Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
Jump to content

The New Ethics

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

The New Ethics
First edition cover
AuthorJ. Howard Moore
LanguageEnglish
PublisherErnest Bell
Publication date
1907 (revised edition, 1909)
Publication placeUnited Kingdom
Media typePrint
Pages216
OCLC681818483

The New Ethics is a 1907 book by the American zoologist and philosopher J. Howard Moore, in which he advocates for a form of ethics, that he calls the New Ethics, which applies the principle of the Golden Rule—treat others as you would want to be treated yourself—to all sentient beings. It builds upon the arguments made in his 1899 book, Better-World Philosophy, and 1906 book, The Universal Kinship.

Background

[edit]
Moore, c. 1899

J. Howard Moore was an early proponent of animal rights, blending his scientific knowledge with a strong moral philosophy in his writings. He was also part of the larger humanitarian movement that emerged in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, which aimed to advocate for better treatment of both humans and animals.[1]

This book is one of several works by Moore, which include Better-World Philosophy (1899) and The Universal Kinship (1906). His body of work collectively argued for the interconnectedness of all living beings and called for a moral evolution toward greater compassion and kindness.[1]

Summary

[edit]

Moore starts by examining how many new ideas are attacked and ridiculed before they eventually find acceptance in society. He then lays out his thesis of the New Ethics, arguing that humans are simply individual sentient beings, existing alongside a number of other sentient beings, differing only in degree, not in kind. Moore asserts that the Golden Rule, which he calls "The Great Law", is applicable to all beings, regardless of their species membership. He contends that the New Ethics is an ethical consequence of Darwin's theory of evolution, which established that all beings are related to each other and that it rejected the anthropocentric belief that non-human animals were produced for the benefit of humans.

Moore then explores human attitudes towards others, looking at both their treatment of other humans and other animals. He laments how humans have become masters over the earth, but have not recognized their responsibilities towards their fellow beings, instead becoming butchers by harming the beings they have duties towards, such as through vivisection, hunting and slaughtering them for food. Moore then criticizes what he considers to be the most common objection to the New Ethics thesis: that it is necessary for humans to exploit others to provide for their needs and desires; he argues that the objection is egotistical because it fails to consider the perspective of the victims.

He then argues that non-human animals have made, and continue to make, significant contributions to the development of human civilization and that humans treat these beings as mere means to an end. Moore contends that the ideal relationship would be one were humans and other animals work together for their mutual benefit. Moore then criticizes the use of animal products, such as fur, for human clothing and describes alternative methods for humans to clothe themselves using plant-based materials. He argues that current developments will lead to a future where humans no longer clothe themselves in animal-based clothing. He then looks at the question of what humans should eat, exploring the nutrients that humans require and examining human physiology, determining that humans are naturally herbivores; he concludes that the ideal diet is vegetarian.

Moore also criticises the claim that humans are required to kill other animals to prevent overpopulation, as well as the use of the survival of the fittest and an appeal to nature as objections against the New Ethics. Moore then sketches the evolutionary development of society—highlighting people such as Copernicus, Galileo and Darwin who have made significant contributions to human progress—and making a case for socialism and the women's movement. He concludes the book by asserting that the popularity or unpopularity of a proposition has no bearing on its truth or falsity and describing his dream of a future celestial civilization where humans are no longer savages and they instead live in justice and brotherhood with every sentient being.

Reception

[edit]

A review in the socialist magazine The New Age, described the book as uneven and overly sentimental, but felt that Moore redeemed himself in the conclusion.[2] The Westminster Review's review highlighted the shortness of the book, described the books central thesis as "extremist altruism" and contended that the book made excellent points.[3]

In 1931, C. M. Knight wrote positively of the book, stating:[4]

Some readers may not approve of Mr. Moore's warm enthusiasm, fervent language, and eloquent indictment of the shortcomings of men, and may wish that he had produced a cold scientific work on the subject; but those who have the humane cause at heart will not carp at methods, and will even overlook lapses from good taste and rejoice in all books which stimulate thought and arouse men form apathy, the greatest curse in the world and the worst stumbling-block in the way of all reform.

Dedication

[edit]

The book was dedicated to Tess,[5]: vii  Moore's pet name for his wife, Jennie. They were both admirers of the character Tess from Tess of the D'Urbervilles by Thomas Hardy.[6]

Publication history

[edit]

The first edition was published by Ernest Bell in London in 1907.[5] A revised edition was published by Samuel A. Bloch in Chicago in 1909.[7]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b Davey, Donna L. (2009). "J. Howard Moore". In Furey, Hester Lee (ed.). Dictionary of Literary Biography. American Radical and Reform Writers: Second Series. Vol. 345. Farmington Hills, Michigan: Gale. ISBN 978-0-7876-8163-0. OCLC 241304990 – via Internet Archive.
  2. ^ "The New Ethics". The New Age. 3 (22): 435. 26 September 1908.
  3. ^ "The New Ethics". The Westminster Review. 169 (2): 234. February 1908.
  4. ^ Knight, C. M. (1931). Knight, C. M.; Hume, C. W. (eds.). The Animal Year-Book. London: The University of London Animal Welfare Society. pp. 110–111. Retrieved 11 November 2021.
  5. ^ a b Moore, J. Howard (1907). The New Ethics. London: Ernest Bell.
  6. ^ "Tired of Life, J. Howard Moore, Teacher, Scholar and Author Goes to Meet His Maker". Cawker City Public Record. Vol. 34, no. 16. 22 June 1916. p. 1. Retrieved 6 June 2020.
  7. ^ "Books Received". International Journal of Ethics. 19 (4): 520–522. 1909. doi:10.1086/intejethi.19.4.2377026. ISSN 1526-422X. JSTOR 2377026. S2CID 222432857.

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]