Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
skip to main content
article
Free access

Lessons from a restricted Turing test

Published: 01 June 1994 Publication History
First page of PDF

References

[1]
Arbib, M. A. More on cornputer models of psychopathic bchavior. Commun. ACM 17, 9 (Sept, I974), 543.
[2]
B lock, N. Psychologism and behaviorism, Phios. Rev. 90, 1 (1981 ), 543.
[3]
Block, N. The computer model of the mind. In An lntroduction to Cognitive Science Ill: Thinking, D. N. Osherson and E. E. Smith, Eds. M IT Press, Cambridge, Mass., I990, pp. 147-289.
[4]
Colby, K. M. Modeling a paranoid mind. Behav. Brain Sci. 4, 4, (1981), 515-560,
[5]
Colby, K. M. Hilf, F. D., Weber, S., and Kraemer, M. C. Turing-like indistinguishability tests for the validation of a computer simulation of paranoid processes. Artif. IntelI. 3, 1 (I972), 199-221.
[6]
Dennett, D. C. Can machines think. In How we Know. Michael Shafto, Ed. Harper and Row, San Francisco, Calif., 1985, pp. 121-145.
[7]
Dreyfus, H. L., Alchemy and artificial intelligence. P. 324.4, The RAND Corporation, 1965.
[8]
Dreyfus, H. What Computers Can't Do. A Critiqu of Artifficial Reason. Harper and Row, New. York, 1979.
[9]
Epsiein, R. The quest for the thinking Computer. AI Mag. 13,2,1992, 81- 91.
[10]
Fodor, J. Psychologcal Explanation. Random House, New York, I968, pp. 126-127,
[11]
French, R, Subcognition and tile limits of the Turing test. Mind 99, 393. (Jan. 1990), 53-65.
[12]
Gibbs-Smith, C. H. Leonardo da Vinci's Aeronautics. Her Majesty's Stationery Office, London, 1967.
[13]
Gomes, L. Computer fools half of human panel. San Jose Mercury News, Nov. 9, 1991, IA, 16A.
[14]
Grosser, M. Gossamer Odyssey, Michael,joseph, London., 1981.
[15]
Gunderson, K. Mentality and Machines. Doubleday and Company, Inc., New York, 1971.
[16]
Krasner, J. Experts try to tell man from machine. Boston Herald Nov. 9, 1991, 2I, 23.
[17]
Lindquist, C. Quest for machines that think, Computerworld (Nov. 18, 1991).
[18]
Moor, J. H. Turing test. In Encyclopedia of Artificial Intelligence, Stuart C. Shapiro, Ed. John Wiley and Sons, New York, 1987, pp. 1126- 1130.
[19]
Moor, J. H. Explaining computer behavior. Philos. Stud. 34, 3 (1978), 325-327.
[20]
Moor, J. H. An anaIysis of the Turing test., Philos. Stud. 30, 4 (1976), 249- 257.
[21]
Neal, J. G. and Walter, S. M. Natural language processing systems evaluation workshop. Tech. Rep. RL-TR-9I- 362, Rome Lab., Griffiss Air Force Base, Rome. N.Y. 1991.
[22]
Reay, D. A. The History of Man-Powered Flight. Pergamon. Press, Oxford, 1977.
[23]
Searle, J. R. Can computers think. In Minds, Brains, and Science, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1984, pp. 28-41.
[24]
Searle, J. R. Minds, brains, and programs. Behav, Brain Sci. 3. 3 (1980), 417-457.
[25]
Stalker, D. F. Why machines can't think: A reply to.James Moor. Philos. Stud. 34, 3 (1978), 317-320.
[26]
Stipp, D. Some computers manage to fool people at game of imitating human beings. Wall Street J. Nov. 11, 1991, p. B3A.
[27]
The Guardian. Machines meet mastermind. Aug. 29, 1991.
[28]
Turing, A. M. Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind 59, 236 (Oct. 1950), 433--460.
[29]
Weizenbaum, J. computer Power and Human Reason. W. H. Freeman, San Francisco, 1976.
[30]
Weizenbaum, J. Reply to Arbib: More on computer rnodels of psychopathic behavior. Commun. ACM 17, 9 (Sept. 1974), 543.
[31]
Weizenbaum, J. Automating psychotherapy. Commun. ACM 17, 7 (July I974). 425.

Cited By

View all
  • (2024)My AI students: Evaluating the proficiency of three AI chatbots in completeness and accuracyContemporary Educational Technology10.30935/cedtech/1456416:2(ep509)Online publication date: 2024
  • (2024)The Origins of Generative AI in Transcription and Machine Translation, and Why That MattersCritical AI10.1215/2834703X-112568532:1Online publication date: 1-Apr-2024
  • (2024)Beyond Chatbot-K: On Large Language Models, “Generative AI,” and Rise of Chatbots—An IntroductionCritical AI10.1215/2834703X-112051472:1Online publication date: 1-Apr-2024
  • Show More Cited By

Recommendations

Reviews

Mark Halpern

The Loebner Prize competition, as I will assume the reader merely needs to be reminded, is an annual competition held since 1991, whose purpose is to encourage the development of a program that will successfully pass the Turing Test. The three closely related documents under review are a paper by Shieber assessing the scientific value of the Loebner Prize competition; a rebuttal by Loebner, donor of the prize; and a rejoinder by Shieber to Loebner. In his opening paper, Shieber makes it clear that he has the greatest misgivings about the validity of the Turing Test even when taken in its full rigor, but he deliberately waives his doubts on that score for purposes of considering the usefulness of the pared-down version of the Turing Test that Loebner has subsidized. In this paper, he accepts the Turing Test for purposes of argument, and limits himself almost entirely to showing that the severely limited version of the Turing Test on which the competition is based is irreparably flawed as a working model of the Turing Test, whatever the test's own flaws may be. In so narrowing his scope, he forgoes the chance to examine the deeper and (to me) more interesting questions about the Turing Test, but this sacrifice enables him to focus sharply on the Loebner Prize competition. Shieber's motive in inquiring into the competition is, he tells us, a desire to correct two abuses: first, the cost is not, as casual observers might easily think, all borne by Loebner; public money is involved too (specifically, National Science Foundation funds). Second, the nature of the competition, and the publicity given it, may have the effect of warping the direction taken by projects in computer science and AI, and<__?__Pub Caret> the public perception of such projects. Shieber, who took part as a referee in the first competition in 1991, and who is acquainted with many of the personalities involved, gives some interesting and colorful behind-the-scenes details of that event. The main value of his paper, though, lies in his analysis of the logic of the competition (and often, by implication if not explicitly, of the Turing Test). There is nothing startlingly original, it may be said at once, in that analysis; it is in the same vein as that by Eric Weiss and me [1], for example. Shieber says, in summary, that the structure of the competition virtually guarantees what we have seen in the three annual competitions held so far: the competing programs are of very low quality; they represent no advance whatever in AI, but rely (in particular, the program that has won all three so far relies) on shallow trickery whose success in fooling some people is better explained by Barnum than by Babbage. He concludes this paper by suggesting what he calls an improved and restructured Loebner Prize competition that might actually have some scientific value, but here he is merely being kind; what he is actually suggesting is not a patched-up but still recognizable Loebner Prize competition, but an utterly different sort of competition that would share with the present competition only its name. Loebner, in his response, opens with a trumpet blast—a slightly off-key blast. “Shieber,” he writes, “proposes to tell me how I should spend my money.” Shieber does no such thing; he does indeed regret what he sees as a waste of private funds, but he nowhere suggests that Loebner has no right to spend his own money as he wishes, waste or not. Then Loebner addresses the question, “Why a Loebner Prize__?__” which Shieber had used as a section title in his own paper, but somehow picks it up by the wrong end. He seems to think Shieber was asking, “What were the circumstances in which Loebner conceived the Loebner Prize competition__?__” when he was really asking, “What is the justification for the Loebner Prize competition__?__” A large part of what Loebner writes in this misdirected attempt at a reply is of little interest except to those who care about his private history. The rest deals with notions for improving the competition that are relatively trivial or marginal; he is dealing with a report by a structural engineer that says his house is unsound and must be demolished, and in response proposes to give that house a fresh coat of paint, discussing the advantages of one color over another. His response to Shieber culminates in the remarkable statement that the reader wanting a full discussion of the “lessons we have learned from our restricted Turing Test” should “see Shieber's companion article…”; remarkable because Shieber's conclusions are that the Loebner Prize competition has no lessons of value to teach us (unless we are connoisseurs of human gullibility), and ought to be changed so radically that what is really proposed is outright abolition. That Loebner imagines that the competition finds support in Shieber's piece suggests a more-than-ordinary failure of communication. In his brief reply to Loebner, Shieber tries to correct several of the misunderstandings I have just mentioned. His effort to set Loebner straight is understandable, but probably futile; he can take comfort, though, in knowing that any careful reader of the two earlier papers will have made the same observations. Incidentally, Shieber thanks a distinguished galaxy of scientists and scholars for reading early drafts of his main paper, but they have not served him as well as they might; none of them caught his statement that “humankind has dreamed of mimicking the power of human thought”; nor his calling the Turing Test a “litmus test” of human intelligence, when he has repeatedly emphasized that the Turing Test is a binary, yes-or-no test; nor such nonstandard English as “I am not ostentatious enough to provide examples….” But these are very minor blemishes; Shieber has performed a service in setting forth at length the real and serious flaws in the Loebner Prize competition, and has made it a little harder in the future for showmanship and publicity-seeking to subvert science.

Access critical reviews of Computing literature here

Become a reviewer for Computing Reviews.

Comments

Information & Contributors

Information

Published In

cover image Communications of the ACM
Communications of the ACM  Volume 37, Issue 6
June 1994
73 pages
ISSN:0001-0782
EISSN:1557-7317
DOI:10.1145/175208
Issue’s Table of Contents
Permission to make digital or hard copies of all or part of this work for personal or classroom use is granted without fee provided that copies are not made or distributed for profit or commercial advantage and that copies bear this notice and the full citation on the first page. Copyrights for components of this work owned by others than ACM must be honored. Abstracting with credit is permitted. To copy otherwise, or republish, to post on servers or to redistribute to lists, requires prior specific permission and/or a fee. Request permissions from [email protected]

Publisher

Association for Computing Machinery

New York, NY, United States

Publication History

Published: 01 June 1994
Published in CACM Volume 37, Issue 6

Permissions

Request permissions for this article.

Check for updates

Qualifiers

  • Article

Contributors

Other Metrics

Bibliometrics & Citations

Bibliometrics

Article Metrics

  • Downloads (Last 12 months)121
  • Downloads (Last 6 weeks)23
Reflects downloads up to 10 Nov 2024

Other Metrics

Citations

Cited By

View all
  • (2024)My AI students: Evaluating the proficiency of three AI chatbots in completeness and accuracyContemporary Educational Technology10.30935/cedtech/1456416:2(ep509)Online publication date: 2024
  • (2024)The Origins of Generative AI in Transcription and Machine Translation, and Why That MattersCritical AI10.1215/2834703X-112568532:1Online publication date: 1-Apr-2024
  • (2024)Beyond Chatbot-K: On Large Language Models, “Generative AI,” and Rise of Chatbots—An IntroductionCritical AI10.1215/2834703X-112051472:1Online publication date: 1-Apr-2024
  • (2024)Our Dialogue System Sucks - but Luckily we are at the Top of the Leaderboard!: A Discussion on Current Practices in NLP EvaluationProceedings of the 6th ACM Conference on Conversational User Interfaces10.1145/3640794.3665889(1-5)Online publication date: 8-Jul-2024
  • (2024)Turing’s Test, a Beautiful Thought ExperimentIEEE Annals of the History of Computing10.1109/MAHC.2024.343227846:3(36-49)Online publication date: 1-Jul-2024
  • (2023)Cognitive Robotics: Integrating Artificial Intelligence and Embodied Intelligence for Advanced Problem SolvingJournal of Artificial Intelligence and Capsule Networks10.36548/jaicn.2023.4.0025:4(462-480)Online publication date: Dec-2023
  • (2023)A Definition and a Test for Human-Level Artificial Intelligence2023 IEEE Symposium Series on Computational Intelligence (SSCI)10.1109/SSCI52147.2023.10372029(115-120)Online publication date: 5-Dec-2023
  • (2023)“Machine Down”: making sense of human–computer interaction—Garfinkel’s research on ELIZA and LYRIC from 1967 to 1969 and its contemporary relevanceAI & SOCIETY10.1007/s00146-023-01793-zOnline publication date: 21-Nov-2023
  • (2023)Research and Application Status of Text Generation Tasks Based on Generative Adversarial NetworkIEIS 202210.1007/978-981-99-3618-2_11(109-122)Online publication date: 5-Aug-2023
  • (2023)Video Turing TestAI Magazine10.1002/aaai.1212844:4(537-554)Online publication date: 8-Dec-2023
  • Show More Cited By

View Options

View options

PDF

View or Download as a PDF file.

PDF

eReader

View online with eReader.

eReader

Get Access

Login options

Full Access

Media

Figures

Other

Tables

Share

Share

Share this Publication link

Share on social media