Abstract
In Kleinberg and Weiss, Math Soc Sci 12:21–30 (1986b), the authors used the representation theory of the symmetric groups to characterize the space of linear and symmetric values. We call such values “membership” values, as a player’s payoff depends on the worths of the coalitions to which he belongs and not necessarily on his marginal contributions. This could mean that the player would get some share of \(v(N)\) regardless of whether or not he makes a marginal contribution to the welfare of society. In this paper it is demonstrated that the set of (non-marginal) membership values include those that embody numerous widely held notions of fairness, such as partial “benefit equalization”, individual rationality and “greater rewards follow from greater contributions”, where one’s contributions are not measured marginally. We also present a very simple and revealing way of interpreting all values, including those having a marginal interpretation. Finally, we obtain a mapping which effectively embeds the space of marginal values in the space of all membership values.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
The name arises naturally from the nature of our first example below.
For a collection of players \(i,\;1 \le i \le n\), a game \(v\) and a coalition \(S \subset \{1,\ldots ,n\}\), we let \(v(S)\) represent the worth of \(S\). Abusing notation, we set \(v(i) = v(\{i\})\) and let \(N\) stand for the grand coalition.
The implications of allowing for input and output or benefit differences has been studied by Arrow (1971), from a utilitarian perspective.
In addition, we are assuming that transfers across players are limited. Otherwise, those most capable of producing utility would get all the inputs and with these they would produce the greatest output. This output would then be reallocated, favoring those “less able to produce benefits”.
To simplify notation, below we will refer to both \(\mathop {\mathop {\sum \nolimits _{{\#S=k}}}\limits _{i \in S}}\frac{v(S)-A(v,k)}{{\small \left( \begin{array}{l} {n-1} \\ {k-1} \end{array} \right) }}\) and \(\mathop {\mathop {\sum \nolimits _{{\#S=k}}}\limits _{i \in S}}(v(S) - A(v,k))\) as player \(i\)’s “variance”.
We thank an anonymous referee for raising this concern.
This fact can be easily inferred from Proposition 1 below.
For an introduction to the relevant theory one may refer to Curtis and Reiner (1962, Chap. 2).
Also known as the equal surplus division (ESD) solution.
The impact of other axioms (e.g. projection, monotonicity, \(\beta \)-efficiency and Roth (1977) strategic risk neutrality axiom) on the constants (\(\{c_0^{k}\}^n_{k=1},\;\{c_1^{k}\}^{n-1}_{k=1}\)) has been explored in Kleinberg and Weiss (1984; 1985a; 1986b), to which we refer the interested reader.
References
Arrow KJ (1971) A utilitarian approach to the concept of equality in public expenditures. Q J Econ 85: 409–415
Aumann RJ, Shapley LS (1974) Values of non-atomic games. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Chun Y, Park B (2012) Population solidarity, population fair-ranking and the egalitarian value. Int J Game Theory 41:255–270
Coleman JS (1968) The concept of equality of educational opportunity. Harvard Educ Rev 38:14–22
Curtis CW, Reiner I (1962) Representation theory of finite groups and associative algebras. Wiley, New York
Driessen TSH, Funaki Y (1997) Reduced game properties of egalitarian division rules for TU-games. In: Parthasarathy et al. (eds) Game theoretical applications to economics and operations research. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, pp 85–103
Dubey P, Neyman A, Weber RJ (1981) Value theory without efficiency. Math Oper Res 6:122–128
Hernández-Lamoneda L, Juárez R, Sánchez-Sánchez F (2007) Dissection of solutions in cooperative game theory using representation techniques. Int J Game Theory 35:395–426
Kultti K, Salonen H (2007) Minimum norm solutions for cooperative games. Int J Game Theory 35:591–602
Kleinberg NL, Weiss JH (1984) Is a value a marginal concept? Working paper. Baruch College Department of Economics & Finance, New York
Kleinberg NL, Weiss JH (1985a) Equivalent n-person games and the null space of the Shapley value. Math Oper Res 10:233–243
Kleinberg NL, Weiss JH (1985b) A new formula for the Shapley value. Econ Lett 17:311–315
Kleinberg NL, Weiss JH (1986a) The orthogonal decomposition of games and an averaging formula for the Shapley value. Math Oper Res 11:117–124
Kleinberg NL, Weiss JH (1986b) Weak values, the core and new axioms for the Shapley value. Math Soc Sci 12:21–30
Malawski M (2002) Equal treatment, symmetry and Banzhaf value axiomatizations. Int J Game Theory 31:47–67
Moulin H (1985) The separability axiom and equal-sharing methods. J Econ Theory 36:120–148
Roth A (1977) The Shapley value as a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility. Econometrica 45:657–664
Ruiz LM, Velenciano F, Zarzuelo JM (1996) The least square prenucleolus and the least square nucleolus: two values for TU games based on the excess vector. Int J Game Theory 25:113–134
Shapley LS (1953) A value for n-person games. Ann Math Stud 28:307–317
van den Brink R, Funaki Y (2009) Axiomatizations of a class of equal surplus sharing solutions for TU-games. Theory Decis 67:303–340
van den Brink R (2007) Null or nullifying players: the difference between the Shapley value and equal division solutions. J Econ Theory 136:767–775
Young HP (1985) Monotonic solutions of cooperative games. Int J Game Theory 14:65–72
Acknowledgments
The authors would like to thank the Editor, an Associate Editor and an anonymous referee for comments and suggestions that significantly improved this paper. Another Associate Editor’s worked-out examples of the solutions presented in Sect. 2 were invaluable in enabling us to derive general formulas for the coefficients. We also thank Michael Rothschild for his motivational role in the genesis of this paper.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Appendix
Appendix
As preparation for the results below, we shall require some tools and definitions. Define, for each \(k, \; 1 \le k \le n\), the map:
and then set \(\mathfrak{M }^k = L^k \mathfrak G \). Clearly, each \(\mathfrak{M }^k\) is isomorphic to \(R^{{\small \left( \begin{array}{l} {n} \\ {k} \end{array}\right) }}\), and may be viewed as a sub-module of \(\mathfrak G \) under the action (3); note that then \(\mathfrak G = \oplus \sum _{k=1}^n \mathfrak{M }^k\). Next let, for each \(k, \; 1 \le k \le n\), and any MV \(T, \; {\tilde{T}}^k \equiv T|_{\mathfrak{M }^k}\); observe that, for any \(v \in \mathfrak G \),
and set \(T^k = L^k \circ {\tilde{T}}^k\). Finally, let \(\Pi _0^{k}\) denote the orthogonal projection of \(\mathfrak{M }^k\) onto \(L^k(\mathfrak{I _0}^\perp )\) and \(\Pi _1^k\) the orthogonal projection of \(\mathfrak{M }^k\) onto \(L^k \left( \mathfrak{I }_0 \right) \). The maps
are each univalent and, for given \(k\), take the diagonal \(\Delta \subset R^n\) onto \(L^k(\mathfrak{I _0}^\perp )\) and \(\Delta ^\perp \) (the vectors whose coordinates sum to zero) onto \(L^k(\mathfrak{I _0})\). Since, for each vector \(v \in \Delta ^\perp ,\,v(i)\) appears exactly \(\left( \begin{array}{l} {n-1} \\ {k-1} \end{array}\right) \) times in \(\phi ^k(v)\), the sum of the coordinates of \(\phi ^k(v)\) is zero as well, showing that \(L^k(\mathfrak{I _0}^\perp ) = L^k(\mathfrak{I _0})^\perp \). Thus, in particular, for each coalition size \(k\) and every \(w \in L^k(\mathfrak I ),\;w = (\Pi _0^{k} + \Pi _1^k)w\) (orthogonal sum). We then have
Lemma 1
For each \(k, \; 1 \le k \le n-1\) and \(v \in \mathfrak{M }^k\), there exist unique games \(\xi ^0(v,k) \in \mathfrak{I _0}^\perp \) and \(\xi ^1(v,k) \in \mathfrak{I }_0\) such that
The maps
are each \(R \mathfrak{S }_n\)-homomorphisms determined by the formulae:
Proof
Define, for each \(k, \; 1 \le k \le n-1\),
We observe that \(\theta ^k\) is an \(R \mathfrak{S }_n\)-isomorphism carrying \(L^1 \left( \mathfrak{I }_0 \right) \) onto \(L^k \left( \mathfrak{I }_0 \right) \) and \(L^1\left( \mathfrak{I _0}^\perp \right) \) onto \(L^k\left( \mathfrak{I _0}^\perp \right) \) (Kleinberg and Weiss 1985a, Proposition 4). This shows that, for each \(k\), the maps \(\xi ^0(\cdot ,k): \mathfrak{M }^k \longrightarrow L^k(\mathfrak{I _0}^\perp )\) and \(\xi ^1(\cdot ,k): \mathfrak{M }^k \longrightarrow L^k(\mathfrak{I }_0)\) exist and are the unique \(R \mathfrak{S }_n\)-homomorphisms determined by:
(note that \(\Pi _0^{k}\) and \(\Pi _1^{k}\) are \(R\mathfrak{S }_n\)-homomorphisms as orthogonal projections onto the invariant subspaces \(\mathfrak{I _0}^\perp \) and \(\mathfrak{I }_0\), respectively). Thus it remains only to demonstrate the formulae.
Towards this end we first observe that, if \(v \in L^k \left( \mathfrak{I _0}^\perp \right) \), then all coalitions of size \(k\) receive the same worth in \(v\) so that, clearly,
Next, suppose that \(v \in L^k \left( \mathfrak{I }_0 \right) \). Then, for any \(i, \; 1 \le i \le n\),
where the last equality follows from the fact observed above that \(v \in L^k \left( \mathfrak{I }_0 \right) \) if and only if \((\theta ^k)^{-1}v \in L^1 \left( \mathfrak{I }_0 \right) \). Thus, for \(v \in L^k\left( \mathfrak{I }_0 \right) \),
Now let \(v \in \mathfrak{M }^k\), and define the game \(A_k(v) = \Pi _0^{k}v\). For clearly \(A_k(v) \in L^k \left( \mathfrak{I _0}^\perp \right) \), and \(\sum _{\#S=k} [ v(S) - A_k(v)(S) ] = 0\), so that \((v - A_k(v)) \perp L^k \left( \mathfrak{I _0}^\perp \right) \). Hence, by (10) and (11),
Since, as was observed above, \(w = (\Pi _0^{k} + \Pi _1^{k})w\) for every \(w \in L^k(\mathfrak I )\), we can set \(v = w + z\), where \(w \equiv (\Pi _0^{k} + \Pi _1^{k})v\) and \(z \equiv v - w = v - \Pi _0^{k}v - \Pi _1^{k}v = \Pi _{ \mathfrak{B }}^{k}v\) (here \(\Pi ^k_{ \mathfrak{B }}\) is the orthogonal projection of \(\mathfrak{M }^k\) onto \(\mathfrak{M }^k \bigcap L^k\left( \mathfrak{I }\right) ^{\perp } \equiv \mathfrak{B }^k\), see the discussion after the statement of the Theorem). Thus \(\Pi _1^{k}v = v - \Pi _0^{k}v - \Pi _{ \mathfrak{B }}^{k} v\).
Now by the definition of the \(\mathfrak{B }^k,\,{\sum _{\begin{array}{l}{\#S=k}\\ {i \in S}\end{array}}} \Pi ^k_\mathfrak{B } v(S) = 0\); hence
Therefore we may conclude
\(\square \)
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Kleinberg, N.L., Weiss, J.H. On membership and marginal values. Int J Game Theory 42, 357–373 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-013-0367-9
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-013-0367-9