Economics and Philosophy, 23 (2007) 343–348
doi:10.1017/S0266267107001526
C Cambridge University Press
Copyright
HARSANYI BEFORE ECONOMICS:
AN INTRODUCTION∗
PHILIPPE FONTAINE
École normale supérieure de Cachan
Upon learning that John C. Harsanyi (1920–2000) was awarded the Bank of
Sweden Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel, in 1994, for
his pioneering work in game theory, few economists probably questioned
the appropriateness of that choice. The Budapest-born social scientist had
already been recognized as a first-rank contributor to non-cooperative
game theory for some time (see, e.g., Gul 1997). However, as many
readers of this journal will be aware, Harsanyi first contributed to welfare
economics, not game theory. More importantly, he was philosophically
minded and accordingly has been “acknowledged as the most influential
philosopher in economics” (Güth 1994: 252).1 This is of some significance
since, before Harsanyi became acquainted with economics around 1950,
his main interest was philosophy and, to a lesser extent, sociology
and psychology. Rather than an economist with philosophical leanings,
Harsanyi was actually a philosopher turned economist.
∗
1
This introductory article was begun as I was Ludwig Lachmann Research Fellow at the
Philosophy Department at the London School of Economics. It would not have been written
without the assistance of one of my students at the École normale supérieure. Sandor
Szakacs-Vass translated Harsanyi’s article of 1947 into French and provided valuable
research assistance. Luc Bovens suggested that it be translated into English. I am grateful
to him for his encouragement and comments. Roger Backhouse commented on a longer
version. Finally, for their assistance and kindness, I thank Anne and Tom Harsanyi.
Güth (1994: 270–271) focuses on game theory and places Harsanyi’s work on economic
philosophy under “Other essential contributions”, a short section before the two-paragraph
“Final remarks”. Arrow (2001: F751) provides a more balanced account, though he stresses
the economic foundations of Harsanyi’s philosophical work – “the founding of ethics on
utilitarian principles and the implications of the Bayesian approach for epistemology” –
more than the philosophical roots of his economic work.
343
344
PHILIPPE FONTAINE
This biographical note introduces an English translation of “A
filozófiai tévedések logikai alkata” – a condensation of Harsanyi’s 50page doctoral dissertation from the University of Budapest – published
in Athenaeum in 1947.2 I would like to take this occasion to point out that
Harsanyi’s inclination towards the axiomatic approach in economics after
1950 is more than simply an illustration of the emerging trend affecting
economics after the axiomatization of bargaining by John Nash (1950) and
of social choice by Kenneth Arrow (1963 [1951]). It also reflects his earlier
pursuits as a student of philosophy.
Only a little information can be retrieved about his personal life before
Harsanyi fled Budapest to Austria in April 1950. By that time, he had
spent some 30 years in a country that had suffered several traumas, from
revolution to territorial losses, occupation, and dictatorship. As with many
other Hungarians of Jewish origin, Harsanyi’s parents had converted to
Christianity and, like most of their peers, they were anxious to give their
son a good education, which would help his assimilation and possibly
protect him from the vicissitudes of political life.
In September 1929, Harsanyi entered the now legendary “Fasori”
Lutheran Gymnasium in Budapest, a high school that trained such
distinguished scientists as John von Neumann and Eugene Wigner. There
he stayed eight years, studying various subjects from Greek, Latin, biology
and physics, to philosophy (in which he developed a strong and lasting
interest) and mathematics. In his last year at the Gymnasium in 1937,
Harsanyi won the first prize in mathematics in a nationwide competition.
After high school, he attended mathematics classes given by Lipót Fejér,
the famous University of Budapest professor, but, looking for applications,
Harsanyi did not find his teacher’s purist preoccupations to his taste and
decided therefore to work at his father’s pharmacy to get some experience.
In the summer of 1939, while war clouds were gathering over Europe,
Harsanyi was sent to Grenoble to learn some French with a view to
studying leather chemistry. Before long, however, his parents called him
home and after an uneasy journey through Italy and Yugoslavia, he was
back in the Hungarian capital.
In Budapest, Harsanyi followed his parents’ advice to study pharmacy,
knowing it would help him get military deferment and a comfortable job
were things to go wrong in Hungary. And so they did with the outbreak
of war in September 1939 following Hitler’s hostile attitude towards its
2
Athenaeum was the journal of the Hungarian Society of Philosophy. Ironically, Harsanyi
published his article in the very last issue of the journal. I am grateful to Madarász Aladár
for information on this. The biographical sketch below draws on the interviews conducted
by Marion Ross (2000) and correspondence with John Harsanyi’s widow and her son. In
this note I do not explore the relations between Harsanyi’s early work in philosophy and
his later work in economics. Another paper (Fontaine 2007) touches upon that issue.
HARSANYI BEFORE ECONOMICS: AN INTRODUCTION
345
eastern neighbours. In that context, it is hardly surprising that, after
becoming a fully qualified pharmacist in 1942, Harsanyi sought to prolong
military deferment. Accordingly, he entered a doctoral program in one
branch of pharmacy. Despite his interest in chemistry, he had to specialize
in botany since the only professor willing to accept a doctoral student of
Jewish origins was a specialist in that field.
By March 1944, following attempts by the Hungarian government
to establish contact with the Western Allies, Berlin resolved to occupy
Hungary. Very quickly, a new, pro-Nazi, government was set up and
from the first days of the occupation, hundreds of Jews were arrested
in Budapest and elsewhere in the country. At the end of March, it was
decided that Jews would wear a yellow armband and a few days later
the ghettoization and deportation process was launched. In May Harsanyi
was drafted into forced labour in the vicinity of Budapest. At the time, the
Jewish community in Budapest had been relatively spared from the abuses
perpetrated against the Jews in the provinces. The removal of the puppet
Nazi government in August and the subsequent attempts to end the war
presaged further improvements, but, following the seizure of power by the
Arrow-Cross Party of Ferenc Szálasi, in mid-October, the political situation
again deteriorated. Deportations, in particular, were resumed. Harsanyi
was among the potential deportees. Yet, by taking off his white armband,
which identified him as a Christian Jew, he managed to escape from the
railway station where a number of Jews had been gathered for deportation
to Austria. Harsanyi knew he could take refuge in a monastery in the centre
of the city. There, a friend of his, a Jesuit priest, hid him for two months. It
was mid-November. The Soviet troops had already reached the outskirts
of Budapest.
After the Red Army entered Pest in January 1945, Harsanyi left his
refuge and joined his parents in the ghetto. From there, they moved back
into their house. It was not long before his mother died and his father
reopened the pharmacy. With normalization on its way in Budapest,
Harsanyi decided to take up a doctorate in philosophy with minors
in sociology and in psychology. In the fall of 1946, while attending
classes in these subjects, he met his future wife, Anne Klauber, who was
studying psychology in the same institute at the University of Budapest.
Capitalizing on his studies in pharmacy, Harsanyi moved quickly through
his doctorate and by 1947 he had completed his dissertation under the
supervision of Gyula Kornis. In “The Logical Structure of Philosophical
Errors”, Harsanyi set out to “investigate the objective difficulties that stand
in the way of an objective settlement of philosophical debates” (Harsanyi
2007 [1947]) and rejected the explanation of differences in philosophical
viewpoints in terms of emotional preconceptions and ideological beliefs.
In answering the question, “How could the greatest philosophers
confuse their subjective “preferences” with logical evidence?”, Harsanyi
346
PHILIPPE FONTAINE
dismissed errors in the form of reasoning and offered instead an
“axiomatic explanation” centred on axiom-derived errors. He concluded
that philosophical theories differ with regard to the scope of validity
of their axioms. Deriving axioms from induction, Harsanyi correlated
differences in philosophical systems with differences in the justness of
their generalizations.
His dissertation completed, Harsanyi was appointed as university
assistant at a Budapest university institute in sociology headed by
Sándor Szalai, a sociologist and philosopher, who was on his dissertation
committee. While teaching on various sociological subjects, Harsanyi
made his anti-Marxist views known; gradually, he became something of an
outcast at university. At some point, around May 1948, while Communists
were putting increasing pressure on Social Democrats to force them to
fuse into a single party, the “Workers’ Party”, Szalai, himself a Social
Democrat, informed Harsanyi that things were getting too dangerous for
him at university and that he would have to give up his teaching post.
Once again, Harsanyi went back and worked with his father.3
With the ongoing Sovietization of academic life, recurrent antiSemitism and the nationalization of many activities, Harsanyi faced an
uncertain future. He had good reason to speculate about his chances of
success in another society, which he did more formally in the following
years as he investigated the “theory of choices involving risk” in the context
of “value judgments concerning social welfare”. After discussing their
prospects in Communist Hungary, Anne and John concluded that they
should emigrate. With the help of Anne’s father, they found someone who
could take them across the Austrian border. John Harsanyi, Anne Klauber
and her parents left Budapest in the second half of April 1950. Three days
later, they were in the Russian-occupied part of Austria, heading towards
Vienna, where they soon found themselves in the American zone. There,
they stayed for two months at the Rothschild hospital, which had been
turned into a refugee centre. With the deterioration of the international
situation in late June, however, the party decided to go to Salzburg – which
was then in the American-occupied part of Austria – where they waited
for an Australian landing permit for some five months. In Salzburg, Anne
Klauber found a job at the International Refugee Organization, which
had been created a few years earlier to deal with the displacement of
people in postwar Europe, while John Harsanyi spent his days reading at
a library maintained by the US Armed Forces. In this library, he perfected
his English, reading numerous books and journal articles, among which
were a few about economics. In this way, Harsanyi became acquainted with
economics before leaving Austria, though his knowledge of the discipline
was still fragmentary.
3
As it turns out, Szalai himself was arrested in 1950 and jailed until 1956.
HARSANYI BEFORE ECONOMICS: AN INTRODUCTION
347
In what follows, the readers of this journal should not expect to find
an insight that will revolutionize their views of Harsanyi’s work. Instead,
readers may expect to discover a useful starting-point for reconsidering the
simple story of a philosopher émigré inevitably seduced by a social science
that found itself increasingly permeable to axiomatization. Harsanyi’s
interest in axioms developed long before he turned to welfare economics.
He was not drawn into economics by a desire to axiomatize the field.
His entry into the subject was accidental: upon arriving at the University
of Sydney the only sociologist he could find was a specialist on the
indigenous population. This was not the kind of sociology Harsanyi was
used to reading while in Budapest or that he was willing to pursue now
that he had landed in Australia. Even so, his M.A. thesis in economics,
Inventions and Economic Growth (1953a), continued to reflect his interest
in the dynamics of societies and, as such, revealed how embedded his
economic thinking was in a sociological framework. Welfare economics
came soon after, but here again Harsanyi’s developments in interpersonal
utility comparisons could easily be related to sociology, more specifically,
Weberian themes such as empathetic understanding. The shift towards
economics was therefore gradual and carried with it both the philosophical
leanings and sociological dimensions of his early thinking. If there was a
break in Harsanyi’s theorizing, it probably occurred after the turn to game
theory in the second half of the 1950s, but this is not to say that his work
on cooperative and non-cooperative games completely erased the earlier
interests.4
Our historical knowledge of Harsanyi is still fragmentary. His archives
focus primarily on the period following his arrival at the University of
California at Berkeley in the mid-1960s. Accordingly, it is helpful to glean
pieces of information here and there to improve our deficient knowledge
of Harsanyi’s gradual endorsement of economics. Most readers of this
journal will not be aware of his 1947 article. This note and the following
translation are nothing more than a modest attempt to shed light on one of
the most important figures of economics and philosophy in the twentieth
century.
REFERENCES
Arrow, K. J. 1963 [1951]. Social Choice and Individual Values. 2nd edn. London, Yale University
Press.
Arrow, K. J. 2001. John C. Harsanyi 1920–2000. Economic Journal 111: F747–52.
Fontaine, P. 2007. The homeless observer: John Harsanyi on interpersonal utility comparisons
and bargaining, 1950–1964. Mimeo.
4
An adaptation of Harsanyi’s M.A. thesis was published under the title “The Research
Policy of the Firm” in Economic Record in 1954. On welfare economics, see Harsanyi (1953b,
1953–54, 1955).
348
PHILIPPE FONTAINE
Gul, F. 1997. A Nobel Prize for game theorists: the contributions of Harsanyi, Nash and
Selten. Journal of Economic Perspectives 11: 159–74.
Güth, W. 1994. On the scientific work of John C. Harsanyi, John F. Nash, and Reinhard Selten.
Discussion Paper, no. 35, Humboldt-University of Berlin, 251–81.
Harsányi, J. 1947. A filozófiai tévedések logikai alkata. Athenaeum 38: 33–39.
Harsanyi, J. C. 1953a. Inventions and economic growth. Masters of Arts Thesis, University of
Sydney, January.
Harsanyi, J. C. 1953b. Cardinal utility in welfare economics and in the theory of risk-taking.
Journal of Political Economy 61: 434–5.
Harsanyi, J. C. 1953–54. Welfare economics of variable tastes. Review of Economic Studies 21:
204–13.
Harsanyi, J. C. 1954. The research policy of the firm. Economic Record 30: 48–60.
Harsanyi, J. C. 1955. Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons
of utility. Journal of Political Economy 63: 309–21.
Harsanyi, J. C. 2007 [1947]. The logical structure of philosophical errors. Economics and
Philosophy 23: 349–57. Translated by Lorinc Redei.
Nash, J. 1950. The bargaining problem. Econometrica 18: 155–62.
Ross, M. 2000. Nobel laureate John Harsanyi: from Budapest to Berkeley. 1920–2000. With an
Introduction by Kenneth J. Arrow. Berkeley, CA, The Regents of the University of
California.