WHAT HAPPENED IN AYODHYA?
Perspectives and A Response
BALAGANGADHARA S.N.
Universiteit Gent
March 2024
PART I
Reading reports and opinions on the Ram Mandir event in Ayodhya is depressing and puzzling. It
is depressing because intelligent people show a penchant for writing unintelligibly on prominent
issues. Even though they see something, they stop short of saying what they ‘see’.
Consequently, the reader is helpless. Hence the puzzle: why bother to write when indifferent to
the reader? Whatever the reason, as readers, we must at least scratch where it itches. Since
unintelligibility is present on the surface, scratching here could reveal what lies beneath. The
surface is the “consecration”; the visible is the equivocation; our sources are reports and
opinions in The Indian Express. All answer the same question: what happened in Ayodhya?
A ‘consecration’, answer some. In that case, who consecrated what? Here are some answers: (i)
an idol, (ii) a temple, (iii) Hinduism, (iv) the Hindu collective narcissism. Surely, if saying what
occurred in Ayodhya depends so much on individual whims and fancies, it speaks of the
inability to identify the object of consecration. Some use Pran Pratishtha here, but what is its
role? Is Pran Pratishtha a synonym for an English word, or does it merely name the act of
consecration? Some, like Liz Mathew in her report of 24th February in the Indian Express, suggest
that ‘inauguration’ and ‘consecration’ are synonyms: “the Ram Temple inauguration” in one
paragraph becomes “the Ram Temple consecration” in the subsequent one. Some even imply
the consecration of God and religion (Hinduism) in Ayodhya. The problem is that neither is
possible. First, consecration requires transmitting a superior force or quality to an object. The
word 'God' loses meaning if something superior to God exists. Second, since consecration
occurs within religion, what could consecrate religion? If religion cannot consecrate itself, no
religion can consecrate another religion if these words have any meaning.
In short, these claims confuse us if taken as descriptions or identifications of the same event.
Not because they are descriptive but because of equivocation, which generates ambiguity
about the event’s identity. Thus, what occurred in Ayodhya?
To reduce ambiguity and equivocation, let us formulate the above question using Indian words:
was there pran pratishtha of the Vigrah or murti of Rama, or was there also pran pratishtha of the
Mandir? Is pran pratishtha of a dharma (‘religion’) possible? Is pran pratishtha the name of a
ceremony, a segment in the act of consecration or the result of consecration? Could there be
pran pratishtha of Atman or Brahman? It is important to note that these questions are not
confusing.
For instance, we can intelligibly say that pran pratistha applies to objects (Vigrah’s or murtis,
mostly). It excludes mandirs but applies neither to qualities or properties of objects nor to
Atman or Brahman. We exclude conceptual or psychological entities (say, like narcissism) from
its scope. The pran pratistha of dharma is impossible even though there could be its
samsthapan, and so on. We might need help to clarify and defend these claims or even give
wrong answers. But they are neither nonsensical nor confusing the way they are when we speak
of consecration in Ayodhya. We can answer, 'What occurred in Ayodhya?' because we used
Indian words to formulate questions.
Let us notice what happened in these two cases. When we used the English word, the question
went unanswered because the answers were incoherent. Using some Indian words, we can
tackle the question because the answers do not threaten to become unintelligible. Even though
1
we speak of the same event in both cases, we do it differently depending on our linguistic
choices.
When speaking in vernaculars, we express our intuitions regarding language use. But we fail to
do the same when using English. There is a breakdown of sorts in the second case. Even where
the English sentences are correct, they render the event's identity and consequences hazy.
However, there is no comparable confusion when using the Indian vernaculars. Why?
Drawing an analogy could help. Imagine an infected biological sample on a glass slide placed
under a microscope. Two people observe it: one ‘sees’ it as a virus and the other as a bacterium.
We can assess both sightings and there is no linguistic issue about using the correct word.
Instead, it is about knowledge: Is it bacteria or viruses? Seeing it as either bacteria or a virus is
insufficient to answer this question. We need bacterial and virological theories, among other
things.
The above analogy holds good for us. The vernacular and English words are both linguistically
legitimate. Both could describe the world. In English, we see the Ayodhya event as
consecration; in the vernacular, we see it as pran pratishtha. These two different ‘seeings’ give
birth to two distinct consequences: the “Indian seeing” allows an intelligible description that is
either true or false; the “English seeing”, by contrast, generates unintelligibility. In the second
case, the description is a mere conglomeration of sentences that confuses and, therefore,
cannot qualify as knowledge even if some sentences are true. What is at stake is the nature of
an event. Its description must answer the question: what occurred in Ayodhya? Our vernaculars
help in giving intelligible answers that are either true or false. Using English not only muddies the
waters but also generates ignorance.
However, in identifying phenomena in the world, our descriptions rely on languages. As
embedded cultural entities, our intuitions are indelibly cultural. Indeed, most Indian writers and
intellectuals share similar cultural and linguistic intuitions. Yet these intuitions go haywire when
writing in English. Why?
In the analogy I used above, two issues are of importance. The first is when we see an object, we
mostly see it as something. One person sees the Ayodhya event as consecration, and the other
sees it as Pran Pratishtha. Why do they see the same event in two diverse ways? The second
critical issue is that they use different theories that make them view the world differently. In one
case, when using English unreflectively, we use theories about consecration implicit in that
language without awareness. None of the reporters or commentators show any learning or
knowledge about the theories of consecration they use. Yet, the grammatically correct use of
English words hides ignorance. In one sense, they do not see consecration but use the word to
cover up a failure. Indians, too, use theories when speaking in vernaculars. Even though this
knowledge is implicitly present in their language use, it enables reflection and thinking. We can
formulate the above argument differently when we realize this idea identifies our predicament
today.
Our political and economic theories, our sociologies and anthropologies, our historiographies,
and our theories in psychologies are all on loan from Western culture. Even those who make
their living selling ‘Indic’ thoughts in India or abroad use Western frameworks to earn their
wages: their ‘ontologies’, ‘epistemologies’, ‘ethics’, ‘metaphysics’, etc. are all borrowed from the
West (‘realism and nominalism’, ‘norms and values’, ‘particulars and universals’, and so on);
their ‘Hinduism(s)’, ‘Buddhism(s)’ and ‘Saivism(s)’ need ‘theologies and theocracies’, ‘deities
2
and their worship’, ‘idols and idolatries’, and even an occasional ‘sanctum sanctorum’. Of
course, western terms are spiced appropriately with Sanskrit words to make the dish appear
entirely Indigenous. This situation indicates that we have massively borrowed theories from
Western culture explicitly and implicitly. However, thoughtless borrowing does not give us
automatic access to that culture or help us understand its biases. It is akin to borrowing money
without knowing that we owe interest on the sum and that there is a due date. It is even worse:
Indian intellectuals do not even seem to know that they have taken vast and massive loans to
meet daily needs. The lender will send strong-arm men to beat us into submission and force a
payback. If, in regular instalments, the EMIs bleed us to death, it is this anaemic patient that you
see in the reports and columns on Ayodhya. If we are oblivious to what we have borrowed (from
whom and how), is the resulting ignorance a wonder?
Our reporters and intellectuals know the English syntax but do not realize that ‘knowing English’
includes seeing the embeddedness of languages and their words in cultures and theories.
Because they are not mere linguistic particles, words generate consequences. If ill-understood
but still used casually to frame descriptions of the world, they merely adorn ignorance. The
current writings on Ayodhya are its exemplifications. How can we take such writings seriously?
What about their further claims on polity, society, and the people of Indian culture? These are
our questions today. But before going there, we must heed two warnings.
The first is about the newspaper reporters. One does not expect them to have expert knowledge
of consecration or a grasp of Latin. Why then write of consecration and use the Latin phrase
"sanctum sanctorum" to speak of garbhagriha? They believe this is how one writes in English, or
each reporter merely imitates the more ‘experienced’ colleague. Whatever the case, my
criticism is not about their ignorance of the meaning of 'consecration’.
The second warning is about a pernicious trap. Even though I am not speaking about words or
their uses, the temptation is to assume this is the crucial issue. We can ask: 'What does it
matter which word we use, consecration or Pran Pratishtha, to speak of the Ayodhya event?' The
answer is obvious: it matters the same way whether we use ‘acidity’, ‘ulcer’, or ‘stomach cancer’
to indicate abdominal unease, prescribe and take medications. The other aspect of the trap is
to think that the problem is a translation issue. It is not. Whether one believes that ‘Prana
Pratishthapana’ is an “Untranslatable Sanskrit” word or that translating the English
‘consecration’ into Indian languages is a “cultural” and not just a linguistic problem, the result is
the same. You will merely go down the proverbial rabbit hole.
3
PART II
In this part, I look at columns in the Indian Express on the Ayodhya event authored by three
respected Indian intellectuals. Before that, some preliminary thoughts are in order.
First, even though there is a talk about the Ayodhya event in these reports, they confuse us by
sheer vagueness: they claim to have seen a consecration, but the focus and the scope of the
event are up for grabs. Second, the puzzlement increases if we read what they say because they
could not have seen what they describe. Third, the columns express a double ignorance: one
about the nature of the phenomena they see and the other about the intellectual resources they
use to describe them. Fourth, they draw the same conclusion despite depicting the situation
very differently. Typically, if there is no clarity about the nature of an object, no consensual
structure can be found in different descriptions. If an object is a cute little puppy to an observer
but is a supernova or a quantum computer to the other, it would be surprising to find these
descriptions arriving at the same conclusion. Yet, that is the case here.
They all see the cementing of a tie between politics and religion. This bond appears to undercut
the enunciated ideals of the Indian constitution. The current political party is held responsible
for this. Indeed, they could not see these in either the act or the ceremony of the pran
pratishtha. These cannot be seen in the constructed temple, complete or otherwise. As a result,
a gulf opens between what they could have seen in Ayodhya and what they say about the event.
Furthermore, the descriptions are internally incoherent. I explore these issues, which are
present in the three columns.
Mehta’s Heroics
In the Indian Express piece of January 22nd, Pratap Bhanu Mehta claims that the Ayodhya event
was an unprecedented “watershed moment in history”. It is crucial that “Pran Pratishtha
following the foundation stone of Ayodhya marks the consecration of Hinduism as a political
religion pure and simple". This thought is cognitively impenetrable and lies in how it goes further.
Here, Mehta picks up the 17th chapter from the Gita, where Krishna uses three classificatory
categories while answering Arjuna's question. One such is Rajas (the other two are Satvik and
Tamas). In the 18th verse, a tapas evincing rajas is spoken of; in the previous verse, it was about
the satvik tapas. Not only does Mehta quilt, but he also distorts and mangles what he quotes. If
this verse can do anything in our context, it is to classify pran pratishtha as a tapas expressive of
rajas. The correctness of this characterisation is not at issue; what Mehta does with the verse is.
He makes the word ‘tapas’ in this verse into a translational equivalent of “penance and
austerity”. The problem with this equivalent is that penance is an act of self-abasement or
devotion expressing sorrow and repentance for sin or compensation for an offence committed.
If one insists that pran pratishtha is rajotapas in Mehta’s description, it becomes (i) a mode of
worship and (ii) a name for a spectacle. It would (iii) originate from pride and (iv) produce
passions and emotional resonances. Finally, (v) its performance is intended to obtain nontransient benefits to the performer. Here, Mehta does not understand borrowed words like
‘penance’, ‘consecration’, ‘worship’, etc., or his culture’s understanding of ‘tapas’, ‘rajas’, ‘pran
pratishtha’, and so on. This double ignorance is built into his description of the Ayodhya event.
Mehta says that Hinduism was consecrated as a political religion. Even a ‘political’ religion is
still a religion, but the pran pratishtha, says Mehta, marks the moment “where Hinduism ceases
to be religious”. How could an entity that ceases to be religious continue to be a religion,
4
whether political or not? What does it mean to say that Pran Pratishtha consecrated religion
(Hinduism) into another entity (a political religion)? Who consecrated what? Did Ram Lalla
perform the consecration? This absurdity becomes painful when we ask what a ‘political’
religion is.
Some political theorists use ‘political religion’ to say phenomena like Authoritarianism, Fascism
and Nazism, Communism, Islamism, etc. Mehta could have this in mind. Even then, the use of
this word is problematic in our case: except for ‘Islamism’, the other phenomena mentioned
above did not have prior existence as religions. Thus, it follows that the ‘Hinduism’ after Ayodhya
is to Hinduism before Ayodhya in the same way that Islamism of today is to Islam of yesterday.
Mehta does not make the bold claims that Islam is dead as a religion and that Muslims have
become Islamists. He only says that ‘Hinduism’ is dead as a religion today. Thus, if Hindus
continue to practice Hinduism after Ayodhya, it entails that all Hindus now practice a political
religion. Mehta does not draw this logical conclusion explicitly; he merely notes that there is no
ideological counterpoint to this. This claim can only mean that this new political religion is an
ideology. But what precisely is the ideological element here: Hinduism or politics? Politics is
different from 'ideology'. In this case, Hinduism is the ideology from which the political religion
gets its ideological element. This claim is both inconsistent and disingenuous. Mehta should at
least know that “bearing witness” if that is what he wants to do, requires that one truthfully says
what one sees.
In any case, according to Mehta, this event further marks the emergence of “collective
narcissism”, an entity made in “the image of God”, an image that we now worship. Thus, we do
not worship God, but an entity made in His image, an entity of our creation. Such worship must
make us into “idol worshippers”. Mehta agrees. He says that Hindus do worship idols. But this
putative claim creates new problems: (a) How could idol worshippers ever create anything "in
the image of God"? Their ‘idols’ would resemble their creators, human beings, but not an entity
they could not possibly know, namely, God. (b) If human beings can create entities “in the image
of God”, do they not become equal to God? People have believed that God created Man "in His
image". If we can also do so, have the Hindus attained full Godhood post-Ayodhya? Is Mehta
saying that pran pratishtha of Ram Lalla marks the self-deification of the Hindus?
He also claims that worshipping idols is central to Hinduism and that idol worship gave a playful
intimacy to Hinduism. Odd. Idol worship (‘idolatry’) names wrongly practised or wrongly
directed worship. Is Mehta saying that this wrongness is central to Hinduism? Besides, how can
idolatry make religion playfully intimate? With whom is such a religion playful and intimate?
From whence the demonic power of idol worship to change religion itself? Idol worship cannot
change the nature of divine worship, while divine worship can break and destroy idol worship.
Such is worship as we understand it today.
Philosophically and theologically speaking, worship is a serious affair. To many, it was and stays
the most serious activity. These people think that the sole purpose of human existence is the
proper worship of God. As a result, we cannot worship God playfully as though we are playing a
game. One might seek intimacy with the object of worship, namely, God. But such a human
quest is neither ‘playful’ nor a ‘game’, even if the world is a game that God plays.
Be it as that may, why would Hinduism prescribe (or recommend) idol worship? To Mehta, this
has to do with the fact that “concentration on the idol was a path to self-consciousness”. This
sentence, too, obscures. If self-consciousness is the goal of human existence, why recommend
the worship of either God or the Devil? If the desire is to reach self-consciousness, why
5
concentrate on idols, whatever they are? If the ‘I’ (a reflexive pronoun) indicates selfconsciousness, is it not advisable to focus on this 'I' to realise self-consciousness instead of
something else? Upanishadic thinkers thought so. No, says Mehta, the focus on ‘I’ reeks too
much of “I-doll”, a possible American spin on the etymology of idolatria, as Mehta would have
Arindam Chakrabarti say.
In any case, these issues get short-circuited when Hindus exchange ‘new’ idols for the ‘old’
ones in Ayodhya. This thought is even odder. If Hinduism ceases to be religious, should worship
not follow the same route, even if it is idol worship? Should this religious act not disappear as
well? If it does not, is it because Hindus are born idolaters? No sensus divinitatis in us then?
On the one hand, religion cannot be consecrated, yet Hinduism is; religion cannot have a
punarjanma, yet Hinduism dies as a religion only to be ‘born again’ as a political religion; the
Hindu idols too are reborn as “mega showpieces”; Hindus engender “collective narcissism” and
consecrate it since they have hewed it in “the image of God”.
On the other hand, tapas becomes ‘penance’ to end up as a mode of worship. Yet, this is not the
case because this tapas is a mere “spectacle”. Accepted by the gullible as a “mega-showpiece”,
it is choreographed by those who “make a show of their worship in what is a sign of lack of real
faith” because they “care about the flag more than they care about dharma”. But who can
provide the required ideological counterpoint when the political universe is governed by the
duplicitous and the disingenuous, the Dharma Dwaji’s as they are named?
Here is the double ignorance I spoke about. Mehta’s impenetrable thoughts are neither Western
nor Indian, nor are the two intelligibly or intelligently mixed. At the end of his column, despite
the virtuoso, we stay as ignorant about idols, what their worship entails, what consecration is,
what religion is, and what happened in Ayodhya as we were before reading it.
Varshney’s warning
Of all the op-ed pieces and the newspaper reports I have read, Varshney’s piece (January 27th,
the Indian Express) is the only one to appeal to a dictionary explicitly. Though laudable, there is
an issue here: what does the act show when we look up a word in a language dictionary? It
means our assumption that the word has its home in a natural language and is not a technical
term. If it were a technical term ('mRNA Vaccines' or 'Quantum Entanglement'), we would not
search Merriam-Webster to find out its meaning or use but look elsewhere instead. There are
other resources, including multiple encyclopedias.
Thus, if Varshney had used other resources, he would have discovered that ‘consecration’ is a
heavy-duty technical word at home in Hebrew, Ancient Greek, and Church Latin; that it has
come into the English language carrying an enormous religious load from the Testaments, both
Old and New. He would have known that consecration has a rich past. Some practices have
been legally codified for a millennium (the Canon Law of the Catholic Church, for instance).
These tell us of the word’s specialised uses; its use in English does not and cannot violate its
technical meanings. ‘Was the Ayodhya ceremony a consecration?’ is a question requiring
theoretical, theological, scriptural, and empirical investigations. One cannot consult the
Webster’s or the OED to answer it.
However, it is only sometimes possible to know whether some or another term is technical
before looking it up in a dictionary. Here is where the dictionary look-up helps. If a term of the art
6
is at issue, it would be difficult to understand the dictionary ‘meaning’ properly. Varshney’s
“simple question” tells us why:
“Can a Prime Minister lead a ceremony of religious consecration? To consecrate, according to the
dictionary, means “to make or declare sacred.” That is typically done by a “holy” or religious figure.”
To begin with, Varshney speaks of ‘religious’ consecration as though there are others: political,
psychological, social, economic, cultural, etc. This qualification makes sense if there are other
kinds of 'consecrations' whose notable instance is religious. Not otherwise. Further, we discover
many difficulties in this definition: ‘sacred’, ‘holy’ and ‘religious’; ‘consecration’ can make or
declare; and the ‘holy’ does or can consecrate. These have an unavoidable reference to human
actions, which have causal consequences. The presence of these words as a cluster and what
they refer to are sufficient to suggest that ‘consecration’ is a term of the art and that we should
know something about the discipline whose technical term it is.
Further, both Varshney and his readers who accept this definition must also assume that these
phenomena exist in our world. They could not 'make', 'declare' or 'do' if they did not. The
definition traces causal consequences in the world: an act makes a thing sacred; it is udertaken
by a person who has the properties of being holy or religious. Thus, understanding this
dictionary definition demands knowing what is 'sacred', 'holy', and 'religion', what they do, and
assuming their existence in our world.
Since a good encyclopedia would say that the word meanings and their existence as
phenomena in the world have been (and continue to be) matters for disagreement, taking a
dictionary definition does not settle the case of knowing what they are. It teaches us word
meanings and their use. A dictionary is not knowledge of phenomena. Thus, to those who know
what a dictionary is and what it does, this definition says that consecration is an object of study
in specialised literature and requires domain-specific knowledge.
There is something more. We see that 'consecration' is defined using words without clear
meanings. This situation tells us that ‘consecration’ involves other words also part of this
domain-specific knowledge. As a result, we see that our problem is not to find a suitable Indian
equivalent for ‘consecration’. An interrelated cluster of Indian words and concepts is required to
make sense of this English word. Thus, we do not face a ‘translation’ problem or a disguised
cultural problem. It cannot be called ‘cultural’ without explaining how and why 'holiness',
"religious', and 'sacred' are cultural but not sociological, psychological, or political.
Varshney claims that a holy or a religious figure typically makes or declares the ‘sacred’. Here,
the qualification guards by immunising it from counterexamples. One can protect oneself while
confronting cases where ‘unholy’ or even ‘a-religious’ figures consecrate an entity by labelling
them ‘atypical’. This academic tendency to ‘hedge’ fails here because the phenomenon of
consecration allows us to ask: “Do such atypical cases exist, or are they impossible?"
To make his “simple question” (about a Prime Minister leading consecration) into a weighty
objection, Varshney needs heavy artillery that includes answers to the following: (a) why are
some figures religious or holy? (b) How does this property enable the making or declaration of
the sacred? (c) What kind of ability is it: genetic, political, cultural, psychological, social, or
religious? (d) Is authority attached to this position? (e) If yes, what kind of authority is it? (f) Why
cannot it be a political authority? Without answers to these problems, Varshney’s question
returns: why cannot “a Prime Minister lead a ceremony of religious consecration”?
7
Because, Varshney suggests, “the very idea of a politician leading a consecration ceremony in
modern times would be abhorrent to most religious leaders and theologians”. Whether such an
action generates abhorrence or not depends on whether ‘consecration’ is an event that (a) is
neutral towards all religions, (b) occurs outside religions, (c) is universally present across
cultures, and (d) has the same structure and typology across the globe. Not otherwise. There
were ‘religious figures’ from some Indian sampradayas present at Ayodhya, yet others followed
the event closely, but none expressed any abhorrence at a politician leading the ceremony. If
the “four Shankaracharyas…had led the consecration”, Varshney might be prepared to call it “a
purely religious event”. Suppose we agree to this suggestion for the sake of the argument, the
issue becomes: did they find it abhorrent that the Indian PM led the event? They do not appear
to have said this because these four Acharyas believed an incomplete temple could not ground
a pran pratishtha. The point here is, whether right or wrong, they did not express 'theological'
disgust at the PM leading the event. Whose abhorrence is Varshney talking about? In whose
theology is it abhorrent that a politician leads consecration? Christian and Jewish theologies?
Islamic religious leaders? While these possibilities could be true, what do they have to do with
an Indian cultural event, the pran pratishtha, which appears not even remotely connected to
consecration, ‘religious’ or otherwise? Varshney’s “simple question” is not solved; it comes
back again.
Varshney begins his column with an ominous warning: the consecration of a temple has “dealt a
monumental blow to India’s constitutional republic”. This blow, however, is “symbolic and
discursive”. In our world, symbols do not go around dealing blows because they cannot causally
interact. No symbol of a Hero can ever kill the symbolic villain: even if Rama ‘killed’ Ravana in a
discursive universe, neither of the two did or could do anything in Lanka as symbols. Words
cannot deal blows either to human actions or to physical structures. Nor can such blows ever
land. Thus, if ‘consecration’, a symbol, deal a symbolic blow (even a symbolically monumental
one) to another symbol, namely, India’s constitutional republic, then these symbols must also
exist in the reader's symbolic universe. If they do not? Well, nothing happens.
Anyway, in his world, Varshney also detects “a paradox” between “symbolic and discursive”
objects and “political and legal” entities. What exactly is the paradox? On the one hand,
‘consecration’ (an entity in one discursive universe) has “fully invalidated the principle of the
state’s religious neutrality” (an entity in another universe). How does an entity in one universe
“invalidate” the principle existing in another universe? If in some universe ("a possible world")
the sum of three angles of a triangle is more than 180°, this does not and cannot “invalidate”
the principle in another universe (that is, in another possible world) that such a sum is exactly
180°. Knowledgeable people would merely assume that this difference tells us about space in
these two universes: one is an n-dimensional space (with more than two dimensions), and the
other, perhaps, is only bi-dimensional. So, how does Varshney perform his magic? I do not
know.
In any case, since this invalidation is “complete”, we must assume that the secular state is
severely damaged. Further, the consecration is complete, but the envisaged ‘Hindu state’ is
incomplete. We learn that it might never even be completed. A pity, perhaps, but where is the
paradox? Is it generated by the difference between “incomplete construction” and “finished
consecration" or because one is "finished" (the consecration) and the other is "unfinished" (the
Hindu state, the temple)? In both cases, it is a nonsensical claim.
Paradoxes are linguistic, logical, mathematical, or semantic. There is no paradox between
'finished' and 'unfinished', ‘complete’ and ‘incomplete’, or between ‘construction’ and
8
‘consecration’. When this is the case concerning independent entities in the same linguistic
universe, it is even more so when the entities populate different universes. There is no logical,
mathematical, semantic, or linguistic paradox between the symbol of consecration in one
universe and an incomplete secular state in another. Hence, there can be no paradox between
consecration in Ayodhya and an incomplete Hindu state in India if 'paradox' has any meaning. A
paradox could nevertheless exist in the symbolic, discursive world constructed by Varshney.
However, in that case, it is invisible to mere mortals. Varshney insists that “political practice is
normally not analysed in binary terms (“yes or no”). It is appraised on a scale (“more or less”)”.
How, then, can we either see the blow or assess its monumental impact in a "non-binary"
fashion? Again, I do not know.
If what happened in Ayodhya was not a consecration, claiming that a Prime Minister led a
religious consecration there is false. Modi could have neither taken part in nor led an event that
did not occur. We would not learn much about the blow and its monumental impact by entering
Varshney's “symbolic and discursive” or "political and legal” worlds.
Palshikar’s Guilt
Much like his colleagues, Suhas Palshikar is tripping even before he begins. He says we are
“witnessing a transition” without recognising that “its nature and consequences are deeply
controversial”. Really. When we witness a transition, we recognise that there is a transition (that
is its nature, after all) that aims at an end-state. (This is its consequence.) The end-state could
have consequences, but the transition is not the cause. In that case, what exactly is
controversial?
Palshikar finds “the “building” of a new temple” as the focal event in Ayodhya. Here, he zeroes in
on “the moment (that) represents our collective entry into an era of erasures”. He lists three of
them: plurality, coexistence and guilt.
Let me begin with what erasure is: it obliterates. What is erased could be writing, a painting, a
carving, a society, or even life. Usually, erasure removes all traces: we cannot discern what was
there earlier or whether anything ever was. However, if we can count them (Palshikar counts
three) and identify and differentiate them from each other (plurality, coexistence, and guilt),
then, strictly speaking, we have ‘palimpsests’ on our hands. In Archaeology, Architecture, Art,
Cultural Studies, etc., the word suggests that something is altered in an object but continues to
bear traces of an earlier form.
The issue is about more than choosing a proper label. If we admit that we are talking about
palimpsests but not erasures, we must also acknowledge that controversies we might have will
be about the past we want to keep. Altering a past would be different from erasure or writing
Stalinist historiography. However, if the goal is to induce righteous indignation in a people to
condemn building a temple morally, we need erasures, not palimpsests. Thus, the need of the
hour is guilt, the third erasure.
Palshikar calls this the “most tragic erasure”. Even in 1996, he notices “among Hindus, there
was a sense of guilt, an admission that something wrong was done”. What on earth does this
mean? Surely, recognising wrongdoing is not tantamount to an admission of guilt: the
recognition that Hitler, Pol Pot or Stalin did wrong is not an admission showing our guilt. Hindus
might have felt that "a wrong was done". However, this cannot generate a sense of guilt in them
unless they are the actual perpetrators. Sensing a wrongdoing is not the same as admitting to a
crime.
9
This sloppiness is more than just a one-off or a casual mistake. It is systematic: “huge resources
were generated by a community to avenge the past”, and it happened apparently without guilt.
This assertion defies all reason: my resources are limited but can grow to a considerable sum if
many more people contribute. Assume this happens. Should I feel guilty of wanting to see a
temple built? Am I guilty because others support this project? What is my guilt: to financially
contribute to an unbuilt temple when the “community” intends to avenge the past by building it?
It needs to be clarified what is wrong: is seeking to ‘avenge the past’ the forbidden act here? If
building a temple where a Mosque stood earlier is forbidden, is it the act or the intention
(“avenging the past”) or the goal (seeking ‘revenge’) that is prohibited? Since building the temple
is not illegal, either the intention or the goal is forbidden. Why should either of the two generate
guilt in me?
Moreover, we can deal with our past only if it continues to survive in the present. If not, the
vengeful act would be futile because it will have no object (‘the past’) to act on. In short, we still
do not know who is guilty and why.
Yet, we are guilty of more. "Unimaginable political investment was made into an exercise that
should have been a matter of spiritual pursuit and religious learning," and this too without guilt.
Who is guilty of what? We cannot answer the question because we cannot even begin to make
sense of this sentence. However, “What does the new temple mean?" elicits the answer, "It is
the erasure of guilt."
How could a temple, any temple, erase guilt? Palshikar claims that the Ayodhya temple “not just
absolves the society or any group or party… it simply erases that fact from history.” If a temple
gives absolution, it also formally releases the accused from guilt and punishment. Absolution is
an ecclesiastical declaration (i.e., a declaration given by the religious or the Church hierarchy) of
forgiveness: one could forgive a sin, a debt, or a punishment. Inducing amnesia is of no help
here. There is a vast difference between forgetting an act and forgiving it. This difference is not
about what the two words mean but is about two different kinds of actions: forgetting occurs in
memory, and its nature depends on the nature and structure of memory. (Memories are of
various types, including 'episodic memory'.) Psychology, Cognitive science, and Brain sciences
study this aspect. Forgiving, by contrast, is moral or religious aimed at a particular act:
trespasses or violations committed only by human beings. Ethics, Theologies, and Moral
psychologies study this phenomenon.
Absolution is not forgiveness alone; it further requires that the absolver have the religious,
moral, or legal authority to do so. Since the temple itself is guilty and must be “made guilt-free,"
it needs an “effective instrument” to do this, which Palshikar finds “in the SC ruling." Without
warning, the guilt shifts from a people or their community to a physical structure. Now, the court
has the authority to absolve.
Even this authority is spurious in our case. Over the years, “our politics made sure that the guilt
was softened and then pardoned. …the Court put a stamp of formal approval”. So, this court
does not make the temple guilt-free, i.e., it does not absolve. It is approved formally. What does
it so approve? The court agrees that politics manages, softens, and ensures the guilt is
pardoned. Does the court merely approve or also approve of this fact? To keep Palshikar
consistent, we must read him as saying that politics made sure that the court obeyed its
dictates, which is why the Supreme Court ruling is a stamp of formal approval. Whether true or
false, where does this bring us? To confusion. We neither know who absolves nor who the guilty
is or why. We do not even know what guilt is. Who or what is erased, then?
10
Apparently, Hindus are guilty of just about everything because they recognise wrongdoing and
therefore admit guilt. They are also guilty of wasting unimaginable political investment in trivial
pursuits and collecting considerable resources to build temples. The temple can absolve and
free society or its members from guilt, yet it is guilty of seeking vengeance against the past.
Formally, it can declare and forgive the sins of a people, but to effectively free itself from guilt,
the Supreme Court is needed. The court can do this only because it is politically managed. Until
politics, the true absolver, enters the picture, we are all guilty of any trespass someone else
commits. Finally, every act can become a trespass because of the absence of the requirement
that it should be an ethical or legal violation. Any which way, the Hindus are guilty until absolved
by politics. Between the lines, one could read that ‘absolving politics’ is not a generic entity for
Palshikar but has a specific ‘Hindu’ identity.
Here, we confront the same problem that we met earlier -- borrowing from elsewhere without
knowing what is borrowed or what debt is incurred. It is unclear what ‘guilt’ is: now it is “a
sense”, then it is “an awareness”. It is a violation of law once (“criminal vandalisation"), a search
later for the forbidden (“seeking vengeance”). Why is vengeance forbidden, and by whom?
Should ‘a’ community obey this dictate, or is an individual agent subject to it?
Guilt requires absolution but, clearly, can also be managed without it. Politics softened guilt,
apparently, but it is not clear what hardens guilt. Guilt envelops Hindus from birth, and whether
only Hindu temples succumb to guilt or all temples do (the Jewish ones, for instance) is
unknown. And so on.
It would be illuminating to go into the history, ontology, and psychology of guilt, but space
forbids such an exercise here. But this much can be said: even though Palshikar seems to think
that guilt has something to do with violating the law, he does not seem to realise that this
insight, even when vague, hides a more profound question: why should any violation of law
generate guilt überhaupt? Indeed, in this context, Palshikar knows of a derivative question
central to Western political thinking, viz., the problem of political obligation.
A Conclusion
Where are we after reading these three pieces? The most straightforward answer: nowhere. This
answer would be wrong because much is seen by our thinkers, even if what they say about their
sightings could be better. In a way, their failure is our failure as well. We have inherited
languages and vocabularies from elsewhere, another culture, but we need to understand the
talk and, therefore, walk the walk. Nothing in our languages or experiences allows us to sensibly
speak of the sacred and the profane, the holy and the consecration, the penance and the
austerities, sin and absolution, forgiveness and guilt, confession and repentance, reconciliation
and salvation, etc. We believe that we know what religion is, how they die, whether they are
reborn, and what idol worship is all about. We do not: even though we know that the British
talked this way, these notions are not original to them. We cannot talk that talk by speaking
English. In knowledge domains, realising the extent of our ignorance requires knowing whether
we know our ignorance. One of the preconditions for knowledge is awareness of our ignorance.
A denial here is not conducive to producing knowledge; instead, it is a hindrance. Forgiveness of
ignorance, whether by God or Man, is not an option here.
‘What happened in Ayodhya?’ stays unanswered, it appears. In the final and concluding part, I
will answer this question unorthodoxly: I will endeavour to show that these respected thinkers
have seen ‘something’ and are not blind. Even if what they say is unintelligible, they are not
11
unintelligent people. The unintelligibility has an outside source and has little to do with their
capabilities. I have partially identified it but have yet to address so far whether we can do
something about it. Ayodhya makes an answer to this more urgent than before.
12
PART III
The Indian traditions speak of tatvadarshis in this world. Who are they? The Sanskrit phrase is a
compound of darshi and tatva. ‘Darshi’ is someone who sees or has seen. What? ‘Tatva’ is a
word compounding tat and tva. ‘Tat’ means ‘that’, while ‘tva’ qualifies. It is the “-ness” in kindness and good-ness. In our case, the compounded words give ‘that-ness’. Thus, a tatvadarshi
has seen ‘thatness’. What does this mean?
When we see an object, we see it as something as a thing with shape, form, size, and other
properties. The world and our abilities, both physical and cognitive, jointly give us what we see,
namely, something which is this or that object. Assume you see an object without knowing or
recognising it as a specific object. If asked what you see, you can point your finger and say, “I
see that”. Suppose you do not use the finger but want to communicate that you see something.
How could you do so? Well, you can say, “I see thatness”. Here, you communicate seeing
something but are unable to identify it. By ascribing the property or quality of ‘that-ness’ to the
object, you use language to point at an object. In a sense, every seen object is a ‘that’ and
knowing it as ‘thatness’ does not tell us what we see. In simple terms, you have seen something,
but you cannot identify what it is. Thus, you say you see ‘thatness’. These are tatvadarshis. Even
though they see something, it stays unidentified because they do not know what they have
seen.
These are our intellectuals as well. They see but do not know what they see, even if they think
they know. They are Tatvadarshi's, not Jnanis. We need the knowledgeable (the jnani) to tell us
what happened in Ayodhya. The tatvadarshi cannot do this, but they are our only jnanis. Why did
this come about, and how? Though it is an important question, I will not answer it here. Instead,
my focus is more modest: What was there to be seen in Ayodhya? To do this, we rely on extant
reports. Hence, we began with our tatvadarshis.
These intellectuals saw the uncommon and the out-of-the-ordinary in Ayodhya. Whether a glitzy
affair or a mega-spectacle, the event appeared to astonish. It was as though the new but the
familiar replaced the old and the familiar: Rama is the old and familiar King of Ayodhya; the Ram
Lalla, the five-year-old, is new but the familiar Rama; the centuries-old mosque, its familiar
structure dotting the skylines of many generations, is violently replaced; even though an
unfinished temple takes over its place, Rama’s new temple is familiar even to those who have
not seen it. Our tatvadarshis see politics leading a profoundly religious ceremony. Thus, they
wonder what the event portends. Of course, our tatvadarshis have said more, but this small
clutch of sentences is sufficient for now.
They refashion these sightings into descriptions of the Hindu state, the demise of secularism,
Hindu Fundamentalism, the emergence of Hindu majoritarianism, the effaced boundary
separating religion from politics, and so on. Is this the only reasonable description of the event,
or is a cognitively better alternative possible? One could give a coherent and consistent
description of the Ayodhya event, which, if true, predicts a disaster. However, an alternative
description is possible that promises and delivers. Neither the promise nor an impending
delivery makes the alternative better. What does this is its cognitive superiority: the alternative’s
assumptions are less suspect, shed better light on issues, and resonate more intimately with
experience. Equally important is that such an alternate description generates new and exciting
cognitive problems and productively opens novel research areas. I outline three reference
14
points that function as indicators and, in what follows, suggest a different route to answer the
question, “What happened in Ayodhya?”
1. Varshney sees Modi using “new vectors of language — such as Dev se desh (divinity to
nationhood)”. The ‘vector’ in this language is not new but ancient, especially if ‘dev’
moves towards ‘desh’. The Jews became a nation, i.e., acquired their nationhood when
Yahweh, the Jewish God, entered a covenant with them. We should not ascribe novelty
to an old use of language. Whether Modi used new vectors or stuck to the old, his
speech in Ayodhya will be my first reference point. Even here, I isolate one striking
thought.
Modi suggests that we look at what is happening in Ayodhya not as an event in the
calendar but as something else, namely, the Kalachakra from which a new age emerged.
What could this thought say? This question is not about what Modi thought, tried, or
wanted to say because I have no clue. I do not need to know them to make sense of the
thought.
As we know and practice it, Historiography maps a domain of events to another domain
consisting of units of time. This mapping is not strict or one-to-one. Many elements from
one domain can be mapped to a single element in the other domain. Then we have a
many-to-one mapping: many events occurred on 15th August of 1947. We could also go
the other way and map many time units to a single event. The Indian independence
movement could be an example of mapping multiple time units to a single event. Thus,
some simple arithmetical operations in one domain might not be possible in the other:
hours, days, weeks, etc., give us an arithmetical sum when added together; an operation
in the events domain could add up to one event. Subtracting multiple units would give
their arithmetical result in the domain of time units, but we could also have one event
despite deleting various events. Consequently, relations and structures from one
domain are not mapped on to the other. The mapping represents a situation where many
elements are associated with a single element from another set.
Invariably, historiographies guide such mappings by adding garden-variety claims about
economics, politics or anthropology, human psychology, sociology, etc. Some of these
assertions are presented as historical explanations. Whether explanations or not, these
transient events are historical, i.e., possessing 'historicity'. Thus, any set of ideas that
appears to have the form of an explanation becomes “historical” if it is about an earlier
event. Of course, we must 'prove' their occurrence, requiring archival research, etc.
Such a mapping of the Ayodhya event to a calendar is not appropriate, says Modi. What
is? We do not expect a philosophical explanation in Modi’s speech, but we do get a
contrast. That is, the contrast is between events in calendars and events from the past.
Events and the units of time are the elements that give us historiography. By contrast,
events neither “occur in time” nor are they mapped to time units in the Kalachakra.
Events structure time here, or time emerges from events. We can linguistically
communicate through such a process, which would not re-count events but narrate
them instead. This story has a beginning, a middle, and an end. But ‘the’ past has no
place here because any event in Kalachakra is past relative to the chosen beginning. The
same applies to future events.
15
Thus, Modi’s remark contrasts history with the past. Historiography gives us the first;
narratives or stories give us the second. Both are structured entities: classificatory units
of time provide a structure to the first; salience gives a narrative structure to events in
the second. These are alternatives: as I have noted elsewhere, to gift history to a people
is to destroy their past. The story that made Rama live and die is a narrative that enables
Rama to become a child again in our present. ‘The’ past that historiography traces are
transient. Hence, it must disappear from our lives. Ayodhya and Rama of ‘the’ past might
be significant to the archaeologist or a historian but not to us. A narrative past, by
contrast, lives in our daily lives as it is an integral part of the story of Rama. That is, the
past merges with the present. Modi draws this contrast when counterposing the
calendar to Kalachakra. What is the new age he talks about, though?
2. In this new age, the tatvadarshis see the fusing of politics and the state with religion. If
the boundary between religion and politics blurs, the secular and the religious intersect,
then a religion of the majority ends up as Hindu majoritarianism. They see this new age
emerging, explicitly confirmed in the event where the PM of a nation leads religious
consecration.
To assess this description better, consider the fragmentary video clips circulating in
social media about Modi’s motorcade in the streets of Srirangam. He was en route to
taking a dip in the sea, one of the many acts meant to qualify him for pran pratishtha. As
the vehicles pass through the town, we hear some chanting and see some people raising
their hands. The raised hands were from older men, naked from the waist up, wearing
yagnopavita, and carrying marks on their foreheads. I learnt later that the chanted verse
was from the Ramayana, the verse ascribed to Kausalya, Rama’s mother. I did not have
to decipher the chant to recognise 'Ashirwad’ in the gestures of these old men. I have no
clue whether Modi knew this or what he thought about it. But evident to any who could
see was the solemnity of this event. Modi senses it; his folded hands do not return
people’s greetings as much as acknowledge and accept the Ashirwad. Why the verse
and why the Ashirwad? I seek neither the motives nor an explanation here but
something else.
To begin with, we seek a description of an event that tells us what makes old men come
to the streets to give Ashirwad to a politician, a Prime Minister, for finding their ‘lost’
would-be King. A king is a paradigmatic political function. So is the prime minister of a
country. Were the people lining the street unaware of this? No, they were aware of the
political nature of the event. Why sing a verse from the Ramayana, a story of kings,
otherwise? If their Ashirwad was to Modi, a human being, a Gujarati, or a person, they
could have chanted more suitable verses for such an act. Yet, they did not. Without
orchestration by a spin doctor, they chose a verse from an epic about politics. One could
say that the older men on the pavement were religious, and even deeply so (Sri
Vaishnavas, probably). Their raised hands were not signalling political messages, like
the Hitler Salute.
Ashirwad’s primary place is in festivals and ceremonies expressing the ‘religious’;
streets and motorcades do not attract them. These were not the blessings of a Pontiff to
the believers thronging the streets either. The people in the streets of Srirangam were
Hindus, yes, but all of them were not followers of the RSS or the BJP, even if some of
16
them were. Yet, all recognised a political event and acknowledged and celebrated the
return of a king. Their Ashirwad focused on a politician. As though this was not enough,
they sang a verse about the King. In short, yes, politics entered daily life, but it did so
with the full knowledge of the actors. As far as these people were concerned, it did not
interfere in a ‘religious event', whether it included taking the ritual dip in the sea or
involved raising hands in Ashirwad. ‘Religion’ mixed with politics, yes. In the streets of
Srirangam, the religious became what it is in India because politics adorned it, even if no
conductor made the choir sing a political verse in chorus.
I speak of Srirangam because what happened there happened in Ayodhya as well.
Politics did mingle with ‘religion’, and this was so experienced by every Hindu (if not
every Indian). When people resonated with the Ayodhya event, they responded to it in an
astonishing way that did not indicate either acceptance or surrender of people to the
BJP or the RSS propaganda. “Positive” talks about Hinduism by the functionaries of the
state do not motivate people. It is the event alone, which is neither “purely religious” as
our tatvadarshis wish nor an admixture of politics and religion, making them “impure”.
What am I trying to say here?
In the intellectual world we inhabit, the sacred and profane, religion and the secular, are
intrinsically different realms because God and the world are separate from each other.
That is, the world of the gods is not and cannot be the world of men. The Creator and His
creations are separate realms in ways that make God’s intervention in our world, the
interference of God in the affairs of Human beings, an exceptional event. Islam does not
allow such interventions, but both Judaism and Christianity need them. Without the
covenant with Yahweh, there is no nation of Israel; before led into the promised land, the
Jews were strangers or slaves elsewhere. Without the Messiah, there is no Christianity or
hope of salvation or the atonement of sins. Even if God is outside time and space,
Semitic religions insist that He created the Cosmos located in time and space. Whether
God is humanly accessible or not, whether He intervenes in the world or not, the realms
do not meet or mingle. If we attempt mixing these, the world becomes impure, and we
blaspheme. Human history records the results of trying to add religion to politics, law to
religion, or religion to human affairs. Derived from an exegesis of the gospel of Luke, the
story of the two swords (the material and the spiritual) is long and tragic. Who should
wield these swords, the Pope, or the emperor? Whatever the answer, this much is clear:
mixing religion and politics has led to strife, pain, and human suffering. While this is
true, this story could become our story if and only if there is an ontological separation
between our world on the one hand and what makes us into “God’s people”, namely
religion, on the other.
Sheldon Pollock, a respected Sanskritist-cum-Indologist, authored a book some time
ago titled The Language of the Gods in the World of Men. In one sense, the title is
appropriate if we think of Hebrew and the tower of Babel. In another sense, it suggests
an incomplete thought because, among other things, the book is about Sanskrit, the
“daivabhasha”, and India. Here, we pursue a different train of thought. Devabhasha can
exist in the world if and only if the Gods live in the human world or if humans live in the
world of divinities. I do not suggest that Indian culture requires seeing the world as
‘sacred’. The Bible would agree here because God’s creations are sacred. They reflect
His Glory. But I do suggest what is a trivial piece of knowledge to all Hindus, if not all
17
Indians: whatever exists in this world has existence only in this world (Jagat, Vishwa)
because there is nothing outside this. The Gods may have their own worlds but are also
in the Vishwa. The world or the Jagat encompasses all that was, is, and shall be. Nothing
is far enough in space nor distant enough in time for it not to exist in our cosmos. If this
were not the case, we could never access the Gods because nothing outside this world
is accessible to us. The human and the divine conduct their affairs in this world, and, of
necessity, there will be interactions in this single Vishwa between these two miniworlds. We might know nothing about the nature of these mini-worlds or the lokas of
Gods; we might not know details and specifics of the hows and whys of these
interactions. It might even be the case that the gods are not there at all and that their
worlds have no existence. Whatever the facts of the matter, we do know there are no
separate realms of existence, speaking ontologically. We and the gods exist together if
either of us exists at all.
Thus, our question becomes: what is politics in such a world? If politics is about human
affairs, what exactly are these affairs? Do they exclude the gods, and if we tried, could
we succeed in excluding them? Who or what can direct and steer the gods if their affairs
include interfering in human affairs? The issue is about something other than whether
you think Ganesha or Kali exist somewhere in the cosmos, on some unexplored planet
or in an unknown galaxy. It is this: working within the circumscription of the framework
just sketched, how could people think about politics in this culture? Surely, our
ancestors thought about politics and formulated some questions and answers about
social and human existence.
It is essential to notice the focus and the scope of my claims: the assertion is not that
the Ancient Indians have answered or could address problems of our 21st century world.
However, the way they formulated issues and the lines they sketched when pursuing
their enquiries are what we need today. Living in a world without knowing the ontological
separation between religion and politics, our ancestors formulated questions about
politics. Even though our world is the same as the one they lived in, the languages we
use, and the conceptual frameworks embedded in these languages differ. We need
clarity about their questions and see the world we share with them. While we pontificate
about secularism, we do so with few clues about what religion is or even what it does.
Idol worship, the holy, consecration, penances, etc., do not belong in our cultural world,
which is why we fail to identify them. If we want to talk about the affairs in this world,
should we not try to find out how our ancestors thought and talked before there was a
Locke or a Mill or a Rawls? We should.
This understanding of the world implies an exciting experience of politics that differs
from what we have been fed. Our knowledge of politics and the nature of our political
practices (to the extent it depends on what we think politics to be) would then be
different from what we know about either of the two today. If politics has to do with
governance, we will investigate the what and the how of governance differently.
What happened in Ayodhya expresses this different awareness, which resonates deeply
with what lives in our culture. Modi signalled this difference while speaking of a new age
and trying to draw a contrast between history and the past. We might want to heap
insults on him, draw on third-rate political psychology to sketch his personality, and do
18
‘comparative politics’ by bringing Putin, Trump, and Erdogan into the picture. Such
activities might endear us to some while irritating others simultaneously. Trolls might
even love us because it would encourage their favourite pastime, trolling. However, if we
focus on this, we will miss a crucial insight: the psychology of an individual is deeply
influenced by the cultural psychology of a people, which, in turn, impacts social
psychology as well. The intellectual poverty of both these psychological domains in
Western thought can only be assessed by those who appreciate the richness and
sophistication of Indian thinking in these areas, even where they are millennia old.
3. The third reference point is also about politics, expanding the previous thread by
partially outlining our task. This act has two players but revolves around Rama Lalla, the
princeling currently resting in the palace.
Mehta puts the issue this way: “Prime Minister Narendra Modi (is) now donning the
mantle of Hindu kingship…” Well, here is what a Hindu might say in reply: with the pran
pratishtha, Rama is back in the palace. He is around five and must grow up to become
an adult before building his Kingdom, the Rama Rajya. Because he is still a child, he
cannot immediately ascend the throne to rule the Kingdom. Currently, the Amatya or the
Maha Mantri stands behind the empty throne, advising when needed, serving the land
and the throne in the name of the would-be King. He serves but does not rule, which is
perhaps why he calls himself a pradhana sevak. Whatever their moral characters, such
political figures are known to us as the Regents. In any case, this Maha Mantri can “don
the mantle of kingship” if and only if he usurps the throne, but not otherwise. Only as the
usurper could he become the King. The question is obvious: apart from acquiring the
title of ‘consecration’, does the Ayodhya Pran Pratishtha celebrate usurpation as well?
Why would anyone (however duplicitous) bring the rightful heir back to the palace and
seat him next to the empty throne in the royal court, only to don the mantle of kingship
thereafter? Is this “the election steal” the US knows so much about?
In any case, for the young prince to grow up and build his Kingdom, he must receive the
required education that makes him fit to rule and be the King he would become. This
means forming and grooming him, and that he acquires knowledge. He must learn many
skills as well. To be fit for the empty throne, the prince needs a teacher. Not anyone can
“don” this mantle: such a person must deserve to be a rajaguru, the one who teaches
the prince to become a king. The problem, of course, is: where and how is this person to
be found?
To begin with, the Maha Mantri should seek such a figure now. Playing the regent and
standing behind the empty throne also gives him this responsibility. It is imperative and
onerous but highly urgent and essential. He is the first of the two players.
We are the second players. As intellectuals, we must produce knowledge. Chanting
Western mantras has not helped so far: the fifty-fifth genealogy of the social contract,
the thousandth commentary on Plato’s Republic or Locke’s Two Treatises, and the
millionth hurrah song on constitutional democracy are useless. Our culture provides the
heuristics required to think creatively, productively, and originally. We have inherited
interesting questions and the ability to think through them. As we proceed, we can make
the required alterations and modifications, developments, and enlargements. We can
19
sketch alternatives to what exists. With robust theories in place, we can end our
mindless mimicry. “Alternative theories in politics” is neither a slogan nor a joke. This
goal requires creating alternatives to sophisticated practices and complex institutions
that have been with us for three thousand years. No individual, group or generation
could accomplish such a mammoth task. Yet, the task remains ours. Knowledge is
needed when ignorance rules. We cannot use vague slogans as new and exciting
knowledge because we do not confront toddlers. As in the old days when learned
people came together to endow the titles of Brahmasri, our Western colleagues will test
our mettle today. They will judge, umpire, and referee because our public is not entirely
or only Indian.
We face many dangers here because our society ceaselessly incentivises mimics, grows
parasites, and stimulates and rewards salesmen selling snake oil. Still, the young
prince, Rama, patiently awaits his Rajaguru. Such a guru can only come from those in
whose hearts Saraswathi has taken a permanent abode. It is possible, just possible, that
the Ayodhya event indeed portends this new age, the Indian Pratyabhijnana.
20