Systems in Context
On the outcome of the Habermas/Luhmann‐debate
Poul Kjaer
Abstract1
Usually regarded as a 1970s phenomenon, this article demon‐
strates that the debate between Jürgen Habermas and Niklas Luh‐
mann continued until Luhmann’s death in 1998, and that the
development of the two theorists’ positions during the 1980s and
1990s was characterised by convergence rather than by diver‐
gence. In the realm of legal theory, the article suggests, conver‐
gence advanced to the extent that Habermas’ discourse theory
may be characterised as a normative superstructure to Luh‐
mann’s descriptive theory of society. It is further shown that the
debate’s result was an almost complete absorption of Habermas’
theory by Luhmann’s systems theoretical complex – an outcome
facilitated by Luhmann’s deliberate translation of central Haber‐
masian concepts into systems theoretical concepts. The article ar‐
gues that both the debate and Habermas’ conversion were made
possible because not only Habermas’ but also Luhmann’s work
can be considered a further development of the German idealist
tradition. What Luhmann did not acknowledge was that this ma‐
noeuvre permitted the achievement of Habermas’ normative ob‐
jectives; nor did he notice that it could eradicate a central flaw in
the system theoretical construction, by allowing the context with‐
in which distinctions are drawn to be mapped – an issue of pivotal
importance for grasping relationships between different social
systems, and coordinating them, via the deployment of legal in‐
struments.
1. Introduction
In the 1970s, much of German social theoretical dis‐
course centred around the debate between Niklas Luh‐
mann (1927‐98) and Jürgen Habermas (1929‐), that was
launched in 1971 by their publication Theorie der Gesellschaft
oder Socialtechnologie – was leistet die Systemforschung?2 The
central question in this debate was whether the idea of
emancipation through rational political steering – the core
element in Enlightenment thinking, as well as in German
idealism – could still be considered as meaningful. Luh‐
1
2
66
European University Institute, Florence. E‐Mail: poul.kjaer@iue.it.
The author would like to thank Claire O´ Brian and Henning
Trüper for extensive comments on an earlier draft. Responsability
for content remains with the author.
Jürgen Habermas/Niklas Luhmann, Theorie der Gesellschaft oder
Sozialtechnologie – was leistet die Systemforschung? (Frankfurt am
Main. Suhrkamp Verlag, 1971).
mann argued that it could not. Habermas conversely advo‐
cated for a revitalisation of Enlightenment ideals and Ger‐
man idealism, to be achieved by development of an
‚updated’ theory of emancipation.3
At a first glance, the debate ended with publication of
Habermasʹ Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns (1981) and
Luhmann’s Soziale Systeme (1984). Subsequently, it was
widely thought, the two theoreticians had moved so far
away from each other that they no longer had anything to
discuss. Luhmannʹs staging of Soziale Systeme as a work
which paved the way for a social theoretical paradigm shift
from thinking in identity to thinking in distinctions,4 was
seen as confirming this view.5 According to Luhmann him‐
self, the latter move represented systems theoryʹs final
break with Enlightenment thinking and the German ideal‐
ist tradition and, therefore, with the starting point of Hab‐
ermasian theory.6
It is the argument of this article, however, that it re‐
mains both possible and fruitful to articulate Habermasʹ
theoretical ambitions, as they have developed since the
publication of Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, using
system theoretical tools advanced by Luhmann from the
publication of Soziale Systeme onwards.
Such an undertaking is less controversial than it may at
first appear. Luhmann himself initiated such a project in
the years after publication of Theorie des kommunikativen
Handelns by posing the question: „Was wäre gewonnen,
was ginge verloren, wollte man die Theorie der rational ar‐
gumentierenden kommunikativen Praxis in eine Theorie
autopoietischer Kommunikationssysteme übersetzen?“7
3
4
5
6
The rather misleading term philosophy of consciousness is nor‐
mally used to capture the tradition from Descartes to Husserl,
whereas the term German idealism is used as a narrower concept
which covers the theoretical development from Fichte to Husserl.
However, in the lack of a better concept German idealism is in this
text used in a broader sense, which captures the tradition from
Kant, Fichte and Hegel over Husserl to Habermas.
Niklas Luhmann, Soziale Systeme. Grundriß einer allgemeinen Theorie
(Frankfurt am Main. Suhrkamp Verlag, 1984), p. 18ff.
E.g. Urs Stäheli: Sinnzusammenbrüche. Eine dekonstruktive Lektüre
von Niklas Luhmanns Systemtheorie (Weilerswist, Velbrück Wissen‐
schaft, 2000), p. 14.
The term systems theory is throughout the article used synony‐
mously with Luhmann’s systems theory.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
He made his reply in a number of articles, often disregard‐
ed, in which he presented a system theoretical reformula‐
tion of central Habermasian concepts, such as lifeworld
(Lebenswelt),8 understanding (Verstehen)9 and trust (Ver‐
trauen).10
Yet Luhmann never completed this task. In the late
1980s, his direction altered as he increasingly focussed on
the concept of paradox, which he had drawn from the work
of George Spencer Brown.11 Additionally, Luhmann’s at‐
tempted translation of central Habermasian into systems
theoretical concepts was a one‐sided project. Consequently,
he failed to appreciate that such an enterprise inevitably
builds a Trojan horse, with potential profoundly to alter
systems theory’s self‐understanding and world‐perspec‐
tive.
This article advances eight hypotheses: 1. The central
difference between Habermas’ and Luhmann’s theoretical
positions is reducible to a difference in assessment of the
time‐consuming character of social operations. 2. Haber‐
masʹ position is based on the concept of lifeworld; but this
concept lacks logical coherence. 3. The concept of reitera‐
tion, presented by Luhmann as an alternative to the concept
of lifeworld, is logically more stringent. 4. Luhmann’s the‐
7
Niklas Luhmann, Autopoesis, Handlung und Kommunikative Ver‐
ständigung (Zeitschrift für Soziologie, Jg. 11, Heft 4, Oktober 1982,
pp. 366‐379), p. 376.
8 Niklas Luhmann, Die Lebenswelt – nach Rücksprache mit Phänome‐
nologen (Archiv für Rechts‐ und Sozialphilosophie, vol. 72, Heft. 2, pp.
176‐94, 1986).
9 Niklas Luhmann, Systeme Verstehen Systeme, pp. 72‐117 in: Niklas
Luhmann and Karl Eberhard Schorr (Hrsg.), Zwischen Intrans‐
parenz und Verstehen. Fragen an die Pädagogik (Frankfurt am Main,
Suhrkamp Verlag, 1986).
10 Niklas Luhmann, Familiarity, Confidence, Trust: Problems and Alter‐
natives, pp. 94‐107 in: Diego Gambetta (ed.), Trust: Making and
Breaking Cooperative Relations (New York. Basil Blackwell Ltd,
1988). The concept of trust is, strictly speaking, not a habermasian
concept. By Luhmann the concept of trust can, however, be under‐
stood as complementary to the concept of meaning, in the sense
that it represents a specific form for the concretisation of meaning.
The presence of trust furthermore acts as a precondition for
achieving understanding. Consequently, the system theoretical
path from meaning over trust to understanding seems to be very
similar to the path from lifeworld over communicative action to
understanding in Habermas’ work.
11 This move towards a focus on paradox was more precisely
launched with the publication of Luhmann´s contribution to femi‐
nology in 1988: See Niklas Luhmann, Frauen, Männer und George
Spencer Brown (Zeitschrift für Soziologie, Jg. 17, Heft 1; Februar,
1988, pp. 47‐71). It will be illustrated later on that this move
towards a focus on paradox did not solve the problems which it
was supposed to solve, since it did not establish a link between the
logical foundations of the systems theory and the level for con‐
crete analysis’ of social phenomenaʹs, just as it did not provide the
theory with an mechanism which can be used to clarify what it is a
given system is constituting itself against.
oretical elaboration nonetheless failed to grasp the impor‐
tance of context for the constitution of social phenomena,
sharply reducing its strength. 5. This shortcoming can be
traced to Luhmannʹs attempt to de‐couple systems theory
from the German idealist tradition – which he executed via
a sophisticated self‐mystification strategy, which sought to
present systems theory as a new theory, lacking connection
to any existing tradition of social thought. Foundational, in
constructing this mythology, was the concept of paradox. 6.
Removing this self‐mystifying overlay, the social theoreti‐
cal toolbox assembled by Luhmann can be used to promote
a radically different world‐perspective, lacking the kind of
scepticism dominating the late Luhmannʹs systems theory,
and which accords with the German idealist tradition from
which systems theory originally emerged. 7. Consequently,
Luhmann’s and Habermas’ legal theories can be viewed as
owning a common basis in the German idealist tradition,
which provides a structural basis for their conversion. 8.
Such a conversion allows for an understanding of the two
theories as complementary, in so far as the late Habermas’
discourse theory becomes a normative superstructure to
Luhmann’s descriptive theory of the society.
2. Time
The difference between Luhmann and Habermasʹ theo‐
retical constructions is a difference in time. The central im‐
portance of time in Luhmann’s work manifests in his adop‐
tion of the mantra in George Spencer Brown’s calculus of
indication: „Draw a distinction“.12 The purpose of intro‐
ducing such a distinction is to produce a difference, because
only a difference between this and that makes possible the
observation of this or that.13 According to Luhmann, the
drawing of a distinction is an operation that unfolds in time.
It takes time for someone – that is, the observer, who is al‐
ways presupposed14 – to draw or set a border, thereby con‐
stituting a form: „Formsetzung ist …Unterscheiden, und
12 George Spencer‐Brown, Laws of Form (London. George Allen and
Unwin Ltd, 1969), p.3. Importantly, distinctions are always made
within a given context in Spencer‐Brown’s account.
13 Niklas Luhmann, Das Erkenntnisprogramm des Konstruktivismus und
die unbekannt bleibende Realität, pp. 31‐58 in: Niklas Luhmann, Sozi‐
ologische Aufklärung 5. Konstruktivistische Perspektiven (Opladen,
Westdeutscher Verlag, 1990), p. 34.
14 According to both Luhmann and Spencer‐Brown, the assumption
of an observer does not imply an ontological point of departure:
the assumption is „brought back“ into the calculus through a so‐
called re‐entry operation. A re‐entry operation implies that the
form re‐emerges in itself and, thereby, constitutes itself as a self‐
referential phenomenon. Furthermore, self‐referentiality implies
that the first distinction is the distinction between the observer and
the observed, and that it is this distinction which is brought back,
with the consequence that it becomes possible for the observed to
observe itself.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
67
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
Unterscheiden ist eine Operation. Und das setzt, wie alles
Operieren, Zeit voraus“.15
But introducing a distinction is only the first step. An
observer also needs to indicate one side of the distinction in
order to remain attached to the distinction. So, Luhmann
defines observation as the unity of distinction and indica‐
tion: „Observing means making a distinction and indicat‐
ing one side (and not the other side) of the distinction“.16
But both sides cannot be simultaneously indicated – even
though they are constituted in the same moment – since
that will lead to the distinction’s disappearance. On the ba‐
sis of difference between distinction and indication, there‐
fore, Luhmann concludes that distinction‐making opera‐
tions are characterised by structural simultaneousness and
operative non‐simultaneousness: „Struktural gesehen ex‐
istiert die Zwei‐Seiten Form im Zeitmodus der Gleichzeiti‐
gkeit. Operativ gesehen ist sie nur im Nacheinander der
Operationen aktualisierbar“.17
This difference between structural simultaneousness
and operative non‐simultaneousness is central to Luh‐
mann’s attempt to theorise the relationship between sys‐
tems and their surroundings. But beyond this, it is the cen‐
tral element in the theory of autopoesis which Luhmann
presented in Soziale Systeme, and which he later coupled to
his version of the calculus of indication.18 The theory of au‐
topoesis is used by Luhmann to conceptualise the reproduc‐
tion of distinction making. Autopoetic systems are defined
as systems which produce the conditions of their own exist‐
ence. Operations are their constitutive element, in the sense
that autopoietic systems maintain themselves through op‐
erations recursively attached to preceding operations.19
Consequently, a system only exists as an actually ongoing
operation for the time period between the preceding and
the following operation.20 As a result, autopoetic systems
are characterised by an autonomous consciousness of time,
in the sense that no direct equivalence exists between a sys‐
tem’s internal time consciousness and time consciousness
15 Niklas Luhmann, Die Paradoxie der Form, pp. 197‐212 in: Dirk Bae‐
cker (Hrsg.), Kalkül der Form (Frankfurt am Main. Suhrkamp Ver‐
lag, 1993), p. 199. Exactly when a calculus starts generating time,
however, is disputed. Luhmann claims that all difference‐making
operations imply the existence of time: Niklas Luhmann, „Die Par‐
adoxie der Form“, p. 198f. With reference to Spencer‐Brown, Dirk
Baecker, however, claims that: „Die Unterscheidungsoperation
verbraucht keine Zeit… Zeit kommt …erst auf der Ebene der
Unterscheidung von Unterscheidungen ins Spiel“, that is when
self‐referentiality has already been established. See Dirk Baecker,
Im Tunnel. pp.12‐37, in: Dirk Baecker (Hrsg.) Kalkül der Form
(Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp Verlag, 1993) p. 29.
16 Niklas Luhmann, The Paradox of Observing Systems (Cultural Cri‐
tique. Fall, pp. 37‐55, 1995), p. 43.
17 Niklas Luhmann, „Die Paradoxie der Form“, p. 202.
68
in its surroundings. Every change within a system takes
place according to the system’s own tempo and in the sys‐
tem’s own rhythm. Consequently, it can be concluded, it is
not only according to the calculus of indication, but also ac‐
cording to the theory of autopoesis, that social systems
should be understood as phenomena operating in their
own time.
That systems operate in their own time has far reaching
consequences: „Was gleichzeitig ist läßt sich nicht beein‐
flussen, läßt sich nicht in die Kausalkonstellationen des Sys‐
tems einbeziehen, läßt sich nicht synchronisieren“.21 In oth‐
er words, any attempt to understand relations between
systems as causal relations are doomed to fail: „denn Kau‐
saliät erfordert eine Zeitdifferenz zwischen Ursachen und
Wirkungen, also ein Überschreiten der Zeitgrenzen des
Gleichzeitig‐Aktuellen“.22
18
This autopoetical concept is not an Luhmanian invention. Rather,
it should be considered as a modernised version of Husserl’s
Phänemenologie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins. See Edmund Husserl,
Vorlesungen zur Phänemenologie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins, in: R.
Boehm (Hrsg.), Husserliana X (Den Haag, 1966). This has been
pointed out by Armin Nassehi among others. See Das Identische
„ist“ das Nicht‐identische. Bemerkungen zu einer theoretischen Diskus‐
sion um Identität und Differenz (Zeitschrift für Soziologie, Jg. 22, Heft
6, Dezember, 1993, pp. 477‐81). Both Luhmann and Husserl seem
attached to Fichte’s concept of the subject which constitutes itself.
See Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Über den Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre
oder der sogenannten Philosophie (Stuttgart. Philipp Reclam Jun.,
[1794], 1972), Niklas Luhmann, „Soziale Systeme“, p. 60, Armin
Nassehi, „Das Identische ‚ist’ das Nicht‐identische“ and Marek J. Sie‐
mek, Fichtes und Husserls Konzept der Transzendentalphilosophie, pp.
96‐116, in: Wolfram Hogrebe (Hrsg.): Fichtes Wissenschaftslehre
1794. Philosophische Resonanzen, (Frankfurt am Main. Suhrkamp
Verlag, 1995). Additionally, Husserl’s concept is closely affiliated
to Augustine’s theory of time, which Luhmann also seems to be
aware of: See Niklas Luhmann, Die neuzeitlichen Wissenschaften und
die Phänomenologie, (Wien, Picus Verlag, 1995), p. 35, footnote 23.
Thence, it is possible to retrace the genealogy to Aristotle’s theory
of temporal substantiality. See Montgomery Forth, Transtemporal
Stability in Aristotelian Substances (The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 75,
1978), pp. 624‐646.
19 In Humberto Maturana’s words: autopoetic systems „…are sys‐
tems that are defined as unities as networks of productions of
components that recursively, through their interactions, generate
and realise the network that produces them and constitute, in the
space in which they exist, the boundaries of the network as com‐
ponents that participate in the realisation of the network“. See
Humberto R. Maturana, Autopoesis, in Milan Zeleny (ed.): Autopoe‐
sis: A theory of living Organization (New York, North Holland,
1981), p. 21. Also quoted in Niklas Luhmann, Essays on Self‐refer‐
ence (New York/Oxford, Columbia University Press, 1990), p. 3.
20 Or, in Jean Clam’s expression, a system is „…a ‚non‐real’, purely
‚actual’ system, containing nothing and made of nothing but oper‐
ations“. See Jean Clam, System’s Sole Constituent, the Operation:
Clarifying a Central Concept of Luhmannian Theory (Acta sociologica,
Vol. 43, Nr. 1, 2000, pp. 63‐79), p. 63.
21 Niklas Luhmann, „Das Erkenntnisprogramm des Konstruktivismus
und die unbekannt bleibende Realität“, p. 42.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
The conceptualisation of social phenomena as non‐
causal runs through Luhmann’s work as a major theme
from beginning to end. Causality was the principal topic of
his first publication, Der Funktionsbegriff in der Verwaltungs‐
wissenschaft23 (1958), and predominant in his first large theoret‐
ical work, Zweckbegriff und Systemrationalität (1968). In the
latter, influenced by the works of Ernst Cassirer, he adopt‐
ed Kant’s concept of „causality of freedom“: „Das Kausal‐
schema ist kein Schema der Determination, sondern ein
Schema der Freiheit“,24 in so far as, „Ursachen und
Wirkungen, also Input und Output, wechselseitig füreinander
als Gesichtspunkte der Selektion fungieren“: 25 Thus, the rejec‐
tion of the notion of causality cannot be understood as a
consequence of the introduction of the calculus of indica‐
tion or the concept of autopoesis. Instead, the introduction
of these new tools delivers a final argument for a long‐
standing desire to reject the notion of causality.
Thus, introduction of the theory of autopoesis and the
calculus of indication undoubtedly increase the possibili‐
ties for observation: they are more potent, and more sophis‐
ticated, than the tools of observation developed in Luh‐
mann’sʹ earlier work. Yet, they do not necessarily enable
our perception of the world in a completely different light,
as Luhmann in effect claims, by staging Soziale Systeme as
the pile driver in a radical social theoretical paradigm shift,
which implies a change from thinking in identity to think‐
ing in difference. Or, differently expressed: the introduc‐
tion of these new tools sharpens system theoretical ideas,
but does not entail any fundamental alteration to the social
perspective of systems theory, since the point of departure
for ‚thinking the social’ in Luhmann’s work, both before
and after Soziale Systeme, remains the idea that society can
be understood as a „causality‐free zone“.The drastic theo‐
retical consequences Luhmann derives from the distinc‐
tion‐theoretical turn thus appear arbitrary. Immanent rea‐
son appears lacking for the shift in perspective between the
early Luhmann, who in 1968 chose to focus on freedom of se‐
lection, due to the non‐existence of causality, and the „in‐
22 Niklas Luhmann, Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft (Frankfurt am
Main, Suhrkamp Verlag, 1997), p. 605.
23 Niklas Luhmann, Die Funktionsbegriff in der Verwaltungswissen‐
schaft, (Verwaltungsarchiv. Zeitschrift für Verwaltungslehre, Verwal‐
tungsrecht und Verwaltungspolitik, vol. 49, 1958, pp. 97‐105).
24 Niklas Luhmann, Zweckbegriff und Systemrationalität. Über die
Funktion von Zwecken in Sozialen Systemen (Frankfurt am Main,
Suhrkamp Verlag, 1968), p. 250.
25 Ibid. p. 250. Luhmann’s italics. See also Gorm Harste, Kant und
Luhmann über Teleologie in politischer Kommunikation und Natur, pp.
169‐83 in Gorm Harste, Thomas Mertens and Thomas Scheffer
(Hrsg.), Immanuel Kant über Natur und Gesellschaft (Odense,
Odense University Press, 1996).
creasingly anarchical“ later Luhmann, who instead chose to
observe the other side of the medal, stating: „Gleichzeitig‐
keit ist Chaos“.26
In contrast to Luhmann’s emphasis on structural simul‐
taneousness and operative non‐simultaneousness of social
operations, Habermas argues that social operations are
characterised by structural and operative simultaneousness.
Habermas’ approach derives from the notion of inter‐sub‐
jectivity, which claims „sprach‐ und handlungsfähigen
Subjekten“27 are constituted through their relations to other
subjects. Consequently, the existence of a plurality of sub‐
jects must be regarded as a structural condition. This point
of departure Habermas combines with the possibility of an
operationally‐established concordance between two or
more subjects’ view on the world. More precisely, it is „die
Gleichursprünglichkeit von Darstellung, Kommunikation
und Handeln“28 which creates this possibility for objectivi‐
ty, since „einer Verständigt sich mit einem anderen über et‐
was in der Welt“.29 Habermas argues, in other words, that
communicative acts can be understood as operations
which, without generating time, can establish accordance
between two or more subjects’ perspective on the world:
„Als Darstellung und als kommunikativer Akt weist die
sprachliche Äuβerung in beide Richtungen zugleich. Zur
Welt und zum Adressaten“.30
3. Lifeworld
It is to illustrate the centrality of operative simultane‐
ousness to communication that Habermas develops his var‐
iant of the concept of lifeworld. The lifeworld is defined as
the context, composed of culturally and linguistically or‐
ganised patterns of interpretation, within which the
„sprach‐ und handlungsfähige Subjekte“31 find them‐
selves. It is a common ground, comprising „Selbstverständ‐
lichkeiten oder unerschütterten Überzeugungen“,32 which
make it possible for two or more subjects to constitute a
26 Niklas Luhmann, „Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft“, p. 527.
27 Jürgen Habermas, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, Band 1.
Handlungsrationalität und gesellschaftliche Rationalisierung (Frank‐
furt am Main, Suhrkamp Verlag, 1981) p. 386.
28 Jürgen Habermas, Warheit und Rechtfertigung. Philosophische Auf‐
sätze (Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp Verlag, 1999), p. 9. Italics in
original.
29 Jürgen Habermas, „Wahrheit und Rechtfertigung“, p. 9. Habermas’
italics.
30 Ibid. p. 9. Habermas’ italics.
31 Jürgen Habermas, „Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, Band 1“,
p. 386.
32 Jürgen Habermas, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, Band 2. Zur
Kritik der funktionalistischen Vernunft (Frankfurt am Main, Suhr‐
kamp Verlag, 1981), p.189.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
69
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
common understanding of the world on the basis of an al‐
ready existing shared interpretation of it.
Nevertheless, the lifeworld cannot just be a ground
(Boden), but must also be a horizon, since the lifeworld is
moving ahead at the same pace as the observer. Conse‐
quently, the lifeworld must be understood as constituted by
the distinction between ground and horizon. According to
Luhmann, this concept of lifeworld, developed by Hus‐
serl33 and adopted by Habermas,34 is based on a paradox.
This is because the lifeworld cannot be the firm ground
where all observations and actions are unfolded and, at the
same time, an infinite horizon which simply is the WORLD:
it cannot be moveable, if it is firm and, if it is firm, it cannot
be moveable.35 Consequently, Luhmann presents an alter‐
native formulation of the problem, replacing the meta‐
phorical concepts of horizon and ground with a distinction
between familiarity and non‐familiarity (Vertrautem/Unver‐
trautem). Now, familiarity represents the ground, and non‐
familiarity the horizon, thereby avoiding the contradictions
inherent in the misleading opposition between the station‐
ary and the movable as found in Husserl’s and Habermas’
concepts of lifeworld.
4. Reiteration
The central element in the calculus of indication, as al‐
ready mentioned, is that only one side of a distinction, and
not the other, is indicated at any given moment. Yet it al‐
ways remains possible to perform a time‐consuming cross‐
ing, from one to the other. Such a crossing, whose purpose
is to indicate the other side, can in principle be reiterated in‐
finitely. In principle, in this situation, on every occasion
one’s indication will be the same. However, though one al‐
ways indicates the same, the result is never the same!36 This
is because indication leads to condensation of the indicated.
Every time an indication is reiterated, the observer obtains
33 Edmund Husserl, Erfahrung und Urteil (Claassen & Goverts, Ham‐
burg, 1948), § 7‐9.
34 Jürgen Habermas, „Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, Band 2“,
p. 182ff.
35 Niklas Luhmann, „Die Lebenswelt“, p. 177ff.
36 This insight originated with Kierkegaard’s treaty Gjentagelsen. See
Gjentagelsen: Et Forsøg i den experimenterende Psychologi af Constan‐
tin Constantius in Søren Kierkegaard. Samlede Værker, Bind 5
(København, Gyldendal, 1843 1995), pp. 113‐194, English transl.
Repetition: A Venture in Experimenting Psychology by Constantin Con‐
stantius in Howard and Edna Hoy (Editors), Fear and Trembling/
Repetition: Kierkegaard’s Writings, Vol. 6 (N.J, Princeton University
Press, 1983), which has also been a source of inspiration for differ‐
ent forms of post‐modern thinking. For a literary example, see
Milan Kundera, Nesnesitelná lehkost byti, 1984, English Transl. by
Michael Henry Heim, The unbearable lightness of being (Faber, 1999),
where the central distinction is weight/lightness, and where
weight is constituted through reiteration.
70
an increased feeling of what is being indicated. Reiteration
attributes an additional value to the indicated, and it is ex‐
actly this value which Luhmann defines as familiarity. The
lifeworld must therefore be understood as, „ein
unvermeidliches Kondensat des Unterscheidens“,37 be‐
cause all indications have a side‐effect, namely a higher de‐
gree of condensation. Consequently, Luhmann can elevate
the lifeworld, so that it assumes the status of a central and
omnipresent phenomenon: „Die Lebensweltdifferenz von
vertraut/unvertraut ist und bleibt die älteste, urtümlichste
primordiale Differenz, weil sie an jeder eingeführten Unter‐
scheidung kondensiert.“38
This attribution has radical consequences. According to
Luhmann, when one reiterates an operation, once the dis‐
tinction familiar/unfamiliar has already been established
through an earlier operation, then the crossing of a distinc‐
tion, to indicate the other side, does not cancel indication of
the side which one is leaving.39 Put differently, when an op‐
eration is a reiterated operation, both sides can, in fact, be
indicated in the same moment. By the lights of Luhmannʹs
own theory, therefore, reiteration must lead to dissolution
of the given distinction, since both sides cannot be indicat‐
ed at the same time if the distinction is to be maintained.
Consequently, one can – at any time – embark on a journey
into the unknown without giving up the known. Just as one
can bring the unknown home, in the form of symbols, „we
can live within a familiar world because we can, using sym‐
bols, reintroduce the unfamiliar into the familiar. We never
have to leave the familiar world. It remains our life‐world:
We never cross the boundary: it remains a horizon that
moves as we move. But we know in a familiar way about
the unfamiliar“.40
With this approach, Luhmann presents a logically co‐
herent and operative version of the phenomenological con‐
cept of lifeworld.41 Since he also clarifies when operative si‐
multaneousness is possible, that is, when an operation is a
reiterated operation, Luhmann also provides an answer to
a crucial question, following automatically from Habermas’
claim concerning the possibility of operative simultaneous‐
ness, and which Habermas himself has never answered.
5. Context dependency
Still, it is important to understand that incorporation of
Habermasʹ notion of lifeworld in the system theoretical uni‐
verse is not a one‐sided undertaking. The concept of life‐
37
38
39
40
41
Niklas Luhmann, „Die Lebenswelt“, p. 182.
Ibid., p. 186.
Ibid., p. 182.
Niklas Luhmann, „Familiarity, Confidence, Trust“, p. 95.
Ibid., p. 95.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
world, to a great extent, is a Trojan horse which, once inside
the walls, can trigger a profound shift of focus within sys‐
tem theory itself. This is not just because the system theo‐
retical concept of lifeworld can be used to clarify the condi‐
tions for achievement of operative simultaneousness; the
concept of lifeworld can also rectify a basic flaw in systems
theory. Systems theory does not contain a mechanism for
determining what a system constitutes itself against,42 giv‐
ing rise to systematic vagueness. Luhmann acknowledges
that the surroundings of a system rarely remains undeter‐
mined: „Normally our indications will frame our observa‐
tions with the effect that the other side implicitly will re‐
ceive a corresponding specification“.43 But this only serves
to displace the problem, given its implication of the exist‐
ence of a second, common boundary: „In this case the indi‐
cation implies a double boundary, the inner boundary of
the frame … and the boundary of this frame“.44
Moreover, Luhmann does not seem to take the conse‐
quence of the insight that the outside typically will be de‐
termined, since his empirical analysisʹ tends to give the im‐
pression that social systems can be viewed as detached
phenomenaʹs, which are being constituted through a dis‐
tinction made in free air. Consequently, the strength of his
empirical analyses is being massively reduced, in so far as
they tend to render a somewhat implausible and counterin‐
tuitive impression of how society operates. This impression
could, however, have been avoided if Luhmann had made
the choice to systematically incorporate the system theoret‐
ical concept of lifeworld when conducting his empirical in‐
vestigations.
6. German Idealism
System theory’s lack of focus on the function of context
is not an isolated technical problem. On the contrary, it is a
fundamental defect that can be traced to Luhmann’s at‐
tempt to de‐couple systems theory from the German ideal‐
ist tradition.
The importance of the problem of context within Ger‐
man idealism is demonstrated by the example of the colour
red in Kantsʹ Kritik der reinen Vernuft (1781): „Wenn ich mir
rot überhaupt denke, so stelle ich mir dadurch eine Be‐
schaffenheit vor, die (als Merkmal) irgend woran angetrof‐
fen, oder mit anderen Vorstellungen verbunden sein kann;
also nur vermöge einer vorausgedachten möglichen syn‐
thetischen Einheit kann ich mir die analytische vorstel‐
42 Jean Clam also draws the attention to this problem. See Jean Clam,
„System’s Sole Constituent“.
43 Niklas Luhmann, „The Paradoxy of Observing Systems“, p. 44.
44 Ibid., p. 44.
len“.45 According to Kant, it is only possible to think the
colour red through a simultaneous indication of the phe‐
nomena in relation to which the colour red stands. A think‐
ing of the colour red, therefore, includes a thinking of the
frame within which the colour red is constituted.46
This insight is a shaft that runs through Kant’s work. In
Kritik der Urteilskraft (1790), he concludes that judgments
must have general validity, since an observer’s judgment
must be related to those of other observers concerning the
same issue. In turn, this implies the existence of a frame of
possible, comprehensible and perhaps overlapping, though
not necessarily completely identical, judgments: „... da der
Urteilende sich in Ansehung des Wohlgefallens, welches er
dem Gegenstande widmet, völlig frei fühlt: so kann er keine
Privatbedingungen als Gründe des Wohlgefallens auffind‐
en, an die sich sein Subjekt allein hinge, und muβ es daher
als in demjenigen begründet ansehen, was er auch bei
jedem andern voraussetzen kann; folglich muβ er Glauben
Grund zu haben, jedermann ein ähnliches Wohlgefallen zu‐
zumuten“.47 So, whereas Luhmann erases the concept of
context from the calculus of indication (in notable contrast
to Spencer‐Brown), thereafter stating that distinctions are
typically made within a context and producing a vast
number of empirical analyses where the importance of con‐
text is downplayed as much as possible, Kantʹs work is
characterised by greater coherence between the logical
foundations and concrete analysis of social phenomena.
Hegel, likewise taking a distinction introduced in a giv‐
en context as his starting point, presents a perspective sim‐
ilar to Kant’s. In the debate between Luhmann and Gerhard
Wagner and others, unfolding on the pages of Zeitschrift für
Soziologie between 1991 and 199548 and which focused on
the relationship between systems theory and Hegelian log‐
ic, Wagner argued that Luhmann’s adaptation of the calcu‐
lus of indication modifies the calculus in a way which
makes his position identical to Hegel’s. Wagner suggested
that, whereas Spencer Brownʹs logic of distinction assumes
that the sides of a distinction must be considered as sym‐
metric and side‐neutral,49 the most important change intro‐
duced by Luhmann lies in the latter’s contrary claim that,
45 Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernuft. Werkausgabe Band III und
IV (Suhrkamp Verlag. Frankfurt am Main, [1781], 1974), B134
46 Will Martens is also using the example of the colour red in his
comment to the relationship between identity and difference
within systems theory. But his point of departure is Hegel instead
of Kant. See Will Martens, Der verhängnisvolle Unterschied.
Bemerkungen zu den Beiträgen von Gerhard Wagner und Niklas Luh‐
mann in der ZfS 4 und 6 1994, (Zeitschrift für Soziologie, Jg. 24, Heft 6,
1995, pp. 229‐234).
47 Immanuel Kant, Kritik der Urteilskraft. Werkausgabe Band X
(Suhrkamp Verlag. Frankfurt am Main, [1790], 1974), B27, B18.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
71
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
„Observations are asymmetric (or symmetry‐breaking) op‐
erations“.50 As is well known, such asymmetric relations
include the distinctions master/slave, subject/object, sys‐
tem/surroundings and text/context,51 where the emphasis
is placed on the former in each pair. According to Luh‐
mann, asymmetries are necessary, as already mentioned,
because „the inner side has connective value“.52 A system
can only reproduce itself by attaching itself recursively to
the inner side: „The inner side is where the problem is – the
problem of finding a suitable next operation“.53 In other
words, the key issue is to connect a purely formal logic with
a social theoretical operationalisation of this logic, and this
necessitates the introduction of the concept of asymmetrical
distinctions.54
In Wagner’s view, this change is crucial since it implies
a shift in focus from dissimilarity („Verschiedenheit“) to
contradictions („Gegensatzpaare“). Dissimilarity, according
to Hegel, is simple difference, in the sense that there is noth‐
ing in the two units necessitating their dissimilarity. It is
purely external, lacks any logical foundation, and is based
exclusively on observation. Amongst typical dissimilarities
are those observed in comparing a car with an orange, or an
elephant with a pen. Oppositely, for Hegel, contradiction is
48 See Niklas Luhmann, Am Ende der kritischen Soziologie (Zeitschrift
für Soziologie, Jg. 20, Heft 2, April, 1991, pp. 147‐152), Gerhard
Wagner and Heinz Zipprian, Identität oder Differenz? Bemerkungen
zu einer Aporie in Niklas Luhmann’s Theorie selbstreferentieller Systeme
(Zeitschrift für Soziologie. Jg. 21, nr. 6, 1992, pp. 394‐405), Niklas
Luhmann, Bemerkungen zu „Selbstreferenz“ und zu „Differenzierung“
aus Anlaß von Beiträgen im Heft 6, 1992, der Zeitschrift für Soziologie
(Zeitschrift für Soziologie, Jg. 22, Heft 2, April, 1993, pp. 141‐146),
Gerhard Wagner and Heinz Zipprian, Anwort auf Niklas Luhmann,
(Zeitschrift für Soziologie. Jg. 22, 1993, pp.144‐46), Armin Nassehi,
„Das Identische ‚ist’ das Nicht‐identische“, Gerhard Wagner, Am Ende
der systemtheoretischen Soziologie. Niklas Luhmann und die Dialektik
(Zeitschrift für Soziologie, Jg. 23, nr. 4, 1994, pp. 275‐291), Niklas
Luhmann, Gesellschaft als Differenz: Zu den Beiträgen von Gerhard
Wagner und Alfred Bohnen in der Zeitschrift für Soziologie Heft 4
(1994) (Zeitschrift für Soziologie. Jg. 23, Heft 6, Dezember, 1994, pp.
477‐81), Will Martens, „Der verhängnisvolle Unterschied“.
49 Gerhard Wagner, „Am Ende der systemtheoretischen Soziologie“, p.
279.
50 Niklas Luhmann, Deconstruction as Second‐Order Observing (New
Literary History, 24, 1993, pp. 763‐782), p. 769. More forcefully:
„Deutlicher als dies bei Spencer Brown geschieht, sollte hier fest‐
gehalten werden, daß Unterscheidungen…in einer fundamentalen
Weise asymmetrisch sind“. See Niklas Luhmann, „Die Lebenswelt“,
p. 181. Also quoted in Gerhard Wagner, „Am Ende der systemtheo‐
retischen Soziologie“, p. 278.
51 Niklas Luhmann, „Gesellschaft als Differenz“, p. 280.
52 Niklas Luhmann, „Deconstruction as Second‐Order Observing“, p.
769.
53 Ibid., p. 769.
54 Niklas Luhmann, Neuere Entwicklungen in der Systemtheorie
(Merkur. Deutsche Zeitschrift für europäisches Denken, vol. 42, 1988,
pp. 292‐300), p.296.
72
dissimilarity refined in a particular way: a contradiction is
based on an inner difference, where the two sides depend
on each other. This is true, for instance, of concepts such as
positive/negative (Hegel’s own example), man/woman and
system/surroundings (Wagner’s examples), and the con‐
cepts of immanent/transcendent, being/non‐being or prop‐
erty/non‐property (Luhmann suggestions).55 According to
Hegel, the logical unity of such contradictions is expressing
identity, since the distinctions are dependent on each other,
which makes them „in einer Identität verschiedene“.56
Hence, Wagner argues that Luhmann does not succeed in
forcing a social theoretical paradigm shift by changing the
focus from identity to a focus on difference, as was his in‐
tention, since his distinctions are, like Hegelʹs, determined
distinctions.57
7. Paradox
Luhmann recognises that „all observations have to pre‐
suppose the existence of both sides of a distinction or
‚frame’ “.58 Nonetheless, the consequence of his views as
described above is to refute that systems theory is based on
a concept of identity. Instead, he argues, his theory is
founded on the paradox which results from his concept of
observation.59 An observation, as stated above, is an opera‐
tion that indicates one side of a distinction, but not the oth‐
er. A distinction of two sides, however, implies the exist‐
ence of a blind spot, since the observer can observe, but
cannot observe his own observation. Only a new, time‐gen‐
erating, observation can do that. One can, therefore, distin‐
guish between a first order observer who focuses on what
(was) is observed, and a second order observer who ob‐
serves how (wie) the first order observer observes. The sec‐
ond order observer can see what the first order observer
cannot – the first order observer’s observation. Yet this does
not give the second order observer a privileged position,
since she cannot observe her own observation either. The
second order observer is therefore a first order observer
herself when she is being observed by another third order
observer.
55 Niklas Luhmann, „Deconstruction as Second‐Order Observing“, p.
769.
56 G. W. F. Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik II. Werke in zwanzig Bänden,
Bd. 6 (Suhrkamp Verlag. Frankfurt am Main, [1813] 1970), p. 60.
57 Illustration of the context‐problem in German idealism could, and
should, be extended in order to include the positions of Fichte and
Husserl, but that task is beyond the scope of this article.
58 Niklas Luhmann, „Deconstruction as Second‐Order Observing“, p.
769. Luhmann adopts the term „frame“ from Erving Goffman, and
claims that his use of it accords with Goffmann’s intentions. See
footnote 21 in Niklas Luhmann, „Deconstruction as Second‐Order
Observing“.
59 Niklas Luhmann, „Gesellschaft als Differenz“, p. 477ff.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
The concept of observation allows Luhmann to avoid
Wagner’s critique: Luhmann can claim that the only basic
element in systems theory is observations observing other
observations. Observations consist of the unity of a distinc‐
tion and an indication, which means they are a unity of two
different elements. Since Luhmann defines a paradox as the
unity of different things, he is entitled to conclude that the
true basis of systems theory is paradox, not identity.60
Hence, in denying the concept of identity as the basic
concept of systems theory, the Luhmann of the late 1980s
and 1990s abandoned not only identity, but also the con‐
cept of distinction as well. The late Luhmann, in other
words, exceeded the distinction between distinction and
identity, in order to base his theory on paradox.
8. Meaning
According to Husserl, Habermas as well as Luhmann
himself the function of the concept of lifeworld is to evade
the kind of paradoxes on which the late Luhmann focused.
Nevertheless, Luhmann claims that a concept of world
is too general to serve as a basis for any profound analysis
of social phenomena.61 An alternative framework for
achieving de‐paradoxialisation, he suggests, would arise
from an answer to the question: „How is it possible to ob‐
serve frames?“62 And to develop such a framework, Luh‐
mann instead emphasises the concept of meaning (Sinn):
„we will certainly need a medium that is the same on both
sides of the frame, on its inside and on its outside. I propose
to call this medium meaning“.63 The latter concept, accord‐
ing to Luhmann, is „coextensive with the world“.64 So,
while he believes the notion of world to be excessively gen‐
eral, he apparently considers the concept of meaning more
useful – in spite of the fact that it includes phenomena iden‐
tical in extent to the world. Luhmann’s rationale for avoid‐
ing the notion of world must therefore lie elsewhere. One
part of it is that, „Sinn ist…ein Produkt der Operationen, die
Sinn benutzen, und nicht etwa eine Weltqualität, die sich
einer Schöpfung, einer Stiftung, einem Ursprung ver‐
dankt“.65 The main purpose of distinguishing the concepts
of world and meaning, in other words, is to avoid associa‐
tions with the Story of the Creation and other acts of initia‐
60 Niklas Luhmann, „The Paradoxy of Observing Systems“, Niklas Luh‐
mann, „Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft“, p. 57 f., Niklas Luhmann,
„Die Paradoxie der Form“.
61 Niklas Luhmann, „The Paradoxy of Observing Systems“, p. 41.
62 Ibid., p. 41.
63 Ibid., p. 41. Luhmann’s italics.
64 Ibid., p. 41.
65 Niklas Luhmann, „Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft“, p. 44. Luh‐
mann’s italics.
tion. Thus, the distinction between world and meaning
does not seem particularly salient, when it is seen in rela‐
tionship to the concepts of lifeworld developed by Husserl,
Habermas and Luhmann himself, since they all understand
the lifeworld as a product of continued social operations,
and not as the result of an act of initiation. Consequently, it
is difficult to identify the real difference between, on one
hand, the intended function of Luhmannʹs concept of mean‐
ing and, on the other, the notion of lifeworld, as it occurs in
the works of Husserl and Habermas: both concepts aim at
the observation of „frames“ – in other words, contexts –
which can be defined as operationally constituted unities,
comprising a distinction and both of its sides.
More concretely, the function of the concept of meaning
in Luhmann is to achieve de‐paradoxialisation through a
neutralisation of the asymmetry he was earlier forced to in‐
troduce into the calculus of indication, in order to make it
an operational social theoretical tool: „Sinn ist also eine
Form, die auf beiden Seiten eine Copie ihrer selbst in sich
selbst enthält. Das führt zur Symmetrisierung des zunächst
asymmetrisch gegebenen Unterschiedes“.66 As an upshot,
Luhmann could have circumvented Wagner’s critique, and
at the same time avoided entering the labyrinth of paradox‐
es if he had complemented the move towards a focus on
paradoxes with an upgraded concept of meaning. The con‐
cept of meaning, as already suggested, can be used to de‐
scribe the kind of social continuity required to ensure a
balancing of the fundamental experience of social disconti‐
nuity which follows from the introduction of a distinction.
On this background, an upgraded concept of meaning
could have emphasised that the constant flow of social op‐
erations is conditioned just as much by the continuing re‐
production of a medium which is identical on both sides of
any given distinction as it is characterised by a reproduc‐
tion of paradoxical tensions. Luhmann chose not to go
down this path and his contingent choice to pursue an es‐
sentially paradox‐based theory instead threatens to under‐
mine one of the key elements of systems theory, namely its
ability to explain how social structures can be characterised
by rupture and stability at the same time. In tandem, a rad‐
ical focus on paradoxes threatens to transform Luhmann’s
theoretical construction into a purely metaphorical exer‐
cise.
The concept of meaning, therefore, remains irre‐
placeable but also crucial to the theory’s overall viability.
While this, in principle, was recognised by the late Luh‐
mann,67 he never transformed the concept of meaning into
66 Ibid., p. 50.
67 Niklas Luhmann, „The Paradoxy of Observing Systems“, p. 41.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
73
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
a useable tool for describing social phenomena. Instead, it
was retained as a general background notion, encompass‐
ing everything and therefore signifying nothing. As a con‐
sequence, Luhmann’s concept of meaning is not sufficiently
precise to rectify the systematic vagueness of systems theo‐
ry, identified above, which prevents determination of what
it is a given system constitutes itself against.
The failing concretisation of the concept of meaning
could have been offset by the concept of trust. Yet, while the
early Luhmann built up an elaborate concept,68 trust was
subsequently marginalised, and almost never deployed by
Luhmann to describe the interaction of social structures.
Moreover, the emphasis of paradox is not in itself suffi‐
cient to constitute a break between systems theory and Ger‐
man idealism. Both Kant and Hegel acknowledge the para‐
doxical character of the world. Kant expresses this through
the distinction between nature and freedom, which also
constitutes the world as a unity of difference. Hegel’s start‐
ing point is the paradoxical unity of the identical and non‐
identical. Thus, neither Kant nor Hegel dismisses the fun‐
damental significance of paradox. Instead they supplement
this ancient insight, introducing the concepts of judgment
and spirit. These they use to establish distance from a given
distinction, without dissolving it, with the aims of balanc‐
ing the experience of paradox, and enhancing the possibili‐
ty of observing contexts within which distinctions are
drawn. Judgment and spirit, in other words, are to the Kan‐
tian and Hegelian theoretical edifices, as the concept of
meaning is to systems theory. As illustrated above, though,
Luhmannʹs idealist predecessors achieved greater coher‐
ence than did he, between the logical foundations of their
respective theories and the level of elaboration necessary to
generate concrete analyses of social phenomena.
9. Self‐mystification
System theory’s inability to grasp the significance of the
context of distinctions is also applicable to the theory itself.
In responding to this flaw Luhmann developed a sophisti‐
cated self‐mystification strategy,69 devising a highly imagi‐
native terminology to go with it. Indeed, so successful was
he in this strategy, that many present day system theoreti‐
68 Niklas Luhmann, „Vertrauen: ein Mechanismus der Reduktion sozialer
Komplexität“, 4. Auflage, Stuttgart: Lucius und Lucius, 2002.
69 The direct result of this self‐mystification strategy was the creation
of an autonomous universe through the development of hundreds
of new concepts. Consequently, it has been deemed necessary to
publish a dictionary aimed at explaining this new language to the
rest of the world. See Detlef Krause, Luhmann‐Lexikon: eine Ein‐
führung in das Gesamtwerk von Niklas Luhmann (Lucius & Lucius,
Stuttgart, 2001).
74
cians appear to believe that Luhmann himself was respon‐
sible for the basic concepts of the systems theory. Conse‐
quently, many theoreticians also believe that systems
theory is not embedded in any existing tradition – a prob‐
lematic view, given that most system theoretical concepts
derive almost directly from German idealism. For example,
this is true of the basic distinction system/world, resem‐
bling the traditional subject/object distinction; the concepts
of meaning (Husserl), autopoesis and temporalisation
(Kant, Fichte and Husserl); Luhmann’s version of the calcu‐
lus of indication (Kant, Hegel); and the concepts of causali‐
ty, reflexivity and rationality (Kant) and self‐reference
(Kant, Fichte). So, even though Luhmann „never engages in
a painstaking and subtle reading of the classical canon of
social theory“,70 of the type undertaken by Derrida and
Habermas, amongst others, one must agree with Haber‐
mas’ statement that Luhmann’s „Unternehmung sucht An‐
schluß … an die Problemgeschichte der bewußtseinsphilos‐
ophie von Kant bis Husserl.“71
Failure to acknowledge this heritage is becoming a
major threat to the systems theory’s future utility as a tool
for social theoretical analysis. This is because, firstly, it has
the consequence that many of Luhmann’s disciples are only
capable of defending systems theory from within, whereas
they require a language bestowing a capacity to argue out‐
side its own frame72; secondly, because it provides a struc‐
tural basis for theoretical fundamentalism, visible, for
example, in the attempt to elevate the calculus of indication
to a position where it supplies the basis of all other system
theoretical concepts. Electing such a strategy for further
theoretical development, however, undermines one of the
strongest elements of system theory – namely, the stability
its non‐reductionist version possesses as a system, precisely
because it is not based on any one element but on a whole
range. One can always fetch another tool from the box if the
first does not seem to fit. Such plurality also secures the the‐
ory against the kind of foundationalism which, as a radical
anti‐totalitarian, Luhmann sought to avoid.
Were a fundamentalist and purely paradox‐oriented
version of systems theory to achieve discursive dominance,
the reduction of the theoretical complex to a Zeitgeist phe‐
70 Urs Stäheli, Writing Action: Double Contingency and Normalization
(Distinktion. Tidsskrift for samfundsteori, Nr. 1, 2000, pp. 39‐47), p.
40.
71 Jürgen Habermas, Der philosophische Diskurs der Moderne. Zwölf
Vorlesungen (Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, 1989), p. 426.
72 Stefan Rossbach The myth of the system: On the development, purpose
and context of Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory, pp. 1‐36, http://
www.essex.ac.uk/ecpr/events/jointsessions/paperarchive/copen‐
hagen/ws9/rossbach.PDF, p. 36.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
nomenon would also be likely. Especially so, given that a
historical view of the up‐ and downturns of thinking in
paradoxes reveals that a focus on paradoxes, with irony as
its faithful guardian, expands in periods of transition.73
Thus, it is no coincidence that the paradox‐oriented version
of systems theory had its breakthrough in terms of social
science in the 1990s, an époque dominated by discontinuity
arising from political upheaval, the dissolution of systems
of thought, and the expansion of fin de siècle semantics.
On an alternative view systems theory represents a fur‐
ther development of the German idealist tradition of Kant,
Fichte and Hegel to Husserl, which presents solutions to a
number of crucial but as yet unresolved problems within
that tradition. In contrast to earlier forms, systems theory is
an explicitly post‐ontological theory. Moreover, Luhmann
delivers the first convincing description of the relationship
between the self‐ and external reference of social systems,
so solving the problem of solipsism, an important dilemma
in German idealism since Fichte’s problematisation of the
tautological constitution of the subject in the works of the
early Kant.74 That Luhmann was able to offer solutions to
such problems provides a good illustration of systems the‐
73
The classic example here is the Renaissance, where thinking in
paradoxes, especially within the literature of scepticism, became a
widespread form of argumentation. See Barbara C. Bowen, The
Age of Bluff. Paradox & ambiguity in Rabelais & Montaigne (Chicago.
University of Illinois Press, 1972), Rosalie L. Colie, Paradoxia Epi‐
demica: The Renaissance Tradition of Paradox (Princeton, N.J., 1966),
A. E. Malloch, The Techniques and Function of the Renaissance Para‐
dox (Studies in philology, vol. 53, 1956, pp. 191‐203) and Michael
McCanles, Paradox in Donne (Studies in the renaissance, vol. 13, 1966,
pp. 266‐287). During the Renaissance, however, there was also
widespread understanding of the limitations of paradox, since it is
a self‐destructive form of argument, where an argument only can
be met through dissolution of the argument which one chooses to
refute it with. Or, as expressed by Montaigne, quoted after A. E.
Malloch, „The Techniques and Function of the Renaissance Paradox“,
p. 203: „ ... this final fencer’s trick [the paradox] should not be
employed except as a last resource. It is a desperate thrust, in
which you have to abandon your weapon in order to disarm your
adversary, and a secret ruse which should be practised seldom
and with reserve. It is a very foolhardy thing to lose your life in
order to kill another“. The paradox, in other words, serves as a
doctrine for mutually assured destruction of argumentation, in the
sense that it serves at the constitutive fundament for any argu‐
ment at the same time at it remains impossible to use in practice.
Luhmann’s dismissal of the distinction between distinction and
identity in order to reject the concept of identity illustrates this
point very well.
74 Niklas Luhmann, Die Form „Person“, pp. 142‐54 in: Niklas Luh‐
mann, Soziologische Aufklärung 6. Die Soziologie und der Mensch
(Opladen, Westdeutscher Verlag, 1995, Original printed in Soziale
Welt, 42, 1991, pp. 166‐75), p. 143ff. See also Dieter Henrich, Fichtes
ursprungliche Einsicht (Vittorio Klostermann, Frankfurt am Main,
1967).
ory’s influence extending far into the universe of philoso‐
phy, notwithstanding Luhmann’s flirtatious rejections.75
Inveterate system theoreticians might reject a „return to
Kant and Hegel“ as a waste of time, or as absurd. But the
suggestion is not for a revival of thinking of the kind which
dominated the era of the French Revolution. Instead, ques‐
tions such as „Hegel or Luhmann?“ a focus of the Luh‐
mann/Wagner‐debate, should be rejected since it is not a
case of either or. Rather, it is necessary systematically to
confront systems theory with its own basis. This genealogi‐
cal endeavour would allow the theory’s liberation from its
own self‐mystifying semantics without total rejection.
Then, Luhmann’s rich social theoretical toolbox can be reo‐
pened and its contents applied to promote perspectives on
society other than the variety of societal scepticism advocat‐
ed by the late Luhmann – a choice that anyhow seems to
reflect the specificities of Luhmann’s personality, and his
experiences as a youth in Nazi Germany, rather than any
theoretical necessity.76
10. Convergence
If systems theory is „opened up“, as described above, it
becomes more compatible with other theories, and especial‐
ly with the theoretical complex resulting from Habermas’
reconstruction and renewal of German idealist insights.
Compatibility, though, is only a structural condition, pro‐
viding a possibility, but not a guarantee, of convergence. In
Faktizität und Geltung (1992) Habermas condensed the de‐
bate between himself and Luhmann, recycling more gener‐
al social theoretical questions into the language of legal the‐
ory. Habermas’ legal theory, moreover, dramatically
increased the links between his general theory and the sys‐
tem theoretical complex. So far reaching were these chang‐
es that it is possible to view Habermas’ theory after Fakti‐
zität und Geltung as a normative superstructure to
Luhmann’s descriptive theory of society.
Of these substantial changes, the first was the introduc‐
tion of the concept called „höherstufige Intersubjektiv‐
ität“77also characterised as a kind of „subjektlose Kommu‐
nikation“.78 With this move, Habermas takes an important
75 Niklas Luhmann, Paradigm Lost: Über die ethische Reflexion der
Moral. Rede anläßlich der Verleihung des Hegel‐Preises (Frankfurt am
Main, Suhrkamp Verlag, 1989), p. 9. This was also recognised by
Habermas through his characterisation of Luhmann as „der wahre
Philosoph“. See Jürgen Habermas, Die Einbeziehung des Anderen.
Studien zur politischen Theorie (Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp Ver‐
lag, 1997), p. 393.
76 Stefan Rossbach, „The myth of the system“.
77 Jürgen Habermas, Faktizität und Geltung. Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie
des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats, (Frankfurt am Main,
Suhrkamp Verlag, 1992), p. 362.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
75
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
step towards abandoning the subject as the nucleus of his
theory,79 thereby mitigating one key difference between the
design of his own and of systems theory. Unfortunately,
though, Habermas has never clarified with what alternative
he intends to replace the concept of the subject. Conse‐
quently, it remains difficult to see how his theory can be‐
come viable without adoption of an elaborated concept of
social systems.
The second substantial change concerns the relation‐
ship between law and morality. When Habermas devel‐
oped his discourse ethics together with Karl Otto Apel in
the 1980s, he insisted on the priority of morality over law.80
Yet in Faktizität und Geltung he states „ich gehe davon aus,
daβ sich auf dem nachmetaphysischen Begründungs‐
niveau rechtliche und moralische Regeln gleichzeitig aus tra‐
ditionaler Sittlichkeit ausdifferenzieren und als zwei ver‐
schiedene, aber einander ergänzende Sorten von
Handlungsnormen nebeneinander treten“.81 Hence, Haber‐
mas no longer presumes the existence of a hierarchical rela‐
tionship between morality and law, and abandons the at‐
tempt to uphold the kind of transcendentalism on which he
previously insisted.82 At the same time, this alteration rais‐
es the question of how society is being integrated. Declining
to provide any straight answer, by implication Habermas
accepts another key insight from Luhmann’s theory of the
society: one must assume, when not integrated through
morality, „[dass] die codes der Funktionssysteme auf einer
Ebene höherer Amoralität fixiert werden müssen“.83
Concretely, this means that it is impossible to insist on
the idea of discourse ethics as a viable framework for a the‐
ory of legitimate coordination within the realms of law and
politics. The alternative is a discourse theory aimed at de‐
veloping tools for achieving coordination, which do not
78 Jürgen Habermas, „Faktizität und Geltung“, p. 362.
79 As Luhmann points out, it is important to remember that a theory
of intersubjectivity has the subject, and not an unspecified „inter“,
as its key element. See Niklas Luhmann, Intersubjektivität oder Kom‐
munikation: Unterschiedliche Ausgangspunkte soziologischer Theorie‐
bildung, pp. 169‐88 in Niklas Luhmann, Soziologische Aufklärung 6.
Die Soziologie und der Mensch (Opladen, Westdeutscher Verlag,
1995. Original printed in Archivio di Filosofia, 54, 1986, pp. 41‐60),
pp. 169ff.
80 See Jürgen Habermas, Diskursethik – Notizen zu einem Begründungs‐
programm, pp. 53‐126 in: Jürgen Habermas, Moralbewusstsein und
kommunikatives Handeln (Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp Verlag,
1983) and Jürgen Habermas, Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik (Frank‐
furt am Main, Suhrkamp Verlag, 1991).
81 Jürgen Habermas, „Faktizität und Geltung“, p. 135. Habermas’ ital‐
ics.
82 This move was criticized strongly by Karl Otto Apel. See K.O.
Apel, Auseinandersetzungen in Erprobung des Transzendentalpragma‐
tischen Ansatzes (Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp Verlag, 1998).
83 Niklas Luhmann, „Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft“, p. 751.
76
claim that such coordination necessarily must be derived
from morality. This is also explicitly recognised by Luh‐
mann: „Der diskurstheoretische (im Unterschied zu einem
diskursethischen) Legitimationsbegriff, den Jürgen Haber‐
mas vorgesellt hat, paβt genau in diese Theorieposition
[The system theoretical position]. Er besteht aus den beiden
Teilen, die man für eine Kontingenzformel benötigt: einem
gänzlich unbestimmt bleibenden Teil, der in der Aussicht
auf Lösung von Kontroversen durch vernünftigen Konsens
(Einverständnis oder Vereinbarung) aller Betroffenen be‐
steht, und der Überführung dieses Letztsinns in handhab‐
bare Verfahrensregeln, die die Vermutung rechtfertigen,
daβ ein solcher Konsens eventuell erzielt werden kön‐
nte.“84 The move away from a discourse ethics, and to a dis‐
course theory, in other words, points towards replacement
of the „old‐European“ striving for totality on the basis of a
concept of morality, with a functional and pragmatic
approach, seeking to develop and deploy tools that can en‐
sure a continued coordination of the ongoing reproduction
of autonomous social systems. Consequently, the design of
mechanisms enabling such coordination is reduced to the
legal task of developing relevant procedural rules and safe‐
guards. The criteria for success, moreover, are being re‐
duced to empirical questions about the degree of coordina‐
tion achieved. In parallel, the normative element is
restricted to evaluation of the success of different coordi‐
nating measures, and their respective abilities to achieve
coordination without damaging the continued reproduc‐
tion and expansion of the functional differentiation of soci‐
ety.
Such an undertaking can be supported by insights con‐
tained in the system theoretical concepts of morality and
critique. As has several times been mentioned, the starting
point for the late Luhmann is the introduction of a distinc‐
tion, characterised by the existence of an asymmetrical rela‐
tionship between its two sides. In that context, the function
of meaning is to re‐introduce symmetry into the relation be‐
tween the two sides, so creating a two‐dimensional form
which, at the same time, is characterised by symmetry and
asymmetry. It is against this background that Luhmann in‐
troduces his concept of morality, stating that „Moral ist im‐
mer symmetrisierter Sinn“.85 The consequence is that he
can understand morality as exercising an alarm function
within the modern society, in the sense that moral commu‐
nication highlights pressing problems and asymmetries
that threaten to undermine the reproduction of functional
84 Niklas Luhmann, Die Politik der Gesellschaft (Frankfurt am Main,
Suhrkamp Verlag, 2000 – published posthumously), p. 124f.
85 Niklas Luhmann, „Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft“, p. 242.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
Poul Kjaer ‐ Systems in Context
differentiation. In contrast to a traditional understanding of
morality, as some sort of super medium, this allows for an
understanding of morality as a specific form of communi‐
cation which exercises a „support function“ for the proce‐
dural rules and safeguards deployed to ensure coordina‐
tion under the condition of continued functional
differentiation.
these concepts need to be applied, and need to achieve a
fundamentally different status within systems theory, since
they could solve a number of its central flaws – such as its
inability to determine what it is a given system constitutes
itself against, and the weakness of Luhmann attempt to
couple formal logic with a concept of social operationalisa‐
bility.
Luhmann’s concept of morality makes it possible to
question his claim that the system theoretical concepts of
lifeworld and meaning do not provide a basis for critique of
modern society.86 This is because the introduction of the bi‐
nary code symmetry/asymmetry de facto defends a „bal‐
anced society“, free from the excessive reduction of mean‐
ing which would flow from asymmetric relations between
different social systems. 87 Thus, Luhmann himself also
provides concepts that can be applied to achieve objectives
set by Habermas.
In sum, one outcome of the Habermas/Luhmann debate
is that the late Habermas’ discourse theory can be regarded
as a normative superstructure to Luhmann’s descriptive
theory of society. But a second is that, beyond the tendency
to the two theoretical complexes’ convergence, a complete
fusion, through the development of a fully fledged „inter‐
systemic“ and „critical“ systems theory, could provide a
viable basis for further theoretical development. Such a
theory might provide an optimal frame for the continuing
reformulation of legal theory.
11. Conclusion
The almost complete incorporation of Habermas’ theo‐
ry into the systems theoretical complex prompts the ques‐
tion: how much of Habermas’ attempt to develop an inde‐
pendent theoretical position actually persists? It appears
that Luhmann left almost nothing behind. Still, Luhmann
did not go far enough in attempting to incorporate Haber‐
mas’ theory. He developed a concept of lifeworld, but
instead of using it, he abandons it. Instead, he continues to
rely on the identical concept of meaning. The latter howev‐
er, is retained as a general background notion of little use in
practice. The concept of trust developed by Luhmann, and
which can in many respects be regarded as the practical
concretisation of the concept of meaning (in the same way
as Habermas’ concept communicative action can be seen as
a concretisation of his concept of lifeworld) is also left be‐
hind, and almost never applied in Luhmann’s empirical
analyses of society. Luhmann’s concept of understanding
suffers the same fate, and the same can be said of his treat‐
ment of the very Habermasian concepts of morality and cri‐
tique. None of Luhmann’s „translations“ of Habermasian
concepts, in other words, are effectively deployed. Yet,
86 Niklas Luhmann, „Die Lebenswelt“, P. 188.
87 Typical examples of asymmetries which lead to moral substitution
are when the economy enters the system of intimacy in the shape
of prostitution, when the medical system colonises the system of
sport through doping, or when the religious system enter the ped‐
agogical system through an intrusion of evangelism in the class
room. That these examples not only refer to the systems of econ‐
omy and power, and their colonisation of their surroundings, as
described by Habermas, illustrates the superiority of Luhmann’s
concept of balance, compared with Habermas’ concept of coloni‐
sation.
ANCILLA IURIS (anci.ch) 2006: 66 ‐ Article
77