Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Criticism of libertarianism

Criticism of libertarianism includes ethical, economic, environmental and pragmatic concerns. With right-libertarianism, critics have argued that laissez-faire capitalism does not necessarily produce the best or most efficient outcome, and that libertarianism's philosophy of individualism and policies of deregulation fail to prevent the abuse of natural resources.[1] Criticism of left-libertarianism is instead mainly related to anarchism. Left and right-libertarians also engage in criticism of each other.

Ethical criticism

edit

Aggression and coercion

edit

The validity of right-libertarian notions of liberty and economic freedom have been questioned by critics such as Robert Lee Hale, who posits that laissez-faire capitalism is a system of aggressive coercion and restriction by property owners against others:[2]

Adam Smith's "obvious and simple system of natural liberty" is not a system of liberty at all, but a complicated network of restraints, imposed in part by individuals, but very largely by the government itself at the behest of others on the freedom of the "some". ... What in fact distinguishes this counterfeit system of "laissez-faire" (the market) from paternalism, is not the absence of restraint, but the absence of any conscious purpose of the part of the officials who administer the restraint, and of any responsibility or unanimity on the part of the numerous owners at whose discretion the restraint is administered.

Other critics, including John Rawls in Justice as Fairness, argue that implied social contracts justify government actions that violate the rights of some individuals as they are beneficial for society overall. This concept is related to philosophical collectivism as opposed to individualism.[3] In response, libertarian philosophers such as Michael Huemer have raised criticisms of the social contract theory.[4]

Authenticity of libertarian goals

edit

Critics such as Corey Robin describe right-libertarianism as fundamentally a reactionary conservative ideology united with more traditional conservative thought and goals by a desire to enforce hierarchical power and social relations:[5]

Conservatism, then, is not a commitment to limited government and liberty – or a wariness of change, a belief in evolutionary reform, or a politics of virtue. These may be the byproducts of conservatism, one or more of its historically specific and ever-changing modes of expression. But they are not its animating purpose. Neither is conservatism a makeshift fusion of capitalists, Christians, and warriors, for that fusion is impelled by a more elemental force – the opposition to the liberation of men and women from the fetters of their superiors, particularly in the private sphere. Such a view might seem miles away from the libertarian defense of the free market, with its celebration of the atomistic and autonomous individual. But it is not. When the libertarian looks out upon society, he does not see isolated individuals; he sees private, often hierarchical, groups, where a father governs his family and an owner his employees.

Will Moyer, a former libertarian, thought that Anarchism was the full realization of libertarianism. Political libertarianism was a distorted version of the philosophy, appealing solely to people who admired libertarianism's feelings but lacked the principle to follow it to its logical (and moral) consequences.[6]

Property

edit

In his essay "From Liberty to Welfare", philosopher James P. Sterba argues that a morally consistent application of right-libertarian premises, including that of negative liberty, requires that a libertarian must endorse "the equality in the distribution of goods and resources required by a socialist state". Sterba presents the example of a typical conflict situation between the rich and poor "in order to see why libertarians are mistaken about what their ideal requires". He argues that such a situation is correctly seen as a conflict of negative liberties, saying that the right of the rich not to be interfered with in the satisfaction of their luxury needs is morally trumped by the right of the poor "not to be interfered with in taking from the surplus possessions of the rich what is necessary to satisfy their basic needs".

According to Sterba, the liberty of the poor should be morally prioritized in light of the fundamental ethical principle "ought implies can" from which it follows that it would be unreasonable to ask the poor to relinquish their liberty not be interfered with, noting that "in the extreme case it would involve asking or requiring the poor to sit back and starve to death" and that "by contrast it would not be unreasonable to ask and require the rich to sacrifice their liberty to meet some of their needs so that the poor can have the liberty to meet their basic needs". Having argued that "ought implies can" establishes the reasonability of asking the rich to sacrifice their luxuries for the basic needs of the poor, Sterba invokes a second fundamental principle, "The Conflict Resolution Principle", to argue that it is reasonable to make it an ethical requirement. He concludes by arguing that the application of these principles to the international context makes a compelling case for socialist distribution on a world scale.[7]

Jeffrey Friedman argues that natural-rights libertarianism's justification for the primacy of property is incoherent:[8]

[W]e can press on from [the observation that libertarianism is egalitarian] to ask why, if ... the liberty of a human being to own another should be trumped by equal human rights, the liberty to own large amounts of property [at the expense of others] should not also be trumped by equal human rights. This alone would seem definitively to lay to rest the philosophical case for libertarianism. ... The very idea of ownership contains the relativistic seeds of arbitrary authority: the arbitrary authority of the individual's "right to do wrong."

Philosopher Jonathan Wolff criticizes deontological libertarianism as incoherent, writing that it is incapable of explaining why harm suffered by the losers in economic competition does not violate the principle of self-ownership and that its advocates must "dishonestly smuggle" consequentialist arguments into their reasoning to justify the institution of the free market.[9]

Robert Lee Hale has argued that the concept of coercion in right-libertarian theory is applied inconsistently, insofar as it is applied to government actions, but it is not applied to the coercive acts of property owners to preserve their own private property rights.[10]

Standards of well-being

edit

Jeffrey Friedman has criticized right-libertarians for often relying on the unproven assumption that economic growth and affluence inevitably result in happiness and increased quality of life.[11] Easterlin [12] amongst others [13] suggests material gain/rising GDP is not statistically correlated with gains in happiness, with the psychological distress associated with social and lifestyle disruption - e.g. smaller living space in growing urban centres - from rapidly changing technology and other negative externalities (e.g. pollution)[14] possibly offsetting the benefits of growth. Economic history also discloses that during the boom years in the USA (1865 - 1930), public education, public healthcare and social security policies were introduced to redress the increase in child exploitation, contagious diseases, and crime (all of which lower living standards).[15] Others counter that economic growth is correlated with increases in happiness [16][17] while other evidence suggests inequality in the distribution of income and wealth, not the level or rate of change, may be more important drivers of community wellbeing and happiness.[18][19] The evidence is thus decidedly mixed.

Theory of liberty

edit

J. C. Lester has argued that right-libertarianism has no explicit theory of liberty.[20] He supplies a theory of liberty, briefly summarized as the absence of imposed cost. Frederick[21] criticizes Lester for smuggling in concepts not specified in the theory. Lester[22] responded. Both Lester and Frederick are proponents of critical rationalism, the epistemological approach of Karl Popper. Lester has criticized libertarians for neglecting epistemology.

Economic criticism

edit

Right-libertarians are accused of ignoring market failures, although not all proponents are market zealots.[23][unbalanced opinion?]

Environmental criticism

edit

Reconciliation of individual rights and the advances of a free market economy with environmental degradation is a problem that few right-libertarians have addressed.[24] Political scientist and author Charles Murray has written that stewardship is what private property owners do best.[24] Environmentalists on the left who support regulations designed to reduce carbon emissions, such as cap and trade, argue that many right-libertarians currently have no method of dealing with problems like environmental degradation and natural resource depletion because of their rejection of regulation and collective control.[11] They see natural resources as too difficult to privatize as well as legal responsibility for pollution or degrading biodiversity as too difficult to trace.[3] As a result, some see the rise of right-libertarianism as popular political philosophy as partially responsible for climate change.[1]

Right-libertarians are also criticized for ignoring observation and historical fact and instead focusing on an abstract ideal.[25] Imperfection is not accounted for, and they are axiomatically opposed to government initiatives to counter the effects of climate change.

Pragmatic criticism

edit

Lack of contemporary examples

edit

In 2013, Michael Lind observed that of the 195 countries in the world, none have fully actualized a society as advocated by right-libertarians:[26]

If libertarianism was a good idea, wouldn't at least one country have tried it? Wouldn't there be at least one country, out of nearly two hundred, with minimal government, free trade, open borders, decriminalized drugs, no welfare state and no public education system?

Furthermore, Lind has criticized right-libertarianism as being incompatible with democracy and apologetic towards autocracy.[27] In response, right-libertarian Warren Redlich argues that the United States "was extremely libertarian from the founding until 1860, and still very libertarian until roughly 1930".[28] Yet prior to 1860, women,[29] indigenous Americans [30] and African slaves [31] rarely enjoyed self-determination and freedom; posing a grave challenge to any suggestion that the US has ever been a land of liberty for all.[32][33]

Counter-criticism

edit

Declan McCullagh, writing for Wired, argued that libertarianism "attracts the most strident criticism from those who understand it the least. Expending little or no effort on research, critics barely familiar with libertarian ideas concoct an unappetizing stew of ideas – anarchism, egoism, and plain selfishness and greed – and mistakenly dub it libertarianism." McCullagh further argues:[34]

Libertarianism is not about anarchy, utopia, or selfishness. Instead, libertarians simply are skeptical of 'nanny government,' and recognize the many ways state power has been abused in the past. They believe that government programs like health assistance, Social Security, foreign aid, and corporate welfare do more harm than good. They argue that everyone must be equal before the law, and everyone has human rights to personal security, to property, and to free speech that the government must protect, not violate.

— Declan McCullagh

However, critics question why the abuse of state power should be singled-out when market and private power can be equally misused to coerce people to act against their own interests [10]

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ a b Matthew, Schneider-Mayerson (2015-10-14). Peak Oil: Apocalyptic Environmentalism and Libertarian Political Culture. Chicago. ISBN 978-0226285573. OCLC 922640625.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  2. ^ Fried, Barbara (2009). The Progressive Assault on Laissez Faire: Robert Hale and the first law and economics movement. Harvard University Press. p. 50. ISBN 978-0674037304.
  3. ^ a b Partridge, Ernest (2004). "With Liberty and Justice for Some" Archived 2019-08-21 at the Wayback Machine. Michael Zimmerman, Baird Callicott, Karen Warren, Irene Klaver and John Clark. Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology (4th ed.). ISBN 978-0131126954.
  4. ^ Huemer, Michael (2013). The Problem of Political Authority.
  5. ^ Robin, Corey (2011). The Reactionary Mind: Conservatism from Edmund Burke to Sarah Palin. Oxford University Press. pp. 15–16. ISBN 978-0199793747.
  6. ^ Moyer, Will (14 June 2014). "Why I left libertarianism: An ethical critique of a limited ideology". Salon. Archived from the original on 12 December 2022. Retrieved 12 December 2022.
  7. ^ Sterba, James P. (October 1994). "From Liberty to Welfare." Ethics (Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell). 105 (1). pp. 237–241.
  8. ^ Friedman, Jeffrey (1993). "What's Wrong with Libertarianism". Critical Review. 11 (3). p. 427.
  9. ^ Wolff, Jonathan. "Libertarianism, Utility, and Economic Competition" (PDF). Virginia Law Review. Archived from the original (PDF) on 12 January 2013. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  10. ^ a b Bruenig, Matt (28 October 2013). "Libertarians Are Huge Fans of Economic Coercion" Archived 2013-11-01 at the Wayback Machine.
  11. ^ a b Friedman, Jeffrey (1993). "Politics or Scholarship?". Critical Review. 6 (2-3). pp. 429–445.
  12. ^ Easterlin, R. A. (2015). Happiness and economic growth–the evidence (pp. 283-299). Springer Netherlands.
  13. ^ Hamilton, C. Affluenza (EasyRead Super Large 20pt Edition). ReadHowYouWant. com.
  14. ^ Knight, J., & Gunatilaka, R. (2011). Does economic growth raise happiness in China?. Oxford Development Studies, 39(01), 1-24.
  15. ^ Engerman, S. L., & Gallman, R. E. (Eds.). (1996). The Cambridge economic history of the United States (Vol. 3). Cambridge University Press.
  16. ^ Veenhoven, R., & Vergunst, F. (2014). The Easterlin illusion: Economic growth does go with greater happiness. International Journal of happiness and Development, 1(4), 311-343.
  17. ^ Clark, A. E., Flèche, S., & Senik, C. (2016). Economic growth evens out happiness: Evidence from six surveys. Review of income and wealth, 62(3), 405-419.
  18. ^ Oishi, S., Kesebir, S., & Diener, E. (2011). Income inequality and happiness. Psychological science, 22(9), 1095-1100.
  19. ^ Ugur, Z. B. (2021). How does inequality hamper subjective well-being? The role of fairness. Social indicators research, 158(2), 377-407.
  20. ^ Lester, J. C. (22 October 2017). "New-Paradigm Libertarianism: a Very Brief Explanation" Archived 2018-07-06 at the Wayback Machine. PhilPapers. Retrieved 26 June 2019.
  21. ^ Frederick, Danny. "A Critique of Lester's Account of Liberty" Archived 2023-04-04 at the Wayback Machine. PhilPapers. Retrieved 19 May 2020.
  22. ^ Lester, J. C. "A Reply to Frederick 2013: 'A Critique of Lester's Account of Liberty'" Archived 2020-10-28 at the Wayback Machine. SSRN. Retrieved 19 May 2020
  23. ^ Brennan, Jason (2012). Libertarianism: What Everyone Needs to Know. OUP US. p. 63. ISBN 978-0199933914. Archived from the original on 8 February 2024. Retrieved 23 September 2017.
  24. ^ a b Bowers, C. A. (2005). "Understanding the Commons within the Context of Contemporary Ideologies". Revitalizing the Commons: Cultural and Educational Sites of Resistance and Affirmation. Lexington Books. p. 135. ISBN 978-2511001516. Archived from the original on 4 April 2023. Retrieved 20 September 2017.
  25. ^ Haworth, Alan (1994). Anti-libertarianism: Markets, Philosophy, and Myth. Psychology Press. p. 14. ISBN 0415082544. Archived from the original on 8 February 2024. Retrieved 23 September 2017.
  26. ^ Lind, Michael (4 June 2013). "The Question Libertarians Just Can't Answer" Archived 2013-06-25 at the Wayback Machine. Salon.
  27. ^ Lind, Michael (30 August 2011). "Why libertarians apologize for autocracy". Archived from the original on 7 April 2019. Retrieved 17 February 2019.
  28. ^ "Was America Ever Libertarian". Independent Political Report. 25 April 2017. Archived from the original on 6 October 2018. Retrieved 6 October 2018.
  29. ^ Byron, T. (2022). An Intimate Economy: Enslaved Women, Work, and America's Domestic Slave Trade.
  30. ^ Blackhawk, N. (2023). The Rediscovery of America: Native Peoples and the Unmaking of US History. Yale University Press.
  31. ^ Logan, T. D. (2022). American enslavement and the recovery of Black economic history. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 36(2), 81-98.
  32. ^ Wright, G. (2022). Slavery and the rise of the nineteenth-century American economy. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 36(2), 123-148.
  33. ^ Beckert, S., & Rockman, S. (Eds.). (2016). Slavery's capitalism: A new history of American economic development. University of Pennsylvania Press.
  34. ^ McCullagh, Declan. "In Defense of Libertarianism". Wired. ISSN 1059-1028. Archived from the original on 2023-06-30. Retrieved 2023-06-30.

Further reading

edit
edit