Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
An historical and post-structural examination of the philosophical debate of phusis (nature) versus nomos (convention) and its employment in two of Sophocles' Theban Plays which were written in late fifth-century Athens.
What are Plato’s views concerning the opposition, or more accurately concerning the relationship, between physis and nomos, and how do those views fit more generally into Plato’s thought?
The Athenian judicial system would be, were it to permeate all aspects of the society of its time, we go from what is theoretically possible to a description of what is real. At no time, even in Euripides, is there any open criticism of the rule of law, nor is the validity of the democratic institutions questioned, but there is an evolution in the consideration of these. Aeschylus is the tragedian who trusts in the power of truth, assuming without doubt the capacity of the human being to arrive at truth because his only mission is to discover, through rhetoric, what the gods have already inscribed within him. On the other hand, Euripides, knowing all the rhetorical mechanisms and managing them with great mastery, centers his interest on exposing possible shortfalls here, those in which society undermines its foundations. Without openly criticizing the values rooted in Athens, he hints at its deficiencies and allows us to intuit, without explicitly proposing it, what could be a new social order, one more in line with the real principles from which it arose. On different lines from those of Aeschylus, Euripides also seeks to justify respect for the legal order, not in its antiquity or in the effectiveness of its application (Harris 2004: 35), but in its goodness and the fact of it being in accordance with human nature. Such an approach would prevent society from being able to identify moral and social norms and to disassociate the right order from the divine order.
ΠΗΓΗ/FONS, 2021
Sophists deal with the problem of relationship between nomos and physis in terms not only of opposition between, but also of intertwinement. On the one side, the discussion leads to an exaltation of the physis, with opposite effects: in some sophists (Hippias and Antiphon) nature warrants the equality among human beings, while, in other sophists (Callicles and Thrasymachus), nature becomes the basis for legitimizing the dominance of the strongest over the weakest. In this context, the nomos is considered an invention of the weakest to inhibit the strongest. On the other side, we find sophists (like Gorgias) that affirm the need to decide to follow the nomos or the physis on the basis of situation, that is to avoid unilateral positions, or sophists (like Anonymous of Iamblichus) that assume a "conciliatory" perspective between nomos and physis. Socrates completes the variety of this debate. In Criton, Socrates applies a manifold movement to the nomos, divine and human, thus deserving respect and, at the same time, modifiable.
In Greek literature the words physiognomy and ekphrasis never occur together: the first occurrence of the noun physiognomonia is in the Hippocratic corpus, namely in Epidemics 2.5.1, a treatise dating back to the end of the fifth century BC; while for the first technical occurrence of ekphrasis as a description of “persons, animated and inanimated things, occasions and places” we have to wait until much later: it occurs only in the first century AD, in the preliminary exercises for the training of orators, the Progymnasmata of the Alexandrian sophist Aelius Theon. We have, for sure, plenty of texts dealing with physiognomy from the Homeric epoch onwards, and we have, also from Homer onwards, ecphrastic texts describing persons, animated and inanimated things, occasions and places. This means that both practices – that of physiognomy and that of ekphrasis – exist in Graeco-Roman literatures much earlier than, and independently from, their explicit theorization. One could even go further and say that physiognomic and ecphrastic passages occur throughout Greek and Latin literature, and that their importance lies in the rhetorical effect they produce on the audience, not in the theories that have been conceived in order to explain them. Still, we face a major problem: can we associate at all the two practices of physiognomy and ekphrasis? This is a tricky question, since we do not have texts that problematize physiognomy and ekphrasis in the same context, or that establish an explicit relationship between them. What we do have is a series of texts from Aristotle to the Second Sophistic in which physiognomical and ecphrastic matters are treated in a way that makes plausible, in not altogether likely, the existence of a reciprocal connection between the two issues. This chapter focuses on the first group of texts that deal with physiognomy and ekphrasis, written either by Aristotle or by his immediate pupils, and with texts roughly belonging to the philosophical and rhetoric movement of the Second Sophistic. We shall see that both groups of texts tackle on the one hand ecphrastic issues that square with the theoretical requirements of physiognomy, on the other physiognomical matters that seem to entail an ecphrastic mode of description. This entails that physiognomy is in itself an ecphrastic practice grounded in rhetorical theory, and that, conversely, the ecphrastic description of persons relies to a great extent on the empirical data of physiognomical analysis.
IV INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE IN GREEK PHILOSOPHY, Madrid, 2022
Section 2: Socrates and the Sophists, 26.04.2022 The Nomos-Physis controversy is regarded as one of the great themes of the sophistic debate in the 5th century BC. This controversy is closely related to the epistemic innovation of sophism: they explicitly use humans as a starting point. Protagoras’ homo mensura theorem sums up this shift in perspective . But what looks like an answer in fact holds a lot of new questions. For as soon as one tries to treat man as a measure, one must consider the question of what exactly the decisive thing about human beings should be. The manifold interests of the Sophists can be grouped in this way. Thus, according to Nerczuk (2016), the Sophists study 'human nature' based on medicine, but from an ethical-political point of view. According to Buchheim (2006), they discover a 'discontinuity' of Nomos and Physis in humans, which makes education possible and necessary as the correct response. The assessment of whether life according to Nomos, i.e. according to social rules and laws, contributes to the individual happiness varies within the sophistic movement depending on the way in which human Physis is understood. In this context, Balla (2018) distinguishes between 'pessimistic and optimistic anthropologies'. Roughly three sophistic classifications of human beings can be identified: 1. Humans are by nature deficient beings (Mängelwesen), incapable of self-preservation and preserving their species, therefore culture and its laws are the conditions of their survival (Protagoras). 2. By nature, there are stronger and weaker people. For the weaker, the laws are a protection and a means of self-preservation. For the stronger, the laws are an obstacle, limiting their pursuit of self-enhancement. As the stronger, they have a natural right to more (Callicles, Thrasymachos). 3. Human nature is ambivalent. It contains the means to preserve life and to destroy it. Education according to the specific laws of our own culture helps us to practise self-control in order to learn how to distinguish the inherently harmful impulses from the useful impulses. In this respect the performance of the laws is ambivalent (Antiphon). In my talk I would like to discuss the question of how the individual and social dimensions of human life relate to each other in the context of the Nomos-Physis controversy. Due to the limited amount of time, I am assuming here that Protagoras’ position is familiar to you. I will analyse the positions of Callicles, Thrasymachos and Antiphon in two steps: 1. What is their understanding of the tension between Nomos and Physis? 2. How do they justify the decisive role of Physis over Nomos?
This essay discusses the problem of the origin and use of the Athenian nomos argias. The law was probably part of the archaic agrarian legislation and it originally concerned inheritance and family rights. However, over the course of the classical period, it broadened its field of application, becoming a law against unemployment and begging. argia – inactivity – agrarian legislation – unemployment – criminality - poverty
Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy, 2023
Plato’s Protagoras is famous for Protagoras' defense of the public practice of sophistry and his great myth, which contains his account of the origins of political life, as well as for Hippias' rejection of the tyranny of nomos in the name of the natural kinship of the wise. What is perplexing is that Socrates makes no explicit response to these arguments. This essay argues that Socrates' indirect response is actually contained in his otherwise unmotivated interpretation of the poem of Simonides, where his description of "laconic philosophy" is in fact an indirect description of his own philosophical practice. While the sophists reject nomos without recognizing their own dependence on its stabilizing force, Socrates argues that genuine philosophers, recognizing at once the necessity as well as the defectiveness of nomos, must "unwillingly praise" convention and only present their criticisms indirectly. Socrates' interpretation of Simonides, then, points the way to his own understanding of the tension between, but also the interdependence of, nomos and physis.
Journal of Fashion Marketing and Management , 2015
in G. P. Brogiolo, M. Ibsen (eds.), Corpus Architecturae Religiosae Europeae (saec. IV-X). Vol. II. Italia I. Province di Belluno, Treviso, Padova, Vicenza. Schede di A. Colecchia, E. Napione, E. Possenti, Zagreb 2009, vol. 2, pp. 81-93
Lazio e Sabina 13. Atti del Convegno, Tredicesimo Incontro di Studi sul Lazio e la Sabina, Roma 25-27 maggio 2022, 2024
Osmanlı’dan Cumhuriyet’e Geçiş Dönemi Kavramları (Cumhuriyet’in 100. Yılına Armağan), 2023
AL-WIJDÃN Journal of Islamic Education Studies
Monte Mesma. Storia, ambiente, arte, spiritualità di una terra alta del Cusio, 2011
Industry and Higher Education, 2011
Fertility and Sterility, 2010
Psychotherapie Forum, 2021
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2005
International Journal of Scientific Reports
JURNAL EKONOMI, SOSIAL & HUMANIORA, 2021
International Journal of Plant Biology, 2020
Studi sulla Formazione/Open Journal of Education