Wellington Webb - Space and Time in The Philosophies of Kant and Bergson
Wellington Webb - Space and Time in The Philosophies of Kant and Bergson
Wellington Webb - Space and Time in The Philosophies of Kant and Bergson
IN
University of Toronto
1956
UNIVERSITY
OF
TORONTO
THE
DEGREE
OF
DOCTOR
OF
PHILOSOPHY
2:00 P.M.
AT
1956
IN
COMMITTEE
Professor Professor Professor Professor Professor Professor Professor Professor Professor
J.
IN
CHARGE
R. O'Donnell, Chai
BIOGRAPHICAL
1925 1951 1952 1953-55
56
--Born, Prescott, Ontario University of Western Ontario --B. A. --M.A., University of Western Ontario --School of Graduate Studies, University of Toronto
.
in the Philosophies of
(Abstract)
This thesis undertakes a systematic investigation of the theories of space and time of Kant and Bergson. Its purpose is to exhibit the relation between these theories and to show that Bergson's theory may be regarded as a logical develop-
ment
of Kant's.
As an essential preliminary to the investigation, an extended discussion of certain problems concerning space and time is presented. Of central importance is the question of whether it is necessary to maike a fundamental metaphysical distinction between space and time. It is concluded that the evidence seems to suggest that a theory which distinguishes between space and time is more tenable than one which treats space and time as exactly analogous elements in a four- dimensional space-time manifold. In addition, the preliminary discussion deals with problems created by the distinction between space and time. Since Kant and Bergson distinguish time from space by recognizing the intrinsic uniqueness of the passage of time, both philosophers are faced with the problems resulting from this distinction.
The introductory discussion provides a framework in which the views of Kant and Bergson are examined. First, by vindicating the distinction between space and time, it indicates the line which a development of Kant's views may justifiably take. Secondly, it uncovers the nature of those difficulties which lead Bergson to a development of Kant's views. Thirdly, it investigates the relationship between space and time and the principle of individuation in a manner which provides two alternative possibilities for the interpretation of Kant's theory of space and time.
It is suggested that a theory of space and time may take two alternative positions with respect to the relationship between space and time and the principle of individuation and other related principles which are the foundation of unity in nature. A theory may take the position that there is a principle of individuation for space which accounts for events in time, or that there is a principle of individuation for time which accounts for objects in space. In this thesis, the former alternative is called "possibility A", the latter, "possibility B".
At this point, Kant's views are introduced, and it is argued that his theory of space and time approximates to possibility B, rather than possibility A. Kant's manner of distinguishing between space and time, amd his doctrine of inner and outer sense are examined. It is shown that he conceived of space and time as homogeneous media, and that the distinction between them rests on the point that time has the characteristic of passage, and is uniquely associated with inner experience, while space is not. Space and outer sense seem to be, for Kant, an abstract aspect of inner sense, the peculiar form of which is time.
pointed out that Kant's exclusion of space from the account of the scherather than possibility A. is argued that Kant's Copernican revolution and his justification of For Kant synthetic a priori knowledge are only possible if he follows possibility B. must show that future experience will be determined in general in accordance with the categories, and this is only possible if the categories, as rules of synthesis which make for the unity of nature, apply to time rather than space. Otherwise, the passage of time might bring about experience not determined in accordance with the categories. In addition, Kant's answer to Hume's scepticism, by the same token, would not be possible except according to a theory which accepted possibility B. Kant's relevsmt statements are examined, and the weight of evidence seems to suggest that his theory of space and time approximates to possibility B.
It
is
matism
In addition,
Bergson's views are then introduced, and the striking similarity between Kant and Bergson in closely associating time and inner experience is pointed out. It is shown that Bergson follows Kant closely in holding that the unique character of time is revealed in inner experience which is in time alone. Kant's views on the impossibility of a science of psychology reveal that, for him, inner experience is quite unlike outer experience. Inner experience constitutes an area of appearances, which, although indubitable, are not subject to categorical determination, and hence do not represent possible experience in Kant's sense. Kant and Bergson are in agreement that knowledge appropriate to spatially related objects is inapplicable to the flow of inner experience.
This raises several problems which Kant does not attempt to solve, but which Bergson deals with at length. Kant's Copernican revolution requires that the categories, which arise independently in the nature of human thinking, should apply directly to time itself. Kant's doctrine of the Transcendental Imagination and the Schematism represents an attempt to mediate between the categories with their independent source, and the concrete flow of time. But how such mediation is possible
remains obscure. Bergson meets this problem by declaring it to be insoluble, a pseudo-problem stemming from a basic misconception of the nature of time.
Kant held that time was adequately representable in terms of concepts appropriate to space. But he was unable to render this doctrine consistent with his view that time is a unique form of sensibility. Bergson's development of Kant's theory consists in large part of showing that the time of inner experience cannot possibly be understood in ternas of concepts appropriate to outer sense. Kant had refused to answer the question of how human experience, which is characterized by two different modes of sensibility, namely, inner and outer sense, comes to have a unity. He gives no clear account of the unifying relation between inner and outer sense, and consequently no answer to the question of the relation between time as a unique form of the perpetual flux of inner experience, and the homogeneous time of outer sense. Bergson attempts to answer this question by showing that homogeneous time is a spurious, spatialized concept, and by an appeal to intuition. Spatial concepts falsify time, but the relationship between space and outer sense, and time and inner sense may be grasped by a metaphysical intuition which reveals how the concrete flow of time is broken up into discrete spatial parts. Bergson, as well as Kant, subscribes to possibility B, in holding that the intellect applies to the basic flow of time. But for Bergson, this application constitutes a falsification of the metaphysical reality of time.
opment
Bergson's view that time is ultimate reality represents a consistent develof Kant's theory of space and time. For Bergson's theory of time as a con-
Crete process of change, which is glimpsed in inner experience, takes advantage of the fact that, for Kant, the appearances and changes of inner experience are beyond the pale of cognition. Inner experience, for Kant, has a status exactly analogous to the status of things- in- themselves in being incapable of being known by means of the categories. Yet inner experience is indubitably real since it is actually experienced as a continuous flux, a point which Kant often stresses. Bergson's theory carries to its logical conclusion the point that beyond the sphere of conceptual determination. there can be no distinction between form and content. Thus time is not merely the
real form of inner sense, as
in the indivisible
is
it
is for
Time
is real,
in itself,
because
it
Bergson's close association of consciousness with the flow of time is related another aspect of Kant's thought. Kant distinguishes between inner sense and apperception, but fails to stress that inner sense is conscious inner sense. Bergson seizes upon this point, combining it with Kant's view that inner sense reveals a perpetual flux which is not cognizable. Kant's distinction between inner sense and apperception, thus represents the seed of Bergson's radical separation of the intellect and real time revealed in inner consciousness.
to
Bergson erects the apprehension of the change revealed in inner experience supreme metaphysical principle. He thus follows Kant's view that a metaphysics which would penetrate beyond appearance to reality itself must be intuitive. But whereas Kant thought this intuition would have to be an intellectual intuition, Bergson, stressing the consciousness of change in inner experience, argues that the intuition is non- intellectual. He rejects Kant's doctrine of judgment, and a logic of temporal process, holding that intellectual thinking is through-and-through a spatialization of a fundamentally non-spatial reality. Following this line of thought Bergson tries to show how matter and the intellect itself arise from the basic flow of duration (la duree). He thus denies the independent origin of the pure concepts of the understanding, and tries to show that logic itself is derivative rather than fundamental. Bergson's development of some aspects of Kant's thought thus ends in a view which would have been anathema to Kant.
into a
GRADUATE STUDIES
Major Subject:
Systematic Philosophy and Metaphysics:
Process
in the
BY
University of Toronto
1956
CONTENTS
CHAPTER ONE:
INTRODUCTION
CIIAPTEc i'uL:
2.
3*
CHAPTSIt TimSE;
1, 2
3.
CHAPTER
FOUxl:
AI^D
ITS
2,
3,
NOTES
BIBLIOGRAPHY
CHAPTER ONE
IKTRODUGTIOK
This thesis aims at a systematic investigation of
the theories of space and tine of Kant and Bergeon,
Its
and to
shov;
mological treatise.
v/e
tir.ie?*',
merely tell us
hovj
themselves.
rious theories of space and time may be presented in different donains of knowledge.
The question of what space
and psychology.
however, not merely in the context of some particular subject matter, but in a v/ider, metaphysical sense.
with certain relations between space, time and change (Ch, II,
Sec. 3).
In connection with the first of these topics, an
thesis is that Kant*s theory of space and time leaves certain problems unsolved.
That is, Kants explanation does
not deal vjith, indeed, does not even attempt to deal with
some of the questions that arise in connection with space
and time.
His doctrine
Kant
explicitly recognizes that he leaves some questions unanswered. Our preliminary discussion of the general features
of the distinction between space and time attempts to clari-
lationship between space and time require answers, Bergson's doctrines may be regarded in this respect as a logical
development of Kant's.
attempted.
4
issues involved in the relation between the theories of these
two philosophers v/ill aid the reader in drav/ing his own conclusions.
and time.
By a fundamental distinction
betvireen
space and
be added that v;hen it is said that time has the characteristic of passage, it is not meant that time itself changes or passes, v/hich is a rather loose way of expressing a
difficult point.
betvjeen space and time, the crux of xijhich turns on the pro-
point in judging in
i.'hat
but may be pressed much further beyond the point ^vhere they
vjere
It is argued by cer-
mental difference between space and time, viz., the characteristic of the passage of time, as opposed to the static
This
viev;
whether Kant's epistenology excludes the possibility of nonEuclidean geometries, v;hich a numbsr of scholars
dealt with,
dering.
liave
ably
v;e
are consi-
ful in physical science, is compatible v;ith Kantian epistemology, from the question of
-.ifhether
a metaphysical theory
we are considering
3uch
v,'ill,
in im-
the passage of time from problems relating to space and time as they are dealt with in physics.
The
fashioned in conformity
'iifith
the latter speaks not merely of physical events in spacetime, but of all events as being in space-time,
1 believe that the universe consists, without residue, of the spread of events in space-time, and that if vje thus accept realistically the four-dimensional fabric of juxtaposed actualities we can dispense v/ith all those dim non-factual cate:3ories Vihich have so bedevilled our rave: the potential, the subsistential, and the influential, the noumenal, the numinous, and the non-natv-ral, 4
tation of time.
Bercson^s develop-
Bergson probes deeper into the naHe sharpens the kind of distinc-
\'ith some
hesitation,
mains unexplained,
and Bergson,
That the philosophies of Kant and Bergson have re-
He
10
IjOW without su^esting' any comparison in iinportance between Kant and Bergson, there is this resemblance bet'.i/QtJii thei.:, that much of bhe in'^crest o-f Jer^son's work consists in his statement and exposition of antincruies to be found in present-day pliilosophy, that as the best road to the solution of these antinomies he errors a ii;;'.; stateirient of w.h& ^aslc or probleni of philosophy, and propounds a new method. Like Kant, his ;vork professes to be critical: to find the main source of difficulties in an uncriticissed assumption, 5
by Kant, one of
xi/hich
It may be said,
It may be that a
hov;ever, that
At any
ture, and for this reason we do not here deal vjith that con-
tingency.
11
of Kants theory of space and time, but rather a clean break
For in one
v.'ay
of the most important reasons for doing so, particularly in his exa:::ination of the relation betvjeen time and inner
sense,
up v;ith his
x-ze
maintain it will be
12
In connection v;ith
a theory of space-
a^id
extensive problem,
and like
others mentioned above, lies outside the parWe take Kant's position
Thus, v;hen
vje
are dealing with is one which includes the premise that time
is ultimately and uniquely different from space,
i\nd
the
reason v;hy we treat of development in this sense is that we feel that there are sound reasons for making this basic distinction.
Finally, it is advisable to
svun
up the similarities
worth no-
13
Kants
The
have already
emphasized, make a fundamental distinction becvjeen space and time, and for both this distinction has a considerable,
if not decisive, bearing on
of their philosophies.
hovj
space.
problems which lead Bergson to a theory v;hich can be regarded as a developuent of Kant's views, and vjhich allow
him to draw out the implications of Kant's node of distingviishing between space and time in a manner which Kant,
u
point of clarification concerning our subject needs to be
iaade#
tlian
historical.
The relations we examine between the two men raay or may not
be paralleled in point ox historical connection, For the 6 most part, they probably are not.
CMFTER TWO
PRELimNARY DISCUSSION OF
BST\\rSEN
TKi*
DISTIIIGTIGN
1,
and Tine
accoi;int
of than the
In everyday experience
are not often confused as to vjhat is spatial and what is But in philosophy, sone questions which
vje
temporal.
can
ask about the world seem to demand that we give some account
of the separation between space and time, ana indicate
hov;,
v;e
15
between them.
vsays in v;hich
cial sciences.
The different ways in which space is regarded in
17
by Gunn,
vjho
in its
ly to considerations of measurement".
two contexts.
For instance, tine as perceived is alivays limited. We never perceive the xifhole of tine. It is also perceived as sensibly continuous, as having a certain directional quality; it is transitive and related in its content to the subject at the moment of experience. Only if the vjider implied temporal perspective and the tirae-span immediately experienced be apprehended as passing into one another can Time be grasped, and in this way it is grasped as a continuura. Time as conceived is unlimited in character, is regarded as infinitely divisible and mathematically continuous like an infinite series. Further, it is looked on as involving an objective order of beforehand-after, ivhich is not to be equated \;ith the past, present or future of a subject, . Conceptual time is also conceived to be a unity in spite of the difficulty of ascribing to it any principle of coherence. Perceptual time, hovjever, is rooted in experience and professions of unity are not to be made in regard There may on this level be many unrelated to it. times. 10
vious that the question of whether or not space and time are
distinct seems to be irrelevant. Were it not for the mer-
It
time in a space-tir.ie continuum, and for a similar merging 11 of space and time in recent metaphysical theories, one might
rest content in the view that they are distinct, and direct
one's attention to grasping the peculiar nature of each.
mature,
Although mathematical attempts to demonstrate the unity of space and time in a single four-dimensional world do not completely obliterate the difference betx-jeen distances and durations, they certainly reveal a much greater similarity betv;een the two notions than vias ever evident in pre-Einsteinian physics, 13
Thus the question arises as to whether space and time are ultimately or fundamentally distinct; and if so,
in what their distinction consists.
It is not merely that
It is
also a question of
xi^hether
19
we deslf^ate as space and tine are sinple and irreducible,
each incapable of further explanation in terms of something
else; or whether they admit of analysis into more basic ele-
ments in
tor/iis
would be explained.
For he is not
and
hov/
20
that they are.
In either case, it v/ill be necessary to take
into consideration the way in which space and time are dis-
the distinction
iii
the cate-
in experience^
the realm of the purely conceptual, and the other as the con-
Are
These are some of the ways in which space and time may be
basically distinguished.
lias a
unity,
either
If it
21
Triat
It v/ill
damental distinctioii
bet\\;een
space and
tiiiie.
us consider the viev; that space and time are distinct sub14 stances. This theory brin;';s certain difficulties into sharp
problem of how one substance can act upon, or be related to another substance.
The concept of substance as that which
itself,
For
substance, and hence two such substances cannot be mutually 16 understood. Kow hovj two such substances can liave any sort
of relation, capable of being known, is indeed a perplexing
question.
22
physical intuition).
substances must have
tvjo
in
corar^ion,
or must resemble
of substance which is at faid.t, and should therefore be discarded, but since we are here concerned only
in the context of an illustration,
vie
i.'ith
substance
to one side.
23
\7ill
not carry
cannot relate
posteriori .
all
vje
coraraon
It
coiiUion
3y naming it
vre
coraraon beti^een
the en-
v/e
solutely unique entities, or alternatively, v/hether everything with which we are acquainted is absolutely unique.
V/e
24
may put this question in other terms and ask v^hether we ever
do have concepts, in terms of common properties, of things
with which we
ai-e
things to escape,
thing
v;e
/uid
tion that there is in the universe a principle ox the vndetermined, vmich remains over v/hen conceptualization has
done its
i-jork,
are con-
view that
oiu-
concepts of
This raises
are dealing
vje
ther
v/e
of course,
tlic
one concept,
lie
does not
Kaiit,
that space
and time.
26
iiegarding the distinction between space and tiue,
corainon.
coiiimon,
sentable by a concept.
There is, ol course, a fifth possibility, which could
be expressed as follovjs: "Iveither space nor time is repre-
(e.g. Vaihinger) who hold that space and time are ''fictions".
vievv's
of both
vje
have mentioned.
corrjaon,
27
/e
could never
If this v;ere,
For al-
though
v;e
unrela-
could never
resolve.
would be frustrated.
by themselves, adequately.
can form a
ti;ae,
A single concept
2g
in fact, the one taken by those who uphold the theory of the
manifold.
question of
vjhat is
choose the
In other words,
make a fundamental
In this case we cannot
expect to be able to understand the relation between space and time, although
v;e
According to this
29
conceivable relation to each other or to anything else.
In
view of
tlie
amont:;
that the relation between space and time would seem, on this
view, no more inexplicable than space and time themselves.
Metaphysics could
proceed only in
r.
tellect.
maining one
v;ill be
For
The
poral determinations.
30
nevertheless,
ment/
Me
s.'iall,
which deals
ivith the
between space and time must take one of the four possibilities
listed above.
Since neither Kant nor Bergson thinks of both
So we shall dis-
regard it.
Possibility
t\vo
represents a
viexv
opposed to any
And since Kant
It
can
lities three and four v;hich provide the general means whereby
Kant and Bergson might explain the distinction between space
and time.
31
of, space, it will not be possible to maintain that space
zation,
;vithin possibilities three and four, there is l?oom,
Space, for
for there would be nothing else like it, which it could resemble.
There
xi?ould
from forLiing a concept of spatiality from the common properties of a plurality of the parts of space.
And in so far as
of it.
It
say of both space and time that they vjere unique entities.
32
An eclecticism of
corrjnon,
have narrowed
T|ie
dotvn
the possivie
principle
tinction between space and time must take one of the three
33
combination of them.
tlie
are distinguished in
x,he
special scionces.
sists.
To return to our
ori;::;inal
question
ox'
ansv.'ers
to tais questioii.
If, for example, it is held that space and time are not re-
this unity.
The fiirther
question of
hov;
Also,
v;ill be a
problem
34
these are quoGtious of a kind which hant, in accordance with
the dictates of his position, gives no answers.
35
2. 31milaritie3 and Differences bet;veeu Space aiid Tirae
aiid tirae
were notv/o
ticed by Locke,
"i;ho
dis~
tinct, simple idcac. To conclude: expansion and duration do mutually embrace and conprehend each otlier; every part of space being in every part of duration, and every part of duration in every part of expansion. Such a conbination of two distinct ideas, is, I suppose, scarce to- be found in all that great variety i;e do or can conceive, and may afford matter to farther speculation. IB
hov/
vides a conspicuous exaciple of the emphasis on the similarities betv;oen space and time.
the doctrine that space and time as they are dealt with ma-
thematically in physical science constitute, v/ithout qualification, what space and time are, it is possible, nevertheless, to maintain the philosopiiic importance of their simi-
indubitable success of the mathematical treatment in allowing predictions to be made concerning spatio-temporal events in
the world.
Yet it should be noted that this point does not
viev;
36
or intrinsically similar,
v/hitehead's
fch-3ory hov/
of space and
it may be pos-
both to space and to tine, and other minor characteristics 20 vjhich are diverse as between space and tine". He explains
this common feature as follows:
37
The characteristic comuon both to space and time is that material can be said to be here in space and here in time, or h ere in space-time, in a perfectly definite sense which does not require for its explanation any reference to other recions of space-time. Curiously enough this charc.cteristic of simple location holds "whether we look on a recion of space-time as determined absolutely
or relatively,
21
Whitehead considers the assumption of the simple location of matter to be a fallacy if it is taken to express a
expressing.
The seventeenth century had finally produced a scheme of scientific thoucht framed by raathenaticians, for the use of mathematicians* The great characteristic of the mathematical mind is its capacity for aealing with abstractions J and for eliciting from, them cloarcut demonstrative chains of reasoning, entirely satisfactory so long as it is abstractions v;hich you v/ant to think about. The enormous success of the scientific abstractions, yielding on the one hand natter with its simple location ih space and time, on the other hand m^a7~perceivi.ng, suffering, reasoning, but not interf ering , h^s foisted onto philosophy the task of accepting then as the most concrete rendering of fact, 22
nection".
of space
charac-
3^
tirie
fom
24
of extensiveness"
IHiitehead
realizes quite clearly that the concept of space-time, conceived as a network of relations, obliterates the distinction
betvjeen space and time.
But this exhibition of the actual universe as extensive and divisible has left out the distinction betvieen space and tiiae. 25
Ilathenatics,
which deals
v;ith the
It is in the concrete,
the emphasis on their analogous properties from the standpoint of pure relation, and in a''dition shov;s how these ana-
It
This is
all the
laore
39
mathematics as a formal science of pure relations.
logiss for
not to be
hi3i
The ana-
a nalo.f^ies
ledged to ba characteristic of time, and those usually acknowladged to be characteristic of space, separately,
tirithout
Geometries
40
after, \.hich are taken to be the fimdanental ones ch^irac-
tcrisoic of tine.
Thus instead of re^arc'ln^ ourselves us, so to speak, swimming along in an ocean of space (as we usually do), we s.re to think of ourselves rather as scnehow' pursuing a course in an ocean of time; x^hile spacial relations are to be. rer;ardeQ as the rianife station of t h e fact thaT th e eTements of t ine f oriu a svstem in conical order ^ couc:vi,::L.lcn );!dc]i u^^y be ctualyned ij_;_ ten.::; oi" " the rela tions of before ancTafterV 2'6
:
shall formulate".
Thus, if this
Vie
need not,
even
dravm
cominon to
41
terminations.
brou'::ht
Bread's representation.
the parts of extension are extension, and all the parts of 31 in other words, space and tine in
Two fur-
42
Time in general is to duration as place to expansion. They are so much of these boundless oceans of eternity and iiamensity, as is set out a.id distinguished froni t^e rest as it vere by landmarks; and so are laade use of" to denote the position of finite real beings, in respect to one anoth<3r, in those uiiiform infln^' -^ -'^ ^=in3 of duration and space, 32
another question,
points out,
fvir:cnt.
narhedly different.
Temporal re-
suppose title:
Spatial extension and the occurrence of spatial relations presuppose temporal duration and a certain deterip-inate forsi of temporal relation. Shape and size are commonly ascribed to particulars which persist through periods of time and have histories of longer or shortar duration. 34
Robb expresses the difference between spatial and tem-
Kow in considering the subject of time as it presents itself to our experience there is one very important respect in which it appears to differ from our spacial experience. L*"J Of an3r two instants which one experiences in one s own mind one is after the other.
'
44
i'iiis relation of after is what is called an asym metrical relation by which is meant a relation ?. such that if B bears the relation it to A then A does not bear the relation R to B. ihus, in the parliicular case considered, if B is after A, then A is not after B, ihere are however relations which are syrjnetrical; such, for e>:ar.iple, as the relat:.on of e<^iialit. ^. where if 3 is equal to a then A is equal to B, i'ovj the relation of two points or two particles in space is a syuiuetrical relation and, if A and B be taken as tv;o distinct points, t^iere is no reason v/hy we should say that B is after A rather than that A is after B, 35
;
tlie
iiobb
metrical character.
not
seei':
to be
tlie
causation.
the flash of light, but does not seem to have been caused
by it.
series.
It is these which
45
mark
tiiae
as different 10^.
cOiiiplete
i:,jj.ctif
uo
>viiao
u .e
attempt to
establish a
breaks doim*
or intrinsic analogy
befcv;een the:Ti
those who hold that the analogies between space and time do not break down, and that to a far greater extent than
v/as
caii
correct statement of the position of those who deny any intrinsic difference betvjeen space and time. We shall examine
(of tine) by showing lations, contrary to radically aliks; or, ordinarily used in a
that tennoral and spatial remuch traditional thought, are more precisely, that (1) terms peculiarly temporal sense have spatial coijinterparts and vice versa, and that accordingly (2) many propositions involving temporal concepts which seen obviously and necesgaril]'- true, are just as necessarily but not so obviously true v/hen reformulated in terns of spatial relations; or, if false in terms of spatial concepts, then false in terms of temporal ones too, 37
A^ain, the notion of direction has a use v.'ith respect to both spatial and tenporal" relations; one can, for irutance, speak of t'.;e diroction Troiij past to future, from future to past, frora north to south, and so on, none of v/hich di:.'ect Ions is any nore or less genuine or intrinsic than the others. 3^
Taylor makes
tliis
time
hinf-;9
on the truth of it
It is obvious that if we
analj-iiihov/
cally.
one
could
It
seeiiis
to experience.
must have
sorae
non-arbitrary court
of appeal v/hich
iirill
analogy and
laere
47
the analogy which they assert.
In the absence of an attempt
\:e
That is,
it.
term "length" or the term "part", for example, has the same
both contexts.
hence no analogy.
46
no clear meaning.
say that
v;e
of our eyes, run through the series from either end, indif-
But if
v;e
find that we
49
present to him.
w'e
vation does take some tine during which the same event will
be both present and not present (past) to him, and so in-
when the event becomes past, i.e. not present to him. It will
therefore not be correct to say that he observes an event
But
50
spatial configurations that they can and often do remain present to an observer during the time he runs through them in
either direction.
may run back and forth over a spatial series that is present
to hin durin.^ the entire time.
As in the case of a temporal
may take.
If we hold
v/e
are
or sensed.
xi?e
said that an
object or event
51
the usage is
rxot
tsnporal.
ference between time as conceived in terms of units of measurement, divisible into parts, and time as it is felt .
The ob-
ject or event which the observer saw was not present to hin
in the sense it was an instant or length a certain number of
hira
in
In other
The pro-
and intrinsic temporal meaning of the term "present" is that of the experience of the present, which involves the distinction between the present which we do experience, and the future and past xvhich we can never experience.
speak of time or temporal relations at all,
vie
If we are to
must be pre-
Me have an unmistakable
sense of the difference between the present and the past, and
betv;een the past and the future, and between the present and
52
We can
always distinguish the present from the future and the past.
The future and the past are, quite simply, not present,
V/e
ture and the past, however, and the clearest proof of this
is that we can remember the past, but not the future.
Russell
says that "it is a mere accident that vie have no memory of 39 the future". But an accident due to what? If we refuse to
the past and the futuj*e, we shall never be able to decide the
present and future, as Broad points out, is intimately associated with the intrinsic direction or sense of time.
How the intrinsic sense of a series of events in Time is essentially boimd up with the distinction A precedes 3 bebetv;een past, present, and future. cause A is past when B is present, 40
Furthermore, if the theory of the four-dimensional
53
as Ions as it is granted that memory gives us avjareness, in some sense, of events which are not present.
Let us say,
Mov;, hov/
this subject
the opposite
Certainly,
tions of A, B, and
C C
It is
valid objection.
First of all,
need the
54
memory relation to relate the memory to the last of the repetitions, v/hich by definition is not present to us,
i.'e
are
still do not
dimension or the
memory relates to the past, that is, one temporal direction rather than another, and further, is likely to involve the
use of memory itself, either in its explanation or in the
between the future and the past, we can never know to v;hich
of these ovt memories relate.
It is to be noted that we can-
v^ay
around.
xre
because
v;e
55
Hence these cognitive characteristics do not suffice to distinguish a past from a present event, sinc3 every event that knoi^s of has both these relations to him. If you add that an event always has the perceptual relation to C '...efore it has the memory relation, you only mean that the event of remembering something is prssent vjhen the event of perceiving it is past, and you have simply defined present and past for 0*s ob.iects in terms of preG?nt and past for his cognitive acts . If you then try to define the latter in tarns of different relations to 0s acts of introspection, you simply start on an infinite regress in which past and present remain obstinately uiidefined at any place v/here you choose to stop, 41
we have no memory of the future, presupposes that past, present and future do not represent unique temporal disi^inctions,
And the vievj that we can define past, present, and future
We must now
We shall
56
We
terms "place" and "part" when applied to space and time respectively.
Vn'ith
the
iUi object cannot be in tv;o places at once, though it can occupy two or more times at only one place. A.2
v/e
can equally
if
v;e
all the
in between",
v;e
If
57
For ob-
can perceive,
tirr.e,
v/hether, in particular, it
v/e
must
v/e
have stressed
cannot assume
is analogous to space.
tensiveness.
The premise of Taylor's ar^Uiiient assxnies without
5?i
ti:.:e",
This, oi
ticie.
For just as vje can an^ordinarily do say that moving about in space i,e, acquiring and losing spatial relations v.-ith other things over a lapse of time does not destroy the identity of a thing, we have equal reason to say that movin^., about in tine i,e, acquiring and losing teiiiporal relations v;ith other things over a does not destroy it either, lapse Ox space
l^J^.
.Por
if there
59
is no intrinsic sense of the tine-series which fijces the
dividuals,
expressed by the fact that there are certain identical individuals, (otherwise identifiable than by their temporal
It is obviously neces-
sary to hold that these individuals are othervrise identifiable than by their relations in the time-series, for if
their individuality depended only on their temporal relations, there v/ould be no means of fixing either their
This follows
60
Thus the
trinsic sense,
events in
tions.
tlie
laust
ijex'ies
c;jncyves
arrow-head on it",
s.'hether
this point
tearias
of a series with
61
We enquire
nov; vjhether
anyone
has an intrinsic diroction involves holding that individuals are not in any sense given.
A corollary of this is the view
v/e
consider to be an individual.
If we want to
abandon the notion that individuals are in any sense givtn, or fixed otherwise than by convention.
It is to be noted
62
tliab
itself,
Qvta
the same.
viduality
Extensiveness
dividuals,
outside.
As we mentioned before,
hov/
Hence,
ther question, and in this regard one might well ask how
ariyone could
It might be asked as well whether conventionality itself is a matter of convention, but a discussion of this would
63
events
..mat
v;e
Hence
v;e
could choose individuals which move either back or forth 46 This is a di-
From the
64
is imsatisfactory,
Goodman,
v:ho
nize "that individuals do not change their temporal relationships to each other as they do their spatial relationships"
:^ives a co^^ent
,
reason
whj'-
'
P.CSLIMIN/.iiY
DISCUSSION OF
THH;
DISTINCTION
3,
First of all,
-we
v;ill
continuum,
.["lets
vie
have already-
re-
reference to some
other point on
"present"
v.'ill
t?i3
continuum.
;jivo
not
memories referred to events in one direction of the timeseries or another, and this diificulty would present
65
66
These
liave laade
in the
to
It is apparent that no
given whole.
It will,
as Broad says, have an order but not a direction. The peculiarity of a series of events in Time is that it has not only an intrinsic order but also Thi'ee points on a straight line an intrinsic sense , have an intrinsic order, i,e, B is between A and C, or C is between 3 and A, or A is between C and B, This order is independent of any tacit reference to something traversin:^ the line in a certain direction, 49
It is clear that if time is conceived as only
a line,
direction at all.
finite.
67
to
,-iv9 it
have our-
It is a clear enough
alon,;:;
v;hich
something moves?
in a picturesque manner.
We are naturally tempted to regard the history of the v;orld as existing eternally in a certain oi^der of events, Alon; this, and in a fixed direction, vie imagine the characteristic of presentness as r.oving, somewhat like the spot of li;:ht from a policemen* s bulls-eye traversing the fronts of the houses in a street, 50 The difficulties with this, however,
ax^e
all
V/illiams
"The
length of time.
spatially.
If the bull*s-eye is
^ absurd.
32
at one end of the series gives it an intrinsic sense. The series goes in a fixed direction because it is contin-
69
Kin^, 's viev;,
ar,
al".;ay3
chan^in^,
Kin-
have no ri~ht to assume that the Present, ..'e as the locus ox motion and becomin;, proceeds throu,e;h a series of instants like that found in the slices of that v;hich has become, and upon ivhich ive have based our theory of chan.^e. Such an assumption results, as vje shall attempt to show, in the postulation of an absolute space and time xvithin which nature v;orks. And the failure to ::uard a,-ainst this coirjnor^Sense assumption ends inevitably in the spatial analogy fallacy, 53
ii;ell
be used to prove
ception of time as a series of events which have become, stretching into the past, and open at one end.
analogous to tlmt of the moving bull*s-eye of the present, namely, the question: "How fast does the becoming
or change proceed?"
the Present,
70
the locus of the act of becoming, is either durative
54
Although we disa
;ree v;ith
the theory
v^e
are now
V/e
xve
have
media must
,':et
If we do not hold
71
coulc'.
should be
Individuals
to regard
As
Russell says:
It was only recently that it became possible to explain notion in detail in accordance TJith Zeno's platitude, and in opposition to the philosopher's paradox. V/e may nov; at last indulge the comfortable belief that a body in motion is just as truly where it is as a body at rest. Motion consists merely in the fact that bodies are sometimes in one place and sometimes in another, and that they are at intermediate places at intermediate times. 55
of motion.
For motion,
If we rer^ard
beinj^ at
shall be hard
72
v.rhere
it is
This
Movement con-
tir.ie,
is,
at
73
tinua of space and tine could not be considered, by themselves, to be individuals in motion, althou<;:h they are
individual differences .
hasten to add
wish to ignore
74
iot;
the soul .
ouj?
sense,
stance.
certain problems.
75
V/e
view of explaining human experience, v/hich, as we mentioned earlier seems to involve a spatio-temporal unity,
We may v;onder, for exaraple, v^hether two substances are
suppose that
cessarj'-
vje
also to brin^: those differentiations native to the rejected substance into relation
v>;ith
tvjo
points:
(a)
we must lit-
erally identify the differentiations native to the rejected substance with either all or some of the differen-
tiations in the continuimi through xAich the accepted substance moves, and (b) we must try to show that laws or
principles
v.-hich
76
tho differentiations in the othor continuum.
alon:: theoe lines,
xve
Thinking
possibilities
(A)
v.'hich
are as follovi's.
metaphysical positions.
v;ill do
continua, or
r.
A.hjr will
i-)art
of a
and
'cirne.
77
It allows one to mako a fundaraential diatinction betv;een
lations Ox objects
ax-e thou^jiht
to be events in time.
by
sayin;-;
of notion by an observer.
thini;:.
n
nor the direction oi any motion would be possible -without
this irreducible reference to the observer or the self.
In empirical science, of course, this reference is taken
physical world are only possible ivhere empirical observations are possible.
It is clear that according to possibility A,
when reference is
j:iade
56
Thus, spatial
that
Here
v^'e
time -continuum.
79
get their identity from the changes in the spatial r3lations of objects.
But, as we pointed out earlier, vjhere
differentiations in an extensive continuum are considered themselves to be individuals, they cannot move ,
lav;s
This iS a
materialistic psychology.
go
There
In addition, the
SI
If
of objects are considered to be events which are added to the end of the time-series.
exist.
Time is
In
Accordin,- to
Accordingly, time is
82
Although it is neceasary,
concerned.
exists as a
vfhole,
According to
changes in it, but space as extensive is only an abstract aspect of the primordial becoming of things. The
S3
considers change to be
theory.
For (B),
Logically conceived, time is for both theories a continuum made up of points v/hich are events or changes.
Dut (A) disregards the fact that the continuum is made
continuum.
In conceiving of time
betv.'een
nev.
events.
Strictly
S4
v.'hat
point
fraction
is next after 1.
no intrinsic direction.
have already
examined
changes.
Time floivs.
lightly to be cast
aside.
1/e
65
notion.
Ox
astrous results).
Theory
(D)
For this
reason it considers chanj;e to be logically prior to objects and space, and its principles relating to the \mity
tliat
activities
But
extensiveness of
tit/ie.
hope to show
86
possibility
(D)
tiiae,
and his
To this task
proceed.
CHAPTEIL THREE
TII-dE
The doctrine that concepts, (intellectual functions) can only yield knowledge when related to in-
tuitions
rr^iven
to sensibility may be
reri;arded as a
view
It is a
This concerns
S7
Critique ,
analytic judgments is held to be the principle of contradiction, a purely negative criterion of truth, ne-
There,
raven "
'
.
59
b^9
of contradiction is held to be characteristic of one use of the intellect, and in each case, this is its purely
lov;ical use.
intimately associated with the operations of the intellect in the use of the principle of contradiction.
Further, though time does not indeed prescribe laws to reason, it yet establishes the chief conditions by the help of which the mind am order ibs notions according; to the laws of reason. Thus I cannot decide whether a thin^ is impossible, except by predicating A and not-A of the same subject at the same time . 61
That Kant meant
x-zhat
Here sensitive
90
of reason",
is expressly repudiated.
Thus of the
Althoui^h this faiaouB principle is thus without content and merely formal, it has sometimes been carelessly formulated in a manner which involves the quite unnecessary admixture of a synthetic element. The foraula runs: It is impossible that something should a_t one and the same time both be and not be... -the proposition is modified' hj the condition of time... The principle of contradiction, however, as a merely logical principle, must not in any way iii/dt its assertions to time-relations. The above fonnula is therefore completely contrary to the intention of the principle. o4
91
Nevertheless, in both
tiiue
in contra-
Kant
And in the
Now a transcendental determination of time is so far hono;;eneous with the cateivory, which con stitutes its unity, in that it is- universal and rests upon an a priori rule. But, on the oth3r hand, it is 30 far homo, ;eneous with a;:pearance, in that time is contained in evsry empirical representation of the manifold. 66
Both in the Inaur.ural Dissertation and the
Critique of Pure Reason Kant distin.Tuishes between space
..ure
intuitions.
This is stated
92
Time is not somethinr- ob.iectivo mia real , It is neither substance nor accident nor relation, but is a subjective condition, necessary ov/in;; to the nature of the huraan mind, of the co-ordinating of all sensibles according to a fixed law; and it is a pure intuition, 67
After
statin,'- tliat
68
intuition",
69
sensations",
Kant
f-oes on
to repeat what he
lias
said
chan,:;:e
in the dis-
of sensibility.
The
chan,':;e
So far is it from bein^ possible that anyone should ever deduce and explain the concept of tine by the help of reason, that the very principle of contradiction presui'poses it, involvin^j it as a condition. For A and not-A are not incompatible tinless they are jud,~ed of the same thin^^ tor:;ethQr (i.e., in the same time) 71
On the oth
.r
lias
completely
93
and intuition;
ical knowledge.
tv/o
pure
on to present his arguments for this contention, vjithout me nt ion in:; any necessary relation of one of these pure
stress thc.t the singular role of time in the philoso hy of Kant does not consist in time enterin.- into the
it applies.
beinj.:
dif-
94
unv.
^ii.ie
ox*
73
v;ords, "Space and time are quanta continua ".
ivriiu's
and there-
fore extensive,
Space and
tiaie
74
quanta of all
oior-
intuition",
of all series",
is in itself a series, and indeed the formal condition 75 but space, on the other hand, "is an
76
not a series".
By this Kant seems to mean
that space or a spatial series has no intrinsic direction, for he says that", ...in space, taken in and by
itself, there is no distinction between progress and re77 gress". There is, hov;ever, a pro-ress in the time-series
Further-
to which
95
bein;.:
added,
Althou:;jh he
puts
Thus v/e necessarily think time as having completely elapsed up to the .^iven moment, and as being itself siven in this completed form. This holds true, even though such completely elapsed time is not determinable by us. But since the future is not the condition of our attaining- to the present, it is a mattjx' of entire indiff^i-ence, in our comprehension of the latter, how we may think of future time, whether as comin,_, to an end or as flowing on -to infinity, Vie have J as it were, the series m, n, o, in which n is ^^iven ug concliticnoU by m, ana" at" the same tTme as bein:-; the condition of oT The series ascends from the from the conditioned n to si (1, k, _i, etc.), and also descends from th^ oonH'ition n t'o the con"" ditioned o (, , r, etc). 79
Time, for Kant, flows, as it v/ere, "down hill",
nev;
events,
They must
But it is
96
resolved.
urthennore, until Kant has explained his aocurine of synthesis, he has to speak as if the uJTiity of space and time were . iven in intuition. It can, hovJever, be ^iven only because of a synthesis which does not belon-:; to sense. The necessary synthetic unity of space (and of timej depends upon, and presu 'ooses, the pure catec'ories of the understanding. All this is onitted from the Aesthetic, but it seenis to me tliat such an omission is defensible, SO A nan cannot explain his whole philosophy at once.
,
marked similarities.
dantly clear that Kant did think that space and time
were capable of bein:^ represented in the same terras.
Besides those definite statements to which we have already
97
draivn
attention Kant
tvjo
somethin.3 in common.
^^'e
mentioned
must maintain
tl-iat
the essential of
will be unnecessai'y.
v.'hich
dif-
in distinguishing them than there would be in distinguishing a multiplicity of separate intuitions of space, and supposin-'-
sphere
oi'
oliat
every-
For ix
tii.ie
..hen
are in
possibility a,
i'hia
psychology entirely,
Kant's position is not, in ibself, radically
different from that of Broad, for both of them, v/hile
conceptually in
tliat
trinsic direction.
V/e
99
jipace and time are concepts lends force to this kind of
criticism.
into
v^e
hive seen, be
hc.ve
betv.'een
The
chapt;i;r
three
tifie
Kant*s doctrine of innor and owtar sense is difficult, and while we shall present what
vje
hope is a
100
101
sayirii:
This in-
troduces another aspect of the distinction which Kant also anticipates in the Inaugural Dissertation , namely, that inner sense is bound up v;ith the staces or re-
presentations of the soul, and that outer sense is associated with spatially extended objects.
or these concepts, the one (i.e. space) properly concerns the intuition of an. object, the other {i.e. time) a state , namely, that of representation. S3
In one place,
what would
it is especially relevant to observe that everything in our knowledge v;hich belon;:s to intuition feelin^ of pleasure and pain, and the will, not beins knowledge, are excluded contains nothing but mere relations, &k
...
,e .
hox^evar,
In other
inner states.
102
sense co/aprises
basis
lOi-
raay
distinction in a
VGi?y
brief form.
inner states and outer objects, but Kant does not elaborate on the nature of these means.
3y means of outer sense, a property of oiir mind, we represent to ourselves objects as outside us, and ail-without exception in apace. In space their shape, magnitude, and relation to one another ar^e determined or determinable. Inner sense, by means of ivhich the mind intuits itself or its inner state, yields indeed no intuition of the soul itself as an object; but thei-e is nevertheless a determinate form (namely, time) in which alone the intuition of inner states is possible, and everything which belongs to inner detenninations is therefore represented in relations of time. S6
This
passa._;e,
importance to which we can hold fast, namely, that vjhatever else Kant may mean by inner and outer sense, the
Although this
raay be,
as with
mutually exclusive.
103
knowledge
All increase in e.^pirical knowledge, and every advance of perception, no matter v.'hat the objects may be whether appearances or pure intuitions, is nothing' but an extension of the determination of inner sense, that is, an advance in time. This advance in time determines everything and is not it&S self determined through anything further,
Thus, as Kant puts it, "There is only one
Inner
domain of sense".
There is, then, some reason to believe that v;hat
throu,;5;h
which alone
104
irical a^joerce'^tion .
Consciousness of self according to the determinations of our state in inn r perception is merely empirical, and alvays chan<;;ing, Ko fixed and abiding self can present itself in this flux of innor appearances; Such consciousness is usuallynamed inner sense, or empirical apperception , 91
It is to be noted that Kant says it is no fixed
and abidin
This in-
terpretation of inner sense requires, hoviever, thst represent rtions of outer sense be included
x-jithin
inner
tlian
92
somethini' in us",
and:
Time is nothing but the form of inner sense, that is, of the intuition of ourselves and our irmer state. It cannot be a determination of outer appearances; it Irias to do neither X'\?ith shape nor position, but vdth the relation of representations in our inner state. 93
It should be noted, however, that Kant does not
105
that
ive
It is,
ether v/ise, he could not possibly ansv/er the 94 queotion "How is pure science of nature possible?",
apperception,
v;e
outv;ar-dly intuited,
Likewise, time
U'liat
is ap-
inner sense.
distin^'-.uishin.-
10i,;ic.l
result of
106
pure intuitions.
that determinations
it,
In the
selves, are purely in spatial relations; other things are jjiven vjhich are purely in temporal relations, namely,
certain
ir,3ntal
w^e
clearly and
But nothing is given
Kor is any-
thin
meanings, or
tv;o az-eas
of representations,
On the
This is a
v.;ide
meaning.
meaninjs.
lu7
in the \vide meaning; often enough to mal:e that meaning
appearances are not thin^js in them . selves, but are the mere play of our representations, and in the end reduce to determinations of inner sense. 96
Yet Kant also often uses the term "inner sense"
to mean whatever pertains to non-spatial "states", and
...
v;nat
has
log
The trojiscendental object is equally \mknown in respect to inner and to outer intuition. But it is not of this that we are here speaking, but of the efiipirical object, which is on lied an external object if it is represented in sr ce , and an inner object if it is represented only in its time - ref; tion st Neither space nor time, Kowever, is to oe found save in us, 9^
In tryin
betv;Gen representations
picturesque language:
I'lattar, therefore, does not mean a kind of substance quite distinct and hetero.^eneous from the object of inner sense (the soul), but only the distinctive nature of those appearances of objects in themselves unknown to usthe representations of which W8 call outer as compared with those we count as belongin,; to inner sense, although, like all other thoughts these outar representations belong- only to the thinking subject,- They have, indeed, this deceptive property that, representing objects in space, they detach themselves as it v/ere from the soul, and appear to hover outside it, 99
'
If we begin with what might be called "total experience", inner sense in the narrow meaning of nonspatial thoui^hts flittin3 through the soul, is an ab-
Similarly, outer
tot-^;l
experience.
109
true bo say that "Time cannot be outv/ardly intuited any 100 more than ap-.ice can be intuited as soniethin;; in us",
but these abstractj.ons \;ill have relevance only for the
v;ill
en-
Fsycholony .
"^;^enetic
x.'ritten,
point of view",
ment:
The apprehension of temporal relations, as they exist for hroman consciousness, is an extremely
110
The part coraplex pro-Iuct of montal devslormGnt, played in it by trains of free ideas is of pre101 dominant importance.
of inner appearances".
that "the
reoreGant:.uions of tba outer senses constitute the 104 proper material viith which we occupy our mind".
terra,
is absolutely indispensable
Without such trains there could be no such thing as the definite apprehension of a time-series, havinr: a distinguishable beginning and end, connected by a train of intermediate events, each havinp its own position determined by its relation to other events which have come before and after it. 105
Ill
If it is indeed a
nieanin;^^^;)
vje
could have no
should havo extended the meaning of inner sense to include all time-relations v/hatever
.
be no ap-
inner sense.
v;e
enou,^:h,
drax-;
Bartlett,
tz-ue
112
apprehension of
tirse,
1-vas
drax-m attention.
sensi-
bility.
the det irnination of the fact and its place in the theory loa of empirical psychology.
a dis-
This third
113
speakin,^:
of inner
sIgo in time-series*
If ab-
be the net-work
"sum of all representations" contains an area of representations which ate both in spatial and temporal relations, by the same token, inner sense in this
riore
inner sense",
114
of 3pace and time and thoir transcendental ideality.
conrin.i;.tion of the fonnor assertion, and hence of the
In
"reason .
Outar sense is the netv;ork of spatial relations throughovA possible experionce, and the objects thus related in
...
ci,ui
also
appearances
x;hat soever ,
lations".
senses, are in tine, and necessarily stand in tine-re112 Inner and outer sense, then, like time and
space, are om-irically real, but transcendent ally ideal,
ai-e
nothing in thenselves.
The
distinction between
inn-Ji-
the
115
Tundaiaental distinction
b'^f.-.'sen
As em-
t.ar sense
Thus external things exist as well as I myself, and both, indeed, upon the immediate witness of my S8lf-con3ciounn8;os, The only difference is that the representation of myself, as the thinking subject, jolon:G to i;in-.- sen.^e only, ivhilo tha representations which raark extended bein^^s belong also to outer sense. 113
As the above quotation indicates, inner sense, on the empirical level, does not exclude outer sense and
its appearances, but must necessarily include these
should
b'3
m.u3t vi
r.;
v;e
call them
inner or outar, as a consciousness onlv of v;hat is 114 Outer objects are redependent on our sensibility".
present;: tions, "-vvhich are entitled outjr because they
outer sense*,
^-ihose
intuition
116
Thus, in
115
fandaiaental distinction b'jtv/ean apace and time,
A3 em-
Thus external things exist as well as I nyself, and both, indeed, upon the immediate witness 0." my 3elf-con3ciou:-,n9oS, The only dirxGi^?nce is that the representation of myself, as the thinking subject, jalon;G to inri-^ 3en.-e oaly, '.'hlL^ t'la representations which roark extended beinrs belon:^ als o to out or sanse. 113
-
.-
must vi
n;
v;e
call them
inner or outsr, as a consciousness onlv of v.;hat is 114 dependent on our sensibility". Outer objects are re-
presentations,
115
is snace":
"-vvhich
intuition
116
Thus, in
116
re;3arded as aspects of possible experience, "the objective
to be dealt with.
to the network of time-relations throughout possible experience, but the inner sense to v?hich Kant refers in
the explanations of the conditions of the possibility of
Apperception and its S3mthetic unity is, indeed, very far from being identical xi/ith inner sense. The former, as the source of all combination , applies to the manxfold of intuitions in general , and in the guise of the cateroFies , prior to all sensible intuition, to objects in general . Inner sense, on the other hand, contains the raere form of intuition, but without combination of the manifold in it, and therefore so far contains no determinate intuition, which is possible only through the consciousness of the determination of the manifold by the transcendental act of imagination, , ,11S
'
Just as the reproductive imagination presup'119 so our emposes a productive imagination, a priori .
categories.
The understanding does not, therefore, find in inner sense such a combination of the manifold, but 120 produces it, in that it affects that sense.
117
After unfolding so many different possible meanings of the distinction between inner and outer sense, it
may be advisable to
sura
them up.
general.
The advance of
lis
"Tor the original appcrcoTntion stands in relation to 122 inn^r sense , ( the sun of all representc-tions )". In
this
v.'idor raeanin^j,
and time is "the form of inner intuition wherein all por124 ce^'tioriL; h l^':.^ a position". In thid wide meaning of inner
sense, outer sense must be regarded as a part of inner
of which we like^;ise take up into our facilty of 125 representation all outor intuitions ". Empirically extei-ms
ternal objects are "thin,",s v;hich ar3 to be found in 126 space", and "space is a form of that intuition vjhich 127 we call outer". Thus, for Kant, inner sense in its wide,
-
119
Finally,
thoughts,
"
Gciousness, desires, which cannot be outwardly intuited, 129 "All these belon;,T to inner aense". Inner sense in this
rceanin^ has the soul or self as an object, -"Now I am
130
of inner sense".
not intrinsically as
ti-jo
absolutely separate
nomenal
.orli,
v.'ide
meaning com-
^..'ide
120
x.'itliiii
ol.l'i
larger v;hola,
ough the I as represented throu^jh inner sense in time, and objects in space outside me, are Si.:.ciric.--lly quito uiGtiiict ai rea. ances, they are not for that reason thou' ht s^'bein- different things. 131
Opposed to
xni.cx
..onae
m
quf.
.:;..
i-a:.-j.
a;
meinlng
with
shax-;e
tine,
throxi^^h
them
v;e
They are
.-J3';r
_
Cwionc,
_
o-r-v"
Inner
appearance, wuilc
thus not only comprises the empirical subject natter of psychology, i.e. thouchts, non-spatial appearances, it
also in 3ome fashion reveals inner sense in the trans-
i^^or- inner experience in general, isia its possibility, or perception- in general and its rel^ri-iou to othor perception, in .-.'hich no spscial distinction or empirical determination is given, is not to JO rejja-'ded an eiipirical'laiouled:-;.3 but as knov.'ledge of the empirical in general, and has to be reckoned^ u'ith the inve3ti.;j;:-.tion of the posoibiliti'' of any rnd every experience, which is certainly a transcendental Gn-piii-y. 134
122
Tine and the Unity of Ilature
3.
t;7o
possibilities
V/e
as to
hov;
have
123
More explicitly, possibility B requires that principles which govern the activities peculiar to the self,
lation to time nust determine in general what kind of objects shall appear in space.
In both cases there must be
Now either of the positions can be given with imaginative connotations,- such as the conception of a self-
124
similarity.
to be imavoidable .
These
Considering, for
consider these
tv;o
possibilities.
125
On epistenological questions, the two positions may
agree or disagree.
Either matter or
tjie
Al-
lavjs
Similarly, as we hope to
had he not shown that the principles pertaining to the knov/ing subject, v;hich are constitutive of objects, have appli-
tir.ie
alone.
126
Ue
must be entitled to say in this regard that if Kant's philosophy is trua, it must have
life ever arose on earth.
heeii
has raality only in relation to these transcendental conditions, in what sense are we entitled to call these conditions
subjective?
If the self which is knovm in inner sense is only phenomenal, what are we to say of the self which Icnows? Is the kno\ving self a thing-in-itself , although the knoivn self is only an appearance? To this question Kant's answer is obsciore: but perhaps v;e may say, in the light of his moral philosophy, that the -self does belong to the realm of things-in -themselves, although 135 as a thing-in-itself it can never be known by us.
127
Above all, can v;e believe if this is Kant* doctrine --that the v;orld as vje experience it is due' to the interplay of t^;o unknovm thin^js-in-thenselves, one of which is a self. v;hile tiie other is perhaps not It is difficuJ.t to accept one \jholly xmknovjn a self? factor. It is alr.iost impossible to accept two. If they are v;holly unknown, how can they be distinguished from one another? I36
This
As Kant himself
Thus,
Copeinican revolution.
phenomenal vjorld
;:ets
I2e5
world?
pertain to
tliat e::cept
for
That the ^I* of apperception, and therefore the in every act of thought, is one ; and cannot be resolved into a plurality of subjects, -and consequently signifies a logically siinple subject, is something already contained in the very concept of thought, and is
'I
therefore an analytic proposition. But this does not mean that the thinking I* is a sinple substance . 137
It is evident that one reason at least for Kant's
But if
h\ar.ian
v;e
of viexv of
discover a se-
of possible experience,
129 experience.
that
v.'e
If our knowledge
We can know something about objects prior to experience only if objects conform to our peculiar modes of cognition. If intuition must conform to the constitution of the objects, I do not see how we could knavi anything of the latter a priori but if the object (as object of the senses )''mu3t conform to the constitution of our faculty of intuition, I have no difficulty in conceiving such a possibility. Since I cannot rest in these intuitions if they are to becone knotm, but must relate them as representations to something as their object, and determine this latter through them, either I must assume that the concepts , by means of v/hich I obtain this deterr.iination, conform to the object, or else I assume that the objects, or what is the same thing, that the experience in v;hich alone, as given objects, they can be "kn ovm , "c onf orm to the concepts. In the former case, I am again in the same perplexity as to how I can know anything a priori in regard to the objects. In the latter case the outlook is more hopeful, 13^
;
(a)
knowledge of objects;
must
shoii?
130
knowled^je of oojcc^s oi experience at all,
v;e
must think
(c)
vje
mean by ()
perhaps it would
perience.
genetic psychological explanation, a thing quite foreign to Ilant's purposes, but concerns how the categories are, in
fact, constitutive and regulative of objects in the phenome-
nal world.
In the metaphysical deduction the a priori origin of the categories has been proved through their complete general logical functions of thought; in the transcendental deduction x^e have shovm their possibility as a priori nodes of knowled;,e of objects of an intuit ion^in general. We have nov; to explain tlie possibility of knowing a priori by necjis of cdte[:,ories whatever objects may present thenselves to our senses , not indeed in respect of the forn of tiieir intuition, but in respect of the lav;s of their conbination, and so, as it vjere, of prescribing laws to natujre, and even of making nature possible. For unless the categories discharged this function, there could be no explaining why everything that can be presented to our senses must a be subject to la\\?s which have their origin "" priori in the understanding alone. 139
agreer.ient witl.. the
131
tlie
"combination" of which Kant speaks must take place in accordance with categories schematised by means of time-detemina-
tions alone.
inde-
independent of time, they must be constitutive and regulative of objects of experience through time, and only through tine : otherwise there v;ould be no necessary reason for
It is just this
founded on arguments of any kind, but is deriv'd entirely 140 from habit" is to be refuted.
Thus, if r.ant is to be considered as giving a con-
shov;
132
tion does not suffice to prove that this vjill be the case,
as Paton observes.
To put the matter xu ^acu>'^er vjay it night be a were accident whether appearances conformed to the
categories or not. No doubt if they did not conform, we should cease to have experience; but in that case so much the v;orse for us. oo far as the argument has gone at present, the conformity of appearances to the cate.~ories must indeed have occurred; for there has been such a thing as human experience. That conformity might, hov;ever, have been due to a pre-established harmony arranged by tjie beneficence of God; and any view of this type is emphatically rejected by Kant. 141
Ue might show conclusively that
v/e
v.'hich
nition, but this does not by itself in the least show that
The
133
brin.-:;
v;e
terra,
This is,
;-;e
feel,
He could, if he
this opportunity.
V/e
spatial schemata.
character of appearances.
We thus find that the schema of each category contains and makes capable of representation only a 142 deteriiination of time.
The principles which represent the rules under which the existence of all appearances is ordered are all deter-
tirae
alone.
The principles can therefore have no other purpose save that of being the conditions of the unity of empirical knowledge in the synthesis of appearances. But such unity can be thought only in the scheEia of the 143 pure concepx; of the understanding,
The unity of empirical knowled^ce is a result of the
constitutive principles.
only time-detenainations.
In this third [medium], the essential form of which consists in the synthetic unity of the apperception ox all appearances, ..'e have fovoid a priori conditions of complete and necessary determination of time for all existence in the (field of] appearance, without which even empirical determination of time 144 would be iiapossible.
135
I'loles
possibility A.
ad -
Dieser Fortgang in
weiter bestimmt)'-.
136
in connection with :;iving an effective ansv/er to Hume,
tees it.
In the sane manner,, therefore, in vjhich time contains the sensible a priori condition of the possibility of a continuous^advance of the existing to v;hat follovvs, the understanding, by virtue of the unity of apperception, is the a priori condition of the possibility of a continuous determination of all positions for the appearances in this time. 147
It is true that here Kant is referring principally
must
likexi'ise be
orable claim that we have no proof that the future will resemble the past.
ISven
would not
features.
ICant
minations.
vje
can
137
The concept of magnitude in general can never be explained except by saying that it is that detemination of a thing vjhereby we are enabled to think how many times a xmit is posited in it. But this how-manytimes is based on successive repetition, and therefore on time and the synthesis of the homogeneous in tiirxe. Reality, in contradistinction to negation, can be explained only if we think time (as containing all being) as either filled with being or as empty. If I leave out permanence (which is existence in all time , nothing remains in the concept of substance save only tne loI4S gical representation of a subject
)
-
136
of appearances, but rather depend on that ordered existence
They
than with the dynamical, on-going progress of nat\ire as it exists , they are nonetheless all dependant on time .
This
successive synthesis,
v/e
c,&t
no detenrninate intuition.
Inner sense, on the other hand, contains the mere form of intuition, but without combination of the manifold in itj and therefore so far contains no determinate, intuition, which is possible only throu^K the consciousness of the determination of the manifold by the transcendental act of imagination (synthetic influence of the uiiderstanding upon inner sense v;hich I have entitled fisurative" synthesis, 153
)
Thus our coxmting, as is easily seen in the case of larger numbers, is a synthesis according to concepts, because it is executed according to a common ground of unity, as, for instance, the decade. In terms of this concept, the unity of the synthesis of the manifold is rendered necessary. 155
It is clear that space and time, or rather the spa-
140
Such raagnitudes may also be called flowing , since the synthesis of productive imar-ination involved in their production is a progression in tiiae, and the continuity of time is ordinarily designated by the tern flowing or flowing axvay. I56
We shall discuss
that quantity of anjrthing in nature in general, is the result of a successive synthesis in time.
Prior to this
as a determinate
quantum.
141
of inner sense,
l.'hat
This parallel
But
lution.
liave
said about
142
:r the spatial features of objects ware insured by that
means,
vje v;o\ild
not necessarily
liave
synthetic a priori
knowledge about the spatial constitution of future experience (in the Humean rather than the Kantian sense), because
we would have no guarantee that future experience would reveal such objects.
Future experience might, for all we know,
It is undoubted-
inability to
inia:::;ine
psychologically
v;e
expect a re-
Thus, just as
tween the future and that past, so likewise, Kant's arguments that objects of experience must have certain a priori
spatial features must rest on the view that the passage of
time will bring such objects of experience into existence.
143
.Ind
\iQ
determinations.
din^2
The mathematics of space (geometry) is based upon this successive synthesis of the productive imagination in the generation of figures. 160
It is
144
a certain quantuu of space will by this process also be
iienercted.
this implies soae kind of union of space and time, and from
the standpoint of the understanding this is a perplexing
thing.
Here we must recall what we have said in Chapter
Two, Section One, about the difficulties of
co::^ni2iing
the
tiine if
v:e
Strictly speaking,
thing in
comrr.on
between then.
dental synthesis,
"this
v;e
145
He
Motion, ho\;'ever, consic'.ered c.s the descriDing of a space, is a pure act of the successive sjmthesis of the laanifold in outer intuition in general by neans of the productive iciar:ination. . ,l62
For Kant, only time is intrinsically successive, or
serial.
Kant tells us, furthermore, how we happen to have the concept of succession.
quanta of space.
\ie
can never
146
have a priori traowieajo of such a specific character.
But
We have also proved that the only manner in which objects can be given to us is by modification of our sensibility; and finally, that pure a priori concepts, in addition to the function of un'^er standing expressed in the catec;ory, must contain a priori certain formal conditions of sensibility, namely, those of inner sense. I65
On the other hand, the schema of a pure concept of understanding can never be brought into any image whatsoever. It is simply the pure synthesis, deterriiined by a rule of that unity, in accordance with concepts, to v;hich the category gives expression. It is a transcendental product of imagination, a product v;hich concerns the deterraination of inner sense in goneral according to conditions of its form (time), in respect of all representations, so far as these representations are to be connected a priori in one concept in con166 formity with the unity of appercsption,
remarkable, for he does not in any essential respects depart from his view that the order of Nature is the result
of the categorical determination of time.
147
may conclude
destruc-
of Kant's system.
space and time together, then the logical result would seem
14fi
[loitf
appearances
v.'hich
and time.
Mental activities, of coiu-se, need not be considered to be in space, since they are not appearances.
But
149
v/hich is completely spatio-tenporal the only possible events
(changes
point is that they are In time alone in the same sense, and
only because, all events are in time.
There is thus no dis-
From
For apperceptioa is soiaetlring real, and its simplicity is already given in the mere fact of its possibility. Now in space there is nothing real v/hich can be simple; points v;hich are the only simple things in space, are merely limits, not themselves anything that can as parts serve to constitute space. From this follov-s the inpossibility of .any explanation in materialist terms of the constitution of the self as a merely l6^ thinking subject.
Kant regarded
rather
150
.jud.-ment
explicable in terms of
materialistic psycholof;:'.
We
V/e
assume
that Kant must have thought that space and time ware ul-
151
respectively.
and time, then each category will have two separate and
distinct raeanin:js.
tv;o
natures.
Kant's
i'r.ctives
(a)
(b)
tirne
time alone;
{e)
are not only not needed, but they could not possibly serve
the p\xrpose.
Thus, in general, there are two basic reasons
for liant's making a fundamental distinction between space and time, for considering tine to be logically prior to
space, and for giving time a position of oven-fheLming im-
152
i:ant*s system woxild othen/ise have been jeopardized.
The
very l>nich-pins of i:ants thought, namely, the transcendental unity of apperception, and the independent origin of
the categories in the nature of logical thinking, v/ould
Apper-
ception and
lo/:"ical
phenomenal world.
Only
som.e
quasi-miraculous doctrine of
Kant, at least,
:;,ives
no indication that he
x-zas
If
ou-r
logical thinking
Kant*s distinction
153
tliis at
length, we
had he obliterated all distinction between space and time,he would never have been ab3ie bo rebut Hixme's criticism at
all.
'
154
terms of diverse re^'ions of space-time, as it can be in terms of the difference between the future and the past, as long
as it is assumed, paradoxically enough, that an identical 169 self can be at different regions of space-tiiae. Kant's an-
In addition, accor-
arbitary
distinction.
155 views.
In so lar as the physical theory of space-tiffie pre-
of lo.^ic
'./e
can express this by saying that, for Kant, part of the dis-
we
CHAPTEH FOUR
i3::;RGS0K'S
THEORY OF SPACE
/iMD
We have already
seei:
V/e
fiaactioqi,
and that in
by a perpetual
fliix.
are conscious of a
157
continuous chan^je.
v;e
empirically attend
(in the
While Kant
does not attach the same kind of importance to this matter that Bergson does, it is nevertheless an indispensable
For, as we have
15S
In addition, we must draw attention
liere
to zhe similarity
relations
(v/hat
lutely inner except those (given) through our inner sense", we may conclude that, for him, the primary meaning of the
terra "inner" is
Kant distinguishes
159
revealing,
iiThat
At any
rate the ansv/ers which Kant and Bergson give to this ques-
There can be
160
themselves.
of the soul
be perceived".
of time, the continuity of v/hich "is ordinarily desir^ated 179 by the tern flov/ing or f leaving away", is the determinate
form "in v;hich alone the intuition of inner states is posIgO sible". While ive cannot be said to perceive time, or to
have a knov;ledge of it by means of a concept, ("Time is
not a disciirsive, or
vjhat is
As such, we
161
actiially sense are appearances, so that
v/e
we can in one way be said to have the sense of time and the
sense of space, in that we do recognise appearances as dif-
ferently related, sone in time alone, ("the empirical object, which is called.
.
V7ith
jto
time,
and taking Kant's ivords at their face value, that this self
is in constant flux, it is navi necessary to enquire into
fli;ix
hov;
Kant
thought of it.
according to
divided.
x^?hich
162
Now Natxire, in this sense of the word, has two main divisions, in -accordance with the main distinction of our sensibility, one of which coi.iprises the objects of the outer , the other the object of the inner -thus rendering possible a two-fold doctrine of 'Mature, the UOCTRIIJii OF JODI and the DOCTRIIiS C? 30UL, the first dealinj with extended ^ and the second v;ith thinking. Nature, 1^5
;
know no other internal principle of and no , other internal activity v/hatever but thought . witK that -which depenas upon it, feeling of' pleasure and pain, and inpulse or x;ill. But these groiinds of determination and action in no wise belong to the presentations of the external sense. 166
Kov; viQ
It is, then,
^ propos to enquire
163
If we compare the doctrine of the soul as the physiology of inner sense, v/itli the'^octrine of the body as a physiology of the object of the outor senses, vje find that while in both riuch can be learnt empirically, there is yet this notable difference. In the latter science nuch that is a priori can be synthetically known from the ir.ere concept of an extended impenetrable being, but in the former nothing ivhatsoever that is a priori can be knovm synthetically from the concept of a tjiinking being. iSg
The implications of this statement are far-reaching.
Concepts employed in physics are not blind because an intuition i3 given for them, because in fact appearances are
If
1^9
164
re-afflrras the flux of inner sense.
For v;e are irnable from our o^.vn consciousness to decide whether, as souls, we are permanent or not. .i'or since the only permanent appearance which v*e encounter in the soul is the representation *I* that accomijanies and connects them all, we are unable to prove that this 'I', a mere thought, may not be IXj. the same state of flux as the other thoughts. . .191 Kant unhes'titingly draws the logical conclusions
Since
192
entitled duration".
and only in time, cannot be an object of scientific knovjledgej all alteration, if it is to be perceived as altera-
165
from the flux of tine in inner sense, and on the other hand
that time itself does not chani^e, but only appearances in
it.
It
v/e
vje
v;e
or a flowing away, he is simply referring to the fact that there are no gaps or bi-eaks in it.
Time itself
vray
166
'A'e
v;e
intuit in
v;ay.
time, and time alone, poses serious problems for Kant, however, ones vjhich he does no more than touch upon in a cur-
sory fashion.
of change involved in such purely temporal succession as is exemplified in inner sense will be radically different
Strictly speaking,
Kant, himself,
167
Wg can only conclude that Kant is using the term
deteminate appearances, the results of synthesis and determination in accordance with the categories.
The self,
except as a "universal correlate of apperception and itself 197 a mere thougnt. , .a thing of undefined signification".
of being perceived by others. Thus the permanence of the-soiil, regarded merely as an object of inner sense, remains undemonstrated, and indeed Indeaonstrable . Its penaansnce diiring life is, of course, evident per se, since the thinking being (as man) is itself likev/ise an object of the outer senses. 19^
neither the ego or self, nor the appearances, nor the kind
of change which characterizes them.
Since
v/e
are directly
things of v;hich
i';e
I6i
claims
psycholoey to be u science.
point is that:
.as iii every natural doctrine only so . much science proper is to be liiet ;/ith therein as there is co'^ition a priori a doctrine of nature can only contain so''niuch science proper as there is in it of applied mathematics. 199
,
iiant ,;:oes on
200 its laws", for in it all that mathematics could lay hold
Ox would be the laxv of permanence in the flovi of its in-
ternal changes.
for example, in
little.
neict
manifold of internal
observation is only separated in thought, but cannot be kept 201 It is to be separate and be connected again at pleasure".
veiry
base of
169
But it carmot be said that Lant has fully apprecia-
of pheno-
mena can alvjays be traced back to the a priori determination of phenomena in accordance v^ith the categories.
vie
If
But since
170
between the way we intuit our inner states, and the way we
intuit spatially extended objc^cts, there
^^rould
be no poss-
forr;is
of sensibility, and
to human faculties.
philosophy,
Kant has offered a solution to the problem of the
fundamental distinction
betv.'een
in Kant's philosophy.
We are
cannot
171
another, and if we attempt to extend the concept of substance to a sphere which is not in space but only in time, the
v;ay.
172
all predicates without any condition distinguishing this presentation of the subject from a something generally,
in short, substance, of which no conception of xvhat it is 205 (is conveyed) through this expression". Altogether,
Those sensations of outer sense may legitimately admit of intensive magnitude, according to Kant, since
173
of
something that endures; it is a genuine arising and perishing, not explicable at all in terms of substance, in
short, the very passage of time itself, as revealed in
inner sense.
Kant has bought the means of distinguishing between
point of fundamental importance in 3ergsons theory of time, namely, that we are aware of it through inner ex-
perience.
v/e
have
categories determine objects and bring about order throughout the phenoiaenal vjorld.
In addition, the appearances in
174
in that both are indeterminate and unknowable by means of
concepts.
Bergson s view, something quite different, indeed, radically different from what is revealed by the deepest in-
trospection.
175
sarae
strictly
This technique
set
It is
character of the
l\xx.
of inner states.
176 the same point that Bergson does, namely, that inner ex-
177
all change.
Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science , but his definitions presuppose that change is possible, (something,
of course, which no one will doubt, even though it may be
merely how space and time are related to change but also
how psychologically . inner sense is related to outer sense.
\i;ords,
the nature of
an
The iuujh discussed question of the coiEinuiiion between the thinking and the extended, if v;e leave aside all that is merely fictitious, coraes then simply to this; hov; in a thinking sub.ject outer intuition , namely, that o? space, with its filling-in of sbape and motion, is, possiule . And this is a question which 209 no man can possibly answer.
17fi
Consequently, the question is no longer of the communion of the soul v;ith other known substances of a different kind outside us, but only of the connection of the representations of inner sense v/ith the modifications of our outer sensibility as to hov/ these can be so connected v;ith each other according to settled laws that they exhibit the unity of a coherent experience. 210
VvTiether
v.'ould
have been impossible for Kant, but which could have been
carried out by a thinker v/illing to follow the implications of it beyond the limiting scope of Kant's categorical
scheme.
ways to Kant's.
is
^Ind
placing a much greater emphasis on the significance of intuition for metaphysics, a development which Kant would
change, and this change can best be felt v/hen the intellect does not interfere to separate the continuous flux
Kant also mentions in saying that "the manifold of inter212 nal observation is only separated in thought".
180
Just as, for Kant, there is no underlying permanence
in inner sense, so also for Bergson the reality uncovered
in inner experience is not a change of the state of some
underlying substratum.
There are changes, but there are imdemeath the change no things which change; change has no need of a support. 213
I/ith Kant,
This is also 3ergsons view. Thus I said that several conscious states are organized into a whole, pemieate one another, gradually gain a richer content, and might thus give anyone ignorant of space the feeling of pure duration; but the very use of the word "several" shows that I had already isolated these states, externalized them in relation to one another, and, in a v/ord, set them side by side; thus, by the very language which I was compelled to use, I betrayed the deeply ingrained 214 habit of setting out time in space.
The above quotation also indicates the similarity
xie
and Bergson have recourse to the notion of intensive magnitudes in referring to the succession of psychic states,
Pure duration, that which consci-msness perceives, must thus be 'reckoned araong the so-called intensive magnitudes, if intensities can be called magnitudes: strictly speaking, hoi;ever, it is -not a quantity, and as soon as we try to measure it, we unwittingly replace it by space. 215
'
inner experience is an all-encompassing, basic reality. And the reasons for this further development, the sources,
1S2
2,
vje
may mention
amounting to artificiality.
a cornerstone of Kants system, and for him, a "closed and '216 Hegel calls "the lifeless completed body of doctrine", 217 And Bergson, as v;e shall see, affirms bones of a skeleton".
problem
v;as
of judgment.
very limit.
Hegel does not repudiate the importance of Bergson not only rejects judgreality, but allows the signi-
ment as a method of
Icn owing
concept .
133
seriously, and to make of it a natter in which static concepts rather than active judgments are emphasized.
Instead
Ivant.
Ue have
nov/
In this regard
we find Kant, with typical candour, accepting on the one hand that the flux of inner sense is bej^ond the
.
\^
of
time?
1S4
part of the same medium, space, and every determinate length of time is a part of time.
The homogeneity of these media
220 It
hovtf
the
1^5
Synthesis of
the homogeneous manifold, even thovigh it is always successive, for Kant, involves holding together in thought all
For if we picture to ourselves each of the sheep in the flock in succession and separately, we shall have to do v/ith laore than a sin^^le sheep. In ornever der that the number shoiild go on increasing in proportion as v;e advance, v/e must retain the successive images and set them alongside of each of the new units
1^6
which we picture to ourselves: now it is in space that such a juxtaposition takes place and not in pure duration. In fact, it will be easily granted that counting material objects means thinking all these objects together, thereby leaving them in space. 221+
It may be thoui];ht that here Bergson has passed
arrive at the synthetic a priori propositions of mathematics by the mere analysis of concepts.
1^7 Pure mathematics, as synthetic cognition a priori , is only possible by referring to no ether objects than those of the senses. At the basis of their empirical intuition lies a pure intuition (of space and time) which is a priori . 226
'."e
successive synthesis.
The mathematics of space (geometry) is based upon this successive synthesis of the productive imagination in the generation of figures. 22^
for "the
time ,
time, and therefore everything that is in inner sense is 230 in constant flux". Kant held that alteration is only con-
It s.^ems clear
that Kant thought of this permanent element as space itself, or rather the pemuixiynce of the real in space, which, of
course, iiaplies the permanence of space.
We have already
flux of inner sense, we cannot obtain an imiuediate representation ox time, but also that we can obtain a mediate,
spatial representation 01 time because of the permanence
or "held-togetherness" of space. For in order that we may afteri;7ards make inner alterations likewise thinkable, vie must represent time (the form of inner sense) figuratively as a line, and the inner alteration through the drawing of this line (motion), and so in this manner by means of outer intuition make compretensible the successive existence of our-selves in different states. The reason of this is that .5.11 alteration, if it to be perceiv3d as alteration, presupposes something permanent in intuition, and that in inner sense no permanent intuition is to ?Z1 be met with.
1^9
Tho extent to
w'
.'lant,
we can represent time by a line, and x'eason from the properties of tnis line to the properties ox time, he also
says that the alteration of inner sense, and hence the
rhe flux of
seera
tv:o
190
repeatedly occur, a
viev;
pretation of him,
or outside of time.
. .1 do find it difficult to suppose. .that our minds are such that to them reality must appear, not only as a succession of changes in time, but as a succession of changes in time which must conform to causal law. There are two v/ays of avoiding this difficulty. One is to assert that the transcendental synthesis of \-jhich Kant speaks is a pre-conscious and noimenal synthesis which somehow constructs the whole physical world for us before we be^in to know it. For this view I can find no basis in Kant, nor does it seem to me to have the least plausibility as a metaphysical theory. 232
it is not
Accor-
imposed on space, through the very continuity of the successiveness of the synthesis.
Thus the logical ground of the
191
this
tv/o
not be perceived.
tiiae
itself cannot
Thus
-iihe
192
-ovorthelesn the syiithesis of -ue maiiiJ?old partn of space, by means of which we apprehend space, is succesnlve, taking place in time ^^d coiitainiiig a series, 234
series:,
-
We can conclude, then, that the C0;:;nitive representation of space is a representation of space as a r.edium
can
193
Our final conclusion, therefore, is that there are tv;o kinds of multiplicity: that of material objects, to v;hich the conception of number is immediately appli-*cable; and the multiplicity of states of consciousness, which cannot be regarded as numerical v/ithout the help of some symbolical representation, in which a necessary element is space. 237
'
and
194
The unity wlilch the mind introduces implies, for
Berp'.son,
tiplicity.
You will never get out of an idea which you have formed anything which you have not put into it; and if the unity by means of which you make up your number is the unity of an act and not of an object, no effort of analysis will bring -out anything but unity pure and simple. No doubt, when you equate the number 3 to the sum of 1 1 1 nothing prevents you from regarding the units vjhich compose it as indivisible: but the reason is that you do not choose to make use of the multiplicity which is enclosed within each of these units. 241
Bergson agrees vjith Kant that
niuiibers
are reached
with quarters, with any units whatever, these units, in so far as they serve to form the said number, will constitute elements v;hich'are provisionally indivisible j and it is alxvays by jerks, by sudden jumps, so to speak, that v;e' advance from one to the other. And the reason is that, in order to get a number. Me are compelled to fix our attention successively on each of the units of v/hich it is compounded. . ..Ind v;hen vje look at humber in its finished state, this union is an accomplished fact: the points 'have become lines, the divisions have been blotted out, the whole displays all the charac242 teristics of continuity.
195
In
speakixii';
They are,
ti.
:,
;id
number,
Section One, it is
'
196
tivo Luiique
tv;o
different forms of
And in this
This, hov;ever,
how we can have the phenomenal self as an object of consciousness, he illustrates this possibility by appealing
to the fact that time can only be represented in spatial
terns
Indeed, that this is how it must be, is easily shownif we admit that space is merely a pure form of by the fact that we the appearances of outer sense cannot obtain for ourselves a representation of time, which is not an object of outer intuition, except under the image of a line, vjhich tire draw, and that by this mode of depcting it alone could we knov/ of the singleness of its dimension; and similarly by the fact that for all inner perceptions we derive the determination of lengths of time or of points of time from the changes which are exhibited to us in outer things, and that the determinations of inner sense have therefore to be arran^^ed as appearances in time in precisely the same manner in which we arrange those of outer sense in space. 244
safiie
relation to cognitive
197
representation.
if it is granted that
must be admitted that as an object it is something absolutely different from the objects of outer sense, and cannot be
kno-vvn
V/e
ner sense and the removal of this from the sphere of cognition.
ly spatialized.
196
Kant's great mistake uas to take time as a homoseneous mediiim. He did not notice that real duration is made up of moments inside one another, and that when it seems to assume the form of a homogeneous whole, it is because it ;_:ets expressed in space. Thus the very distinction which he makes between space and time amounts at bottora to confusinj' time with space, and the symbolical representation of the ego with the ego itself. He thought that consciousness v;as incapable of perceiving psychic states othenvise than by juxtaposition, for^^etting that a medium in which these states are set side by side and distinguished from one another is of course space, and not duration. He was thereby led to believe that the same states can recur in the depths of consciousness, just as the same physical phenomena are repeated in space; this at least is what he implicitly admitted v/hen he ascribed to the causal relation the same meaning and the same function in the inner as in the outer v;orld, 245
V/h?.t
Kant?
.if time, as
homogeneous medium, science vjould be able to deal v/ith it, 246 aB it can with space". This point is implied in Kant's
own criticism of psychology.
a_
199
which re.iuires
a pure
In the
'.vhich
the science is to
science.
... he has to bring in change and motion, but change and raotion are not v/holly free froqi empirical elements, and are not on the same footing as time and space. Furthermore the science of geometry takes account of space only, v;hereas the doctrine of motion must take accoiint of both space and time. Since time is the form of inner sense, a pure science of time should enable us to deal a priori v;ith inner states (not v;ith moving bodies), and should offer a basis for psychology rather than for physics. 24S
Paton adds in a foot-note that "The precise nature 249
of the 'doctrine of motion* is a further difficulty".
It seems clear that there is no such pure temporal science,
200
own position, is hi^^hly questionable.
But it is not merely
himself shoivn the impossibility of such a science in his remarks about inner sense and its constant flux.
The crux of the problem created by Kant's recogni-
Kant is
201
theI observer oetG i:ie is not the time of uy own but ouserver oex^s me is_ noz zne oinie oi uj^ ovvn out or his sensibility so tVie identity vjTiTcTi is nee ^ssarily boiond up v;ith my coneciousness is not therefore boxmd up with his, that is, vjith the consciousness which contains the outer intuition of ray subject, 251
,
This
sense.
o^
ov.osr
202
conception of
tirae,
i.'e
external things,
V/hat,
xi/hole
phenomenal \vorld?
r.im-
203
conception.
He admits
Duration is not successive in a spatial sense, because such a conception of successiveness implies discrete
himself has recognized that there is not the least magnitude in bare succession.
Thus Kants acceptance of the theory
v?e
have called
tirae
as
204
successiveness, wliich, as we
sist in the fact that the
ti;
!iave
however,
tliat
(b)
sive continuum of time is otherwise indistinguishable from that of space, a recognition of becoming would otherwise be
quite impossible.
namely, by a conception of a
But A conceives this becoming as
projecting time-series.
205
already exanined.
concepts
Thus he calls
iiot
206
point that process is -uided or deterniiied by logical 256 categories. But it seems difficult to understand how a
temporal process must necessarily be subject to categorical determination if it is also held that these categories have an origin independent of the process.
V/e
may
that they must get together, that is, that the categories
Other-
very problem.
remains obscure.
The'tv;o extremes ^ namely sensibility and tinderstanding, must stand xn necessary connection with each other through the mediation of this transcendental function ox imagination, because otherwise the former,
207
though indeed yieldinc appearances, v;ould supply no objects of empirical knowledge, and consequently no experience. 257
It is clear that Kant can only maintain this view
i_s
experience if he separates
lui
'le
Kant says, "The schema is in itself alv/ays a product of 25^ ima.-ination'' , But either the production of schemata by
the transcendental imacjination nust have the same apodeictic
II
20a
eludes conceptualization.
which Kant tells us involves holding all the parts synthesized together, and not dropping them out, as they would
be in bare succession.
There is real duration, the heterogeneous moments -of which permeate one another; each moment, however, can be brought into relation with a state of 'the external xvorld vjhich is contemporaneous with it, and can be separated from the other noments in consequence of this very process. The comparison of these two realities gives rise to a S3nnbolical representation 01 duration, derived from space. Duration thus assumes the illusory form of a homogeneous medium, , . 259
'
209
It ia, for Bergson, forever impossible to untler-
But still less coulc". it be represented by con cepts , that is- by abstract ideas, ivhether general or simple. Doubtless no image v;ill quite answer to the original fealing I have of the flowing of myself. But neither is it necessary for rae to try to express it. To him wiio is not ca] able of /^ivin,: hiuself the intuition of the duration constitutive of his being, nothing will ever give it, neither concept nor images. 261
It is apparent that Bergson, too, has accepted the
be determinative of
If we are to understaad
metaphysical intuition.
210
what there is unique and consequently inexpressible in it. Analysis, on the contrary, is the operation which reduces the object to elements already knovm, that is, coiiiraon to that object and others. Analysing then consists in expressing a thing in terras of what is not it. 263
At the root of 3ergsons rejection of a logic of
Bergson can
of time is known, as it is for Kant, (as a form of sensibility), through inner experience, Bergson can stress this
conceptual thinking.
211
In distin^uishinc between the two, Kant did not lay much
develops.
remains.
thus
To create the 'future requires preparatory action in the present, to prepare what v;ill be is to utilize what has been; life therefore is employed from its start in conserving the past and anticipating the future in a duration in v/hich past, present and future tread one on another^ forming an indivisible continuity. Such memory, such 264 anticipation, are consciousness itself,
The idealistic element in Kant's thought necessi-
phenomenal self.
212
as forms of outer and inner sense, respectively, involves
material world;
apprehension of becoming;
Hume.
tions made by the self with the view of space and time as
extensive, which is characteristic of the
tv;o
theories we
\i7hose
points,
(a)
213
inner sense in the narrow and wide meanings, and the problem
narro;-;
tv;o
meaning
points, {c)
and (d) provide the seed of the separation betv/een the in-
tellect and time, a development from the distinction betv/een inner sense and the
further questions,
l.hat
with space?
points.
214
3.
v;e
spatial parts.
Bergson, as
v/e
have seen,
By this token, he
215
rational terns.
on an appeal to intuition.
views, because time and space for him are, above all, pure
intuitions.
V/hen
further inquiry.
Metaphysics may
were to be a knoivledge of things-in-themselves, but an intuition 'Which carries us into the heart of the duration
216
and that this metaphysics is impossible. It would in fact be so if there were no other time or change than those v.'hich Kant perceived and which, moreover, we too must reckon with; . , ,266
of real time.
Intuition doubtless admits of many de,2Tees of intensity, and philosophy many degrees of depth; but the mind once broiight back to real duration will already be alive with intuitive life and its knovjledge of thin,?;s will already be philosophy. Instead of a discontinuity of uoments replacing one another in an infinitely divided time, it will perceive the continuous fluidity of real time which flows along, indivisible. 26?
to Kant's
Kant's theory of
217
area of
Kant,
of inner sense,
v:e
Bergsons theory of
that of Kant.
Thus Bergson*s intuition of time as duration is
an intuition with a concrete content, but a content which
is not broken up in itself into differentiated parts.
Time,
The trick of our perception, like that of our intelligence, like that of our language, consists in extracting from these profoundly different becomings the single representation of becoming in general, undefined becoming, a mere abstraction which by itself says nothing and of which, indeed, it is very- rarely that we think. To this idea, -always the same, and alv;ays obscure or unconscious, we then Join, in each
21^
particular case, one or several clear images that represent states and which serve to distin :uish all becomings from each other. It is this composition of a specified and definite state with change in general and undefined that vie substitute for the specific change. 269
But why should Bergson equate this concrete time
'.Tiat
t''o::^y
Although these appearances are outside of possible experience in Kant's sense of the terra, they are certainly not
psychologically impossible,
B'or
If one were to
219
immediate apprehension of
If the
directly av;are of it as it
and not by
r.ieans
of our
mately real.
requirements.
do
Yet we are
It must, therefore, be
There is a further reason, however, for contending that time is an ultimate reality, and this as well stems
as follows.
Against this theory, which adi:dts the empirical reality of time, but denies its absolute and transcendental reality, I have heard men of intelligence so unanimously voicing an objection,
220
that I must suppose it to occur spontaneously to every reader to whom this way of thinking is unfamiliar. The objection is this. Alterations are real, this bein,2; proved by change of ovir own representations even if all outer appearances, together with their alterations, be denied. ICow alterations are possible only in tirae, and time i;3 therefore something real. There is no difficulty in meeting this objection. I grant the whole argument. Certainly time is something real, namely, the real form of inner intuition. 270
His reply
221
empirically real
foria
Does Patons
The bubble of
l/e
think not.
duration is inextricably bound up with our consciousness that Bergson takes as central to his philosophy.
'272
He tells
which we
knox-*
and he
of this existence.
222
Consciousness becomes
time does not allov; one to apply the saae kind of argument
to prove the absolute reality of space.
marks, "the fact remains that space is said to be the con274 It is dition of some human experience, but not of all".
223
vice versa.
Bergson
Traditional empiricism, he
metaphysics.
Ilais vji empirisrae vrai est celui qui se propose de serrer d'aussi prSs que possible 1' original lui-
ultimate reality.
224
space and time consist?
lie
from tine.
v;ay
he can communicate
liis
expla-
This is, in
He invites us first
man powers,
Vie
varying degrees.
225
Bersson, in effect, agrees with
i.cnt tiiat
the intel-
exi,::^ency.
Kant^s terms reraains insoluble becomes explainable in psychological and biological terms.
But even here psychology
questionable whether he is not doing metaphysics throughout, a metaphysics designed to deal with that question
rests on a metaphysical explanation of how matter and intelligence arise out of the basic flov; of time.
This explanation, how^ever, carries him far beyond
It
226
For Bergson's
I/e
More generally, the relation that we establish in the present chapter between "extension" and "detension" resembles in some aspects that which Plotinus supposes. . .v/hen he makes extension not indeed an inversion- of original Being, but an enfeeblement of its essence, one of the last stages of the procession. , . Yet ancient philosophy did not see v.'hat consequences' v;ould resvilt from this for mathematics, for Plotinus, like Plato, erected mathematical essences into absolute realities. Above all, it suffered itself to be deceived by the purely/ superficial analogy of duration v;ith' extension. It treated the one as it treated the other, regarding change as a degradation of immutability, the sensible as a fall from the intelligible. Whence. . .a philosophy vdiich fails to recognize the real function and scope of the intellect. 279
227
see the point where Bergson's development breaks off and
physics and look out upon the v/orld of outer sense merely
as it is,
i.hat
do
vje
find there?
V.'e
Sian
unaccustomed to the
vjere
only mental
Thus matter is
ov;n
of nature is an accident.
231
228
Perception, for Bercson, is a fxmction of the living organism, and dependent thereon for its scope and richness,
,
contention that
fev; v/ould
dispute.
ception is master of space in the exact measure in v/hich 282 action is master of time". But what does this mastery
involve?
It involves the active powers ox a certain image,
of a part to a whole.
not lay hold of all of the object image. It can only master
229
which
I retain, all that does not concern the needs of the image which I call iny body. 2&'3
speculative interest.
230 2g6
succeed one another".
Here again we have 3ergsons doc-
tion.
and according
It is for
side".
not by ordering principles which stem from pure concepts of the understanding, but by the practical exigencies of
life and the agency of memory.
folloviTS
possibility B, but unlike Kant the means ivhereby he explains objects in space is partly psychological and
biological,
231
Oi to ;/hat extent in Bergson's system material objects are
as they appear in our perception, for "to perceive consists in condensing enormous periods of an infinitely
the exteraal v;orld have an independent existence, for Bergson, if indeed, they have any.
Matter as an aggregate of
images is "an existence placed half-way betv;een the * thing* 290 and the representation*". It is difficult to under-
stand exactly what Bergson means by this spatial metaphor. Perhaps the best way of grasping his meaning is to approach
it from the standpoint of distinctness itself.
The 'thing*
for Bergson, in its clear-cut distinctness, is an unreality, a fiction of the intellect, employed for purely
practical purposes.
The
representation*
as a purely
232
./hat is
in distinctness.
That which is j:iven, that which is real, is something intermediate betvjeen divided extension and pure inextension. It is what v;e have termed extensive . Extensity is ti.e most saliant quality of perception. 291
i.eaiuia emer^^es
network v;hich
v/e
needs of life.
There is much similarity
bet^ifeen
Bergson's account
find no equivalent to
Bergson's vitalism.
v;ith
233
So we have assvuned the existence of a homogeneous Space, and with Kant, distin:;ui3hed this space from the natter which fills it. i/ith him we have adnitted that homogeneous space is a "form of our sensibility", . . 294
duration.
v/e
234
.ilia .^liieiTiativo conLix:;os. -ix-oo ox all, in resardin- the intellect as a special function of the mind, essentially turned tov;ard inert matter; then in saying that neither does matter detemine the form of the intellect, nor does the intellect impose its form on natter, nor have matter and intellect been regulated in re^^ard to one another by vje i-noiJ not what pre-established hannony, but that intellect and matter have progressively adapted themselves one to the other in order to attain at last a common form. This adaptation has . moreover , been brou'ht about quite"riaturallyV because it is the sane inversion of the sa..ie ..lovoiient 'vjiiich'"creates at orxco the inteTlectuality of in'ind and t li e materiality of thin;^s . 29^
'
perceptive faculty
we see neither
hovj
which
is
vrtiat
it is
299
3o
x-te
V/hether Bergson e
Bergson believes
, there is this about it (space) that is , , remarkable that our mind, speculating, on it with its own powers alone, cuts out in it, a priori , figures whose properties we determine a prTori ; experience, vjith v/hich we have not kept in^touch, yet follows us throiigh the infinite complications of our reasonings and invariably justifies them. That is the fact. 300 Kant has set it in clear light,
235
But in spite of this wide divergence between these
work of reason.
To assume an absolute space, that is, one which, because it is not material, ccn be no object of experience as ^iven for itself, means assuming: somethin^j tirhich, neither in itself nor in its consequences (notion in absolute space), can be perceived, for the sake of the possibility of experience, v;hich nevertheless nust always exist Vidthout it. Absolute space is in itself nothing and no object at all, but signifies merely everi^ other relative space that I can at any tine c:.. criv outside the given space, and that I can extend bts/ond each given space. to infinity; one that includes the ,;;riven space and in vjhich I can assume it as moved. But since I have the enlarged, although still material space only in thought, nothing I abstract is known to me of the niatter indicating it, from this, and it is conceived, therefore, as a pure, and absolute space, . 301 non-empirical
Absolute space
236
Similarly, as micht be expected, the divisibility
The whole of matter is niade to appear to our thought as an immense piece of cloth in which we can cut out v:hat we will- and sov; it together again as v^e please. Let us note, in passing, that it is this power 'that v;e affirm vihen we say that there is a space . that is to say, a homogeneous and empty medium, i'nfir.ite and infinitely divisible, lending itself indifferently to any mode of decomposition v;hat soever, A medium of this kind is never perceived; it is only conceived. 303
304
matter is mathematically divisible to infinity",
further, that "mathematics can indeed.
and
.rest in the
certain possession of its evident assertions of the in305 finite divisibility of space". At the same time, Kant is
at pains to point out
tliat
237
it is sensed, or felt,- matter is phenomenal. It is de'307 fined as the "movable in space", and its sensible charac-
Matter J in contradistinction to fom, i';ould be that -which in external intuition, is an object of feeling, and consequently the properly erapirical of sensible and outvjard intuition, because it cannot be given at all 'a priori . In all experience something must be felt, ""and this is the real of sensuous intuition. 30S
Thus, for both Kant and Bergson the divisibility
not a property of
i/hat is
mathematical
each case,
hox-^ever,
matical construction.
potentially divisible,
236
have
absolute conpletion.
would end",
extends itself in space without being abso3.utely extended 310 therein". Thus, in Bergson 's view, there are two kinds
of space, or rather different degrees of spatiality,- the
one exemplified in matter, a kind not carried to complete
admit of degrees.
239
space which is the logical limit of the conceptixal expan-
'..'ith
tiality, and also the notion of something which lies betv/een these limits,
v;ay it
240
is a petitio principii in makin^j geometry arise automati312 It is, of cally from space, and lo^^ic from geonetiT-".
course, just because Bergson does not assuiue the point of
viev; of the
Kant.
241
MOTS
1
Gottfried Ilartin, Kant 3 I-letaphysics and Theory of Science . trans. P.G. Lucas (Kanchester: The I-iaiichester University Press, 1955), p. 11.
<
Iramanuel Kant, Critique of Pure'^leason y trans. Norman Kemp Smith (London: Ilacmillan and Co., Ltd., 1953), p. 6^, Subsequent references to this vork will be designated "Critique", and both the page nuinber of the translation and that of the first and second editions of the original work v/ill be given.
3
Cf, 17, Meinecke, "Die Bedeutung der nichteulvlidischen Geometrie", Kantstudien XI, I9O6. H.J. Pat on, Kant < Metaphysics of Experien ce, (London: Ooorge Allen & Unv.'in, Gottxried T art in, Kant's Ixetaphysics ond Theory of 1936) . Science .
Donald C. .Jilliaras, "The llyth of Passage", Joumr.l of Philo sophy . XLVIII, no. 15, July (1951), p. 457.
'
A. D. Lindsay, The Philosophy of Bergson ^ (London: J.M. Dent & Sons, 1911 J, pp. 2-3.
The predominant -historical influence on Bergson seems to have been French, although the direct and indirect influence of Gerr,ian philosophy cannot be ignored. In this regard see Ben-Ami Scharf stein. Roots of Bergson ^s Philosophy ^ (Ke\J York: Columbia University Press, 1943
)
7
raent of
Perhaps the most notable difference between the measiirespace and the measurement of time, is that spatial lengths can sometimes be compared, side by side, in sensuous intuition, v/hile it is impossible to take one "chunk" of time, and place it beside another.
242
Ernst Cassirer, Substance and Fimction and Einstein *s Theory of llelativltv . trans. ..'illj.nn flurt^a .'^^wn^py anrl Marie CJoilins 3v;abey (Chicago-London: The Open Court Publishing Company, 1923), p. IO5. (Italics not in text).
9
John Alexander Gunni The Problera of Time . (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1929), p. 3?!.
10 Ibid., pp. 373-374.
11
Of. Samuel Alexander, Space. Time and Deity . London, 1934.
12
H, I-iinkovtfski , "Space and Time", in II. A. Lorentz, A, Einstein, -H. Ilinkov/ski, and H. Weyl, The Principle of Rela tivity , trans. W. Perrett and G.B. Jeffery, v;ith notes by A. Sommerfield (London: Metliuen & Co., 1923), p. 75.
13
.Infinity .
14 This is a view v/hich Kant, himself, combats. Cf, Critique . ("A" refers to the page nianber of pp. 8O-0I, A39, 356. the first edition, "B" to that of the second).
, .
15
Ethics . I, Def, 3.
16 Ethics . I, Prop. 3. 17 Cf . The Problems of Philosophy . (London: Williams & Nor19l2); also Mysticism and Lor; ic (London: Longmans, Green c: Co., 191^); also Proceedinj^s""of the Aristo telian Society . (1910-11).
r,ate^ Ltd..
IS John Locke, An Essay concerning Human Understanding , ed. Oxford Oxford University Press, A. S.'Pringle-Pattison 1924), Bk. II, Ch. 15, Sec. 12, p. 121.
( :
243
19
Alfred Horth v/hitehead, Science and the riodern l/orld . (Cambridge: Cambridce University Press, 1925 J, Cheap Edition p, 63,
20
Ibid., p. 62,
21 Ibid., p. 62.
22
Ibid ., p. 70.
23
Alfred North Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas, (Cambridge; Cambridge University Press, 1933 i, p. 197.
Alfred North Whitehead, Science and the
Ibid ., p. 156.
26
A, A, Robb, The Geometry of Time -and Space . (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1936) P 19.
Modem World
p,15o.
27
Ibid ., p. 23.
2g
'
-
CD.
29
Ibid., p. 55.
30
Jolin
Locke, 0. cit .
31
Ibid., II, 15 I Sec, 9, p. Ho. It should be noted that for Locke "ti le" is a term used for measured duration. The latter is the basic idea, and the forrrxer is derived therefrom by measurement. Locke calls space "expansion" to distinguish it from extension, "which by some is used to express this distance only as it is in the solid parts of
244 matter". But Locke is not entirely consistent in this usage, since, in the same chapter, (II, 15), in which he makes this distinction, he reverts to usin^j "extension" as synonyijious with space, Cf, Sec. 9,
32 Ibid., II, 15, Jec, 5, p. 117.
33
CD,
34
p,
53,
CD. Broad, An Examination of IIcTa.f-;;art*s Philosophy . (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1933), II, ^69.
A, A, Robb, o. cit
, .
35
pp, 6-7
36
Ibid ,, p. 20,
37
Richard Taylor, "Spatial and Temporal Analogies and the Concept of Identity", The Journal of Philosophy . LII, Ho, 22, Oct. (1955), p. 59^::
38
Ibid ,, p, 600,
39
Bertrand Russell, Our I^owledge of the gxtemal 1/orld . (Chicago: The Open Court Publishing Co,, 1929), p. 254.
40
CD.
^^
Ibid.
p.
5^.
42
Taylor, o. cit .
43
.
p.
601.
Ibid., p. 601.
44
Ibid., p. 602.
245
45
C.D. Broad, Scientific Thou;?:ht . p. 57.
46
Cf. Taylor, o.
cit .
pp. 610-612.
47
Nelson Goodman, The Structure of Appearance . (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1951), p. 301,
46
Ibid ., pp. 300-301.
49
C.D. Broad, Scientific Thow^ht . p. 57.
50
Ibid ., p. 59.
51
'
'
Donald G. ..illiaras, "The Sea Fi^ht Tomorrow", in Ilenle, Structure, llethod and Leariin,"; . Essays in Honor of' Henry I-I. Sheffer, (llew York: The Liberal Arts Press, 1951), p. 304.
52
p. 302.
H.R, King, "Aristotle and the Paradoxes of Zeno", in The Journal of Philosophy . ILVI (1949), p. 662.
Ibid ,, p. 667.
Bertrand Russell, kysticism and Logic . (London and New York: Longmans Green & Co., 1918), p. S4.
56
This is the viev; taken by Goodman, who remarks, "Strangely enough it turns out not that time is more fluid than- (say) space but rather that time is more static". 0. cit . . p. 300,
57
<
.
246
56
Immanuel Kant, De'Iiundi Sensibilis atgue IntelltTibilis Forma et Principiis . trans. Jonii Iianayside in Kant ^3 Inau^-ural Dissertation and Sarlv Writinps on Space . (Chicago and London: The Open Goui-t Publishing Co., 19^9), p. 45.
Ibid,, p.
247
73
74
Ibid,,
24S
fi9
p. 56; B20.
95
98
Ibid ., p.
99
346';
A372-373.
249
105
stout,
oj3,
cit.
p, 496.
106
F. C. Bartlett, 'Troblems in the Psychology of Temporal Perception", in Philoaophy . XII (1937), p. 461.
107
Ibid ., p. 463.
IQg
Kant's theory of space and time, however, has been profoundly misunderstood by some psychologists. For example, ary 3oax''t*3 comment on a passage from the Transcendental ^esthetic "Time cannot be a priori in the Kantian sense, because knowledge of it both develops in the individual and appears to vary in- different cases", is, of course, irrelevant. (11. 3turt, The Psycholo/^y of Time , p. 10.
'
109
Critique . p. ^7\ A49, 366.
110 111
114
Ibid., p. 351; A37g.
116
Ibid., p. 346; A373.
117 lie
'
'
250
119
Criticuai p. l65; B15-. "In so far as imaelnation is spontaneity^ I sometimes also entitle it the productive imagination , to distinsuish it frora the reproductive iinagination, v;hose synthesis is entirely suoject to empirical laws, the lav;s, namely, of association. .The reproductive synthesis falls within the domain not of transcendental philosophy, but of psychology". Kmpirical la\;s,of course, presuppose the transcendental unity of apperception, the transcendental act of imasination, and the categories. But the analogy concerning the presuppositions of the re<productive sjrnthesis is not entirely exact, as psychology, for Kant, is not a science. See beloxv p. I6l et_ seq .
-
120
C ritique
. .
p. 167; 3x^,.
121 "Taken to.'cether, the analogies thus declare that allappearar^ces lie, and must lie, in one nature". Critique . p. 237; A216, B263.
122
124
Ibid ., p. 226; A200, B2l,3.
125
Ibid.
251 131
Ibid ., p. 352; A379.
132 Ibid., p. 77; A33, 349-50.
133
134
135
I, 64.
136
137
Ibid .. I, 65.
Critique . p. 369; B407.
13fi
139
Ibid ., p. I7O; BI59-I6O.
140
David Hume, A Treatise of- Human Katurej ed. Selby-Bigge' (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1896), Bk I, Pt, 3, Sec. XII, p. 134.
141
142
-
144
Ibid ., p. 236; A217, B264.
145
'
252
146
23?-; A210, B255. Kanr^^-^r^';: ^erke sd.-J. H. German text: Imanuel Kant, o5...^Gliche von Kirchmann, (Ileidel-
14^
Ibid., p. 261} A241, B300.
149
Ibid., p. 251 J A233, 32S6.
150
Ibid*! P 236; A215, B262.
151
Ibid .f p. 196; Al60, B199.
152
Ibid., p. l&k;
153
Alii.3,
Blg2.
154
Ibid ., p. 167; B154.
155
Ibid .y p. 112; A7g, B104.
156
Ibid., p. 204; A170, B211-212.
157
Ibid., p. 295j A291, B347.
153
Ibid., p. 63; A24, B3f^-39.
159
Ibid ., p. 193; A163, B203.
160
253
161
Ibid., p. lo7; B154.
162
Ibid,, p. 167; 13154-155.
163
(Kants footnote).
164
Ibid ., p. 167; B155.
165
Ibid ., p. ira; A13 9-140, B169-170.
166
Ibid ., p. 183; A142, BlCl.
167
'
Paton, . cit.
II, 7^.
I6g
Critique
,
p. 376; B420.
169 This is a paradox because the metaphysical theory of the manifold is supposed to accoiint for all contents of the universe v/ithout residue . In vjhat does the individualioy of the consciousness, which is liiTiited to certain finite regions at certain times, and yet continues the same in di fferent regions at other times, consist?
-
170
Critique , p. 136, AIO7.
171
Henri Bergson, Creative Svolution . trans i Arthur i^itchell (New York: The Kodenn Library, Random House, Inc., 1944),
p. 3.
172
174
Ibid., p.
.,
2^55;
A274, 3330.
254
175
17^
1S2
134
IrananuGl Kant, Iletaph^sical Foundations of Natural Science trans. Smest -ieifort Bax in Kant*s Prolagomena and riGtaphysical Foundations of HaturaT" Science . (London: George Bell and Sons, 1391) i p. 14^. References to this xvork^vill be hereinafter designated "Bax".
135
Bax, p. 137.
133
139
Ibid., p. 255; B291.
255
190
Ibid.
p. 34^; A3 64.
191
Ibid.
!-
3^Jf
Ji.364.
192
Ibid
193
p. 214;
Alg3, 3226.
Ibid.
194
Ibid
>
p. 255; B292
195
Ibid,
p. 254; 3291.
196
Ibid,
p. 353; A3fil.
197
Bax, p. 221,
19s
Grioique . p. 373; 3415.
199
Bax, pp. 140-141.
200
Ibid .
.
p. 141.
201
Ibid ..
202
^By nature, in the empirical sense, we imderstand the connection of appearances as -regards their existence according to necessary rules, that is, according to lav;s.' There are certain laws which first make a nature possible, and the3e lavjs are a priori" . Critique , p. 237; A216, 3253,
203
Critique . p. 167; B154. (Kant repeats this point several times throughout the Critique
)
256
204
Bax, pp. 220-221,
205
Ibid .
206
Ibid .
207
-
'
Henri Ber^son, 'Introduction to I-ietaphysics" , trana, Mabelle L. ikidison in The Creative I_Iind (iJev; York: The Philosophical Library, 194-6 J, PP. 191-192.
20S
Ibid ., p. 191.
209
Critique , p. 359; A392-393.
210
Ibid ., p. 355} A3S6-3g7.
211
Henri Bergson, Tine and Free Will ( Essai sur les donn^ea iimaediates de la conscience trans. F.L. Fogson (London: George Allen ^ Unwin, 1910 j, p. 100.
)
212
Bax, p. 141
213
214
Bergson, Time and Free Will
,
p.
122.
215
Ibid ., p. 106.
216
Critique . p. 17; B viii.
217
G.W.F. Hegel, The Science of Lo,?:ic . trans. .H. Johnston and L.G. Strut hers, 2nd Ed., (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1951), I, 39.
'
257
21g
Critique , p. 77; '03, B49-50.
219
Ibid ., p. 204; A169, B211. 220
Ibid ., p. 196'} A162, B203. (Kants German "Kirn ist das Bevj us G t> se in de s I .annigralt ijs;en Oleic hart i,:en in der Anschauun.a; Ifoerhaupt * . >" v.'ould seem to be less av<rkwardly
hor.;or;eneous
mani-
222
224
Ibid., p. 77.
225
Ibid., p. 7S.
226
Inunanuel Kant , ProlegiCiHena to any ?ut\ire Metaphysics trans. Paul Carus, lieprint Zd, (Chicago and London: The Open Court Publishing Co., 1949), Sec. 11, p. 36.
-
227
230
Ibid ., p. 255; B291.
231
Ibid., p. 255; B292.
232
25S
233
Jritique , p. 214;
MB},
3226.
234
Ibid., p. 38C; A412, B439.
235
Ibid ., p. }B; A412, B439.
236 237
'
Ibid ., p. 214,
..j.o3,
3226.
j'ree
uill . p. S?.
23a
Critique , p. 112; A7S, BIO4.
239
Ibid .
240
Bergson, Time and Free Will , p. SO.
241
Ibid ., p.
242
6'1.
244
Ibid ., p. I6g; BI56.
245
Bergson, Time and Free VJill . p. 232
246
Ibid.
,
p. 234.
' '
247
'
24d
Ibid., I, 12a.
259
249
Ibid . 250
Critique , p. 217; Alfig, B232,
251
Ibid ., pp. 241-242; A362.
252
p.
90.
-
Henri Bergson, Purge et 3imultaneite . 2nd Sd. enlarged, (Paris: Librairie Felix Alcan, 1923 ;, Ch. 3, p. 54.
254
Ibid ., p. 55.
255
Bergson, "The Perception of Change", in The Creative Mind, p. 176.
256
This, in itself, has its difficulties, as for example in Hegel's transition from the Absolute Idea to Nature.
257
259
Bergson, Time and Free V/ill . p. 110.
260
Ibid., p. 111.
261
Bergson, "Introduction to Ketaphysics" in The Creative Mind, p. 195
262
Norman Kemp Smith, A Comiaentary to Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd 3d. rev. co enl., (London: Ilacmillan, 1930),
p. 96.
260
263
264
Henri Jerijson, "Lire and Consciousness" in Mind-Snergy . trans. II. l/ildon Carr (London: Ilacmillan, 1920), p. 13.
265
Critique
.
p. 359; A3 93.
266
Bergson, "r^.iloso rir:al Intuition" in The Creative
Mind , p. 151.
267
Ibid ., p. 150.
26g
Ibid .
269
Ber^son, Creative gvolution . pp. 330-331.
270
'
271
272
273
Ibid ., p. 220.
274
275
'
Paton, o. cit .
I, 146.
276
Ibid ., p. 206. French text:- "Introduction a la Mltaphysique" in La Pensee et Le Iiouvant . Oeuvres Completes d' Henri 3ergson, (Geneva: Editions Albert Skira, 1946),
p. l^g.
261
277
281
Henri Bergson, llatter and Memory , trans. Nancy Margaret Paul and ;v. Scott Palmer (London: George Allen Ez Unwin. * 1911), p. 17.
2g2
Ibid., p. 23.
263
Ibid ., p. 304.
2^4
Ibid ., p. 21.
2^5
Ibid ., p. 292.
26-6
Ibid ., p. 236.
2^7
Ibid ., p. 305.
Ibid ., pp. 277-278.
269
Ibid ., p. 275.
290
Ibid .
.
p. III.
291
Ibid .
.
p. 326.
262
292
Ibid ., p. 305.
293
Ibid ,, p. 273.
294
lioi'^^jpon,
dUl
p. 236.
295
"That is vjhat kaiit orou^ht out so clearly and that, it seems to ne, is the greatest service he rendered to speculative philosophy. He definitively established that, if uetaphysicG is possible, it can be so only throiigh an effort of intuition", "The Perception of Change" in The Creative Mind , p. I65. Thus Bergson agrees with Kant denial of the ability of Reason to knov; ultimate reality. But, of course, Bergson does not agree xvith Kants denial of a metaphysical intuition.
296
Bergson, Creative Svolution . p. 223.
297
Ibid ., p. 225.
296
Ibid ., pp. 225-226.
299
Ibid., p. 224.
300
Ibid ., p. 223.
301
302
'
Bax, p. 151.
304
Bax, pp. 176-177.
263
305
Ibid ., p. 179.
306
Ibid ., pp. l50-lgl. Italics not in text,
30g
Ibid ., p. 151.
309
Bergsoa,
./re^-oivu
'
.liVoiution ,
p. 221.
310
Ibid ., p. 223.
311
Ibid ., p. 230.
312
Ibid ., p. 232,
264
BIBLIOGRAP^fY
TTforks
PRIiViAiTi
ouoi i^-JO
., Creative Evolution , trans. Arthur Mitchell, New York: The Modem Librai?y, Randon House, 1944.
l-latter anc. I'lemory , trans, Ilancy liargaret Paul , and VJ, Scott Palmer, London: George Allen & Unwin, 1911.
.
iiind>;Energy, trans.
192^5
H,
Macmillan,
-. The Great iye Fdnd trans. Ilabelle L. Andison, New York: The Philosophical Library, I946,
An Introduction to Metaphysics , trans. T.E. Hiilmej iutro. Thomas A. Goudge, New York: The Liberal Arts Press. 1949.
Kant, Imiaanuel oSfbmtliche Werke . F^-d. J. H, von Kirchmann, Heidelberg: Georg Jeiss, 1891.
- Kritik der relnen Vernunft . (Yol. I of aboveJT
Iv'orks
as
H.
, Kleinere Schriften zur Ijaturphilosophie . Sd. J. von Kirclmann, Berlin: L. Iieimann, 172,
Critique of Pure Reason , trans. Norman Kemp Smith London: Ilacirdllan Ik Co., 1953. th,
265
- Metaphysical Foundations of Matural Science , trans, .Ernest Belfort Bax, London: Geor/ie Bell Tc Sons, IS9I.
. rrole;?:oraena to any Futui'e rietaphysics . Ed.& trans. Paul Uarus, Chicago and London: Open Court Publishing Co., 1949.
- r.ant*3 Inau.^ural Dissertation and garly Uritin^a on Space , trans. Jolin Ilandyside^ Chicago and London: Open Court Publishing Co., 1929.
SSCOKDARY SOUx^CSS
Books
Alexander, Sai/mel. Space. Time and Deity . London, 1934,
Broad,. C, Di , Scientific Thought . London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner k Co., 1923.
An Examination of IcTa.'^rgart^s- Philosophy . Cambridge: Cambridge l^ni varsity Press, 1933.
I
Infinity .
Ilexir
York: The
Goodman, Kelson, The Structure of Appearance . Cambridge: Harvard Univex'sity Press, 1951.
Gunn, John Alexander. The Problem of Tine . London: George Allen So Unwin, 19W. Hegel, G.V/.F. . The Science of Logic . trans. v',H. Johnstor and LiG. Struthers , 2nd Tild , , London George Allen & Unwin, 1951.
:
266
..enle,
(ed,). ^triicbure. I.ethod and Leaning . New York: The Liberal Arts PrusG, l^^l.
-. De Corpore ,
HuTie,
David. A Treatise of Jlirnan Nature . ed. Selby-Bigge, Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1S56,
Lindsay, A.D. , The Philosophy of Ber/:3on . London: J.M. Dent So JonsV I9II.
Locke, Jolrin, An jJ^Gsay concerning!: II\jiaan Understanding: , ed, A.3, Pringle-Fattison, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1924.
I'lartin,
Gottfried. Kant^s I-Ietaphysics and Theory of Science Manchester: I>Ianchester University Press, 1955.
<
Pat on, H.J, , Kant*s Metaphysics of Iilxperience . London: George Allen ^ Unwin, 1936.
Robb, A. A,
Garabridt!;e
The Geooetry of Time and Space . Cambridge: University Press, 193 &.
Russell, Bertrand, The Problems of Philosophy . London: V/illiams & Worgate, ~I912.
i
F.c
Co., 1918.
Our KnowledF:e of the Sxternal World . Chicago and . London: Open Court Publishing Co., 1929.
Scharf stein, Ben-Ami. x^oots of 3er;^son*s Philosophy . Mew York: Golumbia University Press, 1943.
Smith, Noman Kenp. A Commentary to Kant ^s Critique of Pure. Re ason . 2nd Sd. rev. ic enl. London: Mcmillan
Spinoza,
St hies .
Stout, G.F.. A 1-lanual of Psychology . 6th Sd., London: Tutorial Press, 1938.
267
Alfred North . Science and the Modem Uorld, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1926.
Articles
Bartlett, F.C. .- "Problems in the Psychology of Temporal Perception", Philosophy . XII (1937).
King, H.H, . "Aristotle and the Paradoxes of Zeno", The Joixmrl of Philosophy . XLVI (1949).
Iieinecke, W,-. "Die Bedeutung der nichteiil:lidischen Georaet rie " , Kantstudien XI , ( 1906 )
V/illiams, Donald G.
.
Philosophy .
}[L\T:II
Taylor, Richard . "Spatial and Temporal Analogies and the Concept of Identity", Journal of Philosophy . LII (1955^.