Videos, interviews, podcasts by Victor Caston
Forthcoming & Drafts by Victor Caston
A Philosophical History of the Concept
A history of the concept of concept in Aristotle and his predecessors, mostly devoted to Aristotl... more A history of the concept of concept in Aristotle and his predecessors, mostly devoted to Aristotle's views.
J. Klein & N. Powers (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Hellenistic Philosophy (forthcoming)
Please refer to published version for any citations and quotations.
Abstract. There is a tension in Aristotle's theories between the nature and role of perception. H... more Abstract. There is a tension in Aristotle's theories between the nature and role of perception. He gives perception a prominent role in the explanation of animal behavior and in ethics, presupposing fairly rich contents. Some think, however, that in his psychological theory he restricts it to particulars and even just sensible qualities , and holds that strictly speaking we do not perceive anything as a certain sort of thing, which requires higher abilities. But this line of interpretation is mistaken. On Aristotle's view, perception is essentially a discrimi-native power, which allows us to distinguish between different types of objects. It is best understood as a de re attitude, directed towards particulars which we perceive as a certain sort of thing, even in the simplest case of colors or flavors. He is committed to a state view of nonconceptual content, whereby even nonrational animals can perceive different types of thing without possessing concepts.
Comment at the Am. Philos. Assoc. Eastern meetings (virtual), 18 January 2022
Articles by Victor Caston
Theories of Colour from Democritus to Descartes, 2024
D. Charles (ed.), Hylomophism (OUP), 2022
Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. 2nd c. CE) elaborates a well-developed form of emergentism not only... more Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. 2nd c. CE) elaborates a well-developed form of emergentism not only in his philosophy of mind, but in his natural philosophy more generally, through his own version of hylomorphism. This allows him to answer with great precision questions that hylomorophism naturally raises about the roles of matter and form, respectively, and their relation to one another. Forms for Alexander are causal powers that supervene on matter, which in all cases above the elements will consist in hylomorphic compounds too; consequently he regards the form of each new compound substance as a function of the forms of the underlying matter, the proportion in which they are blended, and their arrangement or construction. This does not prevent them from being new powers, which are irreducible to the powers of the underlying material compounds. This result is a nonreductive form of materialism and layered metaphysics familiar from emergentism.
Jakob Fink & Pavel Gregoric (eds.), Encounters with Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind (Routledge, 2021)., 2021
Nothing might seem more alien, from an Aristotelian standpoint, than the idea of the mind as an i... more Nothing might seem more alien, from an Aristotelian standpoint, than the idea of the mind as an internal theatre, where mental objects appear on stage under lights to be viewed by a ghostly spectator sitting in the dark. The interiority and even privacy suggested by such a model, associated with Descartes, and the notion of the subject as a kind of homunculus, seems to be more distinctive of modernity; indeed many have thought the study of Aristotle offers an escape from it. At the same time many discussions of Aristotle’s account of cognition are framed in such a way as to carry these implications, at least implicity, though few scholars today would care to admit it if challenged directly. A fair question, then, is whether Aristotle’s remarks commit him to such views, or whether these are rather something we unwittingly bring to the table in trying to interpret him.
I argue that the passages where Aristotle seems to speak as though we view internal objects before the mind’s eye can be naturally read without any such implications. Aristotle does allow that we can on occasion reflect on certain of our mental states, just as anyone should. His theory also maintains that phantasmata are representations, and indeed likenesses in some sense, of what they represent. But phantasmata are not themselves viewed and do not look like the objects they are about. They are states of our body, bearing representational content, in virtue of which we can imagine or visualize things, remember, desire, dream, and even think. Aristotle is not committed, even implicitly or inadvertently, to a Cartesian theatre.
L'héritage d'Aristote aujourd'hui: Science, nature et société (sous la direction de Françoise Graziani et Pierre Pellegrin), Alessandriia: Edizioni dell'Orso, 2020
Entreprendre de diviser l'âme, c'est aller au-devant de difficultés, et Aristote le sait. Il pens... more Entreprendre de diviser l'âme, c'est aller au-devant de difficultés, et Aristote le sait. Il pense déjà aux parties de l'âme dès le tout début du De Anima. À peine at -il introduit la question de la psychologie dans les toutes premières lignes, qu'il déclenche un feu roulant de questions sur la divisibilité de l'âme et sur ses implications pour notre enquête. Et il retourne sans cesse à ces questions aux endroits cruciaux de son exposé : en posant les fondements de sa théorie (II 1-3) ; en exposant le programme de sa recherche (II 4) ; et encore une fois à l'apogée de son examen des pouvoirs de l'âme (III 9-10). Rien n'est plus naturel pour Aristote que de s'intéresser aux parties de l'âme étant donné les préoccupations de Platon. Bien que ce dernier n'utilise l'expression qu'en quelques occasions, la division de l'âme en ses parties est au centre de République IV et du Timée 2. Mais ce seul fait ne constitue pas une raison suffisante pour qu'Aristote parle des parties de l'âme comme il le fait et encore moins pour qu'il prenne la peine de démêler et de clarifier cette notion. Pourquoi s'engager dans cette entreprise ? La réponse la plus courante est qu'Aristote s'est simplement approprié cette terminologie, en référence à son maître, en lieu et place de son propre terme technique, dynamis, « pouvoir ». Une fois que le terme « partie » a été débarrassé de toute implication problématique, il peut, pense-ton , l'intégrer sans problème dans sa propre conception. On aurait là un exemple parmi d'autres de la méthode conservatrice d'Aristote 3. 1 Cet article est la version abrégée d'un texte à paraître en anglais dans…. On trouvera dans la version originale anglaise une démonstration plus complète des arguments exposés ici. 2 Rep. 4, 442 B 11, C5, 444 B 3; 9, 577D3-4, 581 A 5-6, 583 A 1-3 (cf. 586E4-5); Tim. 91E5-6; Pol. 309C2; Lois 9, 863 B 1-3 (cf. 10, 904 B 4); et aussi Ps.-Plato, Def. 411E1. Bien que beaucoup de choses aient été écrites sur la tripartition de l'âme chez Platon il n'y a presque rien sur la conception spécifique de ce qu'il considère comme une partie. Pour un correctif dans ce sens, au moins en ce qui concerne la République, voir Shields 2010; et aussi Brown 2012, qui examine la notion de parties afin de développer la notion correspondante d'unité. Comme le note Brown (53 n. 2), Platon utilise fréquemment d'autres mots pour caractériser ces parties, dont eidê (435B9-C1, C5, E2, 439E2; Tim. 69C7) et genê (441C6, 443D3). Il est intéressant de noter qu'il n'utilise pas morion en ce sens : ce mot n'est utilisé pour une partie de l'âme que dans Ps.-Platon, Définitions 415D9. 3 Pour un état particulièrement tranché et influent de la question, accepté depuis comme un lieu commun, voir Barnes 1979 : « Le lexique des parties ne doit pas nous troubler : morion ("partie") est utilisé de manière interchangeable avec dynamis ("pouvoir") et archê ("principe"), sans aucune implication substantielle » (35). Dans la même veine, voir les remarques de Hicks à 432a22 (1907, 550). Un précédent ancien de ce point de vue peut même être trouvé dans le Ps.-Simplicius (In DA 286.34-287.1, contre l'hypothèse que les parties sont différentes des pouvoirs (cf. Ps.-Philopon In DA
Philosophical Problems in Sense Perception: Testing the Limits of Aristotelianism (ed. D. Bennett & J. Toivanen, Springer Verlag), 2020
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2019
Revised entry for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Rhizomata, 2019
Many fragments of interest from Theophrastus on perception are preserved by the late Neoplatonist... more Many fragments of interest from Theophrastus on perception are preserved by the late Neoplatonist, Priscian of Lydia. After some preliminary discussion of source criticism and how to identify the fragments, I turn to his discussions of perceiving and perceptual awareness. While Theophrastus clearly rejects literalism, he also does not embrace "spiritualism": he argues instead that we receive the defining proportions of perceptible qualities in the sense organ, though if this is to avoid literalism, it must be in different contraries than in the perceptible. If Priscian's report is faithful, he also accepts a moderate capacity reading of De anima 3.2, locating awareness in a central monitoring sense, common to the individual modalities; and this has further implications for the unity of consciousness. Theophrastus' method, though aporetic in form, is nonetheless a constructive engagement with the same texts of Aristotle we have ourselves, in the service of a common research program in psychology that he shared with his colleague and former teacher.
Oxford Handbooks Online, 2014
Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies, 2012
A companion to ancient philosophy, Jan 1, 2006
Philosophical inquiry into intentionality�that feature of beliefs, desires, and other mental stat... more Philosophical inquiry into intentionality�that feature of beliefs, desires, and other mental states, in virtue of which they are of or about something�begins long before recent debates about mental content or even the work of phenomenologists towards the beginning of the twentieth century. According to the received view, widespread in the literature, it can be traced back past figures such as Edmund Husserl and Franz Brentano to late medieval discussions in the Latin West; and from these, in turn, to earlier Arabic philosophy. But at ...
Metaphysics, soul, and ethics in Ancient thought: …, Jan 1, 2005
Uploads
Videos, interviews, podcasts by Victor Caston
Forthcoming & Drafts by Victor Caston
Articles by Victor Caston
I argue that the passages where Aristotle seems to speak as though we view internal objects before the mind’s eye can be naturally read without any such implications. Aristotle does allow that we can on occasion reflect on certain of our mental states, just as anyone should. His theory also maintains that phantasmata are representations, and indeed likenesses in some sense, of what they represent. But phantasmata are not themselves viewed and do not look like the objects they are about. They are states of our body, bearing representational content, in virtue of which we can imagine or visualize things, remember, desire, dream, and even think. Aristotle is not committed, even implicitly or inadvertently, to a Cartesian theatre.
I argue that the passages where Aristotle seems to speak as though we view internal objects before the mind’s eye can be naturally read without any such implications. Aristotle does allow that we can on occasion reflect on certain of our mental states, just as anyone should. His theory also maintains that phantasmata are representations, and indeed likenesses in some sense, of what they represent. But phantasmata are not themselves viewed and do not look like the objects they are about. They are states of our body, bearing representational content, in virtue of which we can imagine or visualize things, remember, desire, dream, and even think. Aristotle is not committed, even implicitly or inadvertently, to a Cartesian theatre.