Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
skip to main content
research-article

Coupling first-person cognitive research with neurophilosophy and enactivism: : An outline of arguments

Published: 01 February 2025 Publication History

Abstract

A core issue of embodiment is the question of how phenomenal and agentive consciousness relates to external forms of behavior. Instead of biasing the question in terms of the “hard problem” as to why and how consciousness arises from brain processes (D. Chalmers), it is suggested to ask for psychophysical correlations in a metaphysically neutral way. This, however, demands (1) to explore both sides of the problem with equivalent precision and depth—not only the physical—and (2) to develop a metaphysically neutral tool to formalize them in a consistent way. Concerning (1), the basic structure of mental micro-activities found in first-person studies on cognitive processes suggests extending the scope of qualia as a mark of consciousness. In the context of Structure Phenomenology (H. Witzenmann), functionally negative phenomenality experienced in ambiguous or meaning-deprived situations and inner agentive qualia of mental activities are correlated with the decompositional signature of sensory-neural processing and synchronized neural oscillations. Concerning (2), G. Günther’s Transclassical Logic is briefly introduced and deployed to integrate the mental, psychophysical, and physical contextures in a three-valued formal framework which also includes enacted and embodied aspects. The emerging picture rebalances first-person and third-person aspects of cognition by functionally separating and dynamically integrating them, thus revitalizing the neurophenomenological research agenda with new experimental proposals and concrete hypotheses.

References

[1]
Alvarez M. and Hyman J. (1998). Agents and their actions. Philosophy, 73(2), 219–245. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0031819198000199
[2]
Aristov V. and Stepanyan I. (2022). Hypothesis of cyclic structures of pre- and consciousness as a transition in neuron-like graphs to a special type of symmetry. Symmetry, 14(3), 505. https://doi.org/10.3390/sym14030505
[3]
Atmanspacher H. and Filk T. (2010). A proposed test of temporal nonlocality in bistable perception. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 54(3), 314–321. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jmp.2009.12.001
[4]
Atmanspacher H. and Prentner R. (2022). Desiderata for a viable account of psychophysical correlations. Mind and Matter, 20(1), 63–86.
[5]
Atmanspacher H., Römer H., and Walach H. (2002). Weak quantum theory: Complementarity and entanglement in physics and beyond. Foundations of Physics, 32(3), 379–406. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1014809312397
[6]
Auvray M., Lenay C., and Stewart J. (2009). Perceptual interactions in a minimalist virtual environment. New Ideas in Psychology, 27(1), 32–47. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2007.12.002
[7]
Baars B. J. (1988). A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge University Press.
[8]
Barone P., Bedia M. G., and Gomila A. (2020). A minimal turing test: Reciprocal sensorimotor contingencies for interaction detection. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 14, 102. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2020.00102
[9]
Barrett N. F. (2016). What is at stake in the disagreement between interactivity and enaction? Constructivist Foundations, 11(2), 249–251.
[10]
Barrett N. F. (2017). The normative turn in enactive theory: An examination of its roots and implications. Topoi, 36(3), 431–443. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9355-y
[11]
Bayati M., Valizadeh A., Abbassian A., and Cheng S. (2015). Selforganization of synchronous activity propagation in neuronal networks driven by local excitation. Frontiers in Computational Neuroscience, 9(161), 69. https://doi.org/10.3389/fncom.2015.00069
[12]
Bayne T. and Montague M. (2011). Cognitive phenomenology. Oxford University Press.
[13]
Beer R. D. (2003). The dynamics of active categorical perception in an evolved model agent. Adaptive Behavior, 11(4), 209–243. https://doi.org/10.1177/1059712303114001
[14]
Beer R. D. and Di Paolo E. A. (2023). The theoretical foundations of enaction: Precariousness. Biosystems, 223, Article 104823. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biosystems.2022.104823
[15]
Bennett M. R. and Hacker P. M. S. (2022). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience (2nd ed.). Wiley.
[16]
Bermúdez J. and Cahen A. (2020). Nonconceptual mental content. In Zalta E. N. (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2020 edition). Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/content-nonconceptual/
[17]
Bishop R. (2005). The hidden premise in the causal argument for physicalism. Analysis, 66(289), 44–52. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/66.1.44
[18]
Bitbol M. and Luisi P. L. (2011). Science and the self-referentiality of consciousness. Journal of Cosmology, 14, 4728–4742.
[19]
Bourget D. and Chalmers D. J. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 465–500. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0259-7
[20]
Braddock G. (2001). Beyond reflection in naturalized phenomenology. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(11), 3–16.
[21]
Brancazio N. (2019). Gender and the senses of agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 18(2), 425–440. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-018-9581-z
[22]
Brock A. C. (2013). The history of introspection revisited. In Clegg J. W. (Ed.), History and theory of psychology. Self-observation in the social sciences (pp. 25–43). Transaction Publishers.
[23]
Bühler K. (1907). Tatsachen und Probleme zu einer Psychologie der Denkvorgänge. Archiv für die Gesamte Psychologie, 9, 297–369.
[24]
Buhler K. (2020). No good arguments for causal closure. Metaphysica, 21(2), 223–236. https://doi.org/10.1515/mp-2019-0026
[25]
Burnston D. C. (2016). Computational neuroscience and localized neural function. Synthese, 193(12), 3741–3762. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1099-8
[26]
Cerullo M. A. (2015). The problem with phi: A critique of integrated information theory. PLoS Computational Biology, 11(9), Article e1004286. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1004286
[27]
Chalmers D. (1995). Facing up the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2, 200–219.
[28]
Chalmers D. (2018). The meta-problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 25(9–10), 6–61.
[29]
Choifer A. (2018). A new understanding of the first-person and third-person perspectives. Philosophical Papers, 47(3), 333–371. https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2018.1450160
[30]
Cleeremans A. and Tallon-Baudry C. (2022). Consciousness matters: Phenomenal experience has functional value. Neuroscience of consciousness, 2022(1), niac007. https://doi.org/10.1093/nc/niac007
[31]
Coleman S. (2022). Intentionality, qualia, and the stream of unconsciousness. Phenomenology & Mind, 22, 42–53. https://doi.org/10.17454/pam-2203
[32]
Comte A. and Lenzer G. (Eds.), (2009). Auguste Comte and positivism. The essential writings (5th ed.). Harper.
[33]
Costall A. (2006). Introspectionism’ and the mythical origins of scientific psychology. Consciousness and Cognition, 15(4), 634–654. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2006.09.008
[34]
Crane T. (1992). The contents of experience. Cambridge University Press.
[35]
Danziger K. (1980). The history of introspection reconsidered. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 16(3), 241–262. https://doi.org/10.1002/1520-6696(198007)16:3%3c241::aid-jhbs2300160306%3e3.0.co;2-o
[36]
Dehaene S., Changeux J. P., and Naccache L. (2011). The global neuronal workspace model of conscious access: From neuronal architectures to clinical applications. In Dehaene S. and Christen Y. (Eds.), Characterizing consciousness: From cognition to the clinic? (pp. 55–84). Springer.
[37]
De Leon D. (1997). The qualities of qualia. Lund University Cognitive Studies, 58, 1–10.
[38]
Dennett D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Little, Brown & Co.
[39]
Dewey J. (1910). How we think. D. C. Heath.
[40]
Di Paolo E. and De Jaegher H. (2012). The interactive brain hypothesis. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 6, Article 163. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2012.00163
[41]
Di Paolo E., Rohde M., and De Jaegher H. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction and play. In Stewart J., Gapenne O., and Di Paolo E. A. (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 33–87). MIT Press.
[42]
Di Paolo E., Thompson E., and Beer R. (2022). Laying down a forking path: Tensions between enaction and the free energy principle. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 3(2). https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2022.9187
[43]
Di Paolo E. A. (2009). Extended life. Topoi, 28(1), 9–21. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-008-9042-3
[44]
Doniger W. (1981). The rig veda. Penguin Books.
[45]
Dutta D. and Chandrasekharan S. (2017). Doing to being: Farming actions in a community coalesce into pro-environment motivations and values. Environmental Education Research, 24(8), 1192–1210. https://doi.org/10.1080/13504622.2017.1392485
[46]
Edelman G. M. and Gally J. A. (2013). Reentry: A key mechanism for integration of brain function. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 7, 63. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnint.2013.00063
[47]
Falk J., Eichler E., Windt K., and Hütt M.-T. (2022). Physics is organized around transformations connecting contextures in a polycontextural world. Foundations of Science, 27(1229–1251). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-021-09814-0
[48]
Feibleman J. K. (1954). Theory of integrative levels. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 5, 59–66. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/v.17.59
[49]
Fichte J. G. (1889). The science of knowledge (Kroeger A. E., Trans.). Trübner & Co.
[50]
Fiebich A. and Michael J. (2015). Mental actions and mental agency. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6(4), 683–693. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0289-5
[51]
Froese T. (2023). Irruption theory: A novel conceptualization of the enactive account of motivated activity. Entropy, 25(5), 748. https://doi.org/10.3390/e25050748
[52]
Froese T. and Sykes J. (2023). The pragmatics, embodiment, and efficacy of lived experience: Assessing the core tenets of Varela’s neurophenomenology. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 30(11), 190–213. https://doi.org/10.53765/20512201.30.11.190
[53]
Fuchs C. A. (2010). QBism, the perimeter of quantum bayesianism. arXiv: Quantum Physics. https://arxiv.org/abs/1003.5209
[54]
Fuchs T. (2011). The brain—a mediating organ. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(7-8), 196–221.
[55]
Gallagher S. (2003). Phenomenology and experimental design: Toward a phenomenologically enlightened experimental science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9-10), 85–99.
[56]
Gallotto S., Sack A. T., Schuhmann T., and de Graaf T. A. (2017). Oscillatory correlates of visual consciousness. Frontiers in Psychology, 8, 1147. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01147
[57]
Gebser J. (1986). The ever-present origin (Barstad N. and Mickunas A., Trans.). Ohio University Press.
[58]
Goethe J. W. (1988). Scientifc studies (Miller D., Ed. & Trans.). Suhrkamp.
[59]
Gomez-Marin A. and Arnau J. (2019). The false problem of consciousness. PhilSci-Archive. https://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/16804/
[60]
Gottwald S. (2022). Many-valued logic. In Zalta E. N. (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2022 edition). Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2022/entries/logic-manyvalued/
[61]
Günther G. (1978). Idee und Grundriss einer nicht-aristotelischen Logik [Idea and outline of a non-Aristotelian logic (2nd ed.). Felix meiner.
[62]
Hartmann N. (2017). New ways of ontology. Routledge.
[63]
Heck R. G. (2000). Non-conceptual content and the ‘space of reasons’. Philosophical Review, 109(4), 483–523. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-109-4-483
[64]
Heinämaa S. (2021). On the transcendental undercurrents of phenomenology: The case of the living body. Continental Philosophy Review, 54(2), 237–257. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-021-09534-z
[65]
Hohwy J. (2018). The predictive processing hypothesis. In Newen A., de Bruin L., and Gallagher S. (Eds.), The oxford handbook of 4E cognition (pp. 129–145). Oxford University Press.
[66]
Husserl E. (2001). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis. In Lectures on transcendental logic (Steinbock A. J., Trans.). Kluwer Academic Publishers.
[67]
Hutto D. D. and Myin E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. MIT Press.
[68]
Jansen T., von Schlippe A., and Vogd W. (2015). Contextural analysis—A proposal for reconstructive social research in organisational contexts. Forum: Qualitative Social Research, 16(1), Art.-4. http://www.qualitative-research.net/index.php/fqs/article/view/2200
[69]
Kammerer F. (2021). The illusion of conscious experience. Synthese, 198(1), 845–866. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02071-y
[70]
Kant I. (1987). Critique of judgment (Pluhar W. S., Trans.). Hackett.
[71]
Kant I. (2004). Metaphysical foundations of natural science (Friedman M., Trans. & ed.). Cambridge University Press.
[72]
Karoly P. (1999). A goal systems–self-regulatory perspective on personality, psychopathology, and change. Review of General Psychology, 3(4), 264–291. https://doi.org/10.1037//1089-2680.3.4.264
[73]
Kee H. (2021). Phenomenology and naturalism in autopoietic and radical enactivism: Exploring sense-making and continuity from the top down. Synthese, 198(S9), 2323–2343. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1851-3
[74]
Kirchhoff M. D. and Hutto D. D. (2016). Never mind the gap: Neurophenomenology, radical enactivism, and the hard problem of consciousness. Constructivist Foundations, 11(2), 346–353. https://constructivist.info/11/2/346
[75]
Kleene S. C. (1938). On notation for ordinal numbers. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 3(4), 150–155. https://doi.org/10.2307/2267778
[76]
Kleineberg M. (2017). Integrative levels. Reviews of Concepts in Knowledge Organization, 44(5), 349–379. https://doi.org/10.5771/0943-7444-2017-5-349
[77]
Konen C. S. and Kastner S. (2009). Neural transformation of object information by ventral pathway visual cortex. In Gazzaniga M. S. (Ed.), The cognitive neurosciences (4th ed., pp. 455–466). MIT Press.
[78]
Kornmeier J., Friedel E., Hecker L., Schmidt S., and Wittmann M. (2019). What happens in the brain of meditators when perception changes but not the stimulus? PLoS One, 14(10), Article e0223843. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0223843
[79]
Kriegel U. (2002). Phenomenal content. Erkenntnis, 57(2), 175–198. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1020901206350
[80]
Kriegel U. (2003). Consciousness as sensory quality and as implicit self-awareness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2(1), 1–26. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1022912206810
[81]
Lauber R. (2001) Was ist Information? [What is information?] Computer Aided Design of Dynamic Systems (Vol. 29, pp. 18–35). Scientific Papers of Donezk State Technical University.
[82]
Lewis T. J. and Rinzel J. (2000). Self-organized synchronous oscillations in a network of excitable cells coupled by gap junctions. Network (Bristol, England), 11(4), 299–320.
[83]
Lieberman D. A. (1979). Behaviorism and the Mind. A (limited) call for a return to introspection. American Psychologist, 34(4), 319–333. https://doi.org/10.1037//0003-066x.34.4.319
[84]
Lumma A.-L. and Weger U. W. (2021). Looking from within: Comparing first-person approaches to studying experience. Current Psychology, 42(12), 10437–10453. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12144-021-02277-3
[85]
Lyons W. (1986). The disappearance of introspection. MIT Press.
[86]
Maine de Biran F. P. G. (2021). Of immediate apperception (Sinclair M., Trans.). Bloomsbury.
[87]
Marbe K. (1901). Experimentell-psychologische Untersuchungen über das Urteil. Eine Einleitung in die Logik. Wilhelm Engelmann.
[88]
Marti P., Iacono I., Parlangeli O., and Stienstra J. (2020). Social coordination in human–robot interaction through reciprocal engagement. In Rehm M., Saldien J., and Manca S. (Eds.), Project and design literacy as cornerstones of smart education. Smart Innovation, Systems and Technologies (Vol. 158, pp. 273–285). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-13-9652-6_25
[89]
Maturana H. and Varela F. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition. The realization of the living. Reidel.
[90]
Melloni L., Molina C., Pena M., Torres D., Singer W., and Rodriguez E. (2007). Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas correlates with conscious perception. The Journal of neuroscience: the official journal of the Society for Neuroscience, 27(11), 2858–2865. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.4623-06.2007
[91]
Merleau-Ponty M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (Smith C., Trans.). Routledge Press.
[92]
Michel M., Beck D., Block N., Blumenfeld H., Brown R., Carmel D., Carrasco M., Chirimuuta M., Chun M., Cleeremans A., Dehaene S., Fleming S. M., Frith C., Haggard P., He B. J., Heyes C., Goodale M. A., Irvine L., Kawato M., and Yoshida M. (2019). Opportunities and challenges for a maturing science of consciousness. Nature Human Behaviour, 3(2), 104–107. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-019-0531-8
[93]
Mindt G. (2017). The problem with the ‘information’ in integrated information theory. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 24(7–8), 30–54.
[94]
Mylopoulos M. I. (2015). Agentive awareness is not sensory awareness. Philosophical Studies, 172(3), 761–780. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0332-x
[95]
Nagel T. (1986). The view from nowhere. Oxford University Press.
[96]
Nave O., Trautwein F.-M., Ataria Y., Dor-ziderman Y., Schweitzer Y., Fulder S., and Berkovich-Ohana A. (2021). Self-boundary dissolution in meditation: A phenomenological investigation. Brain Sciences, 11(6), 819–832. https://doi.org/10.3390/brainsci11060819
[97]
Newen A., de Bruin L., and Gallagher S. (Eds.), (2018). The Oxford handbook of 4e cognition. Oxford University Press.
[98]
Noë A. (2004). Action in perception. MIT Press.
[99]
Oevermann U. (2005). Natural utopianism in everyday life practice-an elementary theoretical model. In Reiger T. W. (Ed.), Thinking utopia: Steps into other worlds (pp. 136–148). Berghahn Books.
[100]
O’Shaughnessy B. (2000). Consciousness and the world. Oxford University Press.
[101]
Papineau D. (2001). The rise of physicalism. In Gillet C. and Loewer B. (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 3–36). Cambridge University Press.
[102]
Peacocke C. (2001). Does perception have a nonconceptual content? The Journal of Philosophy, 98(5), 239–264. https://doi.org/10.2307/2678383
[103]
Pecere P. (2020). Reconsidering the ignorabimus: du Bois-Reymond and the hard problem of consciousness. Science in Context, 33(1), 1–18. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0269889720000095
[104]
Perna A., Tosetti M., Montanaro D., and Morrone M. C. (2008). BOLD response to spatial phase congruency in human brain. Journal of vision, 8(10), 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1167/8.10.15
[105]
Petitmengin C. (2017). Enaction as a lived experience. Constructivist Foundations, 12(2), 101–127. http://constructivist.info/12/2/139
[106]
Petitot J. (1999). Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science. Stanford University Press.
[107]
Pinto Y. and Stein T. (2021). The hard problem makes the easy problems hard - a reply to Doerig et al. Cognitive Neuroscience, 12(2), 97–98. https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1838469
[108]
Plessner H. (2019). Levels of organic life and the human: An introduction to philosophical anthropology (Hyatt M., Trans.). Fordham University Press.
[109]
Posner M. I. and Petersen S. E. (1990). The attention system of the human brain. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 13(1), 25–42. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.ne.13.030190.000325
[110]
Proust J. (2015). The representational structure of feelings. In Metzinger T. and Windt J. M. (Eds.), OpenMind. Johannes-Gutenberg Universität. (Frankfurt a. M.). https://doi.org/10.25358/openscience-77
[111]
Ramm B. J. (2018). First-person experiments: A characterisation and defence. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 9(3), 449–467. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0388-1
[112]
Rietveld E., Denys D. A., and Westen M. V. (2018). Ecological-Enactive Cognition as engaging with a field of relevant affordances. In Newen A., de Bruin L., and Gallagher S. (Eds.), The oxford handbook of 4E cognition (pp. 41–70). Oxford University Press.
[113]
Ringach D. L. (2002). Spatial structure and symmetry of simple-cell receptive fields in macaque primary visual cortex. Journal of neurophysiology, 88(1), 455–463. https://doi.org/10.1152/jn.2002.88.1.455
[114]
Rombach H. (1980). Phänomenologie des gegenwärtigen Bewusstseins. Alber.
[115]
Rowlands M. (2018). Disclosing the world: Intentionality and 4E cognition. In Newen A., de Bruin L., and Gallagher S. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of 4e cognition (pp. 335–352). Oxford University Press.
[116]
Ryle G. (2009). The concept of mind (60th anniversary edition). Routledge.
[117]
Saxe G. N., Calderone D., and Morales L. J. (2018). Brain entropy and human intelligence: A resting-state fMRI study. PLoS One, 13(2), Article e0191582. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0191582
[118]
Schwitzgebel E. (2008). The unreliability of naïve introspection. Philosophical Review, 117(2), 245–273. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2007-037
[119]
Sharma C. (2003). A critical survey of Indian philosophy. Motilal Banarsidass.
[120]
Singer W. (1993). Synchronization of cortical activity and its putative role in information processing and learning. Annual Review of Physiology, 55, 349–374. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.ph.55.030193.002025
[121]
Small M. (2011). How to conduct a mixed methods study: Recent trends in a rapidly growing literature. Annual Review of Sociology, 37(1), 57–86. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.soc.012809.102657
[122]
Steiner R. (1964). The philosophy of freedom. (Wilson M., Trans.). Rudolf Steiner Press.
[123]
Steiner R. (1972). An outline of occult science (Monges M. and Monges B., Trans.). Anthroposophic Press.
[124]
Steiner R. (1988). The science of knowing: Outline of an epistemology implicit in the Goethean world view (1st ed.: 1886). Mercury Press.
[125]
Stilwell P. and Harman K. (2021). Phenomenological research needs to be renewed: Time to integrate enactivism as a flexible resource. International Journal of Qualitative Methods, 2(2), Article 160940692199529. https://doi.org/10.1177/1609406921995299
[126]
Taipale J. (2021). Being carried away: Fink and Winnicott on the locus of playing. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 52(2), 193–217. https://doi.org/10.1163/15691624-12341391
[127]
Tewari S. G., Gottipati M. K., and Parpura V. (2016). Mathematical modeling in neuroscience: Neuronal activity and its modulation by astrocytes. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 10(3), 3. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnint.2016.00003
[128]
Thomas N. J. T. (2009). Visual imagery and consciousness. In Banks W. P. (Ed.), Encyclopedia of consciousness (pp. 445–457). Academic Press.
[129]
Thompson E., Lutz A., and Cosmelli D. (2005). Neurophenomenology: An introduction for neurophilosophers. In Brook A. and Akins K. (Eds.), Cognition and the brain: The philosophy and neuroscience movement (pp. 40–97). Cambridge University Press.
[130]
Thompson E. and Stapleton M. (2009). Making sense of sense-making: Reflections on enactive and extended mind theories. Topoi, 28(1), 23–30.
[131]
Tomasello M. (2019). Becoming human: A theory of ontogeny. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
[132]
Tononi G., Boly M., Massimini M., and Koch C. (2016). Integrated information theory: From consciousness to its physical substrate. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 17(7), 450–461. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn.2016.44
[133]
Treisman A. (2002). Features and objects in visual processing. In Levitin D. J. (Ed.), Foundations of cognitive psychology: Core readings (pp. 207–226). MIT Press.
[134]
Tye M. (2006). Absent qualia and the mind-body problem. Philosophical Review, 115(2), 139–168. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2005-013
[135]
van Geen C. and De Vignemont F. (Eds.), (2006). The structure of nonconceptual content. European Review of Philosophy (Vol. 6). CSLI Publications.
[136]
Varela F. J. (1995). Resonant cell assemblies: A new approach to cognitive functions and neuronal synchrony. Biological Research, 28(1), 81–95.
[137]
Varela F. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(4), 330–849.
[138]
Varela F. J., Thompson E., and Rosch E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press.
[139]
Vicente A. (2006). On the causal completeness of physics. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 20(2), 149–171. https://doi.org/10.1080/02698590600814332
[140]
von Foerster H. (2003). Understanding understanding. Springer.
[141]
Wagemann J. (2010). Gehirn und menschliches Bewusstsein – Neuromythos und Strukturphänomenologie [Brain and human consciousness – Neuromyth and structure phenomenology]. Shaker.
[142]
Wagemann J. (2011). The structure-phenomenological concept of brain-consciousness correlation. Mind and Matter, 9, 185–204.
[143]
Wagemann J. (2020). Mental action and emotion—what happens in the mind when the stimulus changes but not the perceptual intention. New Ideas in Psychology, 56, Article 100747. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2019.100747
[144]
Wagemann J. (2022a). Bridging anthroposophy and cognitive science with an experimental first-person method. Steiner Studies, 3(1), 36. https://doi.org/10.0000/STS.951000340-11
[145]
Wagemann J. (2022b). Exploring the structure of mental action in directed thought. Philosophical Psychology, 35(2), 145–176. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2021.1951195
[146]
Wagemann J. (2023). Voluntary auditory change: First-person access to agentive aspects of attention regulation. Current Psychology, 42(18), 15169–15185. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12144-021-02662-y
[147]
Wagemann J., Edelhäuser F., and Weger U. (2018). Outer and inner dimensions of brain and consciousness—refining and integrating the phenomenal layers. Advances in Cognitive Psychology, 14(4), 167–185. https://doi.org/10.5709/acp-0248-2
[148]
Wagemann J. and Raggatz J. (2021). First-Person dimensions of mental agency in visual counting of moving objects. Cognitive Processing, 22(3), 453–473. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10339-021-01020-x
[149]
Wagemann J., Tewes C., and Raggatz J. (2022). Wearing face masks impairs dyadic micro-activities in nonverbal social encounter. A mixed-methods first-person study on the sense of I and Thou. Frontiers in Psychology, 13, Article 983652. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.983652
[150]
Wagemann J. and Walter A. (2024). Consciously choosing and shaping what to comprehend: A mixed-methods approach to first-person aspects of mental agency in ambiguous speech perception. Current Psychology, 43(19), 17500–17524. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12144-024-05614-4
[151]
Wagemann J. and Weger U. (2021). Perceiving the other self: An experimental first-person account of nonverbal social interaction. American Journal of Psychology, 134(4), 441–461. https://doi.org/10.5406/amerjpsyc.134.4.0441
[152]
Waldenfels B. (2011). Phenomenology of the alien: Basic concepts. Northwestern University Press.
[153]
Ward L. (2003). Synchronous neural oscillations and cognitive processes. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(12), 553–559. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2003.10.012
[154]
Watzl S. (2017). Structuring mind. The nature of attention and how it shapes consciousness. Oxford University Press.
[155]
Watzl S. (2018). Consciousness and no self? Ratio, 31(4), 363–375. https://doi.org/10.1111/rati.12216
[156]
Weber A. and Varela F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.
[157]
Weger U. and Wagemann J. (2015). The challenges and opportunities of first-person inquiry in experimental psychology. New Ideas in Psychology, 36, 38–49. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2014.09.001
[158]
Werning M., Tacca M., and Mroczko-Wasowicz A. (2013). High- vs low-level cognition and the neuro-emulative theory of mental representation. In Gähde U., Hartmann S., and Wolf J. H. (Eds.), Models, simulations, and the reduction of complexity (pp. 141–152). DeGruyter.
[159]
Whitehead C. (2010). Cultural distortions of self- and reality-perception. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 17(7-8), 95–118.
[160]
Wiener N. (1948). Cybernetics; or control and communication in the animal and the machine. John Wiley.
[161]
Witzenmann H. (1983). Strukturphänomenologie. Vorbewusstes Gestaltbilden im erkennenden Wirklichkeitsenthüllen. Gideon Spicker.
[162]
Witzenmann H. (Ed.) (2022). Structure phenomenology. Preconscious formation in the epistemic disclosure of reality (Vine T. and Wagemann J., Trans.). Bloomsbury Academic.
[163]
Wu W. (2014). Attention. Routledge.
[164]
Wundt W. (1907). Über Ausfrageexperimente und über die Methoden zur Psychologie des Denkens. Psychological Studies, 3, 301–360.
[165]
Zahavi D. (2017). Husserl’s legacy: Phenomenology, metaphysics, and transcendental philosophy. Oxford University Press.
[166]
Zeman A. (2001). Consciousness. Brain: Journal of Neurology, 124(Pt 7), 1263–1289. https://doi.org/10.1093/brain/124.7.1263

Recommendations

Comments

Information & Contributors

Information

Published In

cover image Adaptive Behavior - Animals, Animats, Software Agents, Robots, Adaptive Systems
Adaptive Behavior - Animals, Animats, Software Agents, Robots, Adaptive Systems  Volume 33, Issue 1
Feb 2025
76 pages
This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 License (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/) which permits non-commercial use, reproduction and distribution of the work without further permission provided the original work is attributed as specified on the SAGE and Open Access page (https://us.sagepub.com/en-us/nam/open-access-at-sage).

Publisher

Sage Publications, Inc.

United States

Publication History

Published: 01 February 2025

Author Tags

  1. First-person methodology
  2. structure phenomenology
  3. transclassical logic
  4. enactivism
  5. neurophenomenology
  6. negative phenomenality and agentive qualia

Qualifiers

  • Research-article

Contributors

Other Metrics

Bibliometrics & Citations

Bibliometrics

Article Metrics

  • 0
    Total Citations
  • 0
    Total Downloads
  • Downloads (Last 12 months)0
  • Downloads (Last 6 weeks)0
Reflects downloads up to 25 Jan 2025

Other Metrics

Citations

View Options

View options

Figures

Tables

Media

Share

Share

Share this Publication link

Share on social media