undertaken to accommodate uctuations in supply and demand. It is positive when supply unexpectedly exceeds demand and goods are taken into stock; it is negative when demand unexpectedly exceeds supply and the stock has to be run down. Planned inventory investment is the net investment undertaken to restore inventory to its target level. Planned investment is positive when inventory is too low and has to be augmented, and is negative when it is too high and has to be run down. The fundamental law of inventory behaviour is that planned investment is undertaken in response to the unplanned investment that has occurred since the last planned investment decision was undertaken. Each time planned investment is undertaken, it is with the object of returning the inventory to its target level. If there are lags in implementing investment plans, then further unplanned investment may occur before the investment is effected, in which case the target level may not actually be realized. If there are no lags, then inventory will return to its target level and remain there until the next disturbance occurs. Most models of inventory systems present a partial analysis of the wholesale and retail distribution of goods produced under constant costs. They emphasize the way that economies of lot size inuence the frequency of inventory adjustment and the target level of inventory. Such models are inappropriate to a general analysis of the role of inventories in market making as a whole. The reason is that they fail to stress the interplay between inventory control and pricing policy. Consider a market-making rm whose inventory has fallen below target level as a result of an unexpected shortfall in supply. It believes that, apart from price effects, uctuations in demand and supply are uncorrelated and serially independent. It therefore regards the disturbance in supply as purely random, and so its expectations of demand and supply for the next period remain unchanged. Its planned inventory investment, however, now constitutes a component of the next periods demand. Its expectation of total demand has therefore increased relative to its expectation of supply. The only mechanism by which inventory plans can be realized is the attainment of a new equilibrium at a higher price. The market maker must therefore increase
Speculative intermediation
137
his buying price and his selling price. Higher prices increase expected supply and reduce expected demand, creating a gap which can be lled by inventory investment. This case illustrates the general proposition that, for a marketmaking rm, price adjustment is the instrument of inventory adjustment.
9.2
The previous section considered how the failure to recontract inuences the provision of market-making services. This section considers the related issue of how the prohibitive cost of making some forward markets inuences the quality of service in the corresponding spot markets. It was argued above that recontracting was undesirable because it delayed the completion of transactions. The only way to avoid delay would be to speed up negotiations to the point where communication costs become prohibitive. It is apparent, therefore, that the time dimension in recontracting is crucial. There is one situation in which there is ample time for renegotiation, and this is when transactors are trading forward claims. Since transactors are planning their trades well ahead, there is time to haggle over the price. Forward claims are useful to households because they are a method of ensuring future supplies of consumption and future demand for labour services. They benet rms, too, for, given the lags in the production system, they enable current decisions to be made so that the future outputs of the different rms are compatible with each other and with household requirements. They are particularly useful in intermediate product markets, where they help to reconcile the output plans of the suppliers with the input plans of the users. For reasons already discussed, forward markets are difcult to operate. Where the user services of durable goods are concerned, forward claims can be established by buying up durable goods in the spot market. Where longterm forward claims on other goods and services are concerned, the costs of making markets in individual claims mean that individuals are often obliged to follow a two-stage procedure. The procedure involves purchasing an asset in a spot market and reselling it later in exchange for a spot acquisition of the good they require. To reduce the administrative cost of resale, it is desirable to hold an asset in which there is a ready secondhand market. To reduce uncertainty about the future spot rate of exchange between the asset and the good, it is desirable to hold an asset whose value is relatively stable in terms of a representative good. The most suitable type of claim is usually corporate debenture: that is, long-term unconditional transferable corporate debt. Neither of these strategies, however, is satisfactory in establishing shortterm forward claims on newly produced or perishable goods. In the absence
138
The market-making rm
of any substitute for such claims, transactors would experience considerable uncertainty when planning ahead. Where intermediate products are concerned, the problem can often be solved by internalization. The buying rm and the selling rm can be merged into a single rm and the problem of enforcing forward contracts largely eliminated. But this strategy is not so readily applicable to households wishing to procure supplies of nal products from other households or rms. Nor does it apply to households selling factor services to other households or to rms. The household is not normally a large enough economic unit to warrant acquiring a rm outright just to provide employment for its factors, and certainly not just to secure supplies of one of its consumption goods. Economies of scale in production usually require rms to combine the factor services of several households and to sell their nal products to a great many more. The potential failure of markets in short-term claims for factor services and nal products has generated an entrepreneurial response which is reected in the way that spot markets are organized. Market-making rms have evolved a system of quoting spot prices which are fairly stable in the short term. This provides price certainty for transactors and so facilitates efcient forward planning. However, the commitment to price stability reduces the market-makers ability to adjust supply to demand through price adjustment. It should be apparent that it also nullies the main instrument of inventory adjustment. The greater the price stability, the lower is the frequency of price adjustment and the more difcult it is to maintain inventory close to its target level. The market maker can respond in one of two ways. He can either increase the target inventory to accommodate wider uctuations in inventory level or he can increase the risk that he will go out of stock.
9.3
Naturally, buyers would rather that a market maker did not go out of stock. If there is no other convenient source of supply, then their plans are frustrated and their welfare reduced. Even if other sources are available, they have wasted resources making contact with the particular market maker involved. If the market maker is out of stock, then buyers will prefer the delay in service to be kept to a minimum. However, given the constraint on price revision, the overall excess demand cannot be controlled. Thus servicing one buyer quickly means more delay in servicing someone else. Some demand will be transitory and if not fullled will disappear again. But permanent unlled demands will cumulate, and the market maker must
Speculative intermediation
139
determine in what order he will ll these demands when supplies become available. The simplest strategy is for the market maker to allow the customers to decide for themselves by asking them to call back. If stock is available, then they will be served; otherwise, they must keep returning until they are successful. Those who call back most frequently stand the best chance of being served rst. This strategy means that the market maker must deal with many requests that he cannot full, but it avoids the administrative cost of recording customers wants. If he decides to record wants, however, he is in a position to establish priorities between customers. The simplest system of priorities is that the rst to order is the rst to be served. But this simple system is not necessarily the most efcient. It must be recognized that some buyers demands may be more urgent than others. These buyers will attach a high value to priority service. Where there are two distinct categories of demand, one urgent and the other not, it is to the market makers advantage to distinguish between them if he can. The idea is to create two categories of customer: the priority customer and the stand-by customer. Whenever there is rationing, priority customers are served before stand-by customers. Priority will be bought by those whose demands are most urgent and who therefore value the risk of delay most highly. The proceeds of the sale of priority enhance the market makers prots. Priorities may be allocated either before or after rationing has occurred. To allocate priority in advance is equivalent to creating a forward market in quality of service. Given the market-making costs involved, it might seem preferable to allocate priority on the spot once rationing has occurred. It is possible, though, that many people may take offence at this improvisation of rationing arrangements. It may appear that the market maker is reneging on his original undertaking to supply at a xed price. Indeed, he is increasing his price at the very time that his overall quality of service has deteriorated. As a result, buyers may withdraw their demand in protest. Although this may not affect the market maker in the short run, because by assumption there is excess demand, it may affect him quite severely in the long run, when buyers as a whole seek out an alternative market maker instead. It appears, therefore, that if priorities are to be allocated, they should be allocated at the outset. To reduce the cost of creating the forward market, it is possible to use implicit contracts, which are informal understandings backed by social sanctions, rather than formal contracts backed by the law. In a typical case, the market maker announces that customers who trade with him regularly and perhaps exclusively can acquire priority over occasional customers. Those who demand priority are then obliged to trade regularly with the market maker. Regular trade is less costly for the market maker to administer than is occasional trade, because costs of contact making are
140
The market-making rm
incurred only once irrespective of how often trade is repeated. This saving is passed on to the regular customer not by discounting the price but by offering priority of service instead. It does not follow, of course, that all regular customers want priority of service, or that those who want priority make the most suitable regular customers. This is the price that has to be paid when priority is bartered for rather than sold outright.
9.4
Trade is not a purely economic activity but a social one as well. Trade involves communication between two people: they must make contact, exchange information about product specication and negotiate a price. Some people are more pleasant to communicate with than others. Communication can increase personal welfare as well as trade itself. A chat with a cheery pub landlord may be some compensation for a poor pint of beer. Because of this, the provision of personal service, and the selection of suitable people to provide it, is often a strong element in non-price competition between market makers. Because trade is a social activity, social conventions restrict the way that it is conducted. Social convention is the aspect of a culture that relates to the behaviour of people towards each other. Social convention tends to be selfpolicing, in the sense that each individual feels personally responsible for punishing deviations from convention. If one of the parties conducts trade in a manner that outs convention, then the other parties will punish him by breaking off trading relations with him. The pleasure that they obtain from punishing the offence outweighs any harm that they may do to themselves in the process. Social convention affects the way in which trade is set up, the terms of the contract, and even the type of goods in which trade is permissible. In setting up a trade, convention may demand that the parties exchange small talk and gossip, and perhaps that one of them should offer hospitality to the other, which then has to be reciprocated. Convention lends structure to negotiations by indicating who should make the rst offer, how many rounds of negotiations are allowed and what sort of threats it is acceptable to make in order to extract concessions from the other party. Convention may also restrict the terms of the contract. It may dictate that certain goods and services must be offered free, as it would be demeaning for the seller to charge for them, and for the buyer to pay for them. It may outlaw the offering of, or the soliciting of, certain services, whether or not payment is made for them. Respect for convention is vital to the success of market making. The market maker is particularly vulnerable to social sanctions as his activities
Speculative intermediation
141
tend to be very public, and therefore easily scrutinized, and he earns his living exclusively by intermediating trade. It is also generally recognized that market makers are opportunists, and that there is not always a very close relation between the market makers margin and the cost of setting up a trade. Competition from new entrants may establish a fair margin in the long run but there is no guarantee of this in the short run. There is no doubt that many cultures are opposed to opportunism, which is seen as making a prot out of the potential misfortunes of others. Opportunists are tolerated because of the services they provide. But opportunists who overstep the mark may have to be punished. Sometimes the punishment is conned to individual market makers: transactors simply switch to competing market makers instead. At other times market makers as a group are punished by the introduction of restrictive legislation, or special taxes, to outlaw, or to compensate for, alleged abuses of market power. The need for the market maker to conform may be a factor motivating the provision of some of the market-making services discussed above. It must be recognized that people are by no means unanimous in supporting the use of price as an allocator of resources. They may concede that price adjustment is necessary in the long run to prevent serious bottlenecks and shortages, but may be hostile towards short-run price adjustments. These may be regarded as evidence of opportunism by the market-maker. If such attitudes are common, the prudent market maker may forgo short-run price adjustment in order to retain the goodwill of his customers. Another sensitive area is the use of price to allocate priorities when goods are out of stock. It has already been shown how the market maker can to some extent disguise the use of price by giving priority to regular customers over occasional ones. The disguise works because of the similarity to the principle of looking after ones friends (that is, regular customers) rst. While the use of price may be socially unacceptable, there is normally no objection to giving priority to ones friends. In some cases, however, social convention may be very strict indeed. For example, queue-jumping of any kind may simply not be tolerated, so that the prudent market maker has no option but to deal with all orders in strict rotation. Alternatively, the market maker may be expected to discriminate between orders on the basis of need. In the context of rationing, need is related to the urgency of demand. But the principle of need usually prohibits the use of price to reveal the urgency of demand. The market maker cannot sell priorities but must confer them freely, using his own assessment of the situation. He may have to do this, even though he knows his own assessments are quite arbitrary, merely to conform with convention.
142
The market-making rm
9.5
It has been shown that, because of the difculty of recontracting, market makers are obliged to hold inventory in order to intermediate transactions. The inventory enables the market maker to offer on demand service to his customers. The market maker needs in fact to hold two inventories, one of the product and the other of payment. The inventory of the product is necessary to facilitate immediate supply of unforeseen orders. The inventory of the payment is necessary to take up unforeseen offers of supply. The need for inventories increases the amount of risk capital required by the entrepreneur and thereby makes it more likely that market-making entrepreneurship will be constrained by personal wealth. Although the constraint can be relaxed by borrowing, the strategic problems involved in nding backers, described above, mean that capital requirements may be a substantial barrier to entry into market making when inventory requirements are large. This situation may be contrasted with the analysis of intermediation in Chapter 3, which was based upon the implicit assumption that recontracting was possible. The intermediator C contracted separately with his partners A and B, but his contract with A was not conrmed until his negotiations with B were complete, and vice versa. Consequently, there was no risk that he would buy from A and then be unable to resell to B. Conversely, there was no risk that he would agree to sell to B and then be unable to obtain supplies from A. If recontracting had been ruled out, then the intermediator would have required an initial endowment of each commodity large enough to cover his proposed sale to each party. He would be exposed to the risk that, if one of the negotiations broke down, then his own consumption would become extremely unbalanced. He would be forced to consume the goods that he had bought from one party in the expectation of resale to the other, and would have to forgo consumption of the goods he expected to obtain from that party in exchange. Thus his initial endowments would constrain his ability to trade, while the risk that one of the transactions would break down and the other go through would reduce the incentive to intermediate in the rst place.
9.6
The need for inventory emphasizes that market making is a speculative activity. The market makers judgment is that there is a gap in the range of market-making services currently on offer to transactors. As a result, poten-
Speculative intermediation
143
tial trades are not taking place. By providing additional market-making services, the obstacles to trade can be overcome, and a prot stream generated from intermediating a series of trades. Speculation occurs when resources are committed to backing ones judgment against that of others. If market-making costs were incurred as and when intermediation is effected, then intermediation would not be speculative, but, in practice, many market-making costs are set-up costs which have to be incurred before any trade can take place. This is certainly true of the costs of market making identied in Chapter 6. Inventory costs are the most obvious example of set-up costs, however. Quality of service depends upon inventory being available before trade begins. The market maker therefore has to back his judgment from the outset by investing in inventory. If his judgment is incorrect and there is no market for the good, then his inventory will almost certainly be worth less than he paid for it, and a capital loss will be sustained. Speculation is concerned not only with whether to invest in inventory of a certain type, but also with how much to invest, and in particular with how much to hold at any one time. If the market maker expects demand to move towards a steady state, then the long-term level of inventory required is determined by the quality of service he intends to offer. The larger the inventory relative to the variability of demand, the lower the probability of stock-out. Although transactors may not know precisely what the market makers level of inventory is, they should be able to assess from experience of repeat-trading (or from his reputation) what the probability of stock-out is. The market maker faces not only a demand for the product but also a demand for each service that goes with it. Implicitly, there is a price for the product itself and another price for availability from stock. If he can estimate the intensities of these demands, then, given his cost of inventory and the relation between inventory level and stock-out probability, the market maker can deduce the prot-maximizing stock-out probability and the associated long-term inventory level. This inventory level then informs his initial speculative investment in stock. The market maker may anticipate that, in addition, there will be systematic variations about the trend growth of demand, or about its subsequent steadystate level. He can exploit systematic variations by varying the amount of inventory held over from one period to the next. If, for example, he believes that supplies will be very scarce in the following period, then current planned inventory investment will be increased and at the same time planned inventory investment for the following period reduced. The market maker thereby prots by buying cheap now in order to sell dear later. If the market makers expectations are correct, then price uctuations will be smoothed out as a result. On the other hand, if his expectations are incorrect, or if his own plans
144
The market-making rm
are swamped by those of ill-informed imitators who drive the current price too high, then the price uctuations will have been amplied instead. It is interesting to note that the market makers ability to exploit systematic variations in demand or supply may be constrained by his commitment to short-term price stability. As a market maker, one of his functions is to quote prices, and to retain goodwill he may have to adhere to these prices for some time. Since price adjustment is the main mechanism of inventory control, he cannot take up speculative positions with respect to price uctuations within this period. Thus if, for example, prices can only be adjusted annually, then systematic uctuations with a frequency of less than a year cannot be exploited for speculative purposes. If there are systematic variations in the market, then the market maker may not be the only one to recognize them. Certainly, the market maker is in the best position to observe them, which is a point that will be developed later on. If he were to exploit them intelligently through short-term speculation, then it is possible that they would go unnoticed by other transactors. But if he is constrained in his speculative activity, then other transactors may recognize the symptoms of disequilibrium and decide to speculate instead. The symptom of disequilibrium is that the market maker goes out of stock. When this occurs, a speculator could sell his inventory at above the market makers quoted price to those who are impatient for supplies. When there are systematic variations, the speculators can predict when the market maker is most likely to go out of stock. Shortly before this time they purchase stock, causing the market maker to go out of stock earlier than he would, as inventory is transferred from the market maker into speculative hands. It is obvious that this situation is intolerable to the market maker. He can attempt to reduce the probability of stock-out by increasing his inventory to a level which is safe given any systematic variation of demand. This means that, if speculators do manage to buy up sufcient inventory to put him out of stock, their supplies will be so large compared to the frustrated demand that no premium can be charged. However, the cost of maintaining this level of inventory is likely to be very high. Under the circumstances, the market maker may be obliged to adjust price more frequently than convention suggests, notwithstanding the loss of goodwill involved. It might be asked why the speculators themselves are not outlawed for outing social convention. The short answer is that they are not established market makers, with a reputation to lose, but casual dealers exploiting an occasional opportunity. In fact, their activities are constrained by the fact that their market-making techniques are very primitive, as bets the small-scale casual nature of their trade. They are the y-by-night operators, the wide boys, of the entrepreneurial world. They operate under the price umbrella of the established market maker. They can be tolerated by him so long as they
Speculative intermediation
145
do not disturb too greatly the x-price equilibrium that he maintains by inventory adjustment. But if their activities become too great a nuisance, then the established market maker will have to change his operations in order to drive them out of the market.
SUMMARY
This chapter has shown that when recontracting is difcult, the market maker must respond by holding inventory. In calculating his target inventory the market maker must take account of constraints imposed by commitments on price stability made to customers and suppliers. He must also consider the disruption to customers plans which results when he is out of stock, and the consequent loss of goodwill that he incurs. Loss of goodwill could in principle be reduced by operating an efcient system of priorities, though in practice an efcient system may actually lose more goodwill if it outs social convention. The constraints imposed by commitments to price stability and to inefcient priorities both imply that the target level of inventory must be increased. This inventory has to be nanced somehow. Because of the judgmental nature of market making, nancial backers may not value the inventory as highly as the market maker, and so the inventory may be regarded as poor security for a loan. It follows that, for market makers with little personal wealth, the nancing of inventory may constitute a serious barrier to entry.
In Chapter 6, six main market-making activities were distinguished. To these can now be added two more, which were identied in Chapter 9: inventory holding (to provide on-demand service) and the provision of personal attention, as demanded by social convention. This chapter considers why a single market maker would wish to undertake all of these activities himself. Why do different market makers not operate in the same market, each specializing in one of these particular activities? Why does a single market maker emerge who packages all of the services together? The simplest answer is that a single entrepreneur has the initial idea of creating the market, and to protect his secret idea he will not want to involve other rms in any of the related activities. However, this only explains why one rm will package together all the activities at the outset. As the market expands, and competitors enter, the advantages of specialization may begin to reveal themselves. Some entrants may specialize in one market-making activity and others in another, allowing buyers to customize their procurement of market-making services. The obvious explanation of why market-making services are packaged on a recurrent basis is that packaging substantially reduces overall transaction costs. If the separate services were not packaged together, then each buyer and seller would have to negotiate individually for each of the specialist services. Without a packager, each buyer and seller would need to be paired up with a supplier of each of the services. With a packager, each buyer and seller is paired only with the packager, and the suppliers of the services are paired only with the packager too. A major component of market-making cost is associated simply with the pairing of transactors, and is independent of the number and size of the transactions which each pair subsequently effects. Thus, by reducing the number of different pairings, the packaging of market-making services offers potentially large savings in market-making costs.
146
147
10.2
It is important to consider how the package of market-making services is priced. Experience suggests that, in many markets, buyers pay only for market-making services if the transaction is successful. The explanation lies in yet another service that the market maker supplies to his transactors. This is insurance against the risk that the transaction will break down. Essentially, the market maker insures the transactor against the risk that the payments he would normally have made for market-making services will be incurred in vain. The market maker is therefore supplying insurance against market entry risk: the risk that the transactor faces when he commits resources to entering a market in pursuit of a trade. The natural explanation is that the market maker is relatively optimistic about the opportunities for creating trade, which is why he has taken a speculative position in entering, or even creating, the market. The customer has no particular reason to be optimistic, and so it is sensible for the market maker to bet with the customer about whether he will eventually make a trade. The market maker encourages the customer to enter the market and if he is correct then the customer will trade at a price which provides the intermediator with a margin that covers not only his market-making expenses but also a payment for winning the bet. To increase his chances of winning the bet, the market maker needs to maximize his opportunity to persuade the customer to change his attitude to the product. This persuasion can be effected at the contact-making stage through the projection of an appropriate image of the market maker, at the product specication stage, by communicating an alluring description of the products attributes, and at the negotiation stage by, for example, attering the customers ego in making him think that he has negotiated a bargain for himself. This argument suggests that there may be a fairly close association between the provision of free market-making services and the potential for impulse buying of the product. The level of provision will of course reect other factors too in particular, the severity of the obstacles to trade that have to be overcome. The hypothesis is that the degree of overprovision of services relative to the obstacles involved will reect the market makers perceptions of buyer attitudes. The more buyers are believed to be vulnerable to persuasion, the greater will be the inducements offered to them to enter the market.
148
The market-making rm
10.3
Nine market-making activities have now been identied: they are shown in the left-hand column of Table 10.1. This section considers to what extent the markets in these services should be internalized by the market maker. The analysis focuses upon the market for a differentiated product which has to be distributed to buyers in different locations. The intermediator purchases the product from a producer who provides the technological know-how required for its production. Table 10.1 Market-making activities and their most suitable contractual arrangements Appropriate contractual arrangement Delegate to retailer Integrate with producer Internalize in hands of employees Delegate to transport rms Integrate quality control with producer Delegate monitoring of distribution to retailer Delegate to legal rms and the state Delegate front-end inventory to retailer Integrate back-up inventory with producer Delegate to retailer Delegate (where possible) to nancial backers
Market-making activity Contact making Product specication Negotiation Exchange of custody Monitoring Enforcement Inventory holding Personal attention Insurance of transactor
It is assumed that the market maker has established a rm and is condent of his arrangements for delegating tasks to his own employees. The issue is whether the market-making services should be provided by his own rm or by other rms. The advantage of employing other rms is that they may have internal access to skills which his rm does not possess. The disadvantage is that there are costs of establishing arms-length contracts with the other rms. Internalization is efcient only if the cost of establishing contracts exceeds the gains from specialization between rms. There are some activities in which the case for internalization is practically overwhelming, and there is little point in analysing these in detail. It is extremely dangerous, for example, to delegate negotiation to someone else unless they can be maintained under the same close supervision as can an employee. The same applies to product specication and to monitoring.
149
There are other cases in which internalization is almost certainly undesirable. For example, the transport services required for exchange of custody are provided by the utilization of vehicles in which there are often major economies of scale. The existence of economies of scale creates a strong incentive to hire transport services from specialist rms. The only case in which internalization of transport may be advantageous is if there is a large volume of regular trade with some particular customer (or neighbouring group of customers). Under these conditions it may be possible for the market maker to keep a large vehicle fully employed carrying only his own trafc. However, where only a small eet of vehicles is involved, there remains the problem of coping with unforeseen breakdowns and so on and, where very small eets are concerned, there may even be problems in replacing vehicles during their regular maintenance. It appears, therefore, that unless there is a large volume of regular trade between the intermediator and a geographically concentrated group of customers, internalization of transport services is unlikely to be efcient. Another market that it is difcult to internalize is the market for enforcement services, that is the market for lawyers, bailiffs, policemen and so on. Services of this kind are highly specialized and it would need a large volume of trade to warrant full-time employment of specialist personnel. Indeed, unless the market maker is a specialist himself, he is unlikely to know whether a specialist is really necessary, and if so what kind of specialist is required and for how long he will need to be employed. Under these conditions it makes sense for the intermediator not to recruit the specialist as an employee, but to buy the specialist services from a market maker in these services, who will give a price quotation and guarantee the quality of the services supplied. In other words, it is efcient not to internalize the market, but to buy enforcement services at arms length from specialist suppliers.
10.4
So far it has been implicitly assumed that the producer and the market maker are two distinct people, connected by arms-length trade in which the producer sells the product to the market maker, who assumes responsibility for its distribution to the nal users. The rationale for this functional specialization is that the producer has technical skill but lacks a knowledge of the market, while the market maker has a knowledge of the market, but lacks the producers technical skill. In principle the arms-length trade effects a separation of responsibilities, whereby the producer bears the risks associated with production and the
150
The market-making rm
market maker bears the risks associated with uncertain market prospects. But in practice the separation of risks is not quite so simple as this. There are at least two cases in which problems encountered in production may spill over to cause problems for the market maker. And there is at least one case in which the technical ignorance of the market maker may pose problems for the producer. Each spillover is concerned with a particular market-making activity. To begin with, consider product specication. As noted earlier, the specication usually emphasizes the products functions: claims are made for what the product will do. In the case of multi-purpose goods, considerable emphasis may be laid upon versatility in use. The market maker will wish to retain responsibility for communicating the product specication to the customers: it is after all a vital element in the contract of sale between them. But the specication reects the design of the product. In many cases, in order to know what the product can do it is necessary to know how it was designed and made. This knowledge resides with the producer rather than the market maker. If the market makers ignorance leads him to make exaggerated claims for the product, then the product may acquire an unjustiably bad reputation. If, on the other hand, the market maker makes too modest claims for the product, then potential demand may remain unlled. In either case, not only the market makers sales will suffer, but the producers too. To minimize these risks, the producer needs to vet the specication that is communicated to the customers. He still needs the market makers expertise to formulate a message that the customers can easily understand, and to ensure that it is broadcast to the right people, but he needs more control over the market maker than he can achieve simply through arms-length sale of the product. Another major spillover arises with quality control. Here the boot is on the other foot: the producer makes mistakes but it is the market maker that may suffer. When the customer buys from the market maker he demands an assurance of quality. Quality means that the product performs in accordance with specication, that is it is t for the purposes intended. There are three aspects to the assurance: rst, that the probability of being supplied with a defective item is small; secondly, that, should a defective item be supplied, a replacement will be readily available; and nally that compensation for damage caused by use of the faulty item will be forthcoming. The question of compensation will normally be covered in the contract of sale. Given the market makers liability, the only questions concern his ability to meet his obligations and this depends mainly upon his wealth. His ability to supply replacements will be determined by his inventory policy, which is discussed later in this section.
151
So far as the rst aspect of the assurance is concerned the improbability of a defective item being supplied in the rst place the market maker is essentially underwriting the quality that has been attained by the producer. The market maker cannot afford to underwrite quality unless he is condent of it himself. Thus, wherever possible, he will wish to screen the supplies of the product for himself. It must be recognized, however, that for many goods it is easier to check quality during production than it is once production is complete. Information about quality is a joint product of the production process itself. Monitoring the act of production itself often provides information which can only be obtained at the end by taking the product apart again. Efcient quality control implies that information from monitoring is used in the evaluation of quality. Since the producer almost certainly has information of this kind, it is important that this information is not wasted. This analysis suggests that it is the producer, rather than the market maker, who should undertake quality control. But this depends upon the market maker having condence in the producer. If he does not, he will need to check the producers own quality controls, resulting in a wasteful duplication of effort. The alternative is for the market maker to monitor production. This implies that he has access to the producers premises, and that he has sufcient technical know-how to understand what he should be looking for. This strategy is likely to work only for production by a widely-known technique. The fact that it is widely known means that the producer has no technical secrets to protect, and so is willing to admit an external monitor to his premises. It also means that a monitor employed by the market maker can readily acquire the skills needed for the job. This suggests that, whenever production involves trade secrets, the producer will wish to assume quality control, and take over one of the market makers functions for himself. Alternatively, the market maker will need to buy the trade secret from the producer in order to gain permission to monitor; in practice this means that the market maker will buy out the producer altogether. A third area of spillover is concerned with inventory policy. One of the market makers responsibilities is to provide quality of service by maintaining an adequate inventory. Once again this is a key function that he will be reluctant to contract out. The inventory level required for a given quality of service depends not only upon the variability of customers demands, but also upon the producers policy of supply. If supply is erratic owing to frequent breakdowns in production, for example, then the market maker is obliged to hold a larger inventory. If the producer reduces transport costs by bulking his deliveries to the market maker, then deliveries to the market maker become less frequent and once again the market makers inventory requirement is increased. Finally, if the producer takes a long time to respond to orders
152
The market-making rm
placed by the market maker, then the market maker is exposed to a greater risk of stock-out from any given uctuation in demand. Rather ironically, every time the producers quality of service to the market maker deteriorates, the market makers target inventory level has to be increased to maintain the safety margin in servicing demand, and so he has to place additional orders with the producer. Thus, in the short run at least, poorer service by the producer leads to higher sales to the market maker. It is apparent that a straightforward arms-length sale from producer to market maker does not encourage efcient distribution of the product. It discourages the producer from making his own inventory readily available to the market maker should the market makers inventory be suddenly depleted. It also discourages the producer from rescheduling production should his own inventory, as well as that of the market maker, become depleted. He has some incentive to reschedule production, but not as great an incentive as the market maker would prefer. In principle the problems of harmonizing production and inventory policies could be overcome using a spectrum of forward claims with different prices for claims of different maturities. In practice, these forward markets are best internalized by bringing production and inventory holding under common control. It has already been shown that problems of inventory control are most acute for products whose demand is highly variable, particularly those where the speculative element is strong. The problems of harmonizing inventory with production are particularly great when there are long lags in the production process, and where there are signicant economies in bulk distribution. Thus there are strong grounds for internalizing product supply when the product has a variable or speculative demand, a long production lag and economies of bulk distribution.
10.5
One of the major weaknesses of conventional economic theory is the scant attention it pays to the spatial dimension of economic activity. Indeed, the theory of entrepreneurship discussed above could be condemned on rather similar grounds. Some attention has been paid to the inuence of transport costs on the economics of bulk trading, and consideration has been given to the spatial distribution of information sources, but that is about all. However, the spatial dimension is of crucial importance when analysing the internalization of contact making and inventory holding. In a spaceless economy where all transactors were concentrated at a single point, the market maker would almost certainly wish to internalize contact
153
making and inventory holding. Like most other market-making activities, they are so crucial to his enterprise that he would be reluctant to delegate them to anyone other than an employee. But many products have a worldwide market. The world is a big place, and it is asking a lot of a customer to make contact with a single worldwide sales point and to accept distribution from a single inventory store. So far as the customer is concerned, quality of service is inversely related to distance. Where contact making is concerned, it is partly geographical distance and partly psychic distance that counts. Geographical distance matters because charges for the use of communication channels (post, telecommunications and so on) normally increase with distance, though not in direct proportion to it. This system of charges by the communications utilities makes economic sense, for in a communication network a long-distance communication not only uses up more energy but typically travels through more different nodes along its route and so incurs higher congestion costs. Psychic distance is a measure of the difference between the language and culture of the place from which the message originates and the language and culture of the place in which the message is received. The greater the psychic distance, the greater the probability that the message will be misunderstood or, alternatively, the greater the cost of ensuring that it will be understood properly. As noted earlier, market makers try to make contact as easy as possible for the customer, but the further away the customer is, the more difcult this becomes. Not only does the cost of contact making rise but the market makers ability to subsidize the customer is reduced. For example, the market maker may be able to arrange with his local telephone company to offer tollfree dialling (that is, freephone facilities) but it may be difcult to extend this privilege to calls originating in other telephone companies areas (for example, international calls). As a result the distant customer, who has to pay the higher charge, also gets a smaller subsidy. It is not only ease of contact that deteriorates with distance speed of supply does too. Assuming that inventory management is perfectly efcient, the speed of supply depends upon two things: how quickly the customers order gets to the market maker, and how long it takes to transport the good to the customer. Both factors are related to distance, but since goods usually are slower to reach their destinations than messages, it is the time required for the delivery of the good that is crucial. Any movement of goods requires time for loading and unloading but, apart from that, the time required is likely to be proportional to the distance, and in this case to geographical distance alone. To improve ease of contact and speed of service, it is desirable to decentralize contact making and inventory holding. This raises the question of
154
The market-making rm
precisely where to decentralize to. The basic principles are not difcult to establish. It is desirable to locate sales ofces for contact making at key nodes on the world communications network, so that all major geographical concentrations of customers are close to one of the ofces, where closeness is understood in terms of the cost structure of the network itself. It is desirable to locate inventory stores at key nodes on the world transport network so that as many customers as possible can be served quickly and cheaply from one of the stores. It is desirable that each sales ofce has easy communication with at least one of the stores. If each ofce can get in touch with several stores, then this will contribute to the exibility of the system. This discussion has implicitly assumed that the market maker will deliver the product to the customer, but in many cases it is more convenient for the customer to collect it. This imposes a further restriction on the location of the store. Because the customer is incurring a xed cost of journeying to the store, he may wish to combine his trip with a visit to other stores. The other stores that he is most likely to be visiting are, rst, stores of perishable essentials (for example, food) and other items which have to be bought regularly, and, secondly, stores of complementary goods. The goods may be technical complements, in the sense that they are required in order to utilize the product (or the product is required to utilize the complements) or they may be taste complements, in the sense that people who like the product usually like the other goods as well. Even if the customer does not collect, he may wish to inspect the good before he sees it. Even if the good is delivered to the customer after purchase, it may still be more convenient for the customer to visit the good for inspection. In this case an inventory of inspection items must be made available at the point of contact, although the main store may be elsewhere. A sales ofce with inspection inventory is known as a showroom, and if the main store is adjacent to the showroom the premises as a whole are known as a shop. The optimal location of a showroom or shop involves a complex of factors. Some of the factors have been outlined above, but a full treatment of them lies well beyond the scope of this book. An enormous diversity of knowledge is required to locate a shop efciently. It is necessary to assess demand for a product, and relate it to the geographical residence of the probable customers. It is necessary to assess the habits of these customers where they travel to and when these habits being in turn a reection of their underlying tastes. Having ascertained where they are likely to be at various times, it is possible to make contact with them in a reasonably selective manner. It is possible to locate inspection stock at a place which can be visited with only a small adjustment to their usual itinerary, and to keep opening hours which t their daily schedule. To encourage them to visit, it may be necessary to display complementary items in the showroom, to offer staple items at discount
155
prices, or even to provide callers with a free gift. Finally, the main store must be located so as to give easy access to the transport network which serves their place of residence. It is apparent that the location of a retail outlet demands extensive local knowledge. It is unreasonable for a market maker in a worldwide market to imagine he has the geographical diversity of knowledge to site all his outlets efciently. The simplest way of obtaining the benets of this knowledge is to delegate the retail function. But to whom should the function be delegated? Even at the local level, the diversity of knowledge required to appraise alternative sites means that opinions will differ about the best location. Who is the market maker to believe? The simplest solution is to determine who is willing to back their own judgment. The market maker should nd a retail entrepreneur who is willing to put up his own nance and thereby insure the market maker against some of the costs of a mistaken location decision. Where several retail entrepreneurs are forthcoming, the most optimistic will select himself for the job by offering the most favourable terms. The actual site for the shop will therefore be chosen by the most optimistic retail entrepreneur. The delegation of the retail function involves the delegation of contact making and of inventory holding. However, it is unnecessary, and indeed probably undesirable, to delegate all inventory holding to the retailer. The retailer will normally wish to hold his own inventory in order to provide prompt service, but there is no reason why all inventory should be allocated among the retailers. Indeed, if the retailers purchase inventory outright from the market maker, then they will be unwilling to accept inventory which they have not ordered. The market maker will therefore need to hold inventory of his own and, for reasons already discussed, it is normally efcient to integrate this inventory with that of the producer. Ideally, therefore, a two-stage inventory will be held: the front-end inventory will be held by the retailer and the back-up inventory by the market-maker and the producer. The front-end inventories will be topped up on demand using the back-up inventory, and the back-up inventory will be topped up by the producer. If the market maker and producer cannot integrate their inventories, then a three-stage inventory will have to be held, with the market maker owning a separate inventory which acts as a buffer between producer and retailer.
10.6
The implication of this discussion is that market makers will often integrate into production, but delegate distribution to independent retailers. In such
156
The market-making rm
cases the distribution channel is coordinated by cooperation between two distinct types of entrepreneur: the producer/market maker and the retailer. These may be termed the producerentrepreneur and the retailerentrepreneur. The producerentrepreneur assumes responsibility for the product specication, quality control and the maintenance of a back-up inventory. The retailerentrepreneur assumes responsibility for contact making and, where appropriate, for drawing peoples attention to the product specication as well. This is a part of the personal service which the retailer is committed to provide. The retailer holds front-end inventory to provide customers with service on demand. Typically, both producer and retailer are responsible for hiring their own transport and enforcement services. The retailer normally depends upon the producers reputation for controlling the quality of the product. His own quality control is generally conned to selecting whose products he will stock. This still provides a service to the customer who does not himself know much about quality differentials between different brands of product. The splitting up of the entrepreneurial function is not without its difculties. These difculties show up in the contractual relations between producer and retailer. It is extremely difcult to devise a simple contractual relationship which affords appropriate incentives to both parties. In practice the most common arrangement seems to be for retailers to purchase goods outright from the producer at a discount on the recommended retail price. The recommended retail price is xed by the producer, and is the price announced by him in media advertising of the product specication. The reason why the retailer purchases the product outright is fairly clear. He has physical custody of the product, and the producer will be reluctant to part with custody without receiving payment because of the risk of default. The discount principle, too, has a fairly simple rationale. It is a reasonable assumption that the retailers efciency in contact making and so on will be reected in the volume of his sales. When delegating the retail function the producer will therefore wish to relate the retailers reward to the volume of his sales. The simplest way of doing this is to offer the retailer a trade discount on each unit sold. The factors inuencing the level of discount are more complex. In principle, the level of discount should reect the amount of responsibility assumed by the retailer. For example, if the producer does little more than formulate the product specication and relies upon local publicity initiated by the retailer to promote product sales, then the retailer will expect a fairly generous discount to cover his advertising costs. If, on the other hand, the producer mounts a worldwide advertising campaign announcing the product specication, then the retailers responsibility for generating sales is correspondingly diminished, and the discount should be lower. The discount should also be
157
reduced if the producer offers certain privleges to the retailer, such as supply on a sale-or-return basis. It should be increased if the producer imposes constraints upon the retailer. One of the most common constraints used to be resale price maintenance, though this is now illegal in many countries. Perhaps the most problematic inuence on the discount is the quality of service the producer offers the retailer, in terms of the speed and reliability with which orders are fullled. Experience suggests that the adequacy of this service is perceived rather differently by producer and retailer. Producers feel that retailers should hold more inventory in order to reduce the incidence of rush orders, while retailers feel that producers should respond to rush orders more promptly. Because of their geographical separation, neither is in a good position to monitor the others activities, and thereby acquire an understanding of the others problems. It is mainly for this reason that conicts arise in producerretailer relations and make these relations the weakest link in the channel of distribution described above.
SUMMARY
This chapter has considered the contractual arrangements which prevail in the supply of market-making services to buyers and sellers. It is shown that these services will normally be packaged by a market maker and sold to the buyers and sellers on a no trade no charge basis. The provision of services on this basis helps to insure the buyers and sellers against the risk of incurring substantial costs in entering the market and then being unable to trade. The market-making function is typically divided between a producer and a retailer. The producer determines the product specication using his technical knowledge, and guarantees the quality (on the grounds that the supervisor of production is in the best position to carry out quality control). The retailer is primarily responsible for contact making and for holding inventory, which is particularly important for inspection goods, and for goods which customers prefer to collect on the spot for themselves. Both producer and retailer retain their own responsibility for negotiation and delegate most of the remaining activities to specialists. The discussion illustrates how very impure the entrepreneurial function becomes in practice. Both producers and retailers are entrepreneurs, though they combine their entrepreneurial activities with many routine activities as well. The specialist suppliers of legal, transport and nancial services are entrepreneurs too, in so far as they are making judgmental decisions about making a market in services to be supplied to other market makers.
158
The market-making rm
PART III
Synthesis
The rm is a unit of control. As such it is not very different from a household. Households control the uses of the goods they own in much the same way as do rms, albeit on a smaller scale. Why, then, are the activities of a rm not performed simply as an extension of the activities of a household? Why create a separate legal entity which can enter into contracts in its own right, quite apart from any contracts which have been entered into by the individuals who own the rm? One obvious reason is that rms enjoy certain legal privileges which households do not. A person who buys in order to resell may register (or incorporate) himself as a rm and thereby become entitled to set expenditures against tax, limit his personal liability for commitments entered into in the course of trade, and so on. The actual privileges acquired depend upon the form of incorporation that is chosen. A rm does not need to buy exactly the same things that it sells in order to qualify for these privileges it is sufcient that the expenditures are on inputs which are necessary in order to produce the output. It is worth noting, though, that members of a household must purchase inputs of food, shelter and so on, to maintain themselves in good health so that they can sell their labour services. However, the need for subsistence in order to maintain the stock of labour is not normally considered an adequate basis for the household to claim the privileges of a rm. Tax law normally provides for subsistence inputs by giving individuals a xed personal allowance against tax liability. To qualify as a rm, the household must do more than look after the personal needs of its members; it must buy inputs with the express purpose of reselling them, or transforming them in some way, in order to meet the needs of others. The other main reason why rms are distinguished from households is concerned with the capital structure of the rm. The capital structure allows different households to share in the ownership of the same rm. It also allows households to specialize in bearing the different kinds of risk incurred by the rm, by holding the different types of equity and debt it issues. The risks incurred by the rm stem in part from production, but chiey from market making. Production risk is incurred when the output generated
161
162
Synthesis
by a given input is dependent upon an uncertain state of nature. A typical production risk is that bad weather will ruin a harvest, or that machinery will unexpectedly break down. Market-making risk arises because the rm insures the buyers of its output and to some extent the sellers of its inputs too against the costs of entering the market. It supplies market-making services which the transactor pays for only if trade is effected. In the absence of forward markets, the rm is constrained to buy and sell at quoted prices which are xed in the short run. In the absence of recontracting, the rm must hold an inventory of output so that buyers can be supplied on demand, and an inventory of a means of payment so that supplies can be purchased on demand. If the entrepreneurs judgment of the market situation is wrong, then he may be left with considerable unsold product inventory which can only be disposed of at a capital loss.
11.2
As noted in the previous chapter, very few rms are pure producers. Most producers integrate forward into the marketing of their product. On the other hand, many rms are pure market makers in the sense that they intermediate markets without producing the goods themselves. As market makers, they normally integrate backwards into the production of some of the marketmaking services, though other services may be produced by subcontractors instead. Typical of the pure market maker is the owner of a retail shop. The retailer shares responsibility with the producers marketing department for making contact with customers and communicating the product specication to them. He negotiates a price with the customer, subject to constraints imposed by the producer. His reputation rests largely upon the quality of his stock, which is determined by his skill in choosing suppliers who produce quality goods. In this respect he acts as a middleman, screening for quality on his customers behalf. He maintains an inventory so that he can supply his customers on demand, and when he is out of stock he rations goods in accordance with social convention. The typical retailer is very exible when deciding whether to internalize the provision of market-making services. Typically, he does most of his contact making through his own shop-window, does his own negotiation and owns the inventory in his shop. He may subcontract some contact making to the media and perhaps leave it to customers to arrange the delivery of the products to their place of residence. Alternatively, he may subcontract delivery to a transport rm; and in a few cases he will do it himself.
163
In orthodox economics, production is modelled on manufacturing. Manufacturing production involves transforming material inputs into material outputs through the utilization of multi-purpose durable goods. Labour is probably the most important example of a multi-purpose durable good. The production of market-making services does not normally involve the transformation of materials but, like manufacturing, it does involve the utilization of multipurpose goods. Labour is probably more important in market making than it is in manufacturing, though it is primarily mental labour and not manual labour that is used. The labour intensity of market making is a feature that it shares with many other service industries. An important feature of the rm is that it brings multi-purpose goods under common control. Coordination of the use of these goods is effected through internal markets (or planning) instead of through arms-length contracts in external markets. External markets are still needed, however, in order to set up the internal markets. External trade in general rights that is, in the multipurpose goods themselves is necessary in order to allow the agglomerations of multi-purpose goods to be formed. Only once these agglomerations have been formed can the internal markets be used to determine which of the specic rights inherent in each general right is to be exercised or, in other words, to determine the use to which each of the multi-purpose goods is to be put. Firms are legal entities which bid in the external markets for the multipurpose goods, and so act as the instruments by which the agglomerations are formed. The capital structure of the rms allows individuals to specialize in bearing the risks involved in the utilization of these agglomerations of goods.
11.3
The advantages of the internal market, as noted earlier, are that it avoids haggling over price and reduces the risk of default. It also facilitates the pooling of information among those involved in the market. It is possible to exercise control in an internal market using procedures which mimic the external market, by setting notional prices for internal transactions between prot centres. However, the free ow of information in the internal market allows the provision of information to be separated from the making of decisions, if desired. This produces a radical change in the way that control is exercised. Coordination is no longer effected by harmonizing decisions through market procedures, that is by the adjustment of price, but by the transmission of information to a central unit of control (or to a satellite of this unit, where multi-level planning is concerned). The internal market now no longer resembles an external market, but involves a hierarchy instead. The hierarchy is
164
Synthesis
best adapted to intra-plant control, while market procedures are best adapted to inter-plant control, though exceptions are possible in both cases. When discussing the organization of the rm, therefore, it is important to remember that both methods of control may be present in some degree. Coordination within the plant is normally best achieved by centralized control. Because the goods are close together, the interactions between them are relatively complex, which makes market methods of coordination inappropriate. Furthermore, because everything is close together, it is easy to supervise the provision of information for control: thus the quality of information can be guaranteed without recourse to market incentives. If the control problem is very complex, then it may be advantageous to introduce multilevel planning. However, this tends to slow down response to change and makes it difcult to allocate responsibility when errors occur. The disadvantages of multi-level planning become more serious as the number of levels in the hierarchy is increased. This sets an effective limit on the efcient size of plant. Once this limit has been reached, it is better to increase output by increasing the number of plants of a given size rather than by increasing the size of a single plant. In a multi-plant rm the geographical separation of the plants serves to buffer the interactions between them. Interactions occur only along channels designed specically for the purpose. A typical interaction arises from the transport of an intermediate product from one plant to another. Control of interactions of this kind normally calls for internal market procedures. The small number of interactions involved means that the full benet is obtained from the selectivity of the information used by market procedures. The spatial separation of plants makes it difcult to supervise the provision of information, so that market incentives are called for in order to ensure the accuracy of the information used for control. Efciency therefore demands that each plant is constituted as a separate prot centre, with the management of each plant being rewarded with a share of its notional prot. The costs of setting up internal markets limit the size of the rm. The efcient size of a rm is set at the margin where the costs of further internalization would just offset the benets obtained. However the costs and benets of internalization vary over time, and it is this variation, together with variation in the size of the market, that governs the dynamics of the growth of the rm. This chapter analyses the processes which underlie the growth, and eventual decline, of a representative rm. It is shown that the concepts developed above lead to a simple explanation of several well-known aspects of the life cycle of the rm.
165
11.4
The origins of a rm lie in the family specically, in the family of its founder. Admittedly, some rms begin life as fully-edged joint stock companies with many shareholders. But the vast majority of rms are founded by just one individual, and their early development is very much tied up with the founders family. Furthermore, although the successful rm will almost certainly outlive its founder, the managers who succeed the founder may well be inuenced by the culture and ethos with which he has imbued the organization. Even if the rm is amalgamated with others this inuence may still live on, either because the rm continues as an autonomous subsidiary or because it is sufciently dominant to inuence the other constituents of the group. Typically, a rm is founded because someone opts for self-employment. By becoming self-employed, a person commits himself to making his own market for his labour services, or for a product derived from those services. He does not rely upon an employer to make a market for him. The distinction is important because it does not normally require a great deal of initiative to nd a job (though it may require initiative to nd a very good job). Employers advertise vacancies, stipulate wages and screen the quality of applicants; all the employee has to do is to apply for the vacancy. The self-employed person has to take over this initiative from the employer. He has to make contact with customers through advertising. He must stipulate a price to the customer instead of having the employer stipulate a wage to him. He must display samples of his work, or provide testimonials from satised customers, in order to build up a reputation for quality. He cannot rely upon his employer to supervise his work and guarantee its quality to the customers. Why should anyone opt for self-employment? Perhaps the most obvious reason is that no employment is available. Self-employment is chosen because unemployment is the only alternative. If the wage rates negotiated by trade unions are too high in the light of the governments scal and monetary stance, then there will be an excess supply of employee labour. Although jobs may be available in the non-union sector, the glut of employees entering from the union sector will severely depress wages. The oor to the non-union wage is set by the subsistence wage, or the unemployment benet rate, whichever is the higher. Under these circumstances self-employment may be seen as the only acceptable alternative to unemployment. Secondly, the individual concerned may be reluctant to alienate control over his own labour. The individual may feel that his personal dignity is offended if his employer can order him about from one job to another. Employment will be particularly demeaning if the employer demands a deferential attitude as well.
166
Synthesis
Another reason for becoming self-employed is that the individual requires only part-time work, to be performed at his own convenience. Perhaps he already has a full-time job, or he simply enjoys the social aspect of the job and wishes to pursue it just as a hobby. Probably the most important reason for becoming self-employed is that the individual feels that employment would give him insufcient scope to exploit his talents. He may believe himself to be an entrepreneur, possessed of privileged information, and so he will be looking for an employer who will encourage him to use his superior judgment in taking decisions on his behalf. The individual is looking for an employer who will channel nancial resources and complementary expertise to him through internal markets. But employers may reject his claims to superior judgment. The employers screening procedures may fail to detect the talent that the individual believes is there. Alternatively, they may recognize the talent but offer what the individual considers to be an inadequate reward. Of the motives for self-employment discussed above, it is the last that augurs best for the success of the rm. The rst three motives are essentially negative ones: the individual simply acts as his own employer of last resort. An individual who nds it difcult to get a job in competition with others, or to hold down a job once it has been obtained, is unlikely to have the personal qualities required for business success. An individual who is averse to employment per se is unlikely to be good at employing others, and this will soon limit the potential for business growth. An individual who only wants to work at his own convenience is unlikely to provide his customers with the quality of service they require, and will therefore not survive for long. The fourth motive, of course, does not guarantee success. It may be suggested, for example, that a self-employed person with no previous experience as an employee will be at a serious disadvantage. To be successful it is desirable for the entrepreneur to start out as an employee. Employees can learn the trade from their employers before branching out on their own. Their experience as delegates may teach them how to delegate properly as their own business grows. As representatives of their employer, they may be able to make contacts which will prove useful later in locating customers or in securing nancial backing. Perhaps the most important thing is that the information passing across their desk as an employee may provide the stimulus for new ideas. It may be as a direct consequence of developing these ideas that the individual parts company with his employer. He may decide simply to steal the idea. He may seek internal resources to pursue the idea and be turned down. He may feel that he has been overlooked for promotion and that this shows that his employer undervalues the idea. In any of these cases the employee may quit to pursue the idea on his own initiative. The
167
internal market has failed him (and possibly his employer too). By becoming self-employed he opts for the external market instead.
11.5
Suppose that the self-employed person has the makings of a successful entrepreneur. Not all self-employed people are entrepreneurs, as indicated above, and by no means all entrepreneurs are successful. The non-entrepreneurs may be able to survive in self-employment, earning an income roughly equivalent to what they would expect to earn doing the same sort of job as an employee. The unsuccessful entrepreneur is almost certainly backing faulty judgment, and he will go out of business when he is unable to sustain his losses. The greatest interest attaches to the way the entrepreneur with superior judgment overcomes the obstacles to success. The rst obstacle is the need for capital: a need shared by nearly everyone who is self-employed. The entrepreneur may need to build up an inventory before he can begin to trade. In order to trade he must advertise his whereabouts and communicate the product specication to interested parties. All these activities incur resource costs before any trade takes place. If the entrepreneur has inherited wealth, then capital will not be a constraint, at least to begin with. But if he lacks capital, then he faces a serious strategic problem in obtaining it. Since he is, by assumption, an entrepreneur, he believes that his judgment differs from that of other people. To obtain a private reward from this superior judgment it is necessary to have a monopoly in exploiting it (see Chapter 4). But since other peoples judgment differs from his, they will be reluctant to lend capital to him to back his judgment against theirs. But if he passes all his information over to them in an effort to convince them of the correctness of his judgment, then he runs the risk that they will compete against him in the exploitation of the information. Indeed, since they already have the capital and he does not, the question is not so much whether they will compete against him as whether he will be able to compete against them. In developed countries, nancial intermediaries merchant banks, and to some extent the clearing banks as well have evolved to ameliorate his problem. The bank debars itself from competing with its clients and guarantees condentiality with respect to information supplied by borrowers in support of their requests for loans. The main alternative to the bank is the family. In developing countries where nancial intermediation is not very sophisticated, the family may be the only feasible source of nance. There are two factors which make the family an effective substitute for a bank. First, the family spans generations, and so can exploit the life-cycle
168
Synthesis
pattern of saving to allow the older generation to nance the younger generation. In effect, the older generation can allow the younger generation to capitalize upon its prospective inheritance. Secondly, the lenders have good information about the personal qualities of the borrowers. This information is likely to be particularly good if the family has stayed together so that borrowers and lenders are still living together. Even if the lenders information is not as good as they think it is, it is likely to err on the favourable side, so that the lender may be just as optimistic as the borrower about the risks involved. There is, of course, no guarantee that the entrepreneurs family or even his friends can supply the amount of capital that he requires. If he is obliged to borrow from a bank, then it is very unlikely that the bank, though optimistic, will be as optimistic as the entrepreneur himself. The cost of bank capital will therefore reect a substantial risk premium. Faced with a high cost of capital, the entrepreneurs rational response is to work harder and save more. He forgoes current leisure and current consumption in order to provide additional funds for investment. This sacrice in his living standards is warranted because of the high rate of return he anticipates from investment in his own business. When the return has been realized he can convert it back into consumption and into leisure too if he chooses to reduce his hours of work. Thus the high cost of capital encourages the entrepreneur to purchase a high future living standard at the expense of his living standard in the present. This behaviour of the capital-constrained entrepreneur appears to be typical of certain kinds of self-employment. Proprietors of corner shops and newsagents are often cited as examples. It should be pointed out, however, that simply working long hours and tolerating a low standard of living does not necessarily indicate that a self-employed person is an entrepreneur. It is perfectly consistent with non-entrepreneurial behaviour by people with little ability, a strong aversion to conventional employment and little preference for leisure. In other words, it may simply reect a petit-bourgeois mentality which seeks to purchase autonomy through increased hours of work. The distinction between the entrepreneur and the non-entrepreneur becomes apparent only later when the entrepreneurs business succeeds and his consumption and leisure increases, while the non-entrepreneur remains in his rut, with static low levels of consumption and leisure. The fact that the successful entrepreneurs leisure may increase later on does not, however, mean that he will take more leisure than the typical nonentrepreneur, merely that he will take more leisure than he did before. It is easy to overstate the antithesis between work and leisure where entrepreneurs are concerned. The entrepreneur may enjoy his work just as much, if not more than his leisure. The greater autonomy conferred by self-employment may reduce the irksomeness of work, though there is bound to come a point
169
where the hours of work are so long that leisure acquires a positive utility. But perhaps the main consideration is that the entrepreneur has something to prove to other people namely that his judgment is correct and that this gives him an enthusiasm for work which is missing in many other people. This suggests that, while the entrepreneur may reduce his hours of work as the capital constraint eases, he will continue to work more than most people until he is satised that he has proved himself not only to his nancial backers, but to the world at large. If no further investment opportunities present themselves, then the entrepreneur can consume the prots of his past success. If further opportunities do appear, then given the entrepreneurs previous success it will now be easier for him to borrow funds. Thus in either case the capital constraint is eased and so the entrepreneur can afford to increase consumption and, if he wishes, to reduce his hours of work too. In the latter case, however, it is unlikely that the capital constraint will disappear at once. One success does not guarantee another, and so the capital constraint will ease only slowly as the entrepreneurs record of successes improves over time. In the meantime, the entrepreneur remains at least partially constrained, and therefore dependent upon internal sources of nance. The primary source is income generated by previous projects. This lends a characteristic dynamic to the growth of the rm, in which prots generated by previous projects constrain the current rate of growth of the rm.
11.6
It is often difcult for a self-employed person to start trading alone as a oneman business. Production may call for teamwork, or market making may call for a secretary to answer the phone and deal with queries while the entrepreneur is tied up in other work. The entrepreneur must therefore begin by hiring labour. As noted in Chapter 7, social and legal constraints prevent effective intermediation in the labour market. Since households are not accustomed to making a market in their own labour services, the entrepreneur must take the initiative in recruiting labour. Labour is of variable quality as regards both integrity and ability. Poorquality labour can impose heavy costs on the employer, and quality is difcult to screen for. Some job applicants come equipped with educational qualications, certicates of training or apprenticeship, or references from a previous employer. However, the inexperienced employer may be uncertain as to what such certicates mean, and whether they are issued by a reputable institution. Under these circumstances the family comes into its own as an internal supplier of labour. The entrepreneur knows his family much better than he
170
Synthesis
knows the rest of the labour market. Thus a man may have more condence in teaming up with his own children than he would with other people. Again he may prefer to use his wife as a secretary than to recruit outside help. The advantages are particularly great if the labour of other family members would otherwise be underutilized because of the costs to those family members of gaining access to the external labour market. As the business grows, the complexity of decision making may be such that the entrepreneur is obliged to delegate. If the business is growing fast, then it may be necessary to allow delegates considerable discretion, for the new opportunities may be missed unless quick decisions are made, and this strongly favours decentralized decision making by delegates who possess signicant autonomy. The problem of quality control in recruiting delegate decision makers is much greater than for the typical employee. It therefore appears to make sense for the entrepreneur to promote family members to decision-making posts and enter the external market initially for lower-quality labour. The problem with this strategy, however, is that the family members may not have the skills required. The internal market afforded by the family may be too limited a source from which to recruit decision makers. In this case the entrepreneurs ability to transcend the boundaries of his family may be crucial to the continued success of the rm. Of course, it is possible that, because family members have similar genes and share the same environment as the entrepreneur, they have similar qualities to his own. On the other hand, if they are entrepreneurs in their own right, they may have ideas of their own, and so may not have either the time, or the nancial resources for that matter, to support another entrepreneur in the same family. It is apparent that the stage at which delegation becomes necessary is a critical one in the growth of the rm. The family is normally too small a pool from which to draw suitable labour. There is no substitute for having recourse to the external market. The entrepreneur must develop skills of his own in recruiting labour. He must not only screen applicants but also provide them with suitable incentives once they take up employment as decision makers. If the incentives are wrong, then the wrong sort of applicant will be attracted to the job. Even if the right sort of person is appointed, he is liable to quit once he has a good idea of his own if the internal rewards are too small. If the entrepreneur is not careful, the only able people who join the rm will be those seeking introductions to key customers and suppliers so that they can set up later in competition with their employer. Similar problems occur in the recruitment of specialists. As the rm grows, the entrepreneur has the opportunity of internalizing markets in specialist services. The volume of trade becomes sufcient to warrant the
171
full-time employment of technicians, designers, accountants and so on. Once the internal market has been established, the economies achieved by pooling the skills of different specialists within the rm may be quite substantial. But to set up the internal market the entrepreneur must rst recruit the specialist. Unless the entrepreneur has at least a supercial knowledge of the specialism he may be unable to appraise the quality of job applicants. He must know enough about each subject to know, for example, what sort of questions to ask at interview and what sort of replies he can reasonably expect. Given the diversity of the different specialisms, the entrepreneur requires a very broad background knowledge to recruit effectively in each area. Without such knowledge the entrepreneur will not only be unable to recruit suitable specialists, but he will be unable to make effective use of them when they are employed. The employment of specialists has important implications for the organizational structure of the rm. It is natural to give each specialist his own area of responsibility and this implies that any employee who makes a decision should take relevant specialist advice rst. There is a danger, however, that each specialist will become too assertive and insist on being consulted about quite trivial matters which are nominally within his area. Demarcation disputes may arise as specialists invade each others territory. The disputes are stimulated because each specialist believes it is to his own advantage to overstate the importance of his own skills. For this reason, an entrepreneur may be reluctant to recruit specialists in case they attempt to take decisions out of his hands. If he does take them on, he may nd himself continually having to adjudicate upon disputes concerning matters about which he himself has very little knowledge. To exploit internal economies of specialism successfully, the entrepreneur must therefore have sufcient general knowledge to keep each of his specialists in his place. Only if a specialist believes that he will be punished for overextending his inuence will he avoid entering into disputes with other parties.
11.7
So far the analysis has focused upon constraints on growth stemming from the supply of labour and the availability of risk capital. Problems of supply response, however, appear only because of the pressure built up by growing demand for the rms product. A major factor affecting the growth of demand is the spread of information about the product. It is assumed that the rm has been created in order to market a new product. In this context the term product must be interpreted very broadly. A new product could be anything from an entirely new design of, say, a multi-
172
Synthesis
purpose good down to a minor differentiation of a personal service. It is assumed, simply, that the product has a unique specication. It is often useful to think of information about a product spreading like an infection, though like all analogies there are important limitations to it. The infection is launched when the product is rst announced, and can be actively spread by the rm through advertising. Alternatively, the rm may take a passive role and allow information networks in society to spread the message. These information networks are built around families, clubs, places of work indeed any places where people meet to socialize supplemented by purpose-designed news and entertainment media: newspapers, television and so on. Display of a product is often important in promoting demand. A product which looks good may be advertised simply by placing it in a shop window. Furthermore, if the use of the product is itself conspicuous for example, clothing or motor vehicles the product may advertise itself even when it is out of the showroom and in the hands of its purchaser. In the case of conspicuous products the message is mainly a visual one, and so it can be communicated through physical proximity, independently of verbal intercourse. Thus infection with information about conspicuous goods is likely to spread faster than in other cases. Not everyone who knows about the product will necessarily want to buy it. Pursuing the previous analogy, the information may be regarded as a virus and demand as a symptom of the illness that is caused. Not everyone is equally susceptible to the virus. The unsusceptible will not buy the product once they get to know of it only the susceptible will do so. An individuals susceptibility is a function of his tastes, his income and the price of the product. The lower the price of the product, the more people will be susceptible to it and the more units each susceptible person will buy. In a very simple infection process, the probability that an uninfected person will come into contact with the virus is proportional to the number of people who have already been infected. In economic terms this is consistent with people meeting at random to exchange information, when those who buy the product pass on the information about it, but those who have decided not to buy it do not. This model is particularly appropriate to a conspicuous good, where a new buyer normally obtains knowledge of the good by witnessing someone elses use of it. In an alternative version of the model, the probability of coming into contact with the virus is related, not to the number of people who have been infected, but to the number of people who have previously made contact with the virus even though they have not been infected. This model is appropriate to inconspicuous goods, where information spreads verbally and those who have not bought the good are just as likely as those who have to pass the information on. In the special case where
173
Figure 11.1
all individuals are susceptible, the two models give the same result: they describe a logistic process which leads rst to an acceleration and then to a deceleration in the spread of the infection. The diffusion curve, showing the number of people infected at any one time, is illustrated in Figure 11.1 by the curve AB. The curve is sigmoid and is asymptotic to the horizontal line YZ, showing that eventually everyone becomes infected.
11.8
At any stage of the diffusion process, the number of infected individuals can be increased through advertising. Advertising does not inform people who would otherwise never hear about the product: it simply means that they hear about it earlier than they otherwise would. In other words, advertising buys time. Advertising may be either a continuous process as with a poster or shop window display which attracts casual passers-by or it may be a oneshot affair as when brochures are mailed out in bulk to a target sample of people. The effect of continuous advertising may be modelled by assuming that one person the entrepreneur spreads infection faster than everyone else. The impact of continuous advertising is illustrated in Figure 11.1 by a switch to the new, steeper, diffusion curve AC. By contrast, the effect of one-shot advertising is to increase at a stroke the number of people who are informed about the product. Suppose, for example, that at time OT1, an additional RS1
174
Synthesis
people had been informed about the product. The state of information is now similar to what it would have been later, at time OT2, if no advertising had occurred. Thus the subsequent spread of information continues from the base S1T1 instead of the base RT1 as before. The new diffusion curve ORS1D exhibits a discontinuity at time OT1. The discontinuity arises because the segment S2B of the original diffusion curve AB has been translated to the left through a distance T1T2 to form the segment S1D of the new diffusion curve. The analysis of one-shot advertising suggests that, the earlier the product is advertised, the more effective the advertising will be. If the product has a nite lifetime before it becomes obsolete, then the earlier the product is advertised, the longer is the period over which the advertising investment is paid back. Furthermore, if advertising is conducted at a time when almost noone is infected, then the probability that those who are contacted already have the information is very small. If the advertising is conducted later, then many of the people contacted will already know of the product, so that part of the effort will be wasted. This explains why advertising is normally carried out at the time a product is launched, and is often only repeated later because the initial launch has failed. This conclusion cannot remain unqualied however. The analysis above implicitly assumes that the population of buyers is xed, whereas in fact the population is constantly turning over because of births and deaths. The obvious implication for advertising is that the population needs to be continually re-educated about the product. The initial effects of the one-shot advertisement will gradually wear off as the composition of the population changes. It is important to recognize that the time path of infection as represented by the diffusion curve is not necessarily the same as the time path of demand. The two paths are the same (up to a constant of proportionality) only if each susceptible person repeats his purchases regularly in perpetuity. If, on the other hand, a purchase represents a once-for-all adjustment of the stock of a durable good, then the time path of demand will be governed by the marginal rate of diffusion: that is, at any time demand will be proportional to the slope of the diffusion curve. Assuming a logistic diffusion of information in a static population, and a constant degree of susceptibility in each person, the demand for a durable good will follow the time path DD in Figure 11.2. In practice, of course, few goods are perfectly durable. They wear out after a certain time and have to be replaced. Infrequent replacement leads to echo effects in product demand. The early peak in initial demand reappears later when these early purchases need to be replaced. This leads to a cyclical pattern of replacement demand where the wavelength of the cycles is equal to the lifetime of the product. Finally, it should be emphasized that the function of advertising is not merely to inform but to persuade. To put this another way, there are advan-
175
Figure 11.2
tages to the producer in ensuring that the information conveyed about the product is highly selective. The information should emphasize the good points and play down the bad points. In particular, it should emphasize the products advantages over its potential substitutes. This will not only increase demand at a given price but reduce the elasticity of demand as well. This will encourage the entrepreneur to capitalize on advertising not only through an increased volume of sales but also by setting a somewhat higher price.
11.9
The preceding discussion of diffusion in particular the analysis based upon the logistic process has implicitly assumed the absence of social barriers within the population. Each individual (except possibly the entrepreneur) has an equal probability of communicating with any other. Yet this is obviously not the case in practice. Communication takes place much more frequently within social institutions, such as families, clubs and rms, than it does between them. Information may move between two institutions only because some person is a member of both. But if the population is effectively segregated into different groups, and each institution typically draws its members from just one group, then members of the different groups may never overlap. Social segregation of this kind may restrict communication so much that information from any given source cannot diffuse throughout the population unless it is channelled through the news and entertainment media. Each medium itself, however, has a selective audience. To communicate with the entire population the entrepreneur may have to use several different media. To reduce the costs of communication he will wish to use comple-
176
Synthesis
mentary media; that is, to use media whose audiences do not signicantly overlap. In practice, though, he may not wish his coverage to be comprehensive. Because of differences in tastes and incomes, not everyone has the same susceptibility to the product. There is little point in communicating with people who are unlikely to express any demand. Suppose, for example, that taste for the product varies over the personal life cycle say the product is demanded by people who are setting up home for the rst time. People at this stage of their life cycle may constitute an identiable social group. They may belong to one particular type of club and not to others. They may read particular types of magazine and visit particular kinds of places. The successful entrepreneur will exploit these social characteristics in making contact with his target audience. He may offer sponsorship to the clubs, advertise in the appropriate magazines and purchase display space in the places that members of the group visit. He may still rely upon the most alert members of the group to pass on the message to the others, though he must recognize that the message will normally be passed on only within the group. However, if his demand originates within just one group, then this constraint may be of little consequence. Social factors exert a potentially strong inuence on product demand. For many products, understanding social trends is the key to forecasting product demand. For example, in an afuent society, changing attitudes to housing may mean that all newly-married couples expect to live in a home of their own. The birth rate of the past determines how many young people are approaching marriageable age, and economic factors may inuence the extent to which marriages are brought forward or postponed. Given suitable economic and demographic information and his knowledge of social trends, the entrepreneur can predict the probable size of his target market, and the best way of communicating with it. The extent to which the entrepreneur can synthesize all this information will determine the accuracy of his forecasts, and his subsequent success in matching supply to demand.
11.10
CAPITALIZING ON EXPERIENCE
Another reason for the entrepreneur to advertise continuously is that the quality of his product may change over time. Improvements in quality depend upon the exploitation of information; some of this information may be generated internally by production and marketing activities, while other information may be obtained externally for example by observing other rms and borrowing ideas from them. The ows of information involved in quality improvement are indicated schematically in Figure 11.3. The gure appears to suggest that quality improvement is a distinct activity carried out by
177
Figure 11.3
specialists, but of course this is not necessarily so. In a small rm quality improvement may be effected by the same person who produces the product and sells it. In such a case the information ows shown would be internal not only to the rm, but to the mind of the individual as well. The use of internal information is an important inuence on the dynamics of the rm. Internal information on production is generated by monitoring the activities of workers and machinery, and noting where slack exists and bottlenecks and errors occur. Internal information on marketing is generated by monitoring buyer reaction, and even more importantly by monitoring the reaction of people who inspect the product, appraise the price but decide not to buy. The amount of information generated in this way will be roughly
178
Synthesis
proportional to the amount of output produced. Each unit produced generates additional experience in production. Each unit sold generates additional information on buyer reaction; and if each unit produced attracts a xed number of appraisals, then experience of non-buyer reaction will be proportional to output as well. Consequently, the total stock of relevant information is roughly proportional to the cumulated output of the rm. As more information is accumulated, so additional information becomes of smaller value, since much of it conrms what is already known, or suggests qualications to existing knowledge which are of ever-diminishing practical signicance. At any instant the rate of quality improvement is likely to be proportional to the rate of increase of the stock of knowledge, though perhaps with a lag due to the time required to put the new knowledge into practice. The factor of proportionality will decline as the stock of knowledge increases, because of the diminishing marginal returns to information noted above. Given that the stock of knowledge is directly proportional to cumulated output, the rate of quality improvement will be directly proportional to the level of output with a factor of proportionality which diminishes with respect to cumulated output. To put this another way, the quality of the product increases with respect to cumulated output, but at a diminishing rate. Improvements in quality are often associated with either a redesign of the product or a change in production technique. Such changes may also increase efciency and so reduce production cost. A change of this kind normally incurs a once-for-all set-up cost which is independent of the amount of output subsequently produced. The run-on cost of each subsequent unit is then reduced until some other change occurs. A redesign of the product or change of production technique may therefore be regarded as an investment which simultaneously improves product quality and reduces run-on cost. The feasibility of the investment is governed by the cumulated output of the rm. The return to the investment will depend crucially upon how effectively the improvement in product quality can be brought to the attention of potential buyers. In principle, the improvement in product quality should render substitutes less attractive. Normally, this increases demand for the product and renders it less price-elastic too. This would encourage the rm to increase the price, were it not for the simultaneous reduction in marginal cost. As it is, the direction of movement in price will depend upon whether or not the demand effect pulling the price up is sufciently strong to outweigh the cost-reducing effect tending to pull the price down. With one or two exceptions, though, the output of the rm will denitely increase once the investment has been made. Not all improvements in quality incur a set-up cost. The quality of output may be improved by an improvement in the quality of inputs. In particular, the quality of the labour input may be improved as employees gain on-the-job experience in production. This is the classic case of learning by doing, in
179
which their cumulative experience gives the rms employees a dynamic absolute and comparative advantage in production. It is most important to recognize, however, that the rm may encounter difculties in capitalizing upon this advantage. Since the experience is a by-product of production it might appear to be the property of the rm. But in practice it may well be appropriated by the employee. The employee may threaten to quit unless he is rewarded for the experience he has gained at his employers expense. If the employer does not pay up, then the employee may decide to set up in competition with his employer. If the employer decides to pay up, then he is redistributing his monopoly reward from himself to his employee. It is not only on-the-job experience that the employer may have difculty in capitalizing upon. Any employee through whom information is channelled within the rm may decide to use this information for himself instead of passing it on in the way he is supposed to. As experience within the rm increases, so the knowledgeability of the employees increases while the employer, if he is not careful, may get increasingly out of touch. Employees may decide that it is no longer necessary for their employer to intermediate between them and the customers. In the long run, therefore, potential rivals may be nurtured within the rm itself.
11.11
Quality improvement and cost reduction are just two examples of the more general phenomenon of the capture and use of information generated within the rm. It has already been noted in discussing the growth of demand that social institutions such as the family and the club have an important role in promoting the ow of information between people. The rm is itself a social institution. It provides facilities for the exchange of information between employer and employee and between different employees. Since the rm is also a unit of production, information is generated on the spot as a by-product of its activities. The role of the rm as a social institution is to channel this information to the employees who can make the best use of it. The information may be used not only for quality improvement and cost reduction, but also for identifying new market opportunities. The new opportunities might relate to new market areas that the product has not yet penetrated, or to new products which could be developed for example, complements in demand, for sale to existing customers, or complements in supply such as goods derived from by-products which previously went to waste. These new opportunities create a drive to diversify the rm both geographically and by product.
180
Synthesis
Diversication, unlike quality improvement, cannot normally be accomplished using only the resources already employed by the rm. It is necessary to hire new resources specically for the purpose. Often there will be economies of scale in the use of these resources. The resources themselves may be indivisible or there may be economies in combining or agglomerating them. As a result a substantial volume of output may be required to utilize them fully. Hiring the requisite bundle of additional resources imposes a recurrent xed cost upon the rm. If the market into which the rm plans to diversify is relatively small, then the xed costs can be spread over only a small volume of output. Diversication will be viable only if the rm can spread the xed costs further by increasing the utilization of the new capacity. One possibility is to hire out user services but, as shown in Chapter 7, external markets in user services are often costly to operate. If the resources are multi-purpose goods, then the obvious alternative is to nd some further market in which to diversify. The demand from this market will increase the demand for the services of the underutilized resources and allow their xed costs to be spread further. It must be recognized, however, that each additional market that is entered not only increases the utilization of existing resources, but creates demands for new ones. To keep these new resources fully utilized may require yet another market to be entered. Given the complexity of an efcient diversication strategy, it might be doubted whether a rm could ever successfully embark upon it. Certainly, it is doubtful if there is an entrepreneur anywhere sufciently far-sighted to plan the diversication of his rm right from the outset. Because processing information in order to take complex decisions is a costly process, the entrepreneur will wish to plan each step in the diversication process separately. He will hope that the prot at each stage is sufcient to cover the additional xed cost incurred, irrespective of whether or not the utilization of resources can be improved at a subsequent stage. Once each step has been accomplished he will look around for the next step. He will be guided in his search by a desire to increase the utilization of underutilized resources. Diversication therefore becomes a dynamic process in which investment made at one stage inuences the search for investments to be made at a subsequent stage. The search for opportunities for diversication has an opportunity cost in terms of the entrepreneurs own effort, or the efforts of those to whom the job is delegated. One way of reducing the opportunity cost is to employ underutilized administrative labour for this purpose. In particular, managers who have been hired to administer the most recent stage of diversication may be required to devote their spare time to investigating new opportunities. These opportunities, when exploited, will allow the managers time to be
181
more fully utilized on routine administrative work. In this way, the existence of managerial excess capacity helps to subsidize internally the search for new investment opportunities. This response to excess capacity depends, however, upon the cooperation of the managers concerned. An underutilized manager has no obvious incentive to increase his own work load, so long as he believes that the work he does is of sufcient value to make his job secure. An additional incentive must be given to managers who identify new investment opportunities, and the incentive must be greater the more the managers own work load is likely to increase as a result. As the rm gets larger and more diversied, so the problems posed by indivisibilities diminish in signicance. This reduces the potential rewards to further growth. When all resources controlled by the rm can be fully utilized by sharing them out internally between different activities, then the rm is likely to have achieved an optimum size. In particular, managerial excess capacity will have been eliminated. This means that there is no pressing need to seek out additional markets, and also there are no spare managerial resources inside the rm to do so anyway. Only when existing markets contract will resources become underutilized and managers be freed to seek out ways of replacing a contracting market with another one. In theory the large diversied rm could remain indenitely in a homeostatic equilibrium, adjusting its portfolio of market demands to match the xed portfolio of resources which it has under its control. In practice, though, it may be difcult to administer the internal incentives required to maintain equilibrium. Sooner or later inadequate incentives may cause the most able decision makers to leave, and less able decision makers to be recruited in their place. The less able people will have more difculty in administering internal incentives and so, as they come to predominate, pressure may build up for incentives to weaken. The ethos of the organization may gradually change from rewarding the able to protecting the inept. Needless to say, once this trend gathers momentum, the protability of the rm will decline. Markets will be lost and not replaced, and so the size and diversity of the rm will diminish too. Eventually, the rm will be either taken over privately and reorganized, or taken over by the state and reorganized or subsidized, or go into liquidation.
11.12
Market structure is usually discussed in the context of an industry. In analysing entrepreneurship it is appropriate to work with a very narrow concept of an industry. Essentially the industry is identied with a single product. The product is in turn determined by its specication. If product
182
Synthesis
specications were dened narrowly enough, then it is possible that every rm would produce a slightly different product and so belong to a different industry. This is very close to the approach developed below, but with one important difference. It is assumed that buyers may not know absolutely everything they would like to know about the product specication. As a result two products which are in reality different may appear indistinguishable. When a signicant number of buyers are in this position, then the two products are said to belong to the same industry. If the buyers are aware that there are differences though they do not know exactly what then they will perceive a quality problem. Given the use of the product that they have in mind, one of the specications may be more desirable than the other. The desirable product is said to be of higher quality than the less desirable one. Using this approach it is possible to distinguish two types of industry: in one the product is homogeneous and in the other it is not. In the rst case all producers are known to supply a product of similar quality while in the second case they are not: buyers believe that there are differences in quality, and it is assumed that they are correct in this belief. The question of homogeneity is closely related to the complexity and the versatility of the product. By and large the more complex the design, and the greater the variety of the uses to which it can be put, the more difcult it is for the buyer to assess the quality. Homogeneous industries are much easier to analyse than inhomogeneous ones, and their market structures are already well understood. Unfortunately for the theory, however, homogeneous industries are far less common than inhomogeneous ones. On grounds of both originality and relevance, therefore, it is appropriate to restrict the following discussion to inhomogeneous industries. Without loss of generality it may be assumed that there is just one rm which is the rst to innovate the product and that over time other rms will then replicate it. If two or more rms innovate simultaneously, then it is just as though replication were immediate. If no other rms replicate, then it is just as though replication has been deferred indenitely. By denition, the innovator is a monopolist for as long as he remains the sole supplier. His degree of monopoly power depends upon the closeness of existing substitutes for his product. He can attempt to consolidate his monopoly by erecting barriers to entry (see Section 4.4). An obvious strategy is to disseminate information about the product to potential buyers as quickly as possible. Besides increasing the present value of the revenue stream, this reduces the latent unsatised demand which an entrant could seek to exploit. This is particularly important where demand is socially or geographically dispersed, for an obvious strategy for an entrant is to identify a segment of
183
the market which news of the innovation has been slow to reach. Reducing unsatised demand may also discourage the entrant by raising his average cost of production. If there are increasing returns at the plant level, up to some minimum efcient scale, then the smaller the residual market the more difcult it is for the entrant to cover his average cost of production. If he cannot cover average cost, then he will not produce at all, and so the residual market will remain unexploited until the innovator himself gains access to it. The entrants ability to cover costs depends of course on the price at which he is able to sell. With a homogeneous product both innovator and entrant must sell at the same price. If the entrants price expectations are based upon the innovators current price, then the innovator can in principle deter entry by setting a limit price. The limit price is set conditional upon the minimum efcient scale of plant (and other relevant parameters of production cost) so that, given production at this scale, no potential entrant could expect to make a prot. However, if the quality of the entrants product is liable to be different, then he may have to sell it at a discount on the innovators price. There are two main reasons for this. First, the entrant may have to rely upon switching some demand from the innovators product. However, the buyers concerned have already experienced the innovators product and are therefore better informed about it. They perceive fewer risks in continuing to purchase the product they know than in switching to an untried alternative. To compensate for these risks the entrant must subsidize the buyers experiment with the alternative product by discounting his price. The second reason is that the innovator can trade upon his greater experience of production and suggest to buyers that his greater experience enables him to offer a product of superior quality. This may persuade the uncommitted to opt for the old-established product. It may, however, be questioned whether the entrants product really is inferior. If it is, then the discount at which it will have to be sold in perpetuity may indeed deter entry. If it is actually superior, buyers scepticism will in the long run be overcome. There is still a barrier to entry, because the delay in penetration of the market will reduce the present value of entry. It may also lead to short-run losses being incurred in getting the product launched, so that the capital requirements may be increased. But, subject to these qualications, entry may now seem worthwhile. But how is it that the entrant can produce a product superior to the innovators, given the innovators greater experience? The answer lies in the appropriability of this experience to the rm. It is conceivable that an outside imitator could at least match the quality of the innovators product by reverse-engineering the design (assuming patent protection was inadequate). A much more likely explanation, however, is that the entrant is an insider
184
Synthesis
who has previously worked for the innovating rm. The experience may have accrued to him as well as to his employer. Indeed, the experience may in the rst instance have been his alone, and only a proportion of this experience may have been passed on to the employer. Thus, when the entrant appears from within the industry, the quality of the entrants product may actually embody more of the innovators experience than does the innovators product itself. Once entry occurs, the battle for customers is joined. The main controversy is over the quality of the rival products. Whichever product is perceived as inferior must be sold at a discount if its producer is to maintain his market share. The main battle, therefore, is over customers perceptions of product quality. It is perceptions of quality which govern prices rather than prices which govern perceptions of quality. True, there may be some consumers who regard a low price as an admission by the producer of low quality in the product. This may actually discourage producers from engaging in price competition, as each may feel that undercutting his rivals price may damage the image of his product. Under these conditions the battle over product quality becomes not a war of prices but a war of words. Each producer will formulate claims which put his product in the most favourable light. Some claims may be true but others may be false. The incentive to make false claims is greater the more difcult they are for the rival to refute. The incentive to falsehood is also normally much greater the more inferior the product is. There seems to be no guarantee, in the short run at least, that the superior product will actually be the successful one. Indeed, the battle may well be inconclusive, with the innovator and entrant achieving stable long-run market shares. There is no reason, of course, why there should be just a single entrant to the industry. If the initial entry has been successful, then this may encourage other entrants to follow suit. Subsequent entries may be much easier because customers may have overcome their suspicion of alternative products, and some may even have come to identify a new product with improved quality. As the range of products increases, so customers may become more experienced at evaluating them. At the same time the movement of managerial and technical personnel between the producers may turn production know-how into a public good within the industry. As a result the industry may move in the long run towards a competitive market for a basically homogeneous product. The main factor inhibiting this trend is economies of scale. Given the size of the market, there may be room for only a limited number of plants in the industry. This will not prevent the product becoming standardized, but it may terminate entry at a point where the industry still has an oligopolistic structure. Given that economies of scale constitute a barrier to entry, this provides
185
an incentive for the oligopolistic rms to collude. Although each rm may have an incentive to cheat upon a collusive agreement, the small number of rms involved makes policing an agreement fairly straightforward. The collusion could be institutionalized by a merger, though given current social and political attitudes to monopoly this would probably not be advisable. A similar objection applies to a formal cartel. The most effective arrangement is probably an informal cartel of which no written records exist, for example the xing of prices and/or quotas at meetings organized on some other pretext. Collusion must not, of course, raise prots to a level which would attract further entrants. The incentive to collude is greatest when, owing to past miscalculations, industry capacity has been expanded to above the level at which long-run normal prots could be earned. This is particularly common in industries subject to an unforeseen contraction in demand due, for example, to a change in tastes or, more usually, to the innovation of a substitute product. Under these conditions collusion may be a success if it simply restores prots to their normal level. It therefore recommends itself very strongly to oligopolistic producers in a declining industry.
SUMMARY
This chapter has synthesized results from previous chapters in order to elucidate the factors which govern the rate of growth of the rm. The formation of a new rm is the consequence not only of the recognition of an entrepreneurial opportunity, but also of a belief that this opportunity is best exploited through self-employment. The founder of a rm is likely to nd problems in both recruiting labour and acquiring capital; the family has a major role as an internal source of both labour and capital. The role of the family exhibits a crucial characteristic of any institution, namely that it facilitates communication and creates an internal pool of information which each member can use at will. The institution captures information that is a by-product of one members activities and makes it available to help others get started on new activities. In the context of the rm, it is the capture of production and marketing experience, its use in developing technical and quality improvements, and its feedback into production and marketing, which generate the main dynamic for the growth of the rm. This activity is supplemented by the scanning of external information sources for new ideas, and the selective dissemination of information through advertising to augment the word-of-mouth processes which are responsible for the growth of product demand. Institutional adaptation becomes more difcult as the size of the rm increases; it may become difcult to retain key employees, who may quit in
186
Synthesis
order to set up in competition with their former employer. This suggests the possibility, rst, of a life cycle for the industry in which the rm is involved and, secondly, a life cycle for the rm itself.
187
(1967) and Webber (1972, 1979). The international diffusion of an innovation is considered by Nabseth and Ray (1974), Sloan (1973) and Tilton (1971). The diffusion of information between rms and the nature of the competitive threat to the innovator has been considered by Baldwin and Childs (1969), Manseld (1961, 1963a, 1963b) and Romeo (1975, 1977). The logistic curve and its variants are extensively used in the study of diffusion processes of all kinds; the mathematical theory is discussed by Bartholomew (1973); its empirical application is exemplied by Stoneman (1976). The impact of product durability on the relation between the diffusion curve and the time path of product demand is considered by Swan (1970). The modelling of the dynamics of product demand is considered as a whole by Massy, Montgomery and Morrison (1970). The role of product quality and non-price product characteristics in general is considered by Abbott (1955), Heebower (1967) and Kotler (1976), while Iremonger (1972) and Lancaster (1966, 1979) have developed an activity-analysis approach which integrates particularly well with the theory developed in this book. The problems posed by uncertainty about product quality are considered in detail by Akerlof (1970), Kihlstrom (1974a, 1974b) and Spence (1977). The distinction between inspection and experience goods is due to Nelson (1970), though a slightly different terminology is employed by him. The signicance of product guarantees, and of producer liability in general, is considered in the symposium edited by McKean (1970). The relation between advertising, consumer information and product quality is discussed by Albion and Farris (1981) and Reekie (1981). The relation between advertising and word-of-mouth processes is considered by Glaister (1974). Life cycles in rms are discussed by Mueller (1972) and Penrose (1959).
The market for entrepreneurs allocates judgmental decisions to entrepreneurs. It has, in fact, four main functions: 1. 2. 3. 4. to identify decisions which are judgmental, to identify entrepreneurs whose judgment is likely to be correct, to match entrepreneurs to judgmental decisions so that wherever possible the right decision is made, and to distribute rewards to the entrepreneurs.
It is sometimes denied that a market for entrepreneurs can exist. This is incorrect. It must be admitted, however, that the market for entrepreneurs has some unusual features which mean that it operates in a different way from most other markets.
12.2
One of the idiosyncrasies of the market for entrepreneurs is indicated by the rst of the functions identied above. It is extremely difcult to determine precisely which decisions are judgmental. As a result it is difcult for anyone to identify a precise source of demand for an entrepreneur. Consider the demand for entrepreneurs within the economy as a whole, and consider too a single period, prior to which the economy has been in operation for some considerable time. A system of property rights has been evolved; decision-making power is conferred by ownership of general rights typically rights to determine the use of multi-purpose goods (see Chapter 7). Many of these rights are vested in institutions such as rms. Each institution has an organization comprising a set of posts lled by delegate decision makers. Delegate decision makers within the same organization coordinate their decisions through either an internal market or a hierarchy. The economy is subject to continuous unforeseen exogenous disturbances due, for example, to changes in population and tastes. Typically, the source of
188
189
information about any change is localized, and diffuses slowly through a network of social contacts. Key elements in this network are institutions such as clubs and rms. Firms in particular attempt to capture information about change and channel this information to the delegate decision makers who are most likely to use it to advantage. It is this system of property rights and social institutions which determine at any one time who is making the decisions about resource allocation, and what information is available to them. The system described above determines not only who will make the decisions but also what form the decisions normally take. For example, if the system is based upon voluntary trade in property rights using a specialized medium of exchange, then decisions will be concerned not only with how to utilize goods that are already under the decision makers control, but also with decisions on whether to sell these goods, or to buy goods which are at present under someone elses control. (The structure of a monetary market economy of this kind was discussed in Chapter 5.) The identication of judgmental decisions within a monetary market economy is itself a judgmental activity. Basically, a judgmental decision is one where some relevant item of information has not diffused to everyone. Those who have the information would therefore decide one way and those without it would decide another way. It is assumed that those who have the relevant information will make the right decision, while those who do not will make the wrong decision. It is possible, of course, that there are other factors, which no-one knows about, which make the available information misleading. It is therefore conceivable that those without the information might make a better decision, though this possibility will be ignored. Some kinds of decision are widely recognized as judgmental: for example, decisions about complex investment projects which have numerous spillover effects. Different people will have different information concerning the probable outcome of such projects. In recognition of this, such decisions are typically taken by the boards of large companies; the companys information network ensures that each board member is well briefed, whilst consideration at board level ensures that the information of the separate members can be pooled before a decision is made. But for many small and apparently simple decisions there is unlikely to be a consensus upon whether the decision is judgmental. Consider, for example, a relatively minor repetitive decision which has to be made anew each period. For reasons explained in Chapter 2, most people making a repetitive decision will tacitly assume that circumstances have not changed from the previous occasion. The decision is not given active consideration; a no change policy is followed automatically. Only those who recognize (or believe they recognize) that a change has occurred will believe the decision to be a judgmental one. They may not know exactly what the change is, but they know enough to
190
Synthesis
know that the tacit assumption of the other decision makers is wrong. The other decision makers tacitly believe that the decision is not judgmental, while those who have recognized a change believe that it is. It follows that the recognition of a judgmental decision is, in many cases, itself a judgmental activity.
12.3
IDENTIFYING AN ENTREPRENEUR
The qualities required of an entrepreneur were discussed in Chapter 2. It was emphasized that some of these qualities are extremely difcult to screen for. There is no objective test of entrepreneurial ability which can guarantee a high degree of accuracy, and there is unlikely to be one in the foreseeable future. Opinions are therefore likely to differ about whether a given individual has entrepreneurial ability. Some people may overestimate a persons ability and others underestimate it. This means that the identication of an entrepreneur is itself a judgmental activity. Various hypotheses can be made about the identication of entrepreneurs. The simplest of them may be called the law of self-esteem. It asserts, basically, that everyone has a higher opinion of his own judgment than anyone else does. This means that many people who believe themselves to be entrepreneurs will not be recognized as such by other people. On the other hand, it denies the possibility that a true entrepreneur may so underestimate himself that he declines to become an entrepreneur when he really should do so. Potential entrepreneurs may be excluded from entrepreneurship by lack of nancial backing or by other barriers to entry, but do not exclude themselves by self-effacement. A second, and much stronger, hypothesis is the law of arrogance: this asserts that no-one thinks anyone else has what it takes to be an entrepreneur. According to the second law, anyone who thinks that he is an entrepreneur can be sure that everyone else disagrees with him. The second law is somewhat extreme, however, as it ignores the fact that, in the long run at least, an entrepreneur can acquire a reputation for successful decision making and thereby acquire the condence of others. It also ignores the fact that there are both formal and informal methods of screening people for entrepreneurial qualities. The formal methods include in-depth interviews and the assessment of performance in simulated business situations; the informal methods rely on continuous observation of the individual at close quarters and are open mainly to family and friends. None of these methods is guaranteed to succeed, but they do allow favourable assessments of other people to be made, albeit only tentative ones. The following analysis therefore accepts only the rst law and rejects the second. It recognizes that the identication of entre-
191
preneurs is judgmental. The most favourable assessment of an individual is likely to be his own, followed (at some distance, possibly) by that of his family and friends. On the whole, the most sceptical assessments are likely to be made by those who have had no contact with the individual at all.
12.4
The matching of decisions to entrepreneurs exhibits another special feature of the market for entrepreneurs, namely the extreme heterogeneity of the commodity that is traded. The commodity is a decision-making service in particular, a service which leads to the making of the right decision. The right decision in this context is the best decision that can be made given the information that is available within the economy. To simplify the analysis it is assumed that each judgmental decision occupies one entrepreneur full-time for one period. To make the market for entrepreneurs like the representative market in neoclassical theory it would be necessary to assume that anyone identied as an entrepreneur could make any judgmental decision with equal success: in other words, that different decisions are perfectly substitutable. Likewise, it would be necessary to assume that any decision identied as judgmental could just as well be undertaken by any of the entrepreneurs: in other words, that different entrepreneurs are perfect substitutes in making any given decision. Under these conditions, market equilibrium would be achieved when the number of entrepreneurs was equal to the number of judgmental decisions that needed to be made. Such a concept of equilibrium is, however, largely irrelevant to the market for entrepreneurs. The reason is that the substitution possibilities described above do not exist. The problem of the heterogeneity of the commodity cannot be eliminated simply by postulating perfect substitutability, as in neoclassical economics. An alternative approach is to deny the possibility of substitution altogether. This approach asserts that each entrepreneur has superior judgment in respect of just one decision, and that, conversely, for each decision there is just one entrepreneur who has the necessary judgment to decide correctly. In this case each individual entrepreneur must be assigned to a particular decision. Equilibrium requires not only that in aggregate the number of entrepreneurs be equal to the number of judgmental decisions: it also requires that each entrepreneur be matched to the right decision. Essentially, therefore, there is not just one market for entrepreneurs: there are as many different markets as there are judgmental decisions to be made. In practice, this model is probably too restrictive: substitution possibilities do exist, though they are very limited. The equilibrium pairing of
192
Synthesis
decisions and entrepreneurs is not unique, though the number of possible combinations is small. In either case the question arises as to how the matching is administered. In discussing this it is most important not to reinvent the market mechanisms dismissed earlier in Chapter 6. These mechanisms are no more relevant to the market for entrepreneurs than they are to other markets. In analysing the market mechanism another peculiarity of the market for entrepreneurs becomes evident. This is the exceptional skill required for intermediation. As noted in Chapter 9, most markets rely upon intermediation to facilitate adjustment. One of the major roles of the market maker is to screen for quality, but, as noted above, screening for the quality of an entrepreneur is exceptionally difcult. Intermediation in the market for entrepreneurs is normally conducted by what may be called the entrepreneurial rm. The entrepreneurial rm has an elaborate network of contacts which enables it to identify judgmental decisions. These decisions concern the appraisal of investment projects designed to exploit potential opportunities for coordination. The rm also has sophisticated screening procedures which enable it to identify entrepreneurial ability with a reasonable degree of success. It also has internal procedures to match individual entrepreneurs to particular decisions. Normally, the entrepreneurs are hired as delegates; they are salaried employees who combine their individual responsibilities for relatively minor decisions with a responsibility for collaborating on major decisions. The matching of decisions and entrepreneurs is achieved by a two-stage process in which the entrepreneurial rm rst enters the labour market to hire entrepreneurial employees, and subsequently makes internal assignments of entrepreneurs to particular decisions. The ability of the rm to supervise its employees enables it to improve its assessment of each entrepreneur in the light of each decision he makes. Information on the outcome of each decision is captured by the rm and used to determine the best subsequent assignment for the entrepreneur concerned. Thus the longer the entrepreneur remains with the rm the more efcient the assignments are likely to become. Because of the inherent difculties of screening, not everyone with entrepreneurial ability can be matched to the appropriate post in an entrepreneurial rm. For example, it is economic for rms to use state educational qualications as a part of their screening criteria, which means that educationally disadvantaged entrepreneurs may be unable to nd employment with a rm. This in turn means that they have to nd their capital for themselves. Banks have evolved to intermediate between self-employed entrepreneurs and their lenders, but banks face somewhat similar problems in intermediation to the entrepreneurial rms. If the entrepreneur is personally wealthy, or has good social contacts, then obtaining nance may be no problem, but otherwise
193
capital requirements may prove an insuperable barrier to entry into entrepreneurship. Another consequence of inaccurate screening is that people without ability may decide to become entrepreneurs. They may be appointed to posts in entrepreneurial rms, in which case these rms bear most of the losses which arise when they make the wrong decision. Alternatively, they may go into business on their own account, in which case they bear the losses themselves (except for losses that are shifted onto their backers if and when they go bankrupt). It is assumed, to begin with, that screening is perfectly efcient in preventing people without ability from becoming entrepreneurs; the only problem with screening procedures is that they also prevent some people with ability from becoming entrepreneurs. This simplifying assumption means that, in terms of the concepts introduced in Chapter 4, anyone who becomes an entrepreneur is a potential leader; followers and failures are eliminated before they can start. Another consequence of this assumption is that the risk of becoming an entrepreneur is understated, for anyone who becomes an entrepreneur is assured that they have the ability to succeed. Some of the consequences of relaxing this assumption are considered in Section 12.6. A person who has entrepreneurial ability and access to capital in one form or another is said to be a qualied entrepreneur. Typically, a qualied entrepreneur is either educationally qualied, personally wealthy or has good social contacts. A person who has entrepreneurial ability but no access to capital is said to be unqualied; to all intents and purposes he may as well have no ability either, for whatever ability he has cannot be exploited.
12.5
In the analysis below there are just two categories of people: the qualied entrepreneurs and the rest. The proportion of able entrepreneurs who are qualied is determined by the screening procedures of the market makers. To simplify the analysis further, it is assumed that each entrepreneur is responsible not only for taking decisions but for identifying these decisions for himself. The activities of the market makers do not extend to identifying decisions on his behalf. This assumption avoids having to analyse simultaneously the activities of two different categories of entrepreneur: the entrepreneur who takes judgmental decisions and the entrepreneur who identies the judgmental decisions to which other entrepreneurs can be matched. The analysis below is essentially concerned with an economy in which the entrepreneur is either a salaried manager or a self-employed businessman and
194
Synthesis
the market maker is, respectively, a large rm or a bank. The market makers stop anyone without entrepreneurial ability from becoming an entrepreneur, but they also stop some people with entrepreneurial ability from becoming entrepreneurs. Thus the individual entrepreneur identies and takes his own judgmental decision and the market makers decide, on the basis of his personal characteristics, whether he shall have permission to proceed. The nature of the reward to entrepreneurship was discussed in the earlier chapters of this book. When an entrepreneur takes a decision with which everyone else, either implicitly or explicitly, disagrees, he can, in a manner of speaking, bet against other people. The bet can take many forms, of which the conventional bet is an insignicant and fairly trivial case. Stock market speculation is more signicant, but the most important types of bet concern the innovation of new technologies or new products. The entrepreneur anticipates that his superior judgment will be conrmed by the way that events turn out. His own beliefs will be proved correct and the beliefs of those who bet against him will be proved false. When the entrepreneur is proved correct his opponents will have to pay up; this payment is a reward to the entrepreneurs superior judgment. A necessary condition for the entrepreneur to be able to bet on favourable terms is that no one else attempts to compete in making the same bet (or, if they do, the size of their bet is insignicant). The most important barrier to competitors is secrecy; the entrepreneur must keep to himself the information upon which he believes his superior judgment is based. No single item of information need be vital; it is the synthesis of information achieved by the entrepreneur that has to be unique. Consider now the long-run factors inuencing entry to, and exit from, the market for entrepreneurs. In the long run, people are attracted into entrepreneurship by the rewards they believe it offers. An important inuence on these rewards will be the pace of change in the economy. If large unforeseen changes are continually occurring, and information about each of these changes is initially localized, the scope for judgmental decision taking is very great. There is ample opportunity for the entrepreneur to take a dissenting view of some situation, based upon privileged access to information. The individual entrepreneurs share of these rewards will, however, depend crucially upon the number of other entrepreneurs in the economy. The more qualied entrepreneurs there are, the smaller is the chance of any one entrepreneur being the rst to identify any given judgmental decision. Furthermore, the greater the number of qualied entrepreneurs, the greater is the chance that two entrepreneurs will simultaneously identify the same judgmental decision. If each knew that the other had identied it, they could collude, or one could withdraw to allow the other a free hand in making the decision and exploiting it. But if neither knows that the other has identied it, then they
195
will unwittingly compete against each other, driving prices up or down against themselves and eliminating their entrepreneurial reward. With competition of this kind the gains from coordination will accrue exclusively to the parties with whom they trade. Even if identication of the judgmental decision is not simultaneous, the presence of many entrepreneurs will reduce the average lag before a competitor appears. This will reduce the duration of the entrepreneurs temporary monopoly and make it more difcult for him to erect a barrier to competition in the short time that is available. It must be recognized, of course, that an increase in the number of entrepreneurs will increase the proportion of the judgmental decisions that can be identied in any given period. Thus one entrepreneurs identication of a judgmental decision is not necessarily at the expense of some other entrepreneur. When the number of entrepreneurs is small, and the proportion of judgmental decisions identied is low, then the main effect of the entry of an additional entrepreneur will be to increase the proportion of judgmental decisions that are identied and the probability of an overlap with an existing entrepreneur is small. But as the number of entrepreneurs increases, so the probability of overlap rises and the increase in the proportion of judgmental decisions identied diminishes. In effect, there is increasing congestion between entrepreneurs in identifying judgmental decisions. The expected reward to entrepreneurship diminishes, not only because the rewards have to be shared out between more entrepreneurs, but because the total reward available to entrepreneurs diminishes on account of competition between them in exploiting the opportunities they nd. An individuals decision upon whether to become an entrepreneur will be based on a comparison of the expected reward to entrepreneurship and the reward to the best alternative use of his time. The individual has a choice of three full-time occupations: entrepreneurship, non-entrepreneurial labour or leisure. Non-entrepreneurial labour receives a competitive wage. Two main kinds of non-entrepreneurial labour may be distinguished. The rst is manual work and the second is non-judgmental decision making (or administration for short). To simplify the analysis it is assumed that all individuals are equally able at both. This implies that no-one has a comparative advantage in manual work rather than administration, so that the competitive wage is the same for both. It also implies that an individuals comparative advantage in entrepreneurship vis--vis non-entrepreneurial work entirely reects his absolute advantage as an entrepreneur. Consider rst the qualied entrepreneurs who value their leisure at less than the prevailing wage. The best alternative to entrepreneurship for these people is other work that is, manual work or administration. The supply of entrepreneurs from this group will be innitely elastic at the prevailing real wage. On the other hand, those who value their leisure more highly than the
196
Synthesis
wage will nd leisure the best alternative to entrepreneurship. The supply of entrepreneurs from this group will begin only when the expected reward to entrepreneurship exceeds the real wage. Those who value their leisure least will be drawn into entrepreneurship rst and as the expected reward increases so those who value their leisure more highly will be drawn in too. Thus there is an upward-sloping supply curve of entrepreneurs above the prevailing real wage. In Figure 12.1 the schedule DD shows how, conditional upon the expected rate of change, the expected reward per entrepreneur varies with the number of entrepreneurs. The schedule DD is not a demand curve in the conventional sense, though the analogy with a demand curve is useful if it is employed with care. The supply of entrepreneurs is illustrated by the schedule SS, which has an innitely elastic portion at the prevailing real wage OW, and is upward-sloping thereafter. (The supply curve never becomes backward-slop-
Figure 12.1
197
ing because each individual is committed to either full-time entrepreneurship or full-time leisure for the period concerned.) The schedules DD and SS intersect at E, corresponding to an expected reward OV accruing to each of ON entrepreneurs. Suppose that initially the number of entrepreneurs was ON1 < ON. At this point the expected reward to entrepreneurship would exceed the opportunity cost, and additional entrepreneurs would be drawn in. They would be drawn in rst from non-entrepreneurial employment and then from leisure. As the number of entrepreneurs increased, so the expected reward to entrepreneurship would fall and the opportunity cost of entrepreneurship would increase. When the expected reward had fallen to OV, there would be no incentive to enter and the situation would stabilize. The expected total reward to entrepreneurship in the steady state is measured by the shaded area OVEN. It is important to recognize that this mechanism of adjustment differs from the kind of market mechanism that is usually considered. The market is equilibrated by individuals response to quantity signals and not price signals. The quantity signal is the number of entrepreneurs that are active. Each individual needs to know the total number of entrepreneurs already active in order to impute a price to his entrepreneurial services. This imputed price governs his decision upon how to use his time. If the demand curve and supply curve remain sufciently stable, then the market will adjust to a steady state over time. The condition that demand is stable is equivalent to a condition that there is a steady pace of change. The condition that the supply curve is stable is much more complex. In principle, there is little reason why individuals should change their valuations of leisure, and hence why the upward-sloping portion of the supply curve should change. However, the remaining portion of the supply curve is governed by the productivity of manual work and administration, which depend on a range of factors, some of which are quite volatile. The implications of this simple model are quite straightforward. Although in the short run the reward of the entrepreneur is a monopoly reward to information, in the long run it is simply compensation for time and effort: namely, for the time and effort spent in identifying and making judgmental decisions. The equilibrium reward is greater, the greater is the demand for entrepreneurs and the smaller is their supply. The demand for entrepreneurs depends upon the pace of change in the economy. The faster change occurs, the greater will be the demand and the higher the reward to the entrepreneur. The relevant concept of supply is the supply of qualied entrepreneurs. The supply will be greater the greater is the stock of entrepreneurial ability among the population; the more effective are the screening procedures of the intermediaries in identifying entrepreneurial ability, the more likely it is that able entrepreneurs rejected by the screening procedures have personal wealth of
198
Synthesis
their own, and that those without wealth have the social contacts necessary to procure nance elsewhere. In summary, therefore, the reward to entrepreneurship depends upon the pace of economic change, the distribution of personal wealth, and the social and institutional framework of the economic system as a whole.
12.6
So far it has been assumed that an individuals decision to become an entrepreneur is based solely upon the expected reward. This implies either that the individual perceives no risk in becoming an entrepreneur or that he is indifferent to risk. The only other possibility is that becoming an entrepreneur is neither more nor less risky than undertaking manual work. None of these conditions is likely to be satised in practice. Even a person with entrepreneurial ability cannot guarantee that his judgment will always turn out completely successfully. Perhaps the greatest risk to an individual in becoming an entrepreneur, however, is uncertainty about whether he has the ability or not. An individual with ability is exposed to a much lower probability of loss than is one without it. As noted earlier, entrepreneurial ability is notoriously difcult to screen for; certainly, introspection is an unreliable guide. It is possible that some entrepreneurs may specialize in screening other entrepreneurs for ability, in which case an entrepreneur may be able to reduce his own uncertainty by undergoing screening by others. However, although the entrepreneurs who do the screening presumably have condence in their own methods, this condence may not be shared by others. In particular, those on whom the screeners reach a negative verdict may in turn reject the screeners methods. This does not imply that those who reject the screeners verdict are necessarily certain that they have ability. The validity of the screening procedures is to some extent a subjective issue about which opinions may rightly differ. Those who have been rejected may simply doubt whether the procedures are of any value merely to preserve their self-esteem. In this case they remain subjectively just as uncertain as they were before about whether or not they have ability. The only widely endorsed test of entrepreneurial ability is to try it out in practice. In principle, the trial could be conducted on a small scale, but there is a risk that, if the trial is on too small a scale, then technical diseconomies may bias the outcome towards failure. The existence of a minimum scale for a fair trial and the consequent need for an irreducible amount of capital to be ventured represents perhaps the major risk in becoming an entrepreneur. In comparing entrepreneurship with other activities, therefore, the expected reward to entrepreneurship must carry a premium to compensate for the
199
unavoidable risk incurred in discovering whether or not the individual concerned has entrepreneurial ability. This premium must be added to the manual wage, or to the value of leisure (whichever is the higher) in measuring the opportunity cost of becoming an entrepreneur.
SUMMARY
This chapter has analysed how the number of entrepreneurs and their rewards are determined. In the short run the entrepreneurs reward is a temporary monopoly rent to superior judgment; this monopoly can sometimes be consolidated by erecting barriers to entry. In the long run the prospect of monopoly rents will attract entrepreneurs into searching for information; they hope to achieve superior judgment by synthesizing this information. Some people are naturally better at synthesizing information than others. This ability, however, is difcult to recognize. People with ability may be unable to proceed with a search for information if other people are unwilling to give them nancial backing. People with ability still need personal wealth, educational qualication or good social contracts in order to enter entrepreneurial activities. Likewise, people without ability may try their hand as entrepreneurs; if they do so, then either they or their backers may incur heavy losses. The opportunity cost of becoming an entrepreneur is equal to the wage income forgone plus a premium for a risk incurred. Market equilibrium is achieved at the point where the expected reward to the marginal entrepreneur is just equal to his opportunity cost. The demand for entrepreneurs is related to the pace of change in the economy, whilst the supply of entrepreneurs depends upon the amount of entrepreneurial ability and the system of screening for it; the latter reects in turn the organization of education, the social structure and the personal distribution of wealth. Equilibrium in the market for entrepreneurs is achieved not by contract but by conjecture. Because information is in common ownership, search cannot be coordinated through contractual arrangements. Entrepreneurs must conjecture the behaviour of other entrepreneurs, and only if these conjectures are mutually consistent will equilibrium be achieved.
One of the main reasons why the entrepreneur has become a cultural hero of capitalism is that he is able to rise from humble origins to a position of power and status. His career reafrms the ideal of an open society in which the underprivileged can achieve eminence on the basis of their personal merit alone. The personal qualities which are rewarded through entrepreneurship are imagination and foresight, and skill in organizing and delegating work. The object of this chapter is to show that this heroic vision of the entrepreneur is, to a large extent, unfounded. Although there are, in most generations and in most societies, some people from humble origins who make it to the top, there are no grounds in theory or in practice for supposing that the probability of making it to the top through entrepreneurship is very high. There are major economic and social barriers to entrepreneurship which someone with potentially superior judgment may well be unable to overcome. The signicance of entrepreneurship is not that it is an easy avenue of personal advancement, but that in comparison with other methods of personal advancement it may offer the best prospects to underprivileged people. In other words, an economically disadvantaged person who wishes to make it to the top may nd it easier to do so through entrepreneurship than through other means. This means that entrepreneurship is of relative importance in social mobility, even if the absolute degree of mobility it affords is fairly limited.
13.2
Before proceeding to the main discussion it is important to emphasize that entrepreneurship can take many different forms depending upon the economic system in which the entrepreneur is operating. The functional denition of entrepreneurship given in Chapter 2 is essentially institution-free: it describes a function which is, in principle, performed in all societies by people whose judgment differs from the norm. Economic systems can be classied in many ways. There is an obvious distinction between a market economy, which relies upon coordination by
200
201
voluntary exchange in external markets, and a command economy, which relies upon coordination by control within internal markets. The market economy depends to a large extent upon goods being in private ownership (and transferable ownership at that). The command economy can also function under private ownership: that, after all, is what the rm is, a command economy in a market environment. On the other hand, when all goods are in public ownership, the economy is perforce a command economy; there is no scope for markets because there is no-one else with whom the state can exchange goods. Finally, when all goods are in common ownership both markets and commands remain in abeyance: under common ownership coordination is possible only by conjecture. Economic systems also differ in the way that ownership is acquired in the rst place. Most systems provide for the intergenerational transfer of private property either at the discretion of the owner or through social convention (for example, the enforcement of primogeniture). Some systems provide for the private appropriation of newly discovered resources, while others do not. Most systems provide for the expropriation of private property by the state, though the constitutional constraints upon this differ considerably from one society to another. Most societies employ a mixture of different economic systems. Typically, different systems are applied to the control of different types of resource. Each system affords some scope for entrepreneurship, though some systems afford much more scope than others. This means that in a typical society the entrepreneur has a choice of institutions within which to exercise his function. This in turn implies that entrepreneurship offers, not a single avenue of advancement, but a number of different avenues, reecting the different kinds of institution available. Consider, therefore, an individual living in a society which has a mixture of different economic institutions: the sort of mixture that prevails in most developed Western economies. The individual concerned is dissatised with the status and the standard of living that he currently enjoys. In the case of a young person he is dissatised with the prospects for a typical person with his kind of background. All sorts of people may come into this category. The individual may come from a very poor family and have a strong desire for conspicuous consumption. He may come from a middle-class family and dislike the prospect of being placed in a secure professional niche. He may be an achiever who has had high aspirations bred into him, or inculcated through his early upbringing. Or he may just be a rebel, perhaps someone who has such a high opinion of himself that nothing is ever good enough for him. In either case it is assumed that the person concerned is motivated to remedy the situation. He does not just aspire to success but has the determination to work for it too.
202
Synthesis
The various avenues of entrepreneurial advancement available to him are indicated in the left-hand column of Table 13.1. Self-employment and salaried management have already been discussed in detail (see Chapter 12). Both involve identifying opportunities for market making, or for designing and operating more efcient production plants, and so on. These opportunities are exploited by purchasing resources in order to control them more effectively. Financial speculation, on the other hand, involves purchasing resources without seeking to exercise control over them. The idea is to resell the resources later for a capital gain. The speculator relies upon the resources appreciating in value once the information upon which he is acting becomes known to the market as a whole. Each of these types of entrepreneurship depends upon the voluntary exchange of private property rights; they are manifestations of private entrepreneurship. The main alternative to private entrepreneurship is establishment entrepreneurship, which involves exercising judgment over resources owned by public and other non-prot-oriented organizations. The term establishment is used to indicate that the organization enjoys considerable social status. Establishment organizations include the civil service, the armed forces, universities and the established church. It should be emphasized that not all decisions made within these bodies are concerned with the allocation of resources at least not on a narrow denition of resource. Within the terms of our denition, therefore, the exercise of judgment in such organizations is not always, strictly speaking, entrepreneurial. A non-prot-oriented organization typically has a very elaborate and rigid hierarchical structure; indeed, this may be a direct consequence of the lack of prot criteria. As a result, the entrepreneurs objective is quite simply to get to the top of the hierarchy. He hopes that the exercise of his superior judgment will be rewarded by rapid promotion. It is not unreasonable, therefore, to describe the strategy of establishment entrepreneurship as pyramid climbing. Salaried entrepreneurs, too, advance themselves by pyramid climbing, but because the pyramids in the private sector are less formal, and rewards are related not merely to position but to prot, the strategy is not so paramount as it is within the establishment. Political entrepreneurship provides advancement through election to a governing ofce. The salaries associated with political posts are often relatively low, but the power and status afforded by the ofce may often be a reward in itself. Moreover, inuence can often be exercised to obtain pecuniary rewards, ranging from consulting fees and remuneration for non-executive directorships to bribes. The political entrepreneur needs to exercise judgment both before and after his election to ofce. The judgment exercised prior to his election is not dissimilar to the judgment exercised by a private entrepreneur. To secure
Table 13.1
Type of entrepreneur Private entrepreneur Self-employed owner of rm Salaried manager Financial speculator Establishment entrepreneur (pyramid climber) Political entrepreneur Revolutionary entrepreneur Criminal entrepreneur
Status
Subject of judgment
Partial
Opportunities for making markets, building plants, etc Valuation of resources Means to achieve non-prot objectives
Yes Yes
Yes No
Partial
Yes
Note:
203
204
Synthesis
adoption and then election it is normally necessary to present a personal manifesto. A manifesto is a package of policies, and is advertised by a set of promises (or claims) of varying degrees of sincerity. The political entrepreneur attempts to spot a gap in the market for manifestos, and to exploit it using a novel policy mix. The analogy should not be overplayed, however. There are at least three important differences between the political and the private entrepreneur. First, the success of the manifesto is determined by a voting mechanism and not a price mechanism. Secondly, once elected, the political entrepreneur has to exercise further judgment in carrying out his policies. His product is not actually delivered until his policies are implemented. Finally, the politician is normally elected for a xed term of ofce, so that the electors cannot revise their purchasing arrangements whenever they like. This affords considerable protection to the politician who cannot deliver the promises he has made. These factors lead to important differences in the tactical behaviour of politicians and private entrepreneurs. They also have obvious implications for the quality of the product supplied to the consumers (the electorate). Revolution and crime are both illegal forms of entrepreneurship (though inevitably a successful revolution acquires retrospective legality). Petty crime does not involve a signicant element of judgment, only a willingness to contravene laws that most other people are willing to respect. It is normally only organized crime that qualies as being entrepreneurial, as it involves the selection of targets that other criminals might well consider too risky or too difcult. Crime exemplies coordination which is private but not social. The simplest crime is theft, which involves the involuntary redistribution of property. Extortion is somewhat more sophisticated, as it involves the sale of protection (often against theft). Extortion has the advantage that it avoids the perpetration of crimes which harm the victim more than they benet the criminal; the criminal makes a market in protection and can appropriate the gains from trade with his potential victim. Extortion therefore involves social coordination with respect to the perpetration of the crime, though not, obviously, with respect to a situation in which the law is obeyed. Perhaps the most entrepreneurial crime is racketeering, which involves the organization of an illegal market: for example, the market for alcoholic drinks under prohibition. Racketeering involves the same skills as any other form of intermediation, in particular skill in inventory management. It is riskier than conventional intermediation because of the possibility of detection and punishment. The racketeer will demand a higher rate of prot to compensate for the risk involved. The higher prot will be earned because the additional risk will deter potential competitors, and so enhance the racketeers monopoly power. The racketeer may even apply additional deterrents of his own, for example the assassination of rivals; for when devising barriers to
205
entry there is no reason why the racketeer should conne himself to legal means.
13.3
Entrepreneurship, of whatever kind, is not the only method of social advancement. Table 13.2 distinguishes three alternatives, though there are undoubtedly others. Competitive professionalism involves pursuing an activity which affords high rewards to people with exceptional ability. It is exemplied by the career of a professional entertainer or a sportsman. In many cases rivalry and Table 13.2 Alternative methods of advancement and their requirements Requirement Social contact with establishment
Method Entrepreneurship Private Self-employment Salaried management Financial speculation Pyramid climbing Political representation Revolutionary activity Crime Non-entrepreneurial methods Competitive professionalism Marriage Hard work and thrift
Note:
Capital
A A A
G G G G G V G
A E A
V E A
206
Synthesis
excellence are key elements in the profession; exceptional ability is required because only being the best, or being rst, will do. Competitive professionalism is risky in at least two ways. First, the career may end prematurely, if fashions change, injuries are sustained, and so on; even the most distinguished careers may be very short as a result. Secondly, it is often difcult for an individual entering a competitive profession to know whether or not he has the ability to succeed. A long time can be spent struggling for recognition which may never come. There is no completely reliable way of screening for the degree of excellence that is required in the competitive professions. It is necessary for an individual to work his way up from the bottom before he can discover whether he has what it takes to compete at the top. The professionals success does not depend upon the continual exercise of superior judgment, but it does involve an initial act of judgment in assessing his own personal ability. Like the entrepreneurs qualities, the professionals qualities are difcult to screen for, so that he has to bear most of the risks himself. The professional must risk his own time and effort in getting his career under way, in the same way that the self-employed entrepreneur risks his capital in getting his business started. In both cases the individual makes an entrepreneurial assessment of whether the probability of success is sufcient to compensate for the cost of getting started. Somewhat similar considerations apply to the second method of social advancement: marriage. In this context marriage represents any strategy of social advancement which seeks to exploit the system of inheritance, dowry or patronage. This system is, of course, a largely traditional and informal one, so that the nancial prospects of a marriage may be insecure. Risks also arise because of the element of competition in the courting of particularly wealthy brides (and bridegrooms, too, for that matter). There is clearly some scope for entrepreneurial judgment in selecting suitable targets which other fortune hunters may have overlooked. Judgment is, however, probably only a small part of the competitive process; personal charm and social connections are probably the most important factors. It is on this basis that social advancement through marriage has been classied as a non-entrepreneurial activity. The nal method of advancement is hard work and thrift. In one sense this is decidedly non-entrepreneurial; taken by itself it is a dull and unimaginative strategy. On the other hand, many social historians have identied industry and thrift as key elements in the ethos of enterprising societies. The explanation offered below is that industry and thrift are useful adjuncts to entrepreneurial advancement because they allow the self-employed entrepreneur to accumulate sufcient wealth to get his business off the ground.
207
13.4
CONSTRAINTS ON ADVANCEMENT
When planning his social advancement, an individual must consider the requirements for the successful pursuit of each of the strategies outlined above. Four main requirements may be distinguished: capital (that is, personal wealth), social contact with the establishment, formal qualications and personal ability. The kind of ability and the type of qualications required will obviously depend upon the strategy involved. Capital is absolutely essential for the nancial speculator. Without capital he cannot purchase nancial assets, for example equities, that he believes will appreciate in value. Capital requirements are to some extent reduced when an organized option market exists; they are also reduced if rms are highly geared. In either of these cases the speculator can purchase his gamble without contributing signicantly to the overall funding of the rm. Even options and the equities of highly-geared rms have a positive value, however, and so, while the capital constraint is eased, it is not eliminated altogether. Capital is also an important requirement for the self-employed entrepreneur. For example, a self-employed market maker may have to invest in advertising and in inventory before his trading can commence. It is difcult for him to borrow because potential lenders do not necessarily share his views, and so may regard the collateral provided by his inventory as rather poor. The obvious way for the market maker to overcome the capital constraint is either to take employment as a manager (with a salary linked to his marketmaking performance) or to save up capital by taking routine work before commencing his entrepreneurial career. It is interesting to reect that in most developed economies there has been a signicant move away from the strategy of thrift towards the strategy of managerial employment. This change has been accompanied by a decline of the ethos of industry and thrift. It is not clear if there is any causal connection between these phenomena or, if there is, in what direction the causation works. It is possible, though, that both these phenomena are linked to a third phenomenon: the rise of formal procedures for screening entrepreneurial ability. It has been repeatedly emphasized that it is impossible to screen perfectly for entrepreneurial ability; and the higher the level of ability is set, the less reliable screening procedures become. Nevertheless, there exist many organizations especially the large conglomerate rms which appear to specialize in screening entrepreneurs. A major instrument in the screening process is the qualication issued by a university, management school or professional association. People with suitable qualications are taken on as probationary salaried entrepreneurs, and in this way can use their qualications as an alternative to personal wealth in getting started on their entrepreneurial career. The devel-
208
Synthesis
opment of high-level education and the sophisticated screening procedures associated with it may therefore explain the marked trend towards managerial entrepreneurship. The enhanced opportunities for managerial entrepreneurship may in turn account for the apparent atrophy of the ethos of industry and thrift. The other main use of formal qualications is in the establishment sector of the economy. Here, it may be suggested, formal qualications act as a substitute for social contact. Institutions which previously recruited from a very limited social group now recruit on the basis of formal qualications instead. Aristocracy has given way to meritocracy: the social background of the establishment entrepreneurs may be more diverse as a result, but in some respects their educational background may be just as restricted. Indeed, the greater time in the formative years that is now spent in academic and professional training may lead to a greater uniformity of outlook in the establishment than there was before. Perhaps the most open avenue of advancement is competitive professionalism, where capital, social contacts and formal qualications have only a relatively minor role. Competitive professionalism depends crucially on personal ability, though, and the development of ability depends in turn upon access to education and training. In the context of social mobility it is not just the overall level of educational provision that matters, but the way in which admission is regulated. The competitive professional from humble origins depends upon the free provision of facilities, not just of a basic kind, but up to a very advanced level. Since advanced facilities are often expensive, and access to them consequently very limited, he is also dependent upon a system of selective advancement by merit. Fortunately, experience suggests that most societies, whether totalitarian or democratic, encourage social advancement through sport and artistic excellence, and so on, and administer their facilities with these criteria in mind. Their motives, of course, may differ; some societies may support the system for providing equality of opportunity while others may regard it as a means of maximizing the supply of talent for enhancing national status and prestige.
13.5
The educational system also has implications for the development of entrepreneurial abilities. Table 13.3 summarizes the various ways in which abilities may be acquired. Perhaps the most interesting point is that further education is shown as advantageous, but not essential, for the private entrepreneur. This reects the view, rst, that professional skills are not essential to the private entrepreneur provided that he knows how to delegate to professionals and to
209
Table 13.3
Personal abilities and the way they are acquired Requirements Academic eduction Innate ability E A A E E Basic E E E E Further A E A A A E Training
Method of advancement for which ability is required Private entrepreneurship Pyramid climbing Political representation Revolutionary activity Crime Competitive professionalism
Note:
A = advantageous, E = essential.
motivate those that he employs. More signicantly, however, it recognizes that in some respects further education may positively disadvantage the entrepreneur. Formal education has an opportunity cost in terms of on-the-job training forgone; time spent in academic pursuits could have been spent learning the trade as a delegateentrepreneur. The training may, of course, follow on from the formal education, in which case the formal education merely delays the start of the entrepreneurs career. But in some cases formal education is used to obtain qualications which give exemption from all or part of the practical training. This exchange of formal education for practical training has two disadvantages. First, it means that the entrepreneur may begin his career in a post where he is delegating tasks which he has never had to perform himself, and as a result the motivation he can supply to his delegates and the quality of supervision he can offer may be very poor. Secondly, formal education may inculcate uniform attitudes among entrepreneurs and so destroy the individuality and diversity of their views. The essence of entrepreneurship is difference of opinion, while the emphasis of much formal education is on conformity of opinion instead. There is also a tendency in formal education to raise only the questions which can be answered precisely, and to avoid issues to which no denitive solution can be given. Entrepreneurship, on the other hand, is very much concerned with situations which cannot be easily dened and often cannot even be categorized because they are without precedent. In this context the concept of a precise solution is irrelevant; precision can only be obtained by introducing arbitrary assumptions, or by changing the question to another one. This highlights why it is that academic training, and the use of aca-
210
Synthesis
demic qualications, has a very limited role in developing and screening entrepreneurs.
13.6
The preceding analysis generates a number of hypotheses about the sort of people who will opt for each particular strategy of social advancement. It suggests, to begin with, that advancement by entrepreneurship is most suitable for people who lack the exceptional abilities required for competitive professionalism. It is relatively easy to enter competitive professionalism, but very difcult to succeed. Exceptional ability is also required for social advancement by revolution: charismatic leadership, organizing ability and tactical awareness are all required if a revolution is to stand any chance of success. It is natural for people with good, though not exceptional, ability to get their ability underwritten by some sort of professional qualication. However, as noted above, becoming qualied calls not only for ability but also for a willingness to conform. People who cannot conform, however supercially, are liable to nd qualications difcult to obtain. As a result, they will nd it difcult to advance themselves as salaried managers or as pyramid climbers within the establishment. Social contact with the establishment is an additional requirement for advancement through pyramid climbing. It is advantageous, though not essential, in most other methods of entrepreneurial advancement too. The main exception is organized crime. Although many people may be deterred by moral scruples, and by the risk of detection and punishment, it is apparent that people without social contact have a comparative advantage in pursuing a criminal entrepreneurial career. Consider now an individual seeking advancement by entrepreneurship, who has adequate, though not exceptional, ability, a nonconformist attitude and a modicum of social contact with the establishment. The main avenues open to him are nancial speculation, self-employment and political representation. The main difference between these methods lies in the amount of capital they require. Financial speculation typically requires a large amount of capital so that personal wealth is practically essential; it is a method by which those who are already wealthy can become much wealthier still. Selfemployment requires a modest amount of capital, of the sort that could reasonably be accumulated through industry and thrift. It could also be obtained through marriage, though to marry wealth is difcult for someone who has only a modicum of social contact with the establishment. The entrepreneur would have to rely upon a two-stage procedure in which the wealth
211
accumulated through industry and thrift is used to buy a way in to the establishment, and the opportunity is then exploited to make a favourable marriage. Advancement through political representation may require only a small amount of capital, at least in launching a political career at local level. Essentially, the political entrepreneur solicits votes in the same way that the private entrepreneur solicits capital from nancial backers: he sells his policies to his supporters so that he can gain control of their resources in the case of voters, the publicly owned resources that he controls in their name. The difference is that the political system provides a ready-made framework within which the political entrepreneur can operate, whereas the self-employed entrepreneur has to set up his own system in order to carry on trade or to produce his product. If it is true that there is easy entry into a political career, then the question arises as to why so many people should opt for self-employment instead. Looking back at Table 13.1, there are three main differences in the role of the politician and the self-employed businessman. To begin with, the self-employed person has greater autonomy, since he is a principal whereas the politician is a representative. This autonomy is likely to be important to the rugged individualist: that is, to the person who is by temperament a nonconformist. If the politician is to exploit the institutional framework of a political party, then he needs to accept the constraints of, for example, the committee system by which both parties and governments operate. No such constraints limit the discretion of the self-employed. Another, and very important, difference is that the self-employed businessman is concerned solely with effecting partial coordination, while the political entrepreneur is concerned with general coordination too (see Chapter 5). The general coordination may be effected at the local, national or international level. In either case the politician is dealing with much wider issues, and more far-reaching proposals for coordination, than is the businessman. The politician works on a broader canvas and pays correspondingly less attention to detail. The businessman seeks to exploit highly specic information within the existing economic order, while the politician uses more general and aggregative information to decide what the economic order should be. Because of the broader issues with which he deals, it is difcult to devise precise criteria by which the politicians performance can be evaluated. Different members of the electorate have different objectives and so will evaluate the same outcome in different ways. Because he deals with narrower issues, and has only his own objectives to consider, the self-employed businessman can operate with a single precise criterion, namely prot. The businessman therefore exercises his judgment in a much more disciplined environment than does the politician. For this reason, politicians and businessmen, though
212
Synthesis
both entrepreneurs, are in terms of their perceptions and attitudes, very different sorts of people. It is interesting to consider the political economy of entrepreneurship in the context of this difference in outlook between politicians and self-employed entrepreneurs. Left-wing politicians, in particular, are often highly critical of the activities of self-employed entrepreneurs, and revolutionaries in capitalist economies, of course, take an extreme attitude on this. For their part, the self-employed often regard politicians and revolutionaries merely as incompetents who would be certain to fail in business. It is possible to understand these attitudes in terms of the difference between partial and general coordination. It may be postulated that those who best understand how partial coordination works, and have the skill to effect it through market-making activities, cannot easily grasp the concept of general coordination as it relates to the reallocation of resources throughout the economy as a whole. They believe that, because it is impossible for any individual to reallocate resources for the entire economy in the same detail, and with the same precision, that they can be reallocated within an individual market, therefore the preparation of outline plans for economy-wide reallocation is a fruitless activity. Likewise, those who understand how general coordination can be achieved through a political process grossly underestimate the difculty of achieving it in microcosm by the operation of an individual market. This is not to say, of course, that the debate on the complex issue of alternative economic systems can be reduced to such a trivial level. But it does suggest a reason why sensible debate on this subject may be so difcult to achieve and why, as a result, popular criticism and support for the capitalist system is allowed to hinge upon a simple parody of the true entrepreneur. It is the selection mechanism, matching personal attitudes to different entrepreneurial roles, that in itself makes a common understanding of the nature of that mechanism so difcult to achieve.
13.7
So far nothing has been said about how religious and ethnic factors inuence the method of social advancement. It is not at all clear that the economist has the professional competence to analyse such issues. It is, however, fairly obvious that in principle both factors affect the kind of person who becomes a self-employed entrepreneur. First, religious views may inuence entrepreneurial temperament (or vice versa). Roman Catholicism, for example, identies personal salvation closely with membership of an institution the church and stresses conformity with this institutions outlook. Protestantism, on the other hand, denies the
213
need for institutional intermediation between the individual and his God. The stress is on individuality rather than conformity and is therefore much more conducive to an entrepreneurial outlook. Many religions emphasize self-denial, which is of course an inducement to thrift. They also emphasize stewardship, which favours maintaining control of assets that have been accumulated as a result of thrift. Some religions, notably Quakerism, discourage entry into certain elds of business and so encourage entrepreneurial activity to be concentrated on the remaining ones. It is not only the religion itself, of course, which constrains the entrepreneur. The attitudes of society towards people with minority religious beliefs also impose constraints. The constraints on religious minorities are typically most severe in establishment institutions, in which there may be formal screening for religious afliation. Social attitudes may also inhibit advancement through a political career, and through some of the professions too. Under these circumstances the anonymity of the market place may provide the most attractive cover for personal advancement. As a result, religious minorities, particularly those whose religions emphasize nonconformity, may predominantly pursue social advancement through self-employment. Religious and ethnic factors are often closely linked. Much of what has been said about religious outlook and attitudes towards religious minorities applies also to social and ethnic outlook, and to attitudes to ethnic minorities. The obvious conclusion is that ethnic minorities, as well as religious minorities, will pursue advancement through self-employment rather than through other means.
SUMMARY
This chapter has considered the alternative avenues of social advancement available to people who believe that they have superior judgment. It is suggested that self-employment is most attractive to people with good all-round ability rather than exceptional ability, with a modicum of social contact but an aversion to conformist institutions, a small amount of capital and a willingness to augment it by thrift, rather poor educational qualications and a tendency to focus on the partial aspects of coordination, rather than the general aspects which are important in the political sphere.
214
Synthesis
work has been done on the social origins of the US business elite: see Bendix and Howton (1959), Hughes (1966b), Mills (1945), Newcomer (1955), Redlich (194051) and Warner and Abegglen (1955a, 1955b). Much less work has been done on UK business elites, though see Copeman (1955), Erickson (1959), Lupton and Wilson (1959) and Sargent Florence (1961). Studies of business elites in other countries include Alexander (1964) (Greece), Marris and Somerset (1971) (Kenya), Nafziger (1978) (India), Papanek (1972) (Pakistan) and Sayigh (1962) (Lebanon). It is interesting that Frank Taussig, best known for his work on the theory of international trade, was sufciently interested in social mobility and business elites to produce two studies on the subject. Unfortunately the rst (Taussig, 1915) is rather cursory while the second (Taussig and Joslyn, 1932) provides a somewhat biased interpretation of the results (though his actual statistics are broadly in line with those reported by others). At the other end of the spectrum there have been a number of interesting studies of the origins and attitudes of small businessmen. See, for example, Ahmed (1977), Davids (1963), Fogarty (1973), Lynn (1974) and Pelzel (1965). Redlich has done some interesting work on the ability of establishment groups to switch into private entrepreneurship when their traditional status is assailed; see, for example, Redlich (1956, 1958). Recent research on social mobility as a whole is critically reviewed by Kaelble (1981). There is a large and very diffuse literature on cultural aspects of entrepreneurship: see in particular Belshaw (1965), Bendix (1957), Cochran (1958, 1965a, 1965b), Fleming (1979), Gerschenkron (1953), Lamb (1952), Owens (1978) and Plum (1977). The classic studies of religion and entrepreneurship are Fanfani (1935), Sombart (1915) and Weber (1930). Of these, the Weber thesis has attracted the greatest interest; for a review of the debate, see Green (1959). Smith, N.R. (1967) offers a simple classication of entrepreneurs according to their personal characteristics; the role of personality in entrepreneurship has also been considered by Collins and Moore (1964) and Jenks (1949, 1965). Criminal entrepreneurs have been studied by Blok (1974) and Smith, D.C. (1978), while Heyl (1978) considers entrepreneurship in prostitution.
This chapter critically reviews the leading economic theories of the entrepreneur: the X-efciency theory of Leibenstein, the market process theory of Hayek and Kirzner, the risk-bearing theory of Knight and the innovation theory of Schumpeter. It also examines the relevance to entrepreneurship of the theories of the rm developed by Andrews and Penrose. It is suggested that the theory presented above is in many respects a synthesis and extension of these theories. Although there are a number of differences between the theories on specic aspects of entrepreneurship, on the whole their similarities are more signicant than their differences. Each theory is valuable because it emphasizes some particular aspect of entrepreneurship. The theories are essentially complementary, both to each other and to the theory presented in this book.
14.2
Leibensteins X-efciency theory, originally developed for other purposes, has been applied by him to analyse the role of the entrepreneur. Basically, Xefciency is the degree of inefciency in the use of resources within the rm: it measures the extent to which the rm fails to realize its productive potential. For a given set of inputs, productive potential is identied with a point on the neoclassical production frontier. X-efciency arises either because the rms resources are used in the wrong way, or because they are wasted that is, they are not used at all. X-efciency is more than a concept, however; it is a new paradigm which, according to Leibenstein, contrasts starkly with the neoclassical paradigm. Where neoclassical theory assumes full rationality, in the sense that decision makers solve their problems using the calculus of maximization, X-efciency theory assumes that there are psychological costs of being fully rational. These limit the extent to which individuals plan to exploit all the opportunities available, and to satisfy all the constraints to which they are subject. If ex ante plans only approximate to actual constraints then ex post the plans will
215
216
Synthesis
turn out differently from what was expected. The more approximately an individual plans, the more likely it is that disequilibrium will result. The anticipation of disequilibrium leads to internally felt pressure. According to Leibenstein, individuals trade off constraint concern for pressure; different individuals have different attitudes, and hence exhibit different degrees of constraint concern and different degrees of neoclassical irrationality. Leibenstein identies four other differences between X-efciency theory and neoclassical theory. One is that contracts are incomplete: in particular, employment contracts do not specify jobs precisely, or quantify the amount of effort required. This in turn means, according to Leibenstein, that effort is discretionary: it is the employee himself, and not the employer, who decides how hard he will work. The employee will take this decision in pursuit of his own interests and not those of his employer. X-efciency theory also asserts that effort is required in order to change the allocation of resources: it is unpleasant to have to break old habits, and it takes time to settle into a new routine. This creates a psychological inertia which discourages the individual from adjusting from one state to another. Inertia, like constraint, is a personality characteristic. Finally, Leibenstein departs from simple neoclassical theory in regarding the rm as an organization of different individuals with no unanimity between them about objectives. The employer (or the shareholders, in the case of a joint-stock company) may be interested in maximizing prots, but the agents who are the actual decision makers are not. The agents pursue their own objectives, which are incompatible with maximum effort. The role of the organization is to apply pressure on the agents to maintain or increase their effort. The pressure is internal to the rm but external to the individual agent. The pressure increases the individuals constraint concern, raises his effort, and thereby moves the rm towards its neoclassical production frontier. Leibenstein regards entrepreneurship as a creative response to X-efciency. Other peoples lack of effort, and the consequent inefciency of the organizations that employ them, create opportunities for entrepreneurs. Entrepreneurial activities pose a competitive threat to an inefcient organization. This is translated into pressure on the agents which encourages them to maintain an adequate degree of constraint concern. Leibenstein identies two main roles for the entrepreneur. Input completion involves making available inputs which improve the efciency of existing production methods or facilitate the introduction of new ones. It is normally effected by intermediation in factor markets, in particular the markets for venture capital and management skills. The role of the entrepreneur is to improve the ow of information in these markets. The second role, gap lling, is closely akin to the arbitrage function emphasized by Kirzner, and described below. Leibenstein provides a very
217
vivid description of gap lling. He visualizes the economy as a net made up of nodes and pathways:
The nodes represent industries or households that receive inputs (or consumer goods) along the pathway and send outputs (nal goods and inputs for the other commodities) to the other nodes. The perfect competition model would be represented by a net that is complete: one that has pathways that are well marked and well dened, one that has well-marked and well-dened nodes, and one in which each element (that is rm or household) of each node deals with every other node along the pathways on equal terms for the same commodity. In the realistic model that we have in mind, there are holes and tears in the net, obstructions (knots) along the pathways, and some nodes and pathways, where they exist, are poorly dened and poorly marked or entirely unmarked from the viewpoint of elements of other nodes. We may refer to this net as impeded, incomplete, and dark in contrast to the unimpeded and well lit net that represents the competitive mode. (Leibenstein, 1978, p. 45)
Few people would probably now object to the gist of Leibensteins argument, though there remain some doubts about his method of analysis. Leibenstein seems to believe that his psychologism is incompatible with the neoclassical view of rational economic man. Yet the main thrust of the neoclassical rationality postulate is simply to rule out inconsistent behaviour. In a world where information is costly and thought has an opportunity cost of time and effort, Leibensteins individuals behave quite rationally. In operational terms their behaviour seems indistinguishable from rational individuals coping with the constraints imposed by limited information. For example, when information processing is costly, it is rational for an individual to apply the same decision rule habitually until a persistent disequilibrium is encountered and then, and only then, to modify it. Without some sort of rationality postulate it is difcult to predict what kind of decision rules will be used; but with a rationality postulate it is possible to identify optimal decision rules and to show how the optimal decision rule varies according to the circumstances. Thus, while the phenomena Leibenstein describes are real enough, his psychologism seems to hinder rather than help the explanation of them. The absence of any substitute for the rationality postulate in Leibensteins theory makes it compatible with a wide range of behaviour. It provides a framework of analysis which can accommodate practically anything. Unlike neoclassical theory, Leibensteins theory can accommodate the entrepreneur. But without further assumptions it can say very little about the way that entrepreneurs behave. There is little or nothing in Leibensteins theory which is incompatible with the theory presented in this book, but the present theory provides specic hypotheses about entrepreneurial behaviour which Leibensteins theory cannot.
218
Synthesis
14.3
Hayeks main contribution to the theory of the entrepreneur is to point out that the absence of entrepreneurs in neoclassical economics is intimately associated with the assumption of market equilibrium. According to Hayek the equilibrium postulate is equivalent to a postulate of full information; not full information in the sense of complete information about every conceivable thing, but full information in the sense that no further information is required in order to modify anyones decisions.
[Equilibrium] means only that the different plans which the individuals have made for action in time are mutually compatible. An equilibrium will continue, once it exists, so long as the external data correspond to the common expectations of all the members of the society. The continuance of a state of equilibrium in this sense is then not dependent on the objective data being constant in an absolute sense and is not necessarily conned to a stationary process It appears that the concept of equilibrium merely means that the foresight of the different members of the society is in a special sense correct. It must be correct in the sense that every persons plan is based on the expectation of just those actions of other people which those other people intend to perform and that all these plans are based on the expectation of the same set of external facts, so that under certain conditions nobody will have any reason to change his plans. Correct foresight is then not, as it has sometimes been understood, a precondition which must exist in order that equilibrium may be arrived at. It is rather a dening characteristic of a state of equilibrium. (Hayek, 1949, pp. 412)
According to Hayek, the empirical content of economics relates to the process of adjustment towards an equilibrium. This process involves the acquisition and communication of knowledge. The main hypothesis is that,
under certain conditions, the knowledge and intentions of the different members of society are supposed to come more and more into agreement or, to put the same thing in less general and less exact but more concrete terms, the expectations of the people and particularly of the entrepreneurs will become more and more correct . The only trouble is that we are still pretty much in the dark about (a) the conditions under which this tendency is supposed to exist and (b) the nature of the process by which individual knowledge is changed. (Hayek, 1949, p. 45)
Hayek himself goes only a short way towards answering these two questions. His main contention is that a decentralized process of voluntary exchange, based upon the price system, is more efcient than a centralized process based upon bureaucratic organization.
We must look at the price system as such a mechanism for communicating information if we want to understand its real function a function which, of course, it fulls less perfectly as prices grow more rigid. (Even when quoted
219
prices have become quite rigid, however, the forces which could operate through changes in price still operate to a considerable extent through changes in the other terms of the contract.) The most signicant fact about this system is the economy of knowledge with which it operates, or how little the individual participants need to know in order to be able to take the right action. In abbreviated form, by a kind of symbol, only the most essential information is passed on only to those concerned. It is more than a metaphor to describe the price system as a kind of machinery for registering change, or a system of telecommunications which enables individual producers to watch merely the movement of a few pointers, as an engineer might watch the hands of a few dials, in order to adjust their activities to changes of which they may never know more than is reected in the price movement. (Hayek, 1949, pp. 867)
By contrast, a centralized system effects a functional separation between those who acquire the information at rst hand, and those who aggregate and act upon the information at second hand. The lack of incentive, the sluggish response and the bureaucratic costs of centralized organization are, to Hayeks mind, overwhelming arguments in favour of decentralization. Fellow-economists who advocate centralization undervalue the market because it has evolved by trial and error and improvisation: it is just one of those formations which man has learned to use after he had stumbled upon it without understanding it. The market is not recognized as the marvel that it is because it is not the result of deliberate human design. Hayek visualizes a world in which there is a continuous process of discovery: not usually major discoveries such as technological breakthroughs, but mostly minor discoveries about individual wants at particular times and places. These discoveries are localized, so that different people have access to different information; in particular, most people know much more about themselves than they do about others. Markets help people to communicate their discoveries to others and to learn of discoveries that other people have made. This enables individuals to coordinate their decisions and thereby move towards a state of equilibrium. But Hayek stops short of modelling the process by which prices are set and by which they are adjusted towards an equilibrium. For Kirzner the adjustment of price is the main role of the entrepreneur. If the wrong price prevails in the market, then an opportunity for prot is created. Somewhere in the market is a frustrated buyer or seller who would be willing, respectively, to pay a higher price or accept a lower one. Then again, if different prices prevail in the same market, there is scope for protable arbitrage between the two segments of the market. Or if the prices of inputs are out of line with the prices of outputs then there is scope for expanding production of some products at the expense of others. According to Kirzner, alertness to disequilibrium is the distinguishing characteristic of the entrepreneur. Alertness enables some individuals to in-
220
Synthesis
tervene in the market by changing the price while other individuals simply respond by changing their buying and selling plans in the light of the newly quoted price. Rather disappointingly, however, the introduction of the concept of alertness signals the end, rather than the beginning, of Kirzners explanation of the market process:
We do not clearly understand how entrepreneurs get their ashes of superior foresight. We cannot explain how some men discover what is around the corner before others do. We may certainly explain how men explore for oil by carefully weighing alternative ways of spending a limited amount of search resources, but we cannot explain how a prescient entrepreneur realizes before others do that a search for oil may be rewarding. As an empirical matter, however, opportunities do tend to be perceived and exploited. And it is on this observed tendency that our belief in a determinate market process is founded. (Kirzner, 1976, p. 121)
The reason for this abrupt termination of the analysis does not seem to be any technical difculty, but rather a belief that further inquiry does not form part of a legitimate research agenda. As a disciple of von Mises, Kirzner maintains that the primary role of economic theory is to explain behaviour in terms of purposeful human action, and to consider to what extent purposeful human actions can interact to produce unexpected outcomes. To pursue the analysis of entrepreneurship further would be to go beyond the limits of this agenda. Worse than that, it would violate one of the tenets of Austrian subjectivism, namely that there is an indeterminacy and unpredictability inherent in human preferences, human expectations, and human knowledge. It is of course, quite conceivable that the entrepreneur believes other peoples actions to be predictable, and that that is why he intervenes in the market process. Conversely, anyone who believes that the entrepreneur is predictable has an incentive to intervene himself in the market process and so become an entrepreneur. To Kirzner this provides a satisfactory basis for asserting the inherent unpredictability of the entrepreneur. It suggests that no predictor can be anything but an entrepreneur himself, and so makes a predictive theory of entrepreneurship impossible.
14.4
Knight identies the entrepreneur as a recipient of pure prot. Prot is the residual income available after all contractual payments have been deducted from the revenues of the enterprise. It is the reward to the entrepreneur for bearing the costs of uncertainty. Knight identies uncertainty with a situation where the probabilities of alternative outcomes cannot be determined either by a priori reasoning or by
221
statistical inference. A priori reasoning is simply irrelevant to economic situations. Statistical inference is impossible because the situation involves a unique event. It does not belong to a larger population of identical events. In particular, there is no precedent for it, so that no assessment of probability can be made on the basis of relative frequency. This is the foundation for Knights distinction between uncertainty and risk. Uncertainty is a ubiquitous aspect of business decisions because production takes time. Decisions on inputs must be made now in order to create output for the future. Households, as factor owners, demand spot payment for their services. At the same time they are unwilling to commit themselves on future demand for the product, because they anticipate that unforseeable changes will occur.
But the consumer does not even contract for his goods in advance, generally speaking. A part of the reason might be the consumers uncertainty as to his ability to pay at the end of the period, but this does not seem to be important in fact. The main reason is that he does not know what he will want, and how much, and how badly; consequently he leaves it to producers to create goods and hold them ready for his decision when the time comes. The clue to the apparent paradox is, of course, in the law of large numbers, the consolidation of risks (or uncertainties). The consumer is, to himself, only one; to the producer he is a mere multitude in which individuality is lost. It turns out that an outsider can foresee the wants of a multitude with more ease and accuracy than an individual can attain with respect to his own. This phenomenon gives us the most fundamental feature of the economic system, production for a market. (Knight, 1921, p. 241)
Knight is mainly concerned to show how markets, together with institutions such as the large corporation, contribute to specializing uncertainty bearing in the hands of those best equipped to make decisions under uncertainty. The main quality required for making production decisions is foresight. Individuals differ in the amount of foresight they have, and competition ensures that individuals with the greatest degree of foresight (relative to other abilities) specialize in making production decisions. However, it does not follow that individuals with foresight will become selfemployed and make decisions on their own behalf. They may instead become managers of a large rm. Knight argues that business uncertainty can be reduced through consolidation. Consolidation is to uncertainty what insurance is to risk: it is a method of reducing total uncertainty by pooling individual instances and allowing each individual to hold a share of the pool. It is widely recognized today that an individuals exposure to uncertainty can be reduced through portfolio diversication in the equity market. Knight recognizes this possibility, which he calls diffusion, but does not accord it much prominence as a vehicle for the reduction of uncertainty. He believes that uncertainty is reduced mainly through the pooling of uncertainties by the large rm.
222
Synthesis
The gains in uncertainty reduction from large-scale organization are, in Knights view, quite considerable, so much so that the most important uncertainties relate, not to producing for a market itself, but to the selection of suitable managers to take production decisions. Once a person with foresight has been recruited by the rm, much of the uncertainty in producing for a market is eliminated. The crucial decisions made within the large rm are decisions about personnel recruitment. The pure prot generated by a large rm is compensation to people for bearing the uncertainty that they have delegated decisions to the wrong sort of person. Knight does not seem to anticipate that there will be much difculty in ensuring that managers with foresight exercise it properly on the stockholders behalf. The moral hazard problem is negligible, presumably because close supervision of the manager is possible. Much greater moral hazard arises with the directors of the rm who recruit the managers and supervise them on the stockholders behalf. The unavoidable moral hazard involved in delegating direction means that directors cannot possibly be fully insured against the consequences of their decisions. They must operate under protrelated incentives, and so effectively they must become stockholders in the rm. Thus directors who make decisions under uncertainty also bear the consequences of those decisions and are ipso facto recipients of pure prot. Some people have good judgment of other peoples abilities and others do not. But no-one can be certain of their own judgment of other peoples abilities. As a result, condence in his own judgment is perhaps the most important characteristic of the entrepreneur. This has to be coupled with a low aversion to risk, as reected in a disposition to back up his judgment with his own capital. The elasticity of supply of self-condent people is, in Knights view, the single most important determinant of the level of prot and of the number of entrepreneurs.
The income of any particular entrepreneur will in general tend to be larger (1) as he himself has ability, and good luck; but (2), perhaps more important, as there is in the society a scarcity of self-condence combined with the power to make effective guarantees to employees. The abundance or scarcity of mere ability to manage business successfully exerts relatively little inuence on prot: the main thing is the rashness or timidity of entrepreneurs (actual and potential) as a class in bidding up the prices of productive services. Entrepreneur income, being residual, is determined by the demand for these other services, which demand is a matter of the self-condence of entrepreneurs as a class, rather than upon a demand for entrepreneur services in a direct sense. We must see at once that it is perfectly possible for entrepreneurs as a class to sustain a net loss, which would merely have to be made up out of their earnings in some other capacity. This would be the natural result in a population combining low ability with high courage. On the other hand, if men generally judge their own abilities well, the general rate of prot will probably be low, whether ability itself is low or high, but
223
much more variable and uctuating for a low level of real capacity. The condition for large prots is a narrowly limited supply of high-grade ability with a low general level of initiative as well as ability. (Knight, 1921, pp. 2834)
Knights analysis exhibits very clearly the difculties of theorizing about entrepreneurship, and in particular the problems of structuring the analysis in a coherent way. As a result, Knights views have been widely misinterpreted in the past. Many parts of the present work are simply a reformulation of ideas rst presented by Knight. The concepts of probability and judgment are slightly different, but the basic view of the way that the market system allocates judgmental decision making to entrepreneurs is the same in both cases.
14.5
SCHUMPETER ON INNOVATION
Schumpeter, perhaps more than any other writer, is very explicit about the economic function of the entrepreneur. The entrepreneur is the prime mover in economic development, and his function is to innovate, or to carry out new combinations. Five types of innovation are distinguished: the introduction of a new good (or an improvement in the quality of an existing good), the introduction of a new method of production, the opening of a new market (in particular an export market in a new territory), the conquest of a new source of supply of raw-materials or half-manufactured goods and the creation of a new type of industrial organization, in particular the formation of a trust or some other type of monopoly. Anyone who performs this function is an entrepreneur, whether they are independent businessmen or the dependent employees of a company such as managers or directors. Not all businessmen are entrepreneurs: the typical entrepreneur is the founder of a new rm rather than the manager of an established one. Schumpeter is adamant that the entrepreneur is not a risk bearer. Risk bearing is the function of the capitalist who lends his funds to the entrepreneur. The entrepreneur bears risk only in so far as he acts as his own capitalist. Unlike Knight, Schumpeter does not perceive much problem of moral hazard for a capitalist lending to an entrepreneur. Entrepreneurs spend a lot of their time doing non-entrepreneurial things:
The entrepreneur of earlier times was not only as a rule the capitalist too, he was also often as he still is today in the case of small concerns his own technical expert, in so far as a professional specialist was not called in for special cases. Likewise he was (and is) often his own buying and selling agent, the head of his ofce, his own personnel manager, and sometimes, even though as a rule he of
224
Synthesis
course employed solicitors, his own legal adviser in current affairs. And it was performing some or all of these functions that regularly lled his days. The carrying out of new combinations can no more be a vocation than the making and execution of strategical decisions, although it is this function and not his routine work that characterizes the military leader. Therefore the entrepreneurs essential function must always appear mixed up with other kinds of activity, which as a rule must be much more conspicuous than the essential one. Hence the Marshallian denition of the entrepreneur, which simply treats the entrepreneurial function as management in the widest meaning, will naturally appeal to most of us. We do not accept it, simply because it does not bring out what we consider to be the salient point and the only one which specically distinguishes entrepreneurial from other activities. (Schumpeter, 1934, p. 77)
The climate most favourable to innovation is when the economy is approaching an equilibrium, for then the future seems relatively easy to foresee. The rst innovations, made by the most talented entrepreneurs, prove successful, and this encourages less talented entrepreneurs to follow suit. Because they are adapting ideas which the pioneers have already tried out, the risks that the capitalists perceive in backing the less talented entrepreneurs are relatively low. A wave of innovation follows, which then, for a variety of reasons, quickly recedes. Schumpeter believed that talented entrepreneurs were a very scarce breed. Their scarcity lies not so much in their alertness, or in their professionalism, as in their psychology. While entrepreneurs are rational economic men, their objective is not the pursuit of consumption in the usual sense of that word. The motivating factors are threefold:
First of all, there is the dream and the will to found a private kingdom, usually, though not necessarily, also a dynasty. The modern world really does not know any such positions, but what may be attained by industrial or commercial success is still the nearest approach to medieval lordship possible to modern man. Its fascination is specially strong for people who have no other chance of achieving social distinction. Then there is the will to conquer the impulse to ght, to prove oneself superior to others, to succeed for the sake, not of the fruits of success, but of success itself. From this aspect economic action becomes akin to sport there are nancial races, or rather boxing matches. Finally there is the joy of creating, of getting things done, or simply of exercising ones energy and ingenuity. Our type seeks out difculties, changes in order to change, delights in ventures. This group of motives is the most distinctly antihedonist of the three. (Schumpeter, 1934, pp. 934)
The precursor to innovation is invention, which is a eld of imaginative activity outside the province of the entrepreneur. The process of invention forms no part of Schumpeters theory, but one of the attractive features of the
225
theory is how easily the dynamics of invention can be grafted onto it. Schumpeter recognized that invention could be an endogenous process stimulated by the desire to alleviate pressing scarcities, but his attitude is basically to regard it as autonomous. The possibility of grafting on a theory of invention may be illustrated as follows. It is often suggested that modern economic growth is related to the innovation of mass-market multi-purpose goods, such as the typical consumer durable. The innovation of these goods often depends critically upon the invention of components from which they can be made up. Innovation of a new multi-purpose good is possible only when the design of each of the constituent components has evolved sufciently to provide the requisite standards of compactness, reliability and performance. If improvements in component design are generated by an autonomous random process of invention, then there will come a critical point at which mass production of the multi-purpose good becomes viable. This is the point at which each of the components has just evolved to the requisite standard. This may trigger off a major innovation such as the railway or the motor car whose repercussions are sufciently widespread to stimulate a wave of subsidiary innovations. This wave of innovations uses up the outstanding stock of inventions which were pending adoption, and leads to a subsequent lull in innovation until the stock of inventions builds up again to a threshold level. Schumpeter himself was very cautious about relying upon major innovations and their consequent economies and spin-offs as an explanation for the clustering of innovation observed during the business cycle. He regarded waves of innovation and their creative destruction as a basic phenomenon of capitalist economic development. He recognized that the waves could take very different forms in different times and places: he was concerned to offer an analytical framework for the interpretation of varied historical experience rather than to formulate a narrow theory to which all historical experience was alleged to conform.
14.6
Andrews theory is not concerned primarily with the entrepreneur, but with providing a realistic account of competition between rms at the industry level. His analysis is relevant to entrepreneurship because he analyses aspects of business strategy which are ignored by the neoclassical theory of the rm, but which are crucial to the success or failure of a business. The decisions which Andrews analyses are very much the decisions with which entrepreneurs are preoccupied in practice.
226
Synthesis
This is no accident. The primary requirement imposed by Andrews is that his theory should conform with the empirical regularities indicated by the eldwork which he and his Oxford colleagues had conducted. Andrews maintains that the typical rm is in a state of disequilibrium or at least incomplete equilibrium but that rms in the same industry manage to maintain oligopolistic stability in the long run. Competition within the industry maintains a fairly uniform price, with the market divided between the rms on the basis that each enjoys the goodwill of a certain group of customers. One aspect of goodwill is loyalty to the manufacturers brand, as in Chamberlins analysis of imperfect competition, but another aspect, on which considerable stress is laid, is the quality of service that the rm provides. Quality of service is achieved by maintaining the price stable and holding adequate inventory to meet all demand from stock. Firms do not adjust price and output to maximize short-run prot, but rather forgo short-run prot so as not to lose goodwill. Most rms produce a range of different products, even though the products may all be within a fairly narrow industrial category. Firms are always prepared to enter others markets; indeed, the typical entrant is not a new rm, which may be small and economically weak, but rather a large rm diversifying into a new product line. The threat of potential entry is normally strong, therefore, and this threat keeps the price level in each industry in line with average costs. Andrews recognizes that the provision of quality of service to customers often has to be delegated by the manufacturer to the retailer. The main reason is spatial: to provide prompt and convenient service, stocks have to be located at all the major centres of demand. But to reach this demand effectively, and to maintain stability in market shares, it is necessary for the manufacturer to have inuence if not control over the retailers activities. It is necessary, for example, to ensure that the retailer holds adequate stocks to back up the demand created by the manufacturers advertising. In Andrews view such control may be quite legitimate, even if it involves restrictive business practices such as resale price maintenance. Andrews develops his analysis using Marshallian techniques which do not seem very well suited to his purposes. It is possible that he was not radical enough in his theorizing and carried over equilibrium techniques to analyse disequilibrium situations. Thus, while the issues that Andrews identies are also the issues which most businessmen (and indeed our own analysis, too) identify as important, his analysis of these issues does not provide entirely satisfactory answers. Penrose, like Andrews, is concerned with injecting greater realism into the theory of the rm. Her analysis, though it does not involve formal technique, is in many respects much more tightly argued than Andrews. She presents a
227
truly dynamic theory of the rm, which explains how the creation and use of information governs the growth of the rm through a feedback mechanism. The starting point is an organizational theory of the rm:
The business rm, as we have dened it, is both an administrative organization and a collection of productive resources; its general purpose is to organize the use of its own resources together with other resources acquired from outside the rm for the production and sale of goods and services at a prot; its physical resources yield services essential for the execution of the plans of its personnel, whose activities are bound together by the administrative framework within which they are carried on. The administrative structure of the rm is the creation of the men who run it; the structure may have developed rather haphazardly in response to immediate needs as they arose in the past, or it may have been shaped largely by conscious attempts to achieve a rational organization; it may consist of no more than one or two men who divide the task of management; or it may be so elaborate that its complete ramications cannot even be depicted in the most extensive chart. In any event, there need be nothing xed about it; it can, in principle, always be adapted to the requirements of the rm expanded, modied, and elaborated as the rm grows and changes. The productive activities of such a rm are governed by what we shall call its productive opportunity, which comprises all of the productive possibilities that its entrepreneurs see and can take advantage of. A theory of the growth of rms is essentially an examination of the changing productive opportunity of rms; in order to nd a limit to growth, or a restriction on the rate of growth, the productive opportunity of a rm must be shown to be limited in any period. (Penrose, 1959, pp. 312)
The personal qualities of the entrepreneur are an important inuence on the growth of the rm. Versatility gives the entrepreneur a wider business horizon and encourages him to experiment with new products; he has the imaginative effort, the sense of timing, the instinctive recognition of what will catch on. Fund-raising ingenuity is crucial, particularly for the owner of a small rm trying to get his business off the ground. Judgment, too, is important, for it is the accuracy of the entrepreneurs image or perception of his environment that allows imagination to be exercised without too much risk of a mistake. Finally, there is the entrepreneurs ambition. Two different types of ambition are distinguished: the ambition of the product-minded or workmanship-minded entrepreneur who may be satised to maintain his rm at a fairly stable size, and the empire builder who is interested in achieving dominance for his rm in its particular industry. Empire builders are often impatient for dominance, and are inclined to pursue growth through the fastest possible avenue, which is that of acquisition or merger. A major inuence on the rms capacity to grow is the volume of managerial resources which are uncommitted to current projects. These managerial resources are available for investigating new avenues of growth. Excess managerial resources exist within the rm because it is normally efcient only to
228
Synthesis
hire indivisible units of management that is, full-time employees. Undertaking new projects expands the demand for routine managerial services and leads to an expansion of the management team. But the expansion is lumpy and so unused managerial resources may persist, leading to further growth in the future. Provided the entrepreneur can adjust the organizational structure to accommodate additional managers, the limit to the size of the rm continually recedes. The ultimate limit on the rate of expansion is set by the ability of the entrepreneur and his existing management team to accommodate changes in the organization. New managers have to be recruited and have to be trained in organizational procedures. If the rm grows too fast, then the organization will become dislocated by excessive demands on managers, and disaster will ensue. It is highly unlikely that large rms will be able to follow up all the openings that their current trading experience suggests are present. The very success of large rms may create interstices that small rms can exploit. They may be able to supply complementary goods to the large rms customers, to exploit spin-off from the large rms production experience, or even to set up as specialist suppliers of one of the large rms inputs. Although Penrose rejects biological analogy, it is not unreasonable to see this as a process by which the large mature rms, quite inadvertently, nurture small rms, some of which will eventually grow to maturity themselves. Where the analogy breaks down is that some of the large rms may continue to get larger, or at least maintain their size, so that not all the mature rms will necessarily eventually die off.
14.7
Each of the theories reviewed above starts, to some extent, from where its predecessor leaves off. Leibensteins theory describes the essential characteristics of the environment in which the entrepreneur operates. In the world of the entrepreneur it is inefciency, not efciency, which is the normal state of affairs. Economic success is of little interest when everyone is successful in making the best use of the resources at their disposal. Success only becomes interesting when failure is the norm. According to Leibenstein, the immediate cause of failure is lack of effort. Of course, if relaxation is a good and effort a bad then lack of effort is not difcult to explain. It does, however, raise the question as to whether relaxation per se can be regarded as an indication of inefciency. An alternative explanation of inefciency is that the wrong decisions are made about the allocation of resources because the people who make the
229
decisions either do not have all the relevant information at their disposal or do not interpret it properly. Possession of inadequate information may be a result of laziness, but it is more likely to reect the fact that information sources are localized and that information is costly to transmit. The recognition of a wrong decision implies, of course, that someone else knows what the right decision is. This in turn means that there is someone who believes that they have better information, or better powers of interpretation, than the decision maker; in other words, that there is someone who believes they have superior judgment. For Hayek, the essence of the efciency problem is to channel information to the people who need it, and to channel it to them with maximum economy, using as sharp a signal as possible. According to Hayek, the best signalling system is the market. Improving the operations of markets is therefore the best way to improve allocative efciency. As Kirzner explains, there is a continual incentive to improve market operations because of the prot opportunities that are created by market disequilibrium. Competition between entrepreneurs in exploiting these arbitrage opportunities causes price to adjust so that the signals reaching other transactors become more accurate indicators of scarcity. With the greater accuracy of the scarcity indicators, buyers and sellers form more realistic trading plans that is, plans which are in equilibrium with each other. But is there any guarantee that those who are attracted into arbitrage have the skills necessary to set the right prices rather than the wrong ones? If the arbitrager can recontract with buyers and sellers, then there is no risk that arbitrage can go wrong. But if recontracting is impossible, then the arbitrager has to buy from the seller before he can sell to the buyer, and if he misjudges the buyers attitude then he may be left with unsold inventory. This speculative nature of entrepreneurship was emphasized by Knight. He analysed speculation not so much in terms of intermediation but in terms of producing for a market. The combination of time lags in production, unforeseen changes in household circumstances, and the absence of forward markets in the product, exposes the producer to uncertainty about product demand. According to Knight, there exist people with sufcient foresight to reduce if not eliminate this uncertainty. The problem is that foresight is not a readily identiable characteristic. Uncertainty is therefore translated into the context of the decision about whom to place in charge of production. In other words, uncertainty is a characteristic not so much of the product market as of the market in management. Having isolated the main locus of uncertainty, Knight then examines how the bearing of uncertainty will be allocated in a market economy. In a sense, his analysis parallels our own, but his exposition is marred by an unfortunate denition of uncertainty. The crucially subjective nature of uncertainty does
230
Synthesis
not lie, as Knight suggests, in the uniqueness of the business situation, but in the fact that opinions differ about what is the most appropriate policy in such a situation. The uniqueness of the situation clearly means that a difference of opinion is difcult to resolve by recourse to a precedent, but it does not, per se, make a difference of opinion inevitable. When there is a difference of opinion there are ex ante gains from betting. One person speculates upon the situation by offering the other insurance against the consequences of pursuing a particular policy. This is the mechanism of inuence by which decisions are taken under uncertainty in Knights world. If Knights analysis is reformulated using a more appropriate concept of uncertainty, then his analysis appears as a prototype of the theory of speculative entrepreneurship developed in this book. Schumpeter offers a much more radical view of entrepreneurship than any of the other theories do. The difference is particularly marked in respect of the Austrians. Hayek and Kirzner focus mainly upon how entrepreneurs function within a given set of markets, while Schumpeter views entrepreneurs operating on a much wider scale, by creating and destroying markets. Reading Kirzner, for example, it appears that the information to which entrepreneurs respond is mainly price information provided by the market itself. Schumpeters entrepreneurs, on the other hand, cannot rely on price information to anything like the same extent because the markets in which they are seeking to operate do not yet exist. Schumpeters entrepreneurs do not merely adjust markets, they make them and they destroy them. They are not just the mechanism, or the agents, through which the market system operates, they are the very creators of the system itself. Schumpeters analysis accords well with our concept of the market-making rm. Our analysis also recognizes the extent to which entrepreneurs make the system. Entrepreneurs themselves depend upon markets, notably markets for inputs of market-making services. These markets are in turn made by other entrepreneurs. The entrepreneurs who control large rms also create a market in delegate entrepreneurs, and it is even conceivable that there are professional company promoters who make a market in large rms themselves. This also ties in with Knight, who emphasized that the greatest entrepreneurial uncertainties arise in the market for the managers of large rms. Schumpeter also recognizes the strategic aspects of entrepreneurship which are emphasized in this book. He recognizes implicitly that the information used by the entrepreneur is in common ownership and that the inability to appropriate the gains from exploiting it is a major disincentive to the entrepreneur. Schumpeter regards entrepreneurship as a very scarce talent, and supports any measures, such as patents and other restrictive business practices, which increase the appropriability of the potential monopoly rents. This point leads naturally into our own discussion of the strategic problems facing
231
the entrepreneur: the problem of giving away information in the course of bargaining with customers or suppliers, or in the course of obtaining external nance. It also relates to our discussion of the competitive search for information and the problems of avoiding unintended duplication of search activity. In Schumpeters theory, the purely entrepreneurial act occupies the entrepreneur for only a small proportion of his time. There may indeed be only one quite ephemeral act, namely the creation of a new rm to effect an innovation. What the entrepreneur does the rest of the time is to manage the growth of his business by building up his organization and defending its strategic interests. The behaviour of the organization is the subject of the institutional theory of the rm the theory of the rm as developed by Andrews and Penrose, amongst others. The subject of these theories is not entrepreneurship per se, but rather the skills that have to go with it: the ability to delegate, to provide internal incentives, to manage inventory, to contract out front-line inventory to retailers, and so on. The integration of these functions with entrepreneurship makes it a multifaceted activity. The analysis of these relatively mundane functions is a key element in integrating the theory of the entrepreneur into mainstream economic theory. This integration is a two-sided process, involving a detailed analysis of entrepreneurial strategy, on the one hand, and the reconstruction of parts of orthodox economic theory, on the other. The objective of this book has been to advance the process of integration which began with the theories reviewed above.
SUMMARY
This chapter has reviewed the leading theories of entrepreneurship and shown how they can be placed in a logical sequence. The interface between these theories and orthodox theory is to be found in the institutional theory of the rm. The present theory synthesizes the main insights of these theories, and develops some of their implications.
232
Synthesis
approach has recently been sympathetically reviewed by Shackle (1981). Many people have claimed to be building upon the work of Knight, but few have actually done so with much success. Schumpeters work, on the other hand, has stimulated both interesting theoretical criticism and valuable historical investigation, see, for example, Gerschenkron (1968), Mason (1951, 1967), Nelson (1974), Nelson, Winter and Schuette (1977) and Solo (1951). An admirable summary of the Schumpeterian system is given by Clemence and Doody (1950); recent empirical work is reported in Hartman and Wheeler (1979). The connection between invention and innovation is considered by Machlup (1962b), MacLaurin (1953), Schmookler (1954, 1962, 1966) and Strassman (1959). The competitive role of product innovation is examined further by Reichardt (1962).
15. Conclusions
15.1 WELCOME BACK, JACK BRASH!
It is now time to return to the point at which we began, namely the biography of Jack Brash, entrepreneur. Jack Brash is to entrepreneurship what King Arthur is to chivalry: a legendary gure who personies qualities which society believes to be important. The biography of Jack Brash can be seen in another light, however. In this chapter it is used to illustrate some of the main predictions of the theory of entrepreneurship. It cannot of course be used to test them, since, as we have seen, the rags to riches career of Jack Brash is very much the exception rather than the rule. Indeed, the predictions of the theory of entrepreneurship do not depend upon the identication of a particular individual, or group of individuals, as entrepreneurs. The predictions of the theory relate to all individuals, and specically to the interactions between them. Entrepreneurship is about economic and social processes as a whole. It is about the interaction between one entrepreneur and another, between entrepreneurs and non-entrepreneurs, between leaders and followers, successes and failures, and so on. The case of Jack Brash can, however, be used to illustrate these economic and social processes: to show how they impinge upon one particular individual, and how certain key individuals can inuence the way that the processes evolve.
15.2
ACCESS TO INFORMATION
This section presents three hypotheses about the role of information in stimulating entrepreneurial activity. (i) Information about prot opportunities needs to be synthesized from different sources. The story of Oskar, Jacks father, illustrates this, perhaps even better than the story of Jack himself. Oskar was an immigrant, and as such had knowledge of economic conditions in two different countries. He was therefore in a good position to identify opportunities for arbitrage. He exploited the opportunity
233
234
Synthesis
to link the supply of Polish products to the demands of the immigrant Polish community; although other immigrants were in the same position, Oskar, as a seaman, had a greater knowledge of the shipping trade than most, and so was able to identify the most efcient means of transporting goods. This suggests two corollaries of the theory: rst, that because migrants have a natural advantage in synthesizing information relevant to arbitrage they will be disposed to enter this particular line of entrepreneurial activity; secondly, that employment in the shipping trade may not only provide this kind of information itself, but allows this information to be synthesized with a practical knowledge of the transport system involved. Transport, and shipping in particular, is therefore a useful starting point from which an entrepreneur can move into merchandising and retailing. He may move out of transport as a result subcontracting the provision of transport services or he may retain his transport interests and integrate his merchandising activities with them. Arbitrage involves a fairly simple form of information synthesis. A much more complex synthesis is required, for example, in product innovation. This is illustrated by Jacks innovation of the Flash Furniture range. On the demand side, Jack recognizes social and demographic factors which are increasing the demand for household furnishing. On the supply side, he is aware of new and cheaper furnishing fabrics which mean that new furniture need no longer be a luxury item. This suggests to Jack that there is a potential mass market for basic furnishing, and that such furnishing can be produced cheaply using new technology and by exploiting economies of scale. (ii) The family is a potentially valuable source of information. The nature and extent of his familys connections inuence the opportunities that are available to an entrepreneur. Even the entrepreneurs knowledge of his own family may be turned to advantage by using the family as a source of labour. This strategy has its limitations, however, because the range of skills available within the family may be very small. Jack Brash is not at all well-connected. He is in a low stratum of society and his father, a potentially important source of contacts, has left home. This closes off many opportunities to Jack. For example, because he has no connection with the establishment, advancement by pyramid climbing is out of the question. Even getting a job when he has been made redundant poses problems, partly because his father is not there to provide tip-offs about jobs that may be going. In fact Jack becomes self-employed because, given the absence of family contacts and his lack of capital and educational qualications, self-employment is the only alternative to unemployment. When he becomes self-employed he still relies upon his family even though only very
Conclusions
235
meagre information is available. It is information about the marketing of his mothers outwork that gives him the idea for arbitraging between the East End and West End of London. Most people so disadvantaged in information would never succeed as entrepreneurs. But Jack Brash is exceptional, and in the long run overcomes his disadvantage. Jack Brash is not very good at delegating, and in particular he is very bad at recruiting managers to whom he can delegate. This gets him into serious difculties on at least one occasion (see hypothesis (viii) below). At the start of his career there is really no-one in his family to whom he could reasonably delegate, but when his nephew grows up he begins to groom him as a senior manager and as his eventual successor. There is no reason, however, for believing that his nephew has the same abilities as Jack; and Jacks assessment of other peoples abilities is known to be unreliable. The fact that the nephew is provided with a good education and rst-class social contacts will certainly help him in acquiring information and making rational decisions, but whether he shares Jacks imagination and foresight must remain an open question. If he does, the business will go from strength to strength; if he does not, it may be a case of clogs to clogs in just two generations. (iii) The feedback of information from past activities is crucial to the longrun success of an enterprise. As noted above, Jack Brash starts with very little information. But information is generated continuously as a by-product of his trading activity, and Jack uses this information to the full. He learns from the deals that he makes, and he learns also from the deals that fall through. By analysing his experience he is able to turn adversity to advantage. Thus, when competitors move in on his eld, he diversies into a slightly different eld. The diversication is successful because it relies upon information already gained in his original eld, and simply puts it to a different use. It is only later on, when Jack integrates forward into a eld about which he has very little knowledge, and in which he underestimates the risks, that he comes unstuck.
15.3
A great deal of entrepreneurial behaviour can be explained in terms of the existence of barriers to entry into entrepreneurship, and the strategies entrepreneurs use to overcome them. This section presents three hypotheses about entrepreneurial strategy.
236
Synthesis
(iv) Lack of personal wealth is a major constraint on the scale of entrepreneurial activity. Entrepreneurial strategy is strongly inuenced by attempts to minimize the impact of this constraint. Informal contacts with family, friends and trading partners are important in obtaining capital, with nancial intermediaries such as banks having only a limited role. The problems of obtaining external nance are most acute in the early years of an enterprise; during this period the rate of growth of the enterprise is much more strongly inuenced by the protability of its existing activities than by the entrepreneurs assessment of its future prospects. It goes without saying that Jack Brash is capital-constrained. No nancial institution would lend to an unqualied lad from Stepney whose family is so poor that they can provide no collateral for a loan. Jack uses considerable ingenuity in obtaining the capital that he needs. He buys his rst handcart on hire-purchase nanced by the man he buys it from. The man has at least met Jack, has admired his determination, and is perhaps sufciently naive to be persuaded by Jack to accept deferred payment. He knows, however, that Jack lives locally and that a handcart, in common with most other vehicles, is fairly easy to repossess. Later on, Jack gets his customers to nance him by making prepayment for the reproduction frames they order. He borrows from his customers because they have dealt with him before and, being already established themselves, they have some capital to spare. Even so the cost of this nance is very high to Jack, for he has to offer an additional 5 per cent discount on the price of the frames to obtain it. This is still cheaper nance than he could obtain elsewhere, and the borrowing is warranted because of the high rate of prot he expects to earn. Once Jack has got established, he buys his way into high society and acquires a small fortune through marriage. This provides him with sufcient capital to reverse his role and extend trade credit to others. If he is a good judge of the risk of default, then he can specialize in extending credit to entrepreneurs whom others are reluctant to nance. He can demand a high rate of interest because of the risks that other nanciers perceive, and so operate in a highly protable way as a banker to the trade. Before his marriage, the expansion of Jacks rm was severely restricted by the need for hand-to-mouth trading. Each batch of new frames had to be nanced by the reinvested prots of the previous batch, and this policy must have lost, or at least deferred, some of his sales. But as the batch size increased, so the prots increased, and the size of the batch could be increased again. Thus, once Jacks ideas had provided the motivation for growth, the rate of growth achieved was determined by the prot generated by the project itself.
Conclusions
237
Jack relies on his bank for nance at only one stage in his career. This is, however, a crucial stage in which the banks role as honest broker is absolutely vital. In seeking a loan, Jack divulges to his bank manager highly condential information which would be very damaging if it were to reach his trade creditors. The bank acts as go-between for Jack, not only in the capital market, but in the market for professional services as well. It puts Jack in contact with specialists who can improve the organization of his business. The banks reward comes from the high rate of interest it charges for the loan that, in conjunction with the professional services, puts the business back on its feet. Finally, it is worth nothing that, in the very early stages of his career, Jack economized on his capital requirement by introducing an element of barter into his transactions. When buying from housewives he often offered partpayment in the form of a cheap replacement from his stock. This reduced the average cash balance he required in order to conduct his trade, at the expense of the inconvenience of having to carry part of his stock around with him. (v) Outside the family, clubs and societies are the most important non-prot institutions in which people can make contacts and acquire and disseminate information. Access to these institutions is often regulated by, for example, expensive subscriptions or by educational and professional qualications. This means that the socially disadvantaged entrepreneur cannot easily gain access to the information and the capital he requires. Jack Brash does not gain acceptance by the establishment until quite late in his career. But he has one stroke of good fortune: the outbreak of war puts him into military service. At the time it seems an unfortunate interruption to a promising business career. But in the armed services Jack makes valuable contacts with people who, though they do not regard him as a social equal, acquire an obligation to him (perhaps reinforced by some polite blackmail on Jacks part). After the war Jack uses these contacts to obtain nance, to get tip-offs about invitations to tender for army surplus, and so on. As a result, Jacks second business starts under much more favourable conditions, and soon overtakes in size and prot anything that Jacks rst business might have become. (vi) Educational qualications are very important in reducing the constraints imposed by lack of personal wealth. Not only do they give entry to establishment institutions, they are also used as a screening device in recruiting managers. One way or another, therefore, they regulate the entrepreneurs access to other peoples capital. People with ability may be prevented from gaining qualications either because of restricted access to the educational
238
Synthesis
system or because the system is biased in favour of conformity. The second factor is probably the greatest constraint on the underwriting of personal ability by the educational system. Jack Brash does not do well at school. The academic education provided does not tap the energy and enthusiasm that become apparent later in his business career. Had he done well at school, he could have won a scholarship and perhaps gone on to become a salaried manager. Opportunities for continued education were much more limited in the East End than elsewhere, of course, and in any case he might have felt unable to take them up because of the need to support his mother nancially; but in the event the question did not arise. It is interesting that later in his career Jack buys academic distinction by endowing universities. Ostensibly, this is charity, but it is possible to distinguish too an element of revenge. He places the academic establishment in the demeaning role of accepting patronage from someone who was previously rejected by it. He dictates that his bequests should be used to remedy defects in the system, and in particular to provide better educational opportunities for people like himself. Thus in bestowing funds he snubs the traditional type of university and favours the newer universities instead, which he identies with a classless meritocratic attitude to education.
15.4
To exploit his superior judgment successfully the entrepreneur may have to call upon a variety of different skills. This section presents four hypotheses about entrepreneurial skills. (vii) egy. Negotiating tactics are an important element of entrepreneurial strat-
Jack Brash starts out as a dealer, buying and selling on doorsteps. The tactical problem facing a dealer is to explain to people simultaneously that he cannot afford to pay much for what they want to sell, but that he has to ask a lot for what it is they want to buy. Those who deal with him know that he is only in it for the margin. Notwithstanding this he must convince his trading partners that his offers cannot be improved, otherwise they are unlikely to agree to his terms. He must be skilled at inuencing their expectations. The standard way of doing this is to give the initial offer careful thought, and then to stick to this offer using a hard-line strategy. This policy is most likely to come unstuck when one entrepreneur employs it against another. Jack Brash discovers this to his cost when he starts bar-
Conclusions
239
gaining with the buyer for a chain of high-street stores. The buyer dictates the terms and, in an attempt to extract concessions, Jack goes into competition on the retail front. But the buyer does not improve his terms and Jacks own efforts soon run into difculties. He learns that, in bargaining with households, simple strategies may be consistently successful, but that it is not advisable to pursue the same approach against other entrepreneurs. (viii) Organizational skills are important for the entrepreneur. There comes a point in the growth of any rm when the collection of information has to be delegated, and later on comes a point when decisions have to be delegated too. Some of the delegates may need to be specialists, who are difcult for the entrepreneur to recruit, and whose quality of work it is hard to check. These are critical points at which growth may falter, and the rm may even fail. At each point the entrepreneur must decide whether to delegate using rules, or to encourage delegates to use their own judgment instead. He must encourage delegates to check the accuracy of their information and to act upon it in their employers interests. In many cases efciency calls for decentralized organization in which the delegate who collects an item of information also acts upon it, and the consequences of that decision are reected in a notional prot imputed to him. The establishment of such an organization may represent a considerable investment for the entrepreneur. Jack Brash encounters considerable difculty with delegation. One of the main reasons is that he has very little experience of working as a delegate himself. He gave up employment at an early age, since when he has always been his own boss. He has forgotten about the frustrations of being an employee. He has worked long hours making a success of his business and expects his employees to do the same even though their rewards are not directly linked to the rms protability. He wants to continue making all the key decisions but forgets to motivate his employees to provide him with accurate information. His lack of education means that he cannot screen applicants for specialist posts. He tries to do without specialists when he needs them, and when he cannot do without them he appoints the wrong sort of person. It needs the advice of a specialist to hire a specialist, and eventually Jack is obliged to act on specialist advice by having professional nominees of the bank appointed to his board. The specialists help to turn round the business, and free Jacks own time to get on with what he does best developing new ideas. (ix) Product innovation is probably the most important form of entrepreneurship, at least in a long-term perspective. A key element in many product innovations is the achievement of product versatility. Versatility is normally
240
Synthesis
obtained using a multi-component design; versatility creates a mass market for the product since the product substitutes for many different specialized goods and thereby enables economies of scale to be exploited in the manufacture of individual components. To render the components compatible, it is normally necessary to standardize their design features and to guarantee precision in manufacture. The versatile good is essentially a concept for marketing a package of compatible components; because the product has many functions it is difcult to specify, and requires considerable skill to advertise. To illustrate product innovation in terms of Jack Brashs career, it is necessary to distinguish between two methods of achieving product versatility. The rst involves the development of a multi-purpose good which combines different components in xed proportion and allows different subsets of components to be activated to meet different uses. The second method involves providing a range of components that customers can combine in their own way to suit their own particular circumstances and tastes. The rst method is most suitable when practically everyone has in mind a similar range of uses for the product. The second method is most suitable when different people have different uses in mind; it allows a degree of product differentiation to be introduced to the multi-purpose good at a minimal cost. The Flash Furniture range exemplies the second kind of versatility. Jack recognizes that, when new homes are being furnished from scratch, the relevant marketing concept is not the individual furnishing item, but the furniture range. Homemakers are looking for a compatible set of furnishing components which can be permutated to meet their personal requirements within the space constraints of their home. The problem of explaining the concept to consumers is overcome, rst, by devising a gimmick, the Adjustable Room Planner, and secondly by demonstrating the furniture arrangements in show-houses on the estates. To reduce the cost of communicating the product specication, the advertising is very carefully directed to the target group. Young people are identied as the main buyers and the furnishings are advertised in the kind of periodicals that they read. It is suggested that the Flash Furniture range is very different from the kind of furniture that might be offered by parents or bought secondhand. The estates chosen for furnished show-houses are those most likely to attract the rst-time buyer. (x) Market making does not call just for the obvious skills such as advertising and salesmanship. It calls too for less glamorous skills such as inventory management and quality control. Lack of attention to these factors can undermine an enterprise, and often does so just at the point where potential sales are about to increase dramatically.
Conclusions
241
It is usually salesmanship that creates the dynamic for the growth of an enterprise. But if the product, or the quality of service associated with it, falls short of customers expectations, then the enterprise may obtain a bad reputation which it is difcult to live down. Problems can arise if unexpected success in salesmanship causes demand to exceed supply. In these circumstances supply must be increased, not only to meet the backlog in demand, but to raise future stocks to a level which will guarantee that future orders are promptly lled. To increase supply at short notice it is tempting to relax quality control; lowering the rejection rate leads to a spontaneous increase in output, and may also facilitate the transfer of factory supervisors to other productive activities. But the reduction in product quality may be quickly perceived by consumers, and in the long run lead to more product resistance than would have been encountered had the quality of service remained poor instead. Jack Brashs experience shows that there is no easy way of guaranteeing a plentiful supply of a high-quality product. At one stage, in an effort to improve retail service, he integrates forward into high-street outlets, but because of lax inventory management this creates more problems than it solves. The informal procedures he has relied upon as a dealer prove inadequate to cope with the day-to-day problems of retail sales through multiple outlets. Jack discovers that the management of a distribution channel calls for professional skills, and that, however good the product, without these skills the business cannot thrive.
15.5
The hypotheses above are formulated in a very general way. They cannot easily be tested without the introduction of additional postulates. It is outside the scope of this book to provide these additional postulates; that is part of the research agenda for the future development of the theory of the entrepreneur. It is, however, possible to describe the nature of these additional postulates. Essentially, they are postulates about the relative costs of different sources of information and of different types of institution for structuring information ow. This cost structure in turn reects both the technology of communication and the structure and the customs of society. Of course, neither the technology of communication nor the social structure is static or autonomous. They are themselves inuenced by the economic processes whose evolution they help to determine. This is the true signicance of economic and social interdependence in a dynamic context. The theory of the entrepreneur is, as noted earlier, really a special case of a general theory of economic and social process. A general theory of this kind
242
Synthesis
has been the grand design of social scientists for many years, although the formulation of a satisfactory theory of this kind is still a long way off. The development of the theory of the entrepreneur is, however, a step in this direction. As it stands, the theory is conditional upon the prevailing social structure. At the same time, there exist theories of social process which are conditional upon prevailing economic structure. At the moment, there is probably more to be gained by developing these two strands of theory separately; their integration might well be premature. If progress in these different elds can be sustained, however, it may eventually be possible to attain the social scientists dream of the unied social science. It is relevant to inquire whether the redirection of economics towards an evolutionary perspective implies a radical break with orthodox theory. Certainly, it suggests a break with the tradition of emulating the physical sciences, and a move towards an economic biology instead. It should be noted, however, that analogies of any kind, though they may be suggestive of new hypotheses, are unreliable when formulating the details of a theory, for there are almost invariably specic points upon which the analogy breaks down. In this book a determined effort has been made to relate the theory of the entrepreneur to relevant areas of orthodox theory and to follow received techniques of analysis wherever these are appropriate. The theory involves a reformulation of orthodox models rather than a rejection of them. While the perspective of the theory is radically different, the technique of analysis is not. The reason is quite simply that the theory, like the neoclassical and Austrian theories, is based upon a rationality postulate. So long as this postulate is maintained, and the information available to the individual is properly specied, the theory rules out inconsistent behaviour and therefore acquires predictive power. Thus while individuals may, for example, follow decision rules to economize on information, their choice of a decision rule is always a rational one. It is the rationality postulate that explains why marginal analysis and its associated techniques hold the key to future developments in the theory of the entrepreneur.
SUMMARY
This chapter has summarized the main conclusions of the study and illustrated them using the biography of a stereotype entrepreneur. The conclusions are remarkable chiey for the fact that the events and circumstances to which they refer are hardly ever mentioned in the neoclassical analysis of the market system. The theory of the entrepreneur offers a completely different perspective on the way that markets operate. It is dynamic rather than static, and evolutionary rather than mechanical. It is, however, still a predictive
Conclusions
243
theory because it is based upon a rationality postulate. At some stage in the future it may be possible to combine the theory of the entrepreneur with a theory of rational social behaviour to provide a unied theory of economic and social process.
Bibliography
Abbott, L. (1955) Quality and Competition: An Essay in Economic Theory, New York: Columbia University Press. Ahmed, M. (1977) Analysis of small-scale entrepreneurs in the Irish plastics industry, Economic and Social Review, 8, pp. 279304. Aitken, H.G.J. (1963) The future of entrepreneurial research, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 2), 1, pp. 39. Akerlof, G.A. (1970) The market for lemons: quality uncertainty and the market mechanism, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84, pp. 488500. Albion, M.S. and Farris, P.W. (1981) The Advertising Controversy: Evidence on the Economic Effects of Advertising, Boston, Mass: Auburn House. Alchian, A.A. (1950) Uncertainty, evolution and economic theory, Journal of Political Economy, 58, pp. 21121. Alchian, A.A. (1965) Some Economics of Property Rights, Il Politico, 30, pp. 81629, reprinted in A.A. Alchian, Economic Forces at Work, Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1977, pp. 12749. Alchian, A.A. (1969) Corporate management and property rights, in H. Manne (ed.), Economic Policy and the Regulation of Corporate Securities, Washington: American Enterprise Institute, reprinted in A.A. Alchian, Economic Forces at Work, Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1977, pp. 22757. Alchian, A.A. and Demsetz, H. (1972) Production, information costs and economic organization, American Economic Review, 62, pp. 77795. Alexander, A.P. (1964) Greek Industrialists: An Economic and Social Analysis, Athens: Centre of Planning and Economic Research. Andrews, P.W.S. (1949) Manufacturing Business, London: Macmillan. Andrews, P.W.S. (1964) On Competition in Economic Theory, London: Macmillan. Andrews, P.W.S. and Brunner, E. (1975) Studies in Pricing, London: Macmillan. Armentano, D.T. (1972) The Myths of Antitrust: Economic Theory and Legal Cases, New Rochelle, N.Y: Arlington House. Arrow, K.J. (1958) Utilities, attitudes, choices: a review note, Econometrica, 26, pp. 123. Arrow, K.J. (1962a) Economic welfare and the allocation of resources for invention, in R.R. Nelson (ed.) The Rate and Direction of Inventive Activity, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 60926.
244
Bibliography
245
Arrow, K.J. (1962b) The economic implications of learning by doing, Review of Economic Studies, 29, pp. 15573. Arrow, K.J. (1970) Essays in the Theory of Risk-Bearing, Amsterdam: NorthHolland. Arrow, K.J. (1975) Vertical integration and communication, Bell Journal of Economics, 6, pp. 17383. Atkinson, J.W. (1957) Motivational determinants of risk-taking behaviour, Psychological Review, 64, pp. 35972. Bain, J.S. (1956) Barriers to New Competition, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Baldwin, W.L. and Childs, G.L. (1969) The fast second and rivalry in research and development, Southern Economic Journal, 36, pp. 1824. Bartholomew, D.J. (1973) Stochastic Models for Social Processes, 2nd edn, London: John Wiley and Sons. Bartos, O.J. (1974) Process and Outcome of Negotiations, New York: Columbia University Press. Basmann, R.L. (1965) The role of the economic historian in predictive testing of proffered Economic Laws, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 2), 2, pp. 15986. Bass, F.M. (1980) The relationship between diffusion rates, experience curves, and demand elasticities for consumer durable technological innovations, Journal of Business, 53, pp. 5267. Bates, J. (1964) The Financing of Small Business, London: Sweet and Maxwell. Baumol, W.J. (1967) Optimal product and retailer characteristics: the abstract product approach, Journal of Political Economy, 75, pp. 67485. Baumol, W.J. (1968) Entrepreneurship in economic theory, American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), 58, pp. 6471. Baumol, W.J. and Ide, E.A. (1956) Variety in retailing, Management Science, 3, pp. 93101. Becker, S.W. and Whisler, T.L. (1967), The innovative organisation: a selective view of current theory and research, Journal of Business, 40, pp. 4629. Belshaw, C.S. (1965) The cultural milieu of the entrepreneur, in H.G.J. Aitken (ed.), Explorations in Enterprise, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, pp. 13962, reprinted in Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 1), 7, pp. 14663. Bendix, R. (1957) A study of managerial ideologies, Economic Development and Cultural Change, 5, pp. 11828. Bendix, R. and Howton, F. (1959) Social mobility and the American business elite, in S.M. Lipset and R. Bendix (eds), Social Mobility in Industrial Society, London: Heinemann, pp. 11443.
246
The entrepreneur
Bennett, W.B. (1943) The American Patent System: An Economic Interpretation, Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press. Bernstein, P.L. (1953) Prot theory where do we go from here?, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 67, pp. 40722. Bishop, R.L. (1964) A ZeuthenHicks model of bargaining, Econometrica, 32, pp. 41017. Blankart, C.B. (1975) Controversies on market failure in rewarding inventors, Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv, 111, pp. 76069. Blok, A. (1974) Maa of a Sicilian Village 18601960: Study of Violent Peasant Entrepreneurs, New York: Harper and Row. Bolton, J.E. (chairman) (1971) Small Firms: Report of the Committee of Inquiry on Small Firms, Cmnd 4811, London: HMSO. Boone, L.E. (1970) The search for the consumer innovator, Journal of Business, 43, pp. 13540. Boswell, J. (1973) The Rise and Decline of Small Firms, London: Allen & Unwin. Boulware, L.R. (1969) The Truth about Boulwarism, Washington, DC: Bureau of National Affairs. Bowman, W.S., Jr (1973) Patent and Antitrust Law: A Legal and Economic Appraisal, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Broehl, W.G., Jr (1978) The Village Entrepreneur: Change Agents in Indias Rural Development, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Brooks, J. (1963) The Fate of the Edsel and Other Business Adventures, New York: Harper and Row. Brown, L.A. (1975) The market and infrastructure content of adoption: a spatial perspective on the diffusion of innovation, Economic Geography, 51, pp. 185216. Bruce, R. (1976) The Entrepreneurs: Strategies, Motivations, Successes and Failures, Bedford: Libertarian Books. Buchanan, J.M. (1972) Notes on irrelevant externalities, enforcement costs and the atrophy of property rights, in G. Tullock (ed.), Explorations in the Theory of Anarchy, Blacksburg, Virginia: Centre for the Study of Public Choice, pp. 7786. Buchanan, J.M. (1973) LSE cost theory in retrospect, in J.M. Buchanan and G.F. Thirlby (eds), LSE Essays on Cost, London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, pp. 116. Buchanan, J.M. and Pierro, A.D. (1980) Cognition, choice and entrepreneurship, Southern Economic Journal, 46, pp. 693701. Buckley, P.J. and Casson, M.C. (1976) The Future of the Multinational Enterprise, London: Macmillan. Bylinsky, G. (1976) The Innovation Millionaires: How They Succeed, New York: Charles Scribners Sons.
Bibliography
247
Campbell, R.H. and Wilson, R.G. (eds) (1975) Entrepreneurship in Britain 17501939, London: A. and C. Black. Cancian, F. (1979) The Innovators Situation: Upper-Middle-Class Conservatism in Agricultural Communities, Stanford: Standford University Press. Cantillon, R. (1755) Essai sur la Nature du Commerce en Gnral (ed. H. Higgs) London: Macmillan (1931). Carstensen, F. and Morris, M. (1978) Credit, infrastructure and entrepreneurial opportunity in developing regions, Journal of Economic History, 38, pp. 2625. Carter, C.F. and Williams, B.R. (1957) Industry and Technical Progress: Factors Governing the Speed of Application of Science, London: Oxford University Press. Carter, C.F. and Williams, B.R. (1959) The characteristics of technically progressive rms, Journal of Industrial Economics, 7, pp. 87104. Carter, E.C., Forster, R. and Moody, J.N. (1976) Enterprise and Entrepreneurs in 19th and 20th Century France, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Casson, M.C. (1979) Alternatives to the Multinational Enterprise, London: Macmillan. Casson, M.C. (1981) Unemployment: A Disequilibrium Approach, Oxford: Martin Robertson. Chamberlain, N.W. (1955) A General Theory of Economic Process, New York: Harper and Brothers. Chamberlain, N.W. (1962) The Firm: Micro-economic Planning and Action, New York: McGraw-Hill. Chamberlain, N.W. (1968), Enterprise and Environment: The Firm in Time and Place, New York: McGraw-Hill. Chamberlin, E.H. (1962) The Theory of Monopolistic Competition, 8th edn, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Chandler, A.D., Jr (1962) Strategy and Structure: Chapters in the History of the Industrial Enterprise, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Chandler, A.D., Jr (1977) The Visible Hand: The Managerial Revolution in American Business, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Chandler, A.D. Jr and Daems, H. (eds) (1980) Managerial Hierarchies: Comparative Perspectives on the Rise of the Modern Industrial Enterprise, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Church, R.A. (1969) Kenricks in Hardware: A Family Business, 1791, Newton Abbot: David and Charles. Clark, J.B. (1894) Insurance and prots, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 7, pp. 4054. Clark, J.M. (1942) Relations of history and theory, The Tasks of Economic History: Supplement to Journal of Economic History, 2, pp. 13242.
248
The entrepreneur
Clark, J.M. (1955) Competition: static models and dynamic aspects, American Economic Review, 45, pp. 45062. Clark, J.M. (1961) Competition as a Dynamic Process, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution. Clemence, R.V. and Doody, F.S. (1950) The Schumpeterian System, Cambridge, Mass: Addison-Wesley. Clower, R.W. (1967) A reconsideration of the microfoundations of monetary theory, Western Economic Journal, 6, pp. 19. Coase, R.H. (1937) The nature of the rm, Economics (N.S.), 4, pp. 386 405. Cochran, R.C. (1958) The organization man in historic perspective, Pennsylvania History, 25, pp. 924. Cochran, T.C. (1965a) Cultural factors in economic growth, in H.G.J. Aitken (ed.), Explorations in Enterprise, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, pp. 12338, reprinted in Journal of Economic History, 20, pp. 515 30. Cochran, T.C. (1965b), The entrepreneur in economic change, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 2), 3, pp. 2538. Cochran, T.C. (1968) Entrepreneurship, in D.L. Sills (ed.), International Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences, Volume 5, New York: Macmillan, pp. 8791. Coddington, A. (1968) Theories of the Bargaining Process, London: Allen & Unwin. Cole, A.H. (1942) Entrepreneurship as an area of research, The Tasks of Economic History: Supplement to Journal of Economic History, 2, pp. 118 26. Cole, A.H. (1954) An appraisal of economic change: twentieth-century entrepreneurship in the United States and economic growth, American Economic Review, 40, pp. 3550. Cole, A.H. (1959) Business Enterprise in its Social Setting, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Cole, A.H. (1962) What is business history?, Business History Review, 36, pp. 98106. Cole, A.H. (1965a) Aggregative business history, Business History Review, 39, pp. 298300. Cole, A.H. (1965b) An approach to the study of entrepreneurship, in H.G.J. Aitken (ed.), Explorations in Enterprise, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, pp. 3040. Coles, F.A. (1973) Financial institutions and black entrepreneurship, Journal of Black Studies, 3, pp. 32949. Collins, O.F. and Moore, D.G. (1964) The Enterprising Man, East Lansing:
Bibliography
249
Bureau of Business and Economic Research, Graduate School of Business Administration, Michigan State University. Copeman, G.H. (1955) Leaders of British Industry: A Study of the Careers of more than a Thousand Public Company Directors, London: Gee and Company (Publishers). Coughenour, C.M. (1968) Some general problems in diffusion from the perspective of the theory of social action, North Central Regional Research Bulletin, 186, pp. 514. Cross, J.G. (1965), A theory of the bargaining process, American Economic Review, 55, pp. 6794. Cross, M. (1981) New Firm Formation and Regional Development, Farnborough, Hants: Gower Press. Cox, D.F. (ed.) (1967) Risk Taking and lnformation Handling in Consumer Behavior, Boston: Division of Research, Graduate School of Business Administration, Harvard University. Dahmen, E. (1970) Entrepreneurial Activity and the Development of Swedish Industry, 19191939 (trans. A. Leijonhufvud), Homewood, Illinois: Richard D. Irwin. Davenport, H.J. (1913) Economics of Enterprise, New York: Macmillan. Davids, L.E. (1963) Characteristics of Small Business Founders in Texas and Georgia, Washington, DC: Small Business Administration. Debreu, G. (1959) Theory of Value, New Haven: Yale University Press. Demsetz, H. (1968) The cost of transacting, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 82, pp. 3353. Denison, E.F. (1962) The Sources of Economic Growth in the United States and the Alternatives Before Us, New York: Committee for Economic Development. Denison, E.F. (1967) Why Growth Rates Differ: Postwar Experience in Nine Western Countries, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution. Durand, D. and Shea, D. (1974) Entrepreneurial activity as a function of achievement motivation and reinforcement control, Journal of Psychology, 88, pp. 5763. Erickson, C. (1959) British Industrialists: Steel and Hosiery, 18501950, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Evans, G.H. Jr (1942) Theory of entrepreneurship, The Tasks of Economic History: Supplement to Journal of Economic History, 2, pp. 1426. Evans, G.H. Jr (1949) The entrepreneur and economic theory: a historical and analytical approach, American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), 39, pp. 33648.
250
The entrepreneur
Evans, G.H. Jr (1959) Business entrepreneurs: their major functions and related tenets, Journal of Economic History, 19, pp. 25070. Fanfani, A. (1935) Catholicism, Protestantism and Capitalism, London: Sheed and Ward. Fleming, W.J. (1979) Cultural determinants of entrepreneurship and economic development: case study of Mendoza Province, Argentina, 1861 1914, Journal of Economic History, 39, pp. 21124. Fogarty, M.P. (1973) Irish Entrepreneurs Speak for Themselves, Dublin: Economic and Social Research Institute, Broadsheet 8. Fox, H.G. (1947) Monopolies and Patents: A Study of the History and Future of the Patent Monopoly, Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Freeman, C. (1974) The Economics of Industrial Innovation, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. Freeman, K.B. (1976) The signicance of McClellands achievement variable in the aggregate production function, Economic Development and Cultural Change, 24, pp. 81524. Galambos, L. (1966) Business history and the theory of the growth of the rm, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 2), 4, pp. 316. Gerschenkron, A. (1953) Social attitudes, entrepreneurship and economic development, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 1), 5, pp. 1 19. Gerschenkron, A. (1968) A Schumpeterian analysis of economic development, in A. Gerschenkron, Continuity and Other Essays in History, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Glade, W. (1967) Approaches to a theory of entrepreneurial formation, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 2), 4, pp. 24559. Glaister, S. (1974) Advertising policy and returns to scale in markets where information is passed between individuals, Economica (N.S.), 41, pp. 139 56. Globe, S., Levy, W.G. and Schwartz, C.M. (1973) Key Factors and Events in the Innovation Process, Research Management, 16, pp. 815. Goss, B.A. and Yamey, B.S. (eds) (1976) The Economics of Futures Trading: Readings, London: Macmillan. Gough, J.W. (1969) The Rise of the Entrepreneur, London: Batsford. Gould, J.P. (1974) Risk, stochastic preference and the value of information, Journal of Economic Theory, 8, pp. 6484. Grabowski, H.G. and Baxter, N.D. (1973) Rivalry in industrial research and development: an empirical study, Journal of Industrial Economics, 21, pp. 20935.
Bibliography
251
Green, R.W. (ed.) (1959) Protestantism and Capitalism: The Weber Thesis and Its Critics, Boston: D.C. Heath. Greenhut, M.L. (1971) A Theory of the Firm in Economic Space, Austin: Lone Star Publishers. Gurzynski, Z.S.A. (1976) Entrepreneurship: true spring of human action, South African Journal of Economics, 44, pp. 126. Hagen, E.E. (1962) On the Theory of Social Change: How Economic Growth Begins, Homewood, Illinois: Dorsey Press. Hgerstrand, T. (1967) Innovation Diffusion as a Spatial Process (trans. A. Pred), Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Harbison, F. (1956) Entrepreneurial Organisation as a Factor in Economic Development, Journal of Political Economy, 64, pp. 36479. Harris, J. (1973) Entrepreneurship and economic development, in L. Cain and P. Uselding (eds), Business Enterprise and Economic Change: Essays in Honor of Harold F. Williamson, Kent, Ohio: Kent State University Press, pp. 14172. Harsanyi, J.C. (1977) Rational Behaviour and Bargaining Equilibrium in Games and Social Situations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hartman, R.S. and Wheeler, D.R. (1979) Schumpeterian waves of innovation and infrastructure development in Great Britain and the United States: the Kondratieff cycle revisited, Research in Economic History, 4 (Greenwich, Conn: Jai Press), 4, pp. 3785. Hawley, F.B. (1907) Enterprise and the Productive Process, New York: G.P. Putnams Sons. Hayek, F.A. (1937) Economics and knowledge, Economica (N.S.) 4, pp. 33 54, reprinted in F.A. Hayek, Individualism and Economic Order, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1959, pp. 3356. Hayek, F.A. (1945) The use of knowledge in society, American Economic Review, 35, pp. 51930, reprinted in F.A. Hayek, Individualism and Economic Order, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1959, pp. 7791. Hayek, F.A. (1949) The meaning of competition, in F.A. Hayek, Individualism and Economic Order, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1959, pp. 92106. Hayek, F.A. (1960) The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Heal, G.M. (1973) The Theory of Economic Planning, Amsterdam: NorthHolland. Heebower, R.B. (1967) The theory and effects of non-price competition, in R.E. Kuenne (ed.), Monopolistic Competition Theory: Studies in Impact, New York: John Wiley and Sons. Hey, J.D. (1979) Uncertainty in Microeconomics, Oxford: Martin Robertson.
252
The entrepreneur
Heyl, B.S. (1978) The Madam as Entrepreneur: Career Management in House Prostitution, Rutgers, New Brunswick: Transaction Books. Hicks, J.R. (1963) The Theory of Wages, 2nd edn, London: Macmillan. Hirschman, A.O. (1958) The Strategy of Economic Development, New Haven, Conn: Yale University Press. Hirschman, A.O. (1970) Exit, Voice and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organisations and States, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Holmes, G. and Ruff, H. (1975) Perils of Entrepreneurial History, Business History, 17, pp. 2643. Hoselitz, B.F. (1951) The early history of entrepreneurial theory, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 1), 3, pp. 193220. Hughes, J.R.T. (1966a) Fact and theory in economic history, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 2), 3, pp. 75100. Hughes, J.R.T. (1966b) The Vital Few: American Economic Progress and Its Protagonists, Cambridge, Mass: Houghton Mifin. Hurwicz, L. (1969) On the concept and possibility of informational decentralisation, American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), 59, pp. 51324. Hutt, W.H. (1939) The Theory of Idle Resources, London: Jonathan Cape. Hyde, F.E. (1962) Economic theory and business history, Business History, 5, pp. 110. Iremonger, D.S. (1972) New Commodities and Consumer Behaviour, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Jaiswal, N.K. (1968) Priority Queues, New York: Academic Press. Jenks, L.H. (1949) The role structure of entrepreneurial personality, in Change and the Entrepreneur, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, pp. 10853. Jenks, L.H. (1965) Approaches to entrepreneurial personality, in H.G.J. Aitken (ed.), Explorations in Enterprise, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, pp. 8092. Jensen, M.C. and Meckling, W.H. (1976) The theory of the rm: managerial behaviour, agency costs and ownership structure, Journal of Financial Economics, 3, pp. 30560. Jewkes, J., Sawers, D. and Stillerman, R. (1958) The Sources of Invention, London: Macmillan. Johnson, P.S. (1975) The Economics of Invention and Innovation: with a Case Study of the Development of the Hovercraft, London: Martin Robertson. Johnson, P.S. and Cathcart, D.G. (1979) New manufacturing rms and re-
Bibliography
253
gional development: some evidence from the Northern region, Regional Studies, 13, pp. 26980. Kaelble, H. (1981) Historical Research on Social Mobility: Western Europe and the USA in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries (trans. I. Noakes), London: Croom Helm. Kalai, E. and Smorodinsky, M. (1975) Other solutions to Nashs bargaining problem, Econometrica, 43, pp. 51318. Kaldor, N. (1934) The equilibrium of the rm, Economic Journal, 44, pp. 6076. Kamien, M.I. and Schwartz, N.L. (1972) Timing of innovation under rivalry, Econometrica, 40, pp. 4360. Kamien, M.I. and Schwartz, N.L. (1974) Patent life and R&D rivalry, American Economic Review, 64, pp. 1837. Kamien, M.I. and Schwartz, N.L. (1975) Market structure and innovation: a survey, Journal of Economic Literature, 13, pp. 137. Kamien, M.I. and Schwartz, N.L. (1978) Potential rivalry, monopoly prots, and the pace of inventive activity, Review of Economic Studies, 45, pp. 547 57. Kaplan, A.D.H. (1948) Small Business: Its Place and Problems, New York: McGraw-Hill. Katz, E. (1957) The two-step ow of communication: an up-to-date report on an hypothesis, Public Opinion Quarterly, 21, pp. 6178. Katz, E. and Foulkes, D. (1962) On the use of the mass media as escape: clarication of a concept, Public Opinion Quarterly, 26, pp. 37788. Katz, E. and Lazarsfeld, P.F. (1955) Personal Inuence, New York: Free Press. Katz, E., Levin, M.L. and Hamilton, H. (1963) Traditions of research on the diffusion of innovations, American Sociological Review, 28, pp. 23752. Kay, N.M. (1979) The Innovating Firm: A Behavioural Theory of Corporate R&D, London: Macmillan. Keller, S. (1953) The Social Origins and Career Lines of Three Generations of American Business Leaders, unpublished PhD dissertation, Columbia University, New York. Kierulff, H.E. (1975) Can entrepreneurs be developed?, MSU Business Topics, 23, pp. 3944. Kierulff, H.E. (1979) Finding and keeping: corporate entrepreneurs, Business Horizons, 22, pp. 615. Kihlstrom, R.E. (1974a) A Bayesian model of demand for information about product quality, International Economic Review, l5, pp. 99118. Kihlstrom, R.E. (1974b) A general theory of demand for information about product quality, Journal of Economic Theory, 8, pp. 41339.
254
The entrepreneur
Kihlstrom, R.E. and Laffont, J.J. (1979) A general equilibrium entrepreneurial theory of rm formation based on risk aversion, Journal of Political Economy, 87, pp. 71948. Kilbey, P. (1971) Hunting the heffalump, in P. Kilby (ed.), Entrepreneurship and Economic Development, New York: Free Press, pp. 140. Kingston, W. (1977) Innovation: The Creative Impulse in Human Progress, London: John Calder. Kirzner, I.M. (1960) The Economic Point of View, Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand. Kirzner, I.M. (1963) Market Theory and the Price System, Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand. Kirzner, I.M. (1967) Methodological individualism, market equilibrium, and market process, Politico, 1, 32, pp. 78799. Kirzner, I.M. (1973) Competition and Entrepreneurship, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kirzner, I.M. (1976) Equilibrium versus market process, in E.G. Dolan (ed.), The Foundations of Modern Austrian Economics, Kansas City: Sheed and Ward, pp. 11525. Kirzner, I.M. (1979a) Perception, Opportunity and Prot, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kirzner, I.M. (1979b) Comment: X-inefciency, error and the scope for entrepreneurship, in M.J. Rizzo (ed.), Time, Uncertainty and Disequilibrium, Lexington, Mass: D.C. Heath, pp. 14051. Klapper, J.T. (1960) The Effects of Mass Communication, New York: Free Press. Knight, F.H. (1921) Risk, Uncertainty and Prot (ed. G.J. Stigler), Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1971. Knight, F.H. (1942) Prot and entrepreneurial functions, The Tasks of Economic History: Supplement to Journal of Economic History, 2, pp. 12632. Kornai, J. (1959) Overcentralisation in Economic Administration: A Critical Analysis based on Experience in Hungarian Light Industry (trans. J. Knapp), London: Oxford University Press. Kornai, J. (1971) Anti-Equilibrium, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Kornai, J. (1980) Economics of Shortage, 2 vols, Amsterdam: North-Holland. Kornai, J. and Liptak, T. (1965) Two-level planning, Econometrica, 33, pp. 14169. Krner, A. (1893) Unternehmung und Unternehmergewinn, Vienna. Kotler, P. (1976) Marketing Management: Analysis, Planning and Control, 3rd edn, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Koutsoyiannis, A. (1979) Modern Microeconomics, 2nd edn, London: Macmillan.
Bibliography
255
Lachmann, L.M. (1969) Methodological individualism and the market economy, in E. Streissler (ed.), Roads to Freedom: Essays in Honour of Friedrich A. von Hayek, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, pp. 89104. Lachmann, L.M. (1976) From Mises to Shackle: an essay on Austrian economics and the Kaleidic Society, Journal of Economic Literature, 14, pp. 5462. Lamb, R.K. (1952) The entrepreneur and the community, in W. Miller (ed.), Men in Business, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Lamberton, D.M. (1965) The Theory of Prot, Oxford: Blackwell. Lamberton, D.M. (1972) Information and prot, in C.F. Carter and J.L. Ford (eds), Uncertainty and Expectations in Economics: Essays in Honour of G.L.S. Shackle, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 191212. Lancaster, K. (1966), A new approach to consumer theory, Journal of Political Economy, 74, pp. 13257. Lancaster, K. (1979) Variety, Equity, and Efciency, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Leff, N.H. (1978) Industrial organization and entrepreneurship in the developing countries: the economic groups, Economic Development and Cultural Change, 26, pp. 66175. Leff, N.H. (1979) Entrepreneurship and economic development: the problem revisited, Journal of Economic Literature, 17, pp. 4664. Leibenstein, H. (1966) Allocative efciency vs. X-efciency, American Economic Review, 56, pp. 392415. Leibenstein, H. (1968) Entrepreneurship and development, American Economic Review, 58, pp. 7283. Leibenstein, H. (1969) Organizational or frictional equilibria, X-efciency and the rate of innovation, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 83, pp. 600 623. Leibenstein, H. (1976) Beyond Economic Man: A New Foundation for Microeconomics, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Leibenstein, H. (1978) General X-efciency Theory and Economic Development, New York: Oxford University Press. Leibenstein, H. (1979) The general X-efciency paradigm and the role of the entrepreneur, in M.J. Rizzio (ed.), Time, Uncertainty and Disequilibrium, Lexington, Mass: D.C. Heath, pp. 12739. Lessner, M. and Knapp, R.R. (1974) Achievement orientation of small industrial entrepreneurs in the Philippines, Human Organization, 33, pp. 17382. Levitt, T. (1965) Industrial Purchasing Behaviour: A Study in Communications Effects, Boston: Division of Research, Graduate School of Business Administration, Harvard University. Loasby, B.J. (1976) Choice, Complexity and Ignorance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
256
The entrepreneur
Lupton, T. and Wilson, C.S. (1959) The social background of and connections of top decision makers, Manchester School, 27, pp. 3051. Lynn, R. (ed.) (1974) The Entrepreneur: Eight Case Studies, London: Allen & Unwin. Machlup, F. (1962a) The Production and Distribution of Knowledge in the United States, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Machlup, F. (1962b) The supply of inventors and inventions, in R.R. Nelson (ed.), The Rate of Direction of Inventive Activity, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 14367. Machlup, F. (1980) Knowledge: Its Creation, Distribution and Economic Signicance, Volume 1: Knowledge and Knowledge Production, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. MacLaurin, W.R. (1953) The Sequence from invention to innovation and its relation to economic growth, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 67, pp. 97 111. Manne, H.G. (1966) Insider Trading and the Stock Market, New York: Free Press. Manseld, E. (1961) Technical change and the rate of imitation, Econometrica, 29, pp. 74166. Manseld, E. (1963a) The speed of response of rms to new techniques, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 77, pp. 290309. Manseld, E. (1963b) Intrarm rates of diffusion of an innovation, Review of Economics and Statistics, 45, pp. 34859. Manseld, E. (1964) Industrial research and development expenditures: determinants, prospects and relation to size of rm and inventive output, Journal of Political Economy, 72, pp. 31940. Manseld, E. (1968) Industrial Research and Technological Innovation: An Econometric Analysis, New York: W.W. Norton. Manseld, E. (1969) The Economics of Technological Change, London: Longmans. Manseld, E., Rapoport, J., Schnee, J., Wagner, S. and Hamburger, M. (1971) Research and Innovation in the Modern Corporation, New York: W.W. Norton. Marris, P. and Somerset, A. (1971) African Businessmen: A Study of Entrepreneurship and Development in Kenya, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Marschak, J. (1968) Economics of inquiring, communicating, deciding, American Economic Review, 58, pp. 118. Marschak, J. (1971) Economics and information systems, in M.D. Intriligator (ed.), Frontiers of Quantitative Economics, Amsterdam: North-Holland, pp. 32107.
Bibliography
257
Marschak, J. (1972) Optimal systems for information and decision, in A.V. Balakrishnan (ed.), Techniques of Optimisation, New York: Academic Press, pp. 35570. Marschak, J. and Radner, R. (1972) Economic Theory of Teams, New Haven: Yale University Press. Marshall, A. (1890) Principles of Economics, 8th edn (ed. G.W. Guilleband), 2 vols, London: Macmillan, 1961. Martin, D.T. (1979) Alternative views of Mengerian entrepreneurship, History of Political Economy, 11, pp. 27185. Mason, E.S. (1951) Schumpeter on monopoly and the large rm, Review of Economics and Statistics, 33, pp. 13944. Mason, E.S. (1967) Monopolistic competition and the growth process in less developed countries: Chamberlin and the Schumpeterian dimension, in R.E. Kuenne (ed.), Monopolistic Competition Theory: Studies in Impact; Essays in Honor of Edward H. Chamberlin, New York: John Wiley and Sons. Massy, W.F., Montgomery, D.B. and Morrison, D.G. (1970) Stochastic Models of Buying Behaviour, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. McClelland, D.C. (1967) The Achieving Society, New York: Free Press. McClelland, D.C. and Winter, D.G. (1969) Motivating Economic Achievement, New York: Free Press. McClelland, W.G. (1967) Costs and Competition in Retailing, London: Macmillan. McGaffey, T.N. and Christy, R. (1975) Information processing capability as a predictor of entrepreneurial effectiveness, Academy of Management Journal, 18, pp. 85763. McKean, R. et al. (1970) Symposium on product liability, University of Chicago Law Review, 38, pp. 1141. McNulty, P.J. (1967) A note on the history of perfect competition, Journal of Political Economy, 75, pp. 3959. McNulty, P.J. (1968) The meaning of competition, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 82, pp. 63956. Mill, J.S. (1848) Principles of Political Economy, new edn (ed. W.J. Ashley), London: Longmans, 1909. Miller, W. (ed.) (1962) Men in Business: Essays on the Historical Role of the Entrepreneur, New York: Harper and Row. Mills, C.W. (1945) The American business elite: a collective portrait, The Tasks of Economic History, Supplement to Journal of Economic History, 2, pp. 2044. Mises, L. von (1949) Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, London: William Hodge.
258
The entrepreneur
Montias, J.M. (1976) The Structure of Economic Systems, New Haven: Yale University Press. Moss, S. (1981) An Economic Theory of Business Strategy, Oxford: Martin Robertson. Mueller, D.C. (1972) A life cycle theory of the rm, Journal of Industrial Economics, 20, pp. 199219. Mueller, D.C. (1979) Public Choice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nabseth, L. and Ray, G.F. (1974) The Diffusion of New Industrial Processes: An International Study, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nafziger, E.W. (1978) Class, Caste, and Entrepreneurship: A Study of Indian Industrialists, Honolulu: University Press of Hawaii. Nash, J.F. (1950) The bargaining problem, Econometrica, 18, pp. 15562. Nelson, P. (1970) Information and consumer behaviour, Journal of Political Economy, 78, pp. 31129. Nelson, R. (1974) Neoclassical vs. evolutionary theories of growth, Economic Journal, 84, pp. 886905. Nelson, R., Winter, S. and Schuette, H. (1977) Technical change in an evolutionary model, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 90, pp. 90118. Newcomer, M. (1955) The Big Business Executive, New York: Columbia University Press. Nicosia, F.M. (1966) Consumer Decision Processes: Marketing and Advertising Implications, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Oi, W.Y. and Hurter, A.P. Jr (1965) Economics of Private Truck Transportation, Dubuque, lowa: William C. Brown Co.; Chapter 2 reprinted as A theory of vertical integration in road transport services, in B.S. Yarney (ed.), Economics of Industrial Structure, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1973, pp. 23362. Owens, R.L. (1978) Anthropological study of entrepreneurship, Eastern Anthropologist, 31, pp. 6580. Oxenfeldt, A.R. (1943) New Firms and Free Enterprise: Prewar and Postwar Aspects, Washington, DC: American Council on Public Affairs. Pandey, J. and Tewary, N.B. (1979) Locus of control and achievement values of entrepreneurs, Journal of Occupational Psychology, 52, pp. 10711. Papandreou, A.G. (1952) Some basic problems in the theory of the rm, in B.F. Haley (ed.), A Survey of Contemporary Economics, vol. II, Homewood, Illinois: Richard D. Irwin, pp. 183219. Papanek, H. (1972) Pakistans big businessmen, Economic Development and Cultural Change, 21, pp. 132. Pelzel, J. (1965) The small industrialist in Japan, in H.G.J. Aitken (ed.),
Bibliography
259
Explorations in Enterprise, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, pp. 16183, reprinted in Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 2), 7, pp. 7993. Pen, J. (1952) A general theory of bargaining, American Economic Review, 42, pp. 2442. Penrose, E.T. (1959) The Theory of the Growth of the Firm, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Plum, W. (1977) The Entrepreneur: Outsider in Industrial Society, Bonn: Friedrich-Ebert-Stiftung. Pollard, S. (1965) The Genesis of Modern Management, London: Edward Arnold. Radner, R. (1968) Competitive equilibrium under uncertainty, Econometrica, 36, pp. 3158. Rapoport, A. (1953) Spread of information through a population with sociocultural bias: I, assumption of transitivity, Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 15, pp. 52333. Rashevsky, N. (1953) Imitative behaviour in nonuniformly spatially distributed populations, Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 15, pp. 6373. Ravenshear, A. F. (1908) The Industrial and Commercial Inuence of the English Patent System, London: T. Fisher Unwin. Redlich, F. (194051) History of American Business Leaders, 2 vols, Ann Arbor, Michigan: Edwards Brothers. Redlich, F. (1949) The origin of the concepts of Entrepreneur and Creative Entrepreneur, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 1), 1, pp. 17. Redlich, F. (1956) The military enterpriser: a neglected area of research, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 1), 8, pp. 2526. Redlich, F. (1958) Business leadership: diverse origins and variant forms, Economic Development and Cultural Change, 6, pp. 17790. Redlich, F. (1959) Entrepreneurial typology, Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv, 82, pp. 15068. Redlich, F. (1963) Economic development, entrepreneurship and psychologism: a social scientists critique of McClellands Achieving Society, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 2), 1, pp. 1035. Reekie, W.D. (1979) Industry, Prices and Markets, Deddington, Oxford: Philip Allan. Reekie, W.D. (1981) The Economics of Advertising, London: Macmillan. Reichardt, R. (1962) Competition through the introduction of new products, Zeitschrift fr Nationalokonomie, 22, pp. 4184. Richardson, G.B. (1960) Information and Investment, London: Oxford University Press.
260
The entrepreneur
Rizzo, M.J. (1979) Disequilibrium and all that: an introductory essay, in M.J. Rizzo (ed.), Time, Uncertainty and Disequilibrium, Lexington, Mass: D.C. Heath, pp. 118. Roberts, B. (1971) Individual inuence over group decisions, Southern Economic Journal, 37, pp. 43444. Roberts, B. and Holdren, B.R. (1972) Theory of Social Process: An Economic Analysis, Ames, Iowa: Iowa State University Press. Robertson, A. (1974) The Lessons of Failure: Cases and Comments on Consumer Product Innovation, London: Macdonald. Robertson, T.S. (1971) Innovative Behaviour and Communication, New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Robinson, E.A.G. (1934) The problem of management and the size of rms, Economic Journal, 44, pp. 24054. Rogers, E.M. (1962) Diffusion of Innovations, New York: Free Press. Rogers, E.M. and Shoemaker, F.F. (1971) Communication of Innovations, New York: Free Press. Romeo, A. (1975) Inter-industry and inter-rm differences in the rate of diffusion, Review of Economics and Statistics, 57, pp. 31119. Romeo, A. (1977) The rate of imitation of a capital-embodied process innovation, Economica, 44, pp. 6370. Rosenberg, N. (1976) Perspectives on Technology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ross, N.S. (1952) Management and the size of the rm, Review of EconomicStudies, 19, pp. 14854. Rothbard, M.N. (1962) Man, Economy and State, New York: D. Van Nostrand. Rothschild, M. (1973) Models of market organization with imperfect information: a survey, Journal of Political Economy, 81, pp. 283308. Rothwell, R. (1975) Intra-corporate entrepreneurs, Management Decision, 13, pp. 14254. Routh, G. (1975) The Origin of Economic Ideas, London: Macmillan. Sarachek, B. (1978) American Entrepreneurs and the Horatio Alger Myth, Journal of Economic History, 38, pp. 43956. Sargent Florence, P. (1961) Ownership, Control and Success of Large Companies, London: Sweet and Maxwell. Sawyer, J.E. (1951) Entrepreneurial error and economic growth, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 1), 4, pp. 199204. Say, J.B. (1803) A Treatise on Political Economy: Or, the Production, Distribution and Consumption of Wealth, New York: Augustus M. Kelley, 1964. Sayigh, Y.A. (1962) Entrepreneurs of Lebanon: The Role of the Business Leader in a Developing Economy, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Bibliography
261
Schelling, T.C. (1960) The Strategy of Conict, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Schelling, T.C. (1978) Micromotives and Macrobehavior, New York: W.W. Norton. Scherer, F.M. (1965) Firm size, market structure, opportunity and the output of patent inventions, American Economic Review, 55, pp. 1097123. Scherer, F.M. (1967) Research and development resource allocation under rivalry, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 81, pp. 35994. Schiff, E. (1971) Industrialization without National Patents: The Netherlands, 18691912; Switzerland, 18501907, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Schmookler, J. (1954) The level of inventive activity, Review of Economics and Statistics, 36, pp. 18390. Schmookler, J. (1962) Economic sources of inventive activity, Journal of Economic History, 22, pp. 120. Schmookler, J. (1966) Invention and Economic Growth, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Schotter, A. (1981) The Economic Theory of Social Institutions, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Schreier, J.W. and Komives, J.L. (1973) The Entrepreneur and New Enterprise Formation, Milwaukee, Wisconsin: Center for Venture Management. Schultz, T.W. (1975) The value of the ability to deal with disequilibria, Journal of Economic Literature, 13, pp. 82746. Schumpeter, J.A. (1934) The Theory of Economic Development, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Schumpeter, J.A. (1939) Business Cycles: A Theoretical, Historical and Statistical Analysis of the Capitalist Process, 2 vols, New York: McGraw-Hill. Schumpeter, J.A. (1942) Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, 5th edn (ed. T. Bottomore), London: Allen & Unwin, 1976. Schumpeter, J.A. (1965) Economic theory and entrepreneurial history, in H.G.J. Aitken (ed.), Explorations in Enterprise, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, pp. 4564. Shackle, G.L.S. (1957) The nature of the bargaining process, in J.T. Dunlop (ed.), The Theory of Wage Determination, London: Macmillan, pp. 292 314. Shackle, G.L.S. (1961) Decision, Order and Time in Human Affairs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Shackle, G.L.S. (1970) Expectation, Enterprise and Prot: The Theory of the Firm, London: Allen & Unwin. Shackle, G.L.S. (1979) Imagination and the Nature of Choice, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Shackle, G.L.S. (1981) F.A. Hayek, 1899, in D.P. OBrien and J.R. Presley
262
The entrepreneur
(eds), Pioneers of Modern Economics in Britain, London: Macmillan, pp. 23461. Shils, E.B. and Zucker, W. (1979) Developing a model for internal corporate entrepreneurship, Social Science, 54, pp. 195203. Shubik, M. (1959) Strategy and Market Structure, New York: John Wiley and Sons. Simon, H.A. (1959) Theories of decision-making in economics and behavioural science, American Economic Review, 49, pp. 25383. Simon, H.A. (1976) Administrative Behaviour, 3rd edn, New York: Free Press. Simon, H.A. (1980) Models of Thought, New Haven: Yale University Press. Sloan, P. (1973) The international diffusion of an innovation, Journal of Industrial Economics, 22, pp. 619. Smith, C.W. (1981) The Mind of the Market, London: Croom Helm. Smith, D.C. (1978) Organized crime and entrepreneurship, International Journal of Criminology and Penology, 6, pp. 16177. Smith, N.R. (1967) The Entrepreneur and His Firm: The Relationship between Type of Man and Type of Company, East Lansing: Bureau of Business and Economic Research, Graduate School of Business Administration, Michigan State University. Solo, C.S. (1951) Innovation in the capitalist process: a critique of the Schumpeterian theory, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 65, pp. 41728. Soltow, J.H. (1968) The entrepreneur in economic history American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), 58, pp. 8492. Sombart, W. (1915) The Quintessence of Capitalism: A Study of the History and Psychology of the Modern Business Man (trans. M. Epstein), London: T. Fisher Unwin. Spence, M. (1977) Consumer misperceptions, product failure and producer liability, Review of Economic Studies, 44, pp. 56172. Stevens, C.M. (1963) Strategy and Collective Bargaining Negotiation, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Stewart, I.M.T. (1970) Information in the Cereals Market, London: Hutchinson. Stigler, G.J. (1957) Perfect competition historically contemplated, Journal of Political Economy, 65, reprinted in G.J. Stigler, Essays in the History of Economics, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1965, pp. 23467. Stigler, G.J. (1961) The economics of information, Journal of Political Economy, 69, pp. 21325. Stigler, G.J. (1967) Imperfections in the capital market, Journal of Political Economy, 75, pp. 28792. Stigler, G.J. (1976) The Xistence of X-efciency, American Economic Review, 66, pp. 21316.
Bibliography
263
Stoneman, P.L. (1976) Technological Diffusion and the Computer Revolution: The UK Experience, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Strachan, H.W. (1976) Family and Other Business Groups in Economic Development: The Case of Nicaragua, New York: Praeger. Strassmann, W.P. (1959) Risk and Technological Innovation: American Manufacturing Methods during the Nineteenth Century, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Swan, P.L. (1970) Durability of consumption goods, American Economic Review, 60, pp. 88494. Taussig, F.W. (1915) Inventors and Moneymakers, New York: Macmillan. Taussig, F.W. and Joslyn, C.S. (1932) American Business Leaders: A Study in Social Origins and Social Stratication, New York: Macmillan. Thirlby, G.F. (1946) The subjective theory of value and accounting cost, Economica, N.S. 13, reprinted in J.M. Buchanan and G.F. Thirlby (eds), LSE Essays on Cost, London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1973, pp. 4368. Thirlby, G.F. (1952) The economists description of business behaviour, Economica, N.S. 19, reprinted in J.M. Buchanan and G.F. Thirlby (eds), LSE Essays on Cost, London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1973, pp. 20124. Tilton, J.E. (1971) International Diffusion of Technology: The Case of Semiconductors, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution. Tucker, K.A. (1972) Business history: some proposals for aims and methodology, Business History, 14, pp. 116. Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. (1974) Judgments under uncertainty: heuristics and biases, Science, 185, pp. 112431. Vanneman, R.D. (1973) Dominance and achievement in entrepreneurial personalities, in E.B. Ayal (ed.), Micro Aspects of Development, New York: Praeger, pp. 12245. Veblen, T.B. (1904) The Theory of Business Enterprise, New York: Charles Scribners Sons. Warner, W.L. and Abegglen, J.C. (1955a) Big Business Leaders in America, New York: Harper and Brothers. Warner, W.L. and Abegglen, J.C. (1955b) Occupational Mobility in American Business and Industry: Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Webber, M.J. (1972) Impact of Uncertainty on Location, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Webber, M.J. (1979) Information Theory and Urban Spatial Structure, London: Croom Helm. Weber, M. (1930) The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (trans. T. Parsons), London: Allen & Unwin.
264
The entrepreneur
Weston, J.F. (1949) Enterprise and prot, Journal of Business, 22, pp. 141 59. Weston, J.F. (1950) A generalised uncertainty theory of prot, American Economic Review, 40, pp. 4060. Weston, J.F. (1954) The prot concept of theory: a restatement, Journal of Political Economy, 62, pp. 15270. Willett, A.H. (1901) The Economic Theory of Risk and Insurance, New York: Columbia University Press. Williamson, O.E. (1964) The Economics of Discretionary Behaviour: Managerial Objectives in a Theory of the Firm, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Williamson, O.E. (1967) Hierarchical control and optimum rm size, Journal of Political Economy, 75, pp. 12338. Williamson, O.E. (1970) Corporate Control and Business Behaviour, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Williamson, O.E. (1971) The vertical integration of production: market failure considerations, American Economic Review, 61, pp. 11223. Williamson, O.E. (1975) Markets and Hierarchies: Analysis and Antitrust Implications, New York: Free Press. Wiseman, J. (1953) Uncertainty, costs and collectivist economic planning, Economica, N.S. 20, reprinted in J.M. Buchanan and G.F. Thirlby (eds), LSE Essays on Cost, London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1973, pp. 22743. Wiseman, J. (1957) The theory of public utility price an empty box, Oxford Economic Papers, 9, reprinted in J.M. Buchanan and G.F. Thirlby (eds), LSE Essays on Cost, London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson, 1973, pp. 24571. Wohl, R.R. (1949) An historical context for entrepreneurship, Explorations in Entrepreneurial History (Series 1), 1, pp. 816. Wohl, R.R. (1953), The rags to riches story: an episode in secular idealism, in R. Bendix and S.M. Lipset (eds), Class, Status and Power, New York: Free Press, pp. 38895. Wohl, R.R. (1954) The signicance of business history, Business History Review, 28, pp. 12840. Wyllie, I.G. (1954) The Self-made Man in America: the Myth of Rags to Riches, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Index
active planning 234 advertising 1726 Andrews, P., on entrepreneurial rms 2256, 231 arbitrage 647 in perfect competition 81 and pricing 67, 229 of stocks 689 and synthesis of information 70, 2334 arrogance, in entrepreneurs 19091 auctioneers (Walrasian) 12, 8083 banks, and entrepreneurial nance 128, 167 bargaining see negotiation barriers to entry 4951, 715, 1823, 1845, 2358 and capital requirements 142, 1679, 2367 in perfect competition 82 see also obstacles to trade betting option on commercial information 1223, 194 see also portfolio speculation bulk trading 934 capital 12730 as a barrier to entry 142, 1679, 2367 and social advancement 207, 21011 capital markets, internalization of 11617, 131 collusion, and competition 1845 combined markets 1079 commercial information 51 exploitation of 119 betting option 1223, 194 by employees 73, 12932, 1667 through coordination 1257 through licensing 54, 12023 through portfolio speculation 1235, 126, 133 internalization of 1223 communication in decision making 27 and information 71, 98 see also advertising; contact making competition 436, 2256 and collusion 1845 development of 1825 for information 514 and information monopoly 49 and neoclassical economics 1213 with a one-part tariff 468 and rewards 1947 theories of see monopolistic competition theory; perfect competition see also barriers to entry; pricing; sequential negotiation; trade competitive professionalism, for social advancement 2056, 208, 209 composite goods see combined markets; multi-purpose goods contact making 148, 1525 see also social contact contingency planning 224 contingent forward claims in information 121 market costs 923 contracts for information searches 534 long-term 50 for market making 148 see also defaults; employment contracts; enforcement services; forward markets; implicit contracts; licensing; negotiation; recontracting; sanctions coordination 356, 121 attitudes to 212 265
266
The entrepreneur economic development, and entrepreneurs 1013 economic systems, types of 200201 economies of scale see scale economies education, and entrepreneurship 20710, 2378 employees exploitation of commercial information 73, 12932, 1667 see also delegation employment contracts 11315, 216 enforcement services 148, 149 see also sanctions entrepreneurial rms 1923 theories of 2258, 231 entrepreneurs characteristics 1314, 25, 2932, 19091, 193, 2235, 227 denitions 1922 as delegates 12932, 192, 203, 2078 matching to decisions 1913 rewards 1939 roles 21617 skills 23841 stereotypes 16 see also producer-entrepreneurs; retailer-entrepreneurs; selfemployment entrepreneurship criminal 203, 2045, 209 and education 20710, 2378 establishment 202, 203, 205, 208, 209 and ethnicity 1112, 213 forms of 200205 markets in 131, 188 political 2024, 205, 209, 21112 private 202, 203, 205, 209 and religion 21213 revolutionary 203, 204, 205, 209 risk in 1989 screening for 1923, 1989, 2078 and social advancement 200, 21013 theories of see Andrews; Hayek; Kirzner; Knight; Leibenstein; Penrose; Schumpeter and uncertainty 22023, 22930 see also decision making; judgmental decisions; market making entry, barriers to see barriers to entry
forward integration into 1257 of information searches 534 politicians aims 21112 see also partial coordination; resource allocation; social coordination copyright, as a barrier to entry 72 costs denitions 856 see also market making, costs; monitoring, costs; pricing; resource costs; transaction costs criminal entrepreneurship 203, 2045, 209 decentralization of contact making 1525 of inventory stores 1525 decision makers, recruitment of 170 decision making 2021 activities involved 256, 30 delegation in 269, 239 demand for 224 qualities needed 25, 2932 resource costs 248 by teams 289 see also information; judgmental decisions; managerial capacity; risk; uncertainty decline, of rms 181 defaults in decision making 27 in trade 87, 9091 see also enforcement services; monitoring; sanctions delegation in decision making 269, 239 to entrepreneurs 12932, 1912, 203, 2078 see also employees; establishment entrepreneurship demand for decision making 224 see also markets; product demand development see economic development; innovation; international development discounts, for retailers 1567 distribution 148, 149, 1525 diversication 17981, 2278
Index establishment entrepreneurship 202, 203, 205, 208, 209 ethnicity, and entrepreneurship 1112, 213 external markets 1067, 11213 families as information sources 2345 as suppliers of capital 11617, 1678 as suppliers of labour 16970 family rms, and self-employment 11617 nance see capital nancial speculators, and social advancement 202, 203, 205, 207, 210 rms characteristics 1612, 216 control within 1634 development of founding of 1657 constraints on growth 1679 growth of product market 1716 building on experience 1769 diversication 17981 growth of competition 1825 decline 181 forward claims 1323 labour supply 16971, 239 scope of 1623 see also banks; entrepreneurial rms; joint-stock companies; marketmaking rms forward integration, into coordination 1257 forward markets for rms 1323 in quality of service 13940 trading in 1378 see also contingent forward claims functional denitions, of entrepreneurs 2022 goodwill as a barrier to entry 50, 745 see also reputation Hayek, Friedrich von, on market adjustment 21819, 229
267
implicit contracts, and priority setting 13940 indivisibilities, and diversication 17981, 2278 industries, denitions 1812 information access to 2335, 237 and communication 71, 98 competitive search for 514 costs 23, 859, 989 and decision making 223, 26 and diversication 179 feedback from 235 monopoly of 49, 51 in perfect competition 82 and quality improvement 1769 synthesis of 7071, 2334 and trade 3841 see also commercial information; decision making; judgmental decisions; uncertainty innovation 2235, 23031 see also product innovation; technological innovation intellectual rights see copyright intermediate product markets, internalization of 112 intermediation see market making internalization of contact making 1525 of distribution 149, 1525 of enforcement services 149 and forward contracts 138 of inventories 1525 of labour services 11316 of market making 1489 of markets 1067, 11113 in capital 11617, 131 in information 1223 of production 112, 14952 internal markets, control in 1634 international development, and entrepreneurs 11 invention, and innovation 2245 inventories 148 decentralization of 1525 investment in 1367, 138, 1512, 155 and speculation 142, 1434 opportunity costs 1356
The entrepreneur and product specications 150 and retailing 1557 services packaging of 146 pricing 147 and social conventions 14041, 1445 speculation in 1425 market-making rms 1516, 979 see also banks; entrepreneurial rms markets combining 1079 in entrepreneurship 131, 188 external 1067, 11213 internal, control of 1634 internalization of 1067, 11113, 11617, 1223, 131 see also labour services market structure 1815 marriage, for social advancement 205, 206 merchant banks see banks middlemen 3641 monitoring 148 costs 100101, 1023 of information provided 121 in internal markets 1634 and market making 15051, 2412 of trade 91, 96 see also risk control monopolies as barriers to entry 50, 73 of information 49, 51 monopolistic competition theory 823 multi-part tariffs 46, 48 see also one-part tariffs multi-purpose goods 10911 see also labour services negotiation 41, 579, 88, 148, 2389 see also recontracting neoclassical economics of arbitrage 657 and the competitive process 1213 criticisms 1213, 7984, 21819 developments to 1316 and X-efciency theory 21516, 217 see also perfect competition obstacles to trade 845 see also barriers to entry
joint-stock companies 128 judgmental decisions 2021 identication of 18890 selection of entrepreneurs for 1913 Kirzner, Israel on arbitrage 64 on market adjustment 21920, 229 Knight, Frank, on uncertainty 22023, 22930 labour services internalization 11316 to new rms 16971, 239 see also delegation; self-employment Leibenstein, Harvey, X-efciency theory 21517, 2289 leisure, for entrepreneurs 1689, 1957 licensing of commercial information 54, 12023 see also patents loans see capital long-term contracts 50 managerial capacity, utilizing 18081, 2278 market adjustment in perfect competition 1213, 823 theories of 21820, 229 market failure, and obstacles to trade 845 marketing see advertising; contact making market making activities 148 and contact making 1525 costs factors 8993 of information 23, 859, 989 and price/quantity determination 99104 reduction of 935 internalization of 1489 and monitoring 15051, 2412 for new rms 1716 and production 14952, 1557
Index one-part tariffs 40, 468 opportunism, and market making 141 organizational skills, in entrepreneurship 239, 24041 packaging of composite goods 1089 of market-making services 146 partial coordination 567 and arbitrage 649 and product innovation 634 and sequential negotiation 579 and synthesis of information 7071 and technological innovation 5962 patents as barriers to entry 723 see also licensing Penrose, E.T., on entrepreneurial rms 2268, 231 perfect competition 1213, 8084 planning see active planning; contingency planning; decision making political entrepreneurship 2024, 205, 209, 21112 portfolio speculation 1235, 126, 133 see also betting option price discrimination and arbitrage 689 and market-making costs 1024 pricing 48, 74 and arbitrage 67, 229 as a barrier to entry 183 and inventory adjustment 1367, 138, 144 and market adjustment 21820 and market-making costs 99104 of market-making services 147 and product development 178 and product innovation 634 and quality 183, 184 as a rationing tool 141 and social coordination 62, 64 and technological innovation 6062 see also perfect competition; spot price stability; Walrasian auctioneers priorities, under rationing 13840 private coordination 35 private entrepreneurship 202, 203, 205, 209
269
producer-entrepreneurs 1557 product demand, social factors 1756 product development, and information 1769 product innovation 634, 70, 23940 see also multi-purpose goods; technological innovation production concepts of 15 internalization of 112, 14952 and market making 14952, 1557 see also scale economies product specications 867, 148 and market making 150 and market making costs 8990 prot and uncertainty 22023 see also rewards pyramid climbing see establishment entrepreneurship qualications see education qualied entrepreneurs 193 quality and pricing 183, 184 see also product development; service quality quality control see monitoring quantity of trade see trade, volume racketeering 2045 rationality, in neoclassical economics 21516, 217 rationing 13840, 141 recontracting 83, 142 failure of 1357 recruitment of entrepreneurs 1913 for new rms 17071, 239 see also screening religion, and entrepreneurship 21213 repeat-trading 945, 967 in labour services 11415 reputation and entrepreneurial loans 128 establishment of 945, 97 see also goodwill resale restrictions, on information 1212 resource allocation 11, 345
270
The entrepreneur through nancial speculation 202, 203, 205, 207, 210 through marriage 205, 206 social contact and entrepreneurial advancement 210, 2345, 237 see also contact making social conventions, and trade 14041, 1445 social coordination 35, 4041, 48 and arbitrage 65, 67, 69 and crime 204 and information searches 54 and prices 62, 64 in product innovation 64 in technological innovation 62 social factors, in product demand 1756 specialists, recruitment of 17071, 239 speculation in market making 1425 see also betting; nancial speculators; portfolio speculation spot price stability, and forward markets 1378 stocks allocation of 4950 arbitrage of 689 see also inventories synthesis, of information 7071, 2334 tariffs see multi-part tariffs; one-part tariffs; pricing teams, decision making by 289 technological innovation 5962, 70, 72 see also product innovation trade defaults in 87, 9091 see also enforcement services; sanctions in forward markets 1378 with full information 389 with limited information 3941 monitoring 91, 96 negotiation in 41, 579, 88 obstacles to 845 and social conventions 14041, 1445 through middlemen 3641 time lag costs 90 volume determination, and market making costs 99104
see also competition; coordination; trade resource costs, of decision making 248 resource ows, allocation of 4951 resources, sequential negotiation for 579 resource utilization of managerial capacity 18081, 2278 theories of 21517, 2289 retailer-entrepreneurs 1557, 162 retailing 1547, 226 revolutionary entrepreneurship 203, 204, 205, 209 rewards of entrepreneurs 1939 see also prot risk in entrepreneurship 1989 and uncertainty 22023, 22930 risk control 12930, 1323 see also monitoring sanctions in trade 967 see also enforcement services scale economies, as a barrier to entry 734, 1845 Schumpeter, Joseph, on innovation 2235, 23031 screening for entrepreneurship 1923, 1989, 2078 see also recruitment secrecy, as a barrier to entry 49, 73 self-employment 11517, 1657, 203, 205, 207 personal qualities 21012 self-esteem 190 sequential negotiation, for resources 579 service quality, forward markets in 13940 shops see retailing social advancement 200, 21013 constraints 2078 through competitive professionalism 2056, 208, 209 through education 2378
Index see also barriers to entry; bulk trading; competition; contracts; forward markets; market making; pricing; repeat-trading; reputation training see education transaction costs 1415, 83, 845 transport services see distribution uncertainty, and risk 22023, 22930 unqualied entrepreneurs 193 versatility, and product innovation 23940 Walrasian auctioneers 12, 8083 X-efciency theory (Leibenstein) 21517, 2289
271