Paper presented at the Pacific Rim Real Estate Society (PRRES) conference, Christchurch New Zealand
January 2002.
TOWARDS A DEFINITION OF PROPERTY RIGHTS
John Sheehan* & Garrick Small #
* National Native Title Spokesperson, Australian Property Institute, National Secretariat 6 Campion
Street Deakin ACT 2600, and Member Land Tribunal, Level 9 Tank Street Brisbane. Queensland
4000.
Email : sarasan@ihug.com.au
# Senior Lecturer, University of Technology, Sydney, Property Studies Program.
Email: garrick.small@uts.edu.au, garricks@optusnet.com.au
ABSTRACT
The notion of property rights has undergone fundamental change recently as a result of the
commodification of natural resources such as water and biota. All property rights result in
the conferral of three qualities or capacities, namely a management power, and ability to
receive income or benefits, and an ability to sell or alienate the interest.
However the transition from open access to property rights for natural resources has
drawn attention to just how we define whether “particular rights” are in fact property
rights. Property in the more familiar sense of land and buildings conveys a tenor of
regularity, constancy, and fixity – this is not so with the new forms of property which are
inherently sui generis.
As knowledge is gained as to the nature of these less familiar property rights accepted
truths regarding the notion of property rights are being shown to be only partial and
incomplete visions.
KEYWORDS
Property rights; property; water property rights; biota property rights
INTRODUCTION
Mario Vargas Llosa, a Peruvian novelist recently observed that while the discipline most closely
associated with globalisation is economics, other disciplines related to matters social, ethical and
cultural act as reminders that regional cultures remain surprisingly robust, pointing out that:
Page 1
2
[g]lobalisation will not make local cultures disappear; in a framework of worldwide
openness, all that is valuable and worthy of survival in local cultures will find fertile
ground in which to bloom.1
This is a poignant reminder that customs and laws of many societies have only undergone
incremental change throughout history, notwithstanding the sometimes violent precursors of such
change. Anglo-Australian land law is one such complex amalgam, and recent studies of its roots
in English custom and law reveal according to linguist Masson:
… a curious and most marvellous gift for mutability and metamorphosis, rooted in a rich,
complex and strange multilayered, multicultural history.2
Further, Masson observes of this legal transmogrification that:
[t]he violence and bloodiness of part of this [Norman] conquest which, unlike the earlier
Roman and Anglo-Saxon invasions, sought to extirpate an entire culture by destroying the
upper reaches of the conquered society and assimilating the rest by incorporating them
into a new system of law, are in many ways like the violent, bloody history of the frontier in
Australia, combined with the more peaceful installing of colonial administration..
Further,
[f]eudal Norman law, devised to firmly control both Norman lords and Anglo-Saxon
populace through a complex system of obligation and responsibility, was grafted onto
certain aspects of English law, which itself still had vestigial elements of both Roman and
Celtic laws. The genius of the Normans was ever in their syncretism.3
Inescapably property was of pivotal concern to those involved in conquest and dispossession, and
hence once acquired the value of property crystallised in the hands of the conquering Normans. In
keeping with other parts of Western Europe, the value of property was central to the maintenance
of civilisation. While the Norman lords held rights to the land and economic benefits, these were
conditional on service to the society. In particular, defense and civil order were funded from land
rents. Intermediate lords enjoyed property titles that were burdened by both rental obligations to
the higher lords, or the king, and service obligations to their vassals.
The connection between property ownership and obligation to the community was diluted over
time, despite the continuation of the formal feudal tradition of tenure. Land value emerged
explicitly as rental obligations to the sovereign and one's vassals were dissolved, leaving the
benefit of property liberated for personal enjoyment. It is the concept of economic value, often
1
Mario Vargas Llosa, “Locally speaking, global is good” The Sydney Morning Herald (10 February 2001)
3S
2
Sophie Masson “Here today, gone yesterday” The Sydney Morning Herald (14 October, 2001) 8S
3
Ibid
Commented [DGS1]: I think that you would benefit from
researching and reflecting further on this part of English
history.
Firstly, the culture each side of the channel was not as
dissimilar as recent English writers would like to imagine.
Both the Normans (named because they came to Gaul from
the north) and the Angles & Saxons were drawn from early
Germanic tribes, which meant that they shared a certain
primal cultural similarity. This is especially the case in the
ruling families of each. In addition, both were Christian and
shared much of the same understanding of society within that
religious framework, especially since St. Augustine of
Canterbury had linked the English closely to Europe five
centuries earlier.
Secondly, William was not an invading adventurer, but a
noble who for complicated reasons peculiar to the Middle
ages believed that he was not invading at all, but merely
taking over a birth right that had been denied him. That belief
explained his enthusiasm, the support he was able to muster
and also the acceptance his act received through the rest of
Christendom. This is not to say that the Saxons, especially the
former ruling class, did not resent his act. There later grew up
a kind of English mythology that has lauded the Germanic
spirit of the Angles and Saxons (& other pirate invaders) that
is somehow seen as the genesis of the superior quality of that
nation. This is usually pitted against the Roman culture that
crumbled (in the face of Germanic barbarian invaders) and
later European culture (William). The myth was useful when
England turned against European culture in the sixteenth
century and is symbolically evident in the pirate Francis
Drake who has become the hero of England and in many
ways one of the fathers of its empire.
Thirdly, the system of property and government that he
established was not novel in his time, despite being a better
refined form that England had previously seen. Feudalism
had been in existence as the dominant form of
political/economic organisation almost since the central
administration of Roman failed. William did reorganise it and
did put his men in the key positions. In some cases, his law
may have overturned native English practice, but not to a
significant degree, at least not to the degree necessary to
make the statement of the quote here.
Finally, the currently popular opinion of European (and
especially English) feudalism usually fails to take sufficient
account of the rationale justifying the apparent property
wealth of the nobility. Both poles of liberal thought today
entertain a vision of ancient feudal relationships that could
not have actually existed. These imagine ancient feudal lords
to be tyrants who created a system of property for the
oppression of the ordinary person. Under that model, kings
and their vassals used their property wealth to maintain an
unjust level of personal wealth and a standing army kept for
the purpose of suppressing the populace. There were some
corrupt lords, and they all tended to have a comfortable
lifestyle. However, their lifestyle was considered appropriate
because of the dignity of their station and the personal risks
and responsibilities that that they accepted. The income
differentials, especially in terms of net personal consumption,
between ancient kings and their people and contemporary
CEOs and the basic wage probably would make the kings
look poor. This is evident in the second part of the caricatue:
the purpose of the standing armies. While kings kept armies,
real battles in those days were mainly won by foot soldiers. ...
3
linked to its political implications of power, which tends to lie at the core of most discussions of
property rights, and as Ely observes in the North American context:
English common law provided the legal foundation for property ownership in the colonies.
Common law was customary law, deriving its authority from long-established usage. Royal
courts in England fashioned the common law into a body of rules that defined and
protected property rights…
The high value attached to landownership by the colonists is best understood in terms of
the English experience. In England, as in Western Europe generally, land was the
principal source of wealth and social status. Yet landownership was tightly concentrated in
relatively few hands, and most individuals had no realistic prospect of owning land.
Moreover, in theory no person owned land absolutely. All land was held under a tenurial
relationship with the Crown. Although there was a bewildering variety of tenure
arrangements, property ownership was conditional and involved continuing obligations to
a superior.4
Conceptually, property rights and the concept of value necessarily emerged as the twin liet motifs
of English property law, and its colonial American progeny. Anglo-Australian property law was
also a legal sibling of this tradition.
A Concept of Value for Property Rights
The modern concept of value, especially when given monetary expression, involves the potential
private allocation of worth to a particular parcel of land, usually as an estimate of its capitalised
future potentiality based on its current utility. The concept of ascribing monetary value to a
natural resource such as land has it roots according to Anderson in the:
…perdurable inheritance of classical antiquity. The Roman Empire, its final historical
form, was not only itself naturally incapable of a transition to capitalism. The very advance
of the classical universe doomed it to a catastrophic regression, of an order for which
there is no real other example in the annals of civilization. The far more primitive social
world of early feudalism was the result of its collapse, internally prepared and externally
completed.5
The transition between late Roman civilisation and the early Dark Ages was the atrophy of
property value. The estates of late Rome conferred great wealth on their owners, but this was of
little value in the face of civil decay. In the absence of civil government strong enough to enforce
private rights of property it was open to plunder by any party that had sufficient strength relative
to the owners. Feudalism was the result of fearful property owners surrendering formal title to
their property to military overlords in return for security. The overlords eventually appropriated
the mantle of government with formalised obligations to the community. While they technically
had title to property, its net value to them was low since it brought with it the onerous obligations
of providing security and other services now associated with the public sector. In that way, the
4
James W Ely Jnr. The Guardian of Every Other Right: A Constitutional History of Property Rights 2nd ed
Bicentennial Essays on the Bill of Rights (New York: Oxford University Press 1998) 10
5
Perry Anderson Lineages of the Absolutist State ( London: Verso 1979) 420.
Commented [DGS2]: John: I think that this quote is a little
oblique for our purpose. Historically, payment of money for
land goes back at least to Moasic times (see Leviticus 25).
The Romans no doubt had some trade in land, though I
suspect that such trade changed in nature during the course of
the empire. Even the early feudal period is probably not a
good time to cite for monetary trade in land - more tended to
change hands for military reasons.
4
value of property that existed in the civilised world of late Rome dissolved as private enjoyment
of property wealth was re-absorbed into the community in the person of the feudal lord. Value
began to re-emerge as the Dark Ages made its transition into the Middle Ages following the reign
of Charlemagne in the ninth century.
The re-civilisation of Europe created an arbitrage for the property-owning aristocracy since the
cost of providing defence and security fell as civil order returned. The aristocracy continued to
hold the land, but now with diminished effective obligations, which meant that it had a private
value to them. From this point, property once more meant private wealth, similar to the estates of
late Rome. The social sanction of its personal enjoyment and its economic potential for
concentration provided the fundamentals for the initiation of its capitalistic use in a way that late
Rome may have developed had civil order not failed. Marxist writers such as Anderson see
medieval Europe as a slow although inexorable transition to the “capitalist mode of production”,
although this phenomena appears however to have been unique to Europe because:
…the countryside of European feudalism also underwent an evolution that had no parallel
elsewhere. The extreme rarity of the fief system as a type of rural property…was never
known in the great Islamic states, or under successive Chinese dynasties, both of which
had their own characteristic forms of agrarian land tenure.6
The difference between the trajectory of feudalism in Europe opposed to other cultures was
largely connected with the unique evolution of commerce in Europe that was more quickly
extended into property. China, Japan, South America and Islam all displayed the intimate
connection of property and government that characterises feudalism. They also have histories
marked by the concentration of power, usually linked to property, that Marxist thought identifies
with capitalism. Unlike capitalism, that sanctions the commercial concentration of power, they
appropriated and held power directly using military or political means. While effective, that
approach was inferior to capitalism since it required Machiavellian discretion within the
appearance of holding property and power for an honourable purpose. European commerce was
signified by the elimination of the underlying ethic that made property a conditional right. This
ethical evolution at first proceeded discretely, but eventually flourished as Medieval ethics were
usurped by the social revolutions of the sixteenth century7. Anderson described this transition in
the European feudal notion of property rights as follows:
[t]he pure feudal mode of production was characterised by conditional private property in
land, vested in a class of hereditary nobles. The private or individual nature of this
landownership demarcated it, as Marx saw, from a whole range of alternative agrarian
systems outside Europe and Japan, where formal State monopoly of land, either original or
durable, corresponded to much less strictly ‘aristocratic’ possessing classes than knights
or samurai. But, once again, European development branched beyond that of Japan with
the transition from conditional to absolute private property in land, in the epoch of the
Renaissance.8
So, conditional private property in land was transformed to absolute private property with the
result according to Anderson being as follows:
6
Ibid 424
See Weber (1974) and Fanfani (1939)
8
Ibid
7
5
[t]he formula, however, contains a profound truth if applied in a somewhat different sense:
the transformation of one form of private property – conditional – into another form of
private property – absolute – within the landowning nobility was the indispensable
preparation for the advent of capitalism and signified the moment at which Europe left
behind all other agrarian systems. In the long transitional epoch in which land remained
quantitatively the predominant source of wealth across the continent, the consolidation of
an unrestricted and hereditary private property in it was a fundamental step towards the
release of the necessary factors of production for the accumulation of capital proper. The
very ‘vinculism’ which the European aristocracy displayed in the early modern age was
already evidence of the objective pressures towards a free market in land that was
ultimately to generate a capitalist agriculture.9
The transition of property from low value conditional to high value absolute/private paralleled the
rise in the merchant class to para-aristocracy. The period also saw the beginnings of the rise of
manufacturers to follow the steps of the merchants as challengers to landowners for private
wealth. Agricultural capitalism was overtaken by mercantile capitalism, industrial capitalism and
now financial capitalism as the most powerful visible forms of wealth control. As seen in the
failure of property after the decline of Rome, these can only exist in environments where civil
government has the strength and inclination to uphold the requisite property institutions. The
beneficiaries of property in early modernity recognised the importance of reinforcing civil
government as a means of securing their own position. Hence, private rights in property arose in
tandem with the emergence of ‘absolutist public authority’, where according to Anderson:
The increase in the political sway of the royal state was accompanied, not by a decrease in
the economic security of noble landownership but by a corresponding increase in the
general rights of private property. The age in which ‘Absolutist’ public authority was
imposed was also simultaneously the age in which ‘absolute’ private property was
progressively consolidated.10
These developments were paralleled by developments in social and ethical thought. Early postRoman feudalism of the Dark ages (500-800AD) was based on the equitable exchange of
property title for military protection and civil order. The Middle ages theory of property (800AD
to 1100AD) was based on an organic understanding of Christian society with the king as the
dispenser of the secular aspect of the will of God. The Medieval period (1100AD to 1500AD)
developed a more flexible concept of property based on human nature. In that theory of property,
the Aristotelian dual notion of private ownership with common use was developed. Feudalism
fulfilled the dual aspects of property. Being owned by the king, property could be efficiently and
responsibly managed, in a way that no socialist society has been able to match. However, the king
held title on the condition that its income was used appropriately for the welfare of the
community. This was the application of the benefit of property for the entire community, that is,
managed common use. The transition to absolutism required the development of the supposed
Divine right of kings that subtly released the king from this obligation by giving him absolute
authority over the use of the property with which he was entrusted. Absolute authority gave the
king the power to grant property absolutely to others thus giving freehold private enjoyment of
9
Ibid 425
Ibid 429
10
Commented [DGS3]: There were three pre-modern
economic institutions that distinguished it from capitalism.
These were 1. Property as obligation; 2. Just price; & 3.
Rejection of usury. Capitalism arose as a result of changes to
community attitudes of at least the first two, though inversion
of ethical sentiment towards all three was the hallmark of the
Renaissance. If you want to pursue this line in history we
should also discuss Weber's Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of
Capitalism of one of the other commentaries on the cultural
connection between the moral changes that flowed from the
religious changes of that century. Anderson's point about
Europe's unique trajectory towards capitalism compared to
other early feudal societies has more to do with fundamental
changes in European religious sentiments than a Marxist
would wish to admit. The reason why the Moslems did not
change was that their religion did not (and has not) change in
its economic ethics. China is similar, though in that case it
was more a matter of ethics based on paternal respect that
was not usurped till the twentieth century.
The notion of absolutism in the monarchy, or even the
aristocracy in general needs to be understood in the context of
this change. The pre-modern monarch (say 700AD, but
certainly 800AD, to 1500AD) was not absolute but held
power within Christian culture that generally understood that
the monarch's power was conditional exercising it consistent
with the will of God. After the sixteenth century that relation
was inverted in what is known as the principle of the divine
right of kings. That principle claimed that kings by nature did
the will of God, therefore they had no need to consider His
will in making judgements. This created the context for
absolutism that was manifested in
Marxist thought, built as it is on a conflict theory of human
relationships, has considerable difficulty recognising the
system of obligations that marked any of the feudal systems,
and hence is likely to miss the central dynamic of European
history, especially in contrast to other cultures.
6
property its ethical foundation. Once property could be unconditionally privately held, it acquired
value to the extent of the set of freehold rights that were granted.
Absolutism was primarily a political principle and was ushered in using a revised theory of
authority. It effectively dissolved the theoretical foundation for property as it had existed for the
previous millennia. The first attempts to rebuild a theory of property in an absolutist regime
followed the Medieval strategy of appealing to the nature of things. John Locke is often
considered the father of modern property theory when he reasoned:
"Though the Earth and all inferior Creatures be common to all Men, yet every Man has a
Property in his own Person. This no Body has any Right to but himself. The Labour of his
Body, and the Work of his Hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he
removes out of the State that Nature hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his Labour
with, and joyned to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his Property."11
Locke accepted that a man's labour was naturally his own and hence not to have title to it would
be a violation of natural justice. Since the farmer applies his labour to the land, if he did not have
title to the land, then his natural title to his labour would be uncertain. Hence, private property is a
necessary way to ensure natural justice. Locke's theory of property was consistent with his overall
vision of politics and economics, but it was flawed. His theory could only validate partial title,
based on the value of improvements. It would mean that a tenant clearing the virgin lands of a
landlord would gain title to them. Moreover, Locke was mute on how much labour one would
have to expend on property before title was warranted, on the contrary, he claimed:
"Thus the Grass my Horse has bit; the Turfs my servant has cut; and the Ore I have digg'd
in any place where I have a right to them in common with others, become my Property,
without the assignation or consent of any body" 12
The shortcomings of Locke's approach were recognised and later Enlightenment thinkers took
another approach at demonstrating the natural origins of absolute private property. Following the
revised notion of what constituted natural, the empiricists considered that human nature was
revealed by observing unconstrained human action. Hume went so far as to claim that nothing
more could be known of human nature than what was observed. On this basis, Hume's colleague,
Adam Smith, observed that private property was a fact of English society, and that it was
supported by English law. He emphasised the fact of possession and a legal/governmental
framework supporting a particular institution of property. In this way he could assert:
Property and civil government very much depend on one another. The preservation of
property and the inequality of possession first formed it, and the state of property must
always vary with the form of government.13
Legally sanctioned possession was the Enlightenment understanding of property, which led to
Smith's eighteenth century colleague, Lord William Blackstone, to summarise in his memorable
definition of property as:
11
Locke, John. 1693/1967. Two Treatises of Government. Edited by W. vonLeyden, critical edn.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Bk.2 Ch.V, n27]
12
ibid [II, ch V, n.28]
13
Smith, Adam. 1978. Lectures on Jurisprudence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ( p. 410)
7
"... that sole and despotic dominion which one man claims and exercises over the things of
the world, in total exclusion of the right of any individual in the universe." 14
This view of property has not changed appreciably since the eighteenth century, despite being
assailed by the socialists. It now tends to be justified more on the basis of supposed economic
efficiency than any recourse to the metaphysics of natures. It suits the absolutist approach, though
recent decades have seen the success of various appeals to soften the strong implications of
property being a despotic right.
With absolute private property, there emerged a concurrent need for definition of the territoriality
of the rights and interests within:
…[an] international state-system that defined and demarcated the continent as a whole.15
With this need for accurate definition, came the need for concomitant valuation of the worth of
the private property so defined. Murray usefully describes the concept of value, which has
emerged to deal with private property as follows:
Value in the economic sense means the benefit conferred by ownership, which includes not
only the possibility of exchange for other commodities, but all the satisfaction that may
arise from possession.16
Further, he states that the valuer:
…normally has to deal only with that concept of value which is known as “value in
exchange.” In other words he has to measure the market value; that is to say, the relativity
existing between the subject property and other properties and commodities.
The market value of land at a certain date may be defined as the amount of money that the
land would bring in the open market by voluntary bargaining between vendor and
purchaser, both willing to trade but neither of them so anxious to do so, that he would
overlook any ordinary business consideration. We must further suppose both to be
perfectly acquainted with the land, and cognizant of all circumstances which might affect
its value, either advantageously or prejudicially, including its situation, character, quality,
proximity to conveniences or inconveniences, its surrounding features, the then present
demand for land and the likelihood, as then appearing, to persons best capable of forming
14
Blackstone, Willian. 1979. Commentaries on the Laws of England: A facsimile of the First Edition of
1765-69. Edited by S. N. Katz. 4 vols. Chicago: Chicago University Press. (p. 2)
Ibid 431
16
John F N Murray Principles and Practice of Valuation (Sydney: Commonwealth Institute of Valuers),
1969
15
8
an opinion, of a rise or fall for what reason soever in the amount which one would
otherwise be willing to fix as the value of the property.17
This description of market value by Murray has it roots in a definition enunciated in Spencer v
The Commonwealth of Australia (1907) 5 CLR 418 at 441, where Isaacs J applied the following
test for market value:
To arrive at the value of the land at that date, we have…to suppose it sold then, not by
means of a forced sale, but by voluntary bargaining between the plaintiff and a purchaser
willing to trade, but neither of them so anxious to do so that he would overlook any
ordinary business consideration. We must further suppose both to be perfectly acquainted
with the land and cognizant of all circumstances which might affect its value, either
advantageously or prejudicially, including its situation, character, quality, proximity to
conveniences or inconveniences, its surrounding features, the then present demand for
land, and the likelihood as then appearing to persons best capable of forming an opinion,
of a rise or fall for what reasons soever in the amount which one would otherwise be
willing to fix as to the value of the property.
Jefferies usefully answers the question of what is value in the following way:
Value has many interpretations depending upon the definition and terminology used. There
can be different types of value, such as replacement value, sale value, loan value, market
value, insurance value….
For something to have value it must have utility, or be able to arouse desire for its
possession to satisfy some need through its possession or use. Mere usefulness or even
necessity on its own will not create value in an economic sense unless there is also the
element of scarcity. A common example is air, which because it is in free abundance does
not have a value in an economic sense, though having a very high utility. However, with
some modern buildings and structures, such as fully enclosed shopping complexes and
modern office blocks, specially conditioned air is supplied as part of a controlled
environment which certainly adds value to the space for leasing purposes.
For something to be valued it must also be negotiable in a market, having the purchasing
power to be exchanged for money.
Therefore to be valued, property must have utility and scarcity, which arouses the desire of
a purchaser who has the purchasing power and ability to acquire it and obtain its
possession.
Real estate, has the added characteristic of permanence compared with other consumer
goods which may be used up in satisfying the short-term needs or desires of the purchaser
with possibly some residual waste for disposal, Real estate is durable property which has
17
Ibid
9
the almost unique characteristic of extending the benefits of its ownership over very long
periods. The value of real estate arises out of its future benefits to the owner and therefore
its value is the present worth of the future utility to be enjoyed from its possession in the
future. As a result the value of real property must take into account the trends in the local
and general economy, and should reflect the degree to which the market recognises future
benefits. The utilities that real estate gives to an owner may include the anticipation that
there will be some benefit in the use and occupation of the property; some profit in its
rental; a potential for development into a higher and more intense use than present; or the
anticipation that the real value will increase and provide the owner with a capital gain.18
In applying these definitions of market value, a body of valuation theory and practice has
developed in Australia and New Zealand over the past century, and can be ascertained in classic
works such as Murray19, Jefferies20 and Rost and Collins21. Indeed, the activity of ascribing the
worth of property can be traced back to at least biblical times according to Murray22, who notes
that Ephron in selling his field to Abraham is quoted as saying:
My Lord, hearken unto me: the land is worth 400 shekels of silver; what is that betwixt me
and thee? (Genesis xxiii)
However, the body of valuation theory and practice has been garnered from an understanding that
the property rights to be valued are in the familiar guise of useful buildings constructed upon a
basic site. This familiar union of human product, fused to a natural, and primevally common,
resource blurs appropriate understanding of the underlying issues. There is a tenor of regularity,
constancy, and fixity in such property, all of which comes from the site alone, reflecting a
synergy of absolute private property, despotic control and enjoyment, territorial definition, and
economic/legal value .
The extent of property rights is always a positive human convention. The development of
absolute private property was a gradual accretion of private rights out of the public, or common
domain. Rights such as exclusive possession tend to be necessitated first by agricultural people.
The right to bequeath or sell land becomes a priority when either the land contains durable human
products or the culture sanctions the private enjoyment of land rent. The separation and exclusion
of certain rights to minerals within the land is a relatively recent development, driven by the
relative value of these things and the recognition by the state that they have a worth not to be
alienated lightly. Recent developments in urban organisation have necessitated focus on the right
to construct improvements and the control and sharing of that right through urban planning statute
and the use of easements.
The definition of land, a key component of the current property institution, is a human art that has
a long history. Geometry was first developed for land definition in Egypt and land surveying
grew as a specialisation of land administration in England parallel to the emergence of absolute
18
Rodney L Jefferies Urban Valuation in New Zealand Vol 1 (Wellington: New Zealand Institute of
Valuers, 1978) 5-1.
19
Murray 76
Jefferies 1-1
R.O. Rost & H.G. Collins Land Valuation and Compensation in Australia (Sydney: Australian Institute
of Valuers) (1984) 18
22
Murray 14
20
21
10
private property. Land definition is possible because of the fixed nature of land and is facilitated
by human artefacts, including fencing, buildings and other monuments This is not so with the
new forms of property rights which, due to the challenges that they present in terms of definition
and control, are inherently land property sui generis.
The commodification of natural resources such as water and biota, 23 and the recognition by the
High Court in 1992 of native title24 has resulted in changes to fundamental understandings of
property rights. 25 Indeed, the interplay between indigenous and non-indigenous rights and
interests has bought starkly into focus quite different values ascribed to property rights, all of
which are nevertheless expressions of worth. 26
All non-indigenous property rights result in the conferral of three qualities or capacities, namely a
management power, an ability to receive income or benefits and an ability to sell or alienate the
interest. In particular, the transition from open access to property rights for natural resources has
drawn attention to just how we define whether particular “rights” are in fact property rights.
Confounding this issue of transition is the long established pattern of self-regulation which
according to Arrow27 has resulted in the emergence of social institutions to meet this need,
namely:
…private property rights, frequently hard to define, on the one hand, and the supervision of
the state, on the other, [which] only begin to exhaust the list of social devices to balance
individual initiative with prevention of injury to others.
A test for property rights
In attempting to develop a test for property rights which accommodates new forms of “property”,
it is important that the paradigm within which this test is to operate is interrogated and
understood. To a large extent the development of a test for such property rights is an endogenous
enterprise pertaining to a particular culture, which to be meaningful in Australia must emerge
from the hegemonic epistemology of settled anglo-Australian land law.
Hence, any methodology used to value new forms of property rights, especially those in natural
resources, will depend on the use to which the resource is to be put, and the purpose of the
valuation. The likely reasons for attributing a value to such a property right has to do with
maximizing the economic benefit of the resource, balancing social any aspects, compensation for
loss of rights, access and the voluntary sale or purchase of property rights by private parties.
Rosemary Lyster “(De)regulating the Rural Environment” Environmental and Planning Law Journal
18:5 (2001) 447. See also Judson Agius “Biodiversity Credits: Creating Missing Markets for Biodiversity,
Environmental and Planning Law Journal 18:5 (2001) 490.
24
Mabo-v-Queensland(No.2) (1992) 175 CLR 1
25
Permits and licenses have in a number of cases been held to be property i.e. Dovey –v- The Minister for
Primary Industries (1993) 119ALR108; Western Mining Corporation-v-Commonwealth (1994)
121ALR661; Newcrest Mining (WA) Ltd –v- Commonwealth (1997) 147ALR42.
26
Lyster 455
27
Kenneth J Arrow “Foreword” in Rights to Nature: Ecological, Economic, Cultural, and Political
Principles of Institutions for the Environment, eds S Hanna, C Folke and K Maler (Washington: Island
Press, 1996) xiv
23
11
The ability of holders of property rights in natural resources to sell, or lease their rights is more
limited than holders of more widely encountered property rights such as freehold or leasehold. In
certain circumstances, property rights in natural resources may be inalienable, capable only of
surrender to the Crown.
In this paper, the notion of property rights in natural resources will be discussed in generic rather
than specific terms. Benefits are discussed in terms of their characteristics, rather than focusing
on the physical nature of the resource, an approach rooted in consumption theory requiring a level
of abstraction allowing the resultant advice to be applicable to a broad range of circumstances.
This prerequisite is especially important where there is regional variability in the use of natural
resources such as water, and possible regional changes over time to such rights. This approach
also accommodates the conceiving of different possible bundles of rights in natural resources as
“property”, and the different forms in which such rights may be held including exclusive and nonexclusive. This aspect will be developed later in this paper in the context of fundamental
characteristics, which must be evident for a property right to exist.
It is generally accepted in the literature that recognised grants of property define the range of
privileges and responsibilities of holders to specified rights in natural resources. It is generally
believed that such rights are either legal rights or economic rights, or both. 28 In attempting to
construct a test to determine whether a right is indeed a property right, it is important that the
different but necessarily interrelated notions of legal and economic rights are clearly understood.
When such rights are viewed as legal rights they involve an assignation by the State through
legislation, common law or other means (e.g. custom) to an individual, group of individuals or
organisation, of specified property rights that the State wishes to assign. Even when assigned,
there is the question of regulation which can be critical to the value of the legal rights, which as
Denman asserts lies in:
…the extent to which restraints can and should be imposed by the State on the use of the
private property rights…Restraint may be severe and curtail the absolute rights of property
to the near practical abolition of them; or the touch of the State power may be exceedingly
light and leave near absolute power with the holders of the private property right.
Political debate in these circumstances centres round the extent and nature of the restraint
to be imposed by the State over the exercise of property rights…29
However, regulation restraining the use of specified property rights is accepted as a necessary
feature of their continued existence in society, as explained in Mason-v-Tritton (1994) 34
NSWLR 572 where Kirby P. (at 592-593) stated:
28
29
Yoram Barzel, Economic Analysis of Property Rights, (New York: Cambridge University Press 1997) 3
Donald Denman, “Recognising the property right”, The Planner 67:6 (1981) 161.
12
…[i]n the ordinary case, control and regulation of the rights and privileges associated
with property ownership is consistent with continued property ownership. Indeed civilized
societies demand that proprietary rights and interests be highly regulated.
The new forms of “property”, especially water, show that for these to be provided as legal rights
they must now occur as a result of formal arrangements which derive from a subtle interplay
between constitutional law, legislation, common law and case law. There is nowadays almost no
recognition space in such formal arrangements for informal conventions and customs that may
have developed over time in relation to access and usage of natural resources. This fact is
highlighted by the inadequacies of water access rights in NSW which until recently relied heavily
on the good will of the Minister and his Department for any real security and duration of tenure 30.
Economic rights depend on, and are subsidiary to, the capacity of legal rights to permit and allow
the holder to enjoy as a benefit from the natural resource in question. In the past, the creation of a
market for rights in natural resources has been impeded by the inability of holders to alienate.
Over time, administrative structures for the allocation and use of such resources (in particular
water) have developed, permitting an understanding (albeit poorly developed), of the economic
worth of the resource notwithstanding the inchoate nature of these rights. This has also not
prevented their valuation.
However, it is clear that the conceiving of such property rights remains at best conjectural, and
possibly confused by sophistry. This is evidenced by the absence of a definition of “water
property rights” in the Water Management Act 2000 (NSW), notwithstanding assertions by the
Department of Land and Water Conversation (DLWC) that the new legislation would:
…maximize the specification and tenure of water entitlements whilst still being able to
manage adaptively.31
This omission was also evident in the Second Reading speech to the Bill where the Minister
merely stated that:
[i]t is the term of a plan that really helps to define water rights, and the period of 10 years
provides a much better basis for business confidence and investment. 32
Further, that:
30
The Water Management Act 2000 (NSW) repeals the Water Act 1912 (NSW), which licensed water users
and access for the majority of the last century.
31
DLWC, 13.
32
Richard Amery, Minister for Agriculture, and Minister for Land and Water Conservation, Second
Reading speech, Water Management Bill 2000, 31 October 2000, 3.
13
[t]he conditions of these water access licences will also be linked to the 10-year water
management planning cycle. These amendments are more consistent with the Council of
Australian Governments [COAG] requirement to specify water rights as clearly as
possible. They also provide more certainty for water users.33
This simplistic view of the security to be provided to water users has been criticised by Crase,
Dollery and Lockwood who point out that:
…successful water markets are predicated on the premise that “…buyers must feel
confident that they will receive and be able to use the right purchased…[and]…welldefined and enforced mechanisms and criteria must be in place to assure that users are
adequately compensated when their rights are confiscated or transferred to higher societal
preferences”…By way of contrast, the Water Management Bill would appear to do little to
allay the concerns of irrigators about the strength of their property rights in water.
…We contend that the attenuation of property rights in this form constrains the capacity of
the market to generate surplus by limiting the incentives to undertake trade. 34
Further, irrigation water users have in their submission to the NSW Government argued that the
legislation:
…completely lacks detail on the specification of water rights.
…[E]ntitlements [must be] backed by separation of water property rights from land title
and clear specification of entitlements in terms of ownership, volume, reliability,
transferability and, if appropriate, quality. 35
An inspection of the Water Management Act 2000 (NSW) suggests that there has been a
significant reluctance by the drafters of the legislation to provide detail as to the nature of water
property rights. Also, contrary to the Minister’s assertions in the Second Reading speech, it would
appear that the basic policy position for the implementation of water property rights proposed by
the Agriculture and Resource Management Council of Australia and New Zealand (ARMCANZ)
36
has not been adequately implemented.
33
Ibid.
Lin Crase, Brian Dollery & Mike Lockwood, “Towards an Understanding of Static Transaction Costs in
the NSW Permanent Water Market: An Application of Choice Modelling”, unpublished paper submitted to
Australian Journal of Agricultural and Resource Economics (2000), 4.
35
NSW Irrigators Council (NSWIC) NSW Irrigators Council Submission to the Draft Water Management
Bill, roneo (Sydney, 2000) 1.
36
ARMCANZ) Water Allocations and Entitlements: A National Framework for the Implementation of
Property Rights in Water, Task Force on COAG Water Reform Occasional Paper No.1 (Canberra: Standing
Committee on Agriculture and Resource Management, 1995) October.
34
14
Research by Chant et al37 into the efficiency of natural resource allocation shows that undesirable
socio-economic and environmental impacts can be ameliorated if property rights are well defined.
Based on the methodology of Coase, they claim that a “socially optimal result” can be achieved
once property rights have security and are tradeable. 38
In addition, it is argued that when such rights are clarified and enforced, the market place will
more readily provide the best allocation of property rights in natural resources. Furthermore,
when property rights are held exclusively it is argued that the rationing of natural resources
among competing users acts as a financial incentive to protect and use the asset because of the
exercise of such property rights, albeit within an environmental protection legislative framework
to prevent consequential adverse effects.
From the perspective of sustainable development, it is interesting that economists 39 argue that
natural resources must be now paid and accounted for. Natural resources such as water have
suffered damage because the cost has been traditionally borne publicly rather than privately.
From this line of inquiry, it can be concluded that the specification of water property rights will
create a market in water which provides incentives for greater stewardship by the holders of the
resource.
As stated earlier, it is suggested that the extent of the property rights of all holders should be
defined, together with the amount of resource (eg water) which should be reserved for
environmental and community purposes. It is argued by ARMCANZ that a property rights
framework in water would be created which incorporates environmental constraints within which
these rights can be traded.40
A fundamental flaw
It may seem prosaic in the extreme, but any discourse on “new property rights” ought to be
embarked upon from the standpoint that such rights must meet a defensible test of what a
property right is. If these property rights are to be meaningful to users, purchasers, and especially
the banks and financial organisations that will use these rights as collateral for mortgage-based
loans, then the test of whether they are indeed property rights is crucial.
In constructing such a test, it is essential to gain an appreciation of existing judicial considerations
of the notion of “property”. Starke J. in The Minister of State for the Army-v-Dalziel (1944) 68
CLR at 290 (Dalziel) indicated that such a definition:
John Chant, Donald McFetridge, Douglas Smith and John Nurick, “The Economics of the Green
Society”, in Reconciling Economics and the Environment, eds. J. Bennett and W Block (West Perth:
Australian Institute for Public Policy, 1991) 67, 69.
38
Chant, McFetridge, Smith and Nurick, 66.
39
Lyuba Zarsky “Economy and Ecology: Sustainable Development”, in Economics as a Social Science:
Readings in Political Economy, eds G. Argyrous and F. Stilwell (Sydney: Pluto Press, 1996) 173, 175.
40
ARMCANZ, 4.
37
15
…extends to every species of valuable right and interest including real and personal
property, incorporeal hereditaments such as rents and services, rights of way, rights of
profit or use in land of another, and chooses in action.
Starke J. (at 290) also comments that:
…to acquire any such right is rightly described as an acquisition of property.
This approach to constructing a definition of “property” has been further strengthened in a recent
decision Yanner-v-Eaton (1999) HCA 53 (unreported 7 October 1999) (Yanner), where the High
Court took the opportunity to contrast property in the conventional sense with the “property” or
“ownership” that the Crown asserts over natural resources.
The Court stated that:
The word “property” is often used to refer to something that belongs to
another….”property” does not refer to a thing; it is a description of a legal relationship
with a thing. It refers to a degree of power that is recognised in law as power permissibly
exercised over the thing. The concept of “property” may be elusive. Usually it is treated as
a “bundle of rights”.
But even this may have its limits as an analytical tool or accurate description, and it may
be…that “the ultimate fact about property is that it does not really exist; it is mere
illusion”.41
Also, the Court usefully stated that the common law position of natural resources was as follows:
At common law there could be no “absolute property”, but only “qualified property” in
fire, light air, water and wild animals42
Even previously accepted sovereign rights and interests over territory, such as sea lands, are no
longer viewed as completely settled. For example, in the recent decision in Commonwealth –vYarmirr (HCA unreported 11 October 2001) it was held by the majority that while the waters
around Croker Island where internationally recognised as part of the territorial sea of Australia,
such sea lands where not part of the original “territory” of England, and therefore not owned. 43
41
Yanner-v-Eaton (1999) HCA 53, at 8 per Gleeson CJ, Gaudron Kirby & Hayne JJ.
Ibid, 11.
43
The majority judges cited the decision in R.-v-Keyn (1876) 2 Ex D 63 (Keyn’s case)as authority for this
view that recognition does not necessarily result in ownership of territory.
42
16
Nevertheless, as stated earlier in this paper, “property” is generally understood as a titled right to
land or to exploit natural resources such as minerals. Commonly these property rights are referred
to by the terminology “real estate”, with its emphasis on the immoveable nature of the “property”
concerned such as land, buildings and minerals.
The range of interests that are classed as “property” while limited only by our imagination, has
however been restrained by the Courts of common law countries who have only recognised a few
kinds of interests in land, which are regarded as usual property rights. Some of these rights will
be readily recognised such as freehold and leasehold, however a few such as mining rights,
fishing rights, and water entitlements have also been recognised.
There has also been the very recent recognition of carbon as a property right, and legislation in
various states is developing this concept.44 The objective in recognizing carbon as “property” is:
…to provide secure title for carbon sequestration rights through registration on the land
title system. The practical effect of this will be that a carbon right attached to property will
be held separately from the land ownership, and the carbon right attached to land will be
viewable on a property title search, putting the world on notice of the obligations that flow
with that land.45
Even more recently, it has been suggested that the use of biota such as genetic botanicals may
have to be not only regulated but also recognised as property if they are to be conserved. It is
argued that the creation of such property rights would act as a “real economic incentive” 46 to
sustainably utilise these natural resources. The current enquiry into bioprospecting by the House
of Representatives Standing Committee on Primary Industries and Regional Services strongly
suggests that:
…[t]he regulation of access to biological resources for research and exploitation has been
problematical.47
However, a common feature of these property rights is that the interests in question are territorial,
in so much as the right is contained only within defined boundaries. This is commonly achieved
by way of a legal description of the boundaries, which have been defined by means of a cadastre.
In addition, these rights are also proscribed in so far as what activities can occur within the
territory48, the manner in which the right is to be paid for, and other obligations incurred or
limitations imposed.
44
Jacqueline Bredhauer “Tree Clearing in Western Queensland – a Cost Benefit Analysis of Carbon
Sequestration”, Environmental and Planning Law Journal 17:5 (2000) 389.
45
Ibid.
46
Nicole Veash “River of no Returns” The Australian Magazine (18-19 November 2000) 40. See also
Zarsky 173.
47
Information and Research Service of the Department of the Parliamentary Library Bioprospecting and
Regional Industry Development in Australia – Some issues for the Committee’s Inquiry Paper prepared for
the House of Representatives Standing Committee on Primary Industries and Regional Services (Canberra:
2000) 2.
48
Denman, 161.
17
Some of these usual property rights can be acquired outright, while some such as fishing rights
and water entitlements may be attached to rights that are held in a parcel of land adjacent or
nearby.
Common qualities or capacities of property rights
As previously stated, in varying degrees all “property rights” result in the conferral of three
qualities (or capacities):
1. a management power,
2. an ability to receive income or benefits, and
3. an ability to sell or alienate the interest.
The degree to which these three qualities are evident in a particular property right depends on the
mix of fundamental characteristics that the particular property right contains.
As stated earlier in this paper, an understanding of these fundamental characteristics is crucial to
ascertaining whether a particular right is a “property right”. There have been significant attempts
over the past few years by national governments to commodify natural resources, notably
fisheries. The history of subsidised open access to fisheries has led to the view of the American
Fisheries Society that:
…transferable fishing quotas are coming into being as a way of conferring property rights
on wild food (unfarmed) stocks in an effort to encourage more enduring harvests.49
This transition from open access to property rights for natural resources is reflected in increasing
attention by Australian courts to these less familiar forms of “property”. A notable example of
these judicial considerations is found in Minister for Primary Industry and Energy and Australian
Fisheries Management Authority-v-Davey and Fitti (1993) 119 ALR 108, where the Court was
asked inter alia whether the fishing capacity permitted for the Northern Prawn Fishery expressed
in “units of fishing capacity” was in fact “property” within the meaning of para.51(xxxi) of the
Australian Constitution which states that:
The Parliament shall, subject to this Constitution, have power to make laws for the peace,
order, and good government of the Commonwealth with respect to: …The acquisition of property on just terms from any State or person for any purpose in
respect of which the Parliament has power to make laws:
49
Bob Beale, “Depths of Despair”. The Sydney Morning Herald (6 June 1998) 10s.
18
In deciding whether the “units of fishing capacity” were property, it was noted by the Court that
the limits of operation of para.51 (xxxi) have not been determined precisely. However, the Court
drew upon the definition of property as discussed in the Dalziel case which was referred to earlier
in this paper, and noted that the approach in Dalziel was approved in Australian Tape
Manufacturers Association Ltd-v-Commonwealth of Australia (1993) 112 ALR 53 at 65.
The Court decided that the “units of fishing capacity” were property rights which were generated
by statute, and were “property” for the purposes of para.51 (xxxi).
Fundamental characteristics
It will be seen that existing judicial considerations of the notion of “property” fall short of
providing a defensible test of what a property right is. As stated previously, all property rights
have the three qualities or capacities of management, income/benefit and alienation, each in
varying combinations. At a more fundamental level, there are also characteristics which are
present in any property right, and which, depending on the blend and quality of the
characteristics, determines the relative influence of the three qualities or capacities outlined
earlier.
The concept of property rights arises from a need to address problems emerging from the actual
requirements of society. Nowhere more apparent is this seen than in the recent commodification
of increasingly valuable natural resources such as water, which in the conferring of a property
rights regime is hoped, in line with other resources such as fisheries to become more sustainably
used.50
There is a significant history in the literature of attempts to identify the fundamental
characteristics present in any property right. Hargreaves and Helmore 51 point out that the
foundations of modern Western property rights lie in the legal “world of the Middle Ages”,
however, like other branches of law, their present form is more dependent on the historical forces
of the intervening centuries. Despite the radical demise of the social obligations of Medieval
feudal property in the sixteenth century, the holder of property has never totally escaped a certain
remnant of duties to the community:
There has always been a thin trickle of public law which imposed duties upon landowners,
but these duties – mainly concerned with sanitation, from the old public nuisance to the
modern control by local government bodies of subdivision of land and building and the
duties imposed by statute on rural landholders…were not sufficient to disturb the emphasis
upon private rights as the essential feature of ownership.52
The despotic character of property probably reached its zenith in the eighteenth century, but since
then the laissez faire view that private property rights were almost absolute has waned to the point
that Teh & Dwyer could conclude:
50
Beale, 10s.
A.D. Hargreaves & B.A. Helmore, An Introduction to the Principles of Land Law (New South Wales)
(Sydney: The Law Book Co, 1963) 4.
52
Hargreaves & Helmore, 155.
51
19
[t]here is now general acceptance that property in land must be subject to restrictions in
the interests of preserving public safety, health, natural resources and social harmony.53
The value of a property right may be considered as the net private benefit of the particular
positive institution as it exists within a particular society. The benefit of the absolute right is
partially negated by the concurrent restrictions. This led Gray & Gray to point out that:
…there may well be graduations of “property” in a resource. The amount of “property”
which a specified person may claim in any resource is capable of calibration – along some
sort of sliding scale – from a maximum value to a minimum value…Far from being a
monolithic notion of standard content and invariable intensity, “property” thus turns out
to have an almost infinitely gradable quality.54
This view is of considerable interest in attempting to deduce those fundamental characteristics
that are present in any property right, in particular in natural resources such as water. It will be
observed that a “characteristics” approach has been adopted by the courts in some cases such as
Milirrpum & Anor v Nabalco Pty Ltd & The Commonwealth (1971) 17 FLR 141 when
attempting to ascertain whether a particular interest could be regarded as a property right. This
approach pivots on the identification of commonly encountered characteristics, namely:
The right to use
The right to alienate
The right to exclude
However, Teh and Dwyer note that this approach has been discredited as too limiting because
some forms of property rights may fail to exhibit some of these characteristics, while other
interests may exhibit the full range and yet not be true property rights.55
Given the above, a review of select literature for this paper suggests that a more comprehensive
tabulation of fundamental characteristics ought to provide a level of certainty such that a
meaningful discourse for property rights can be constructed.
A definition of property rights
Part of the difficulty in defining property rights within a particular society is the fact that they are
no more than a positive cultural artefact. The interesting question of what property should be is of
little relevance to commerce in property where the pivotal issue is where legally defensible
property rights are. Anthony Scott,56 (1986) described a comprehensive specification of
Gim Leong Teh and Bryan Dwyer, Introduction to Property Law 2nd ed. (Sydney: Butterworths 1992) 7.
Kevin Gray & Susan Francis Gray, “The Idea of Property in Land”, in Land Law: Themes and
perspectives eds Susan Bright and John Dewar (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998) 16.
55
Teh & Dwyer, 8.
56
Anthony Scott Evolution of Individual Transferable Quotas as a Distinct Class of Property Right edited
version of a paper presented at the NATO Conference on rights-based fishing, Reykjavik, June 1988 and
the APPAM Conference, Seattle, January 1989.
53
54
20
fundamental characteristics of a property right suitable for its inclusion in Western commercial
exchange. Scott outlined a test for property rights, which relies upon the identification of a
minimum of six fundamental characteristics, which he asserted to be present in any property
right. His characteristics are especially directed to the economic value of property rights, and as
such are applicable to societies such as the USA. As such they may be useful in developing a
definition of property rights suitable for contemporary Australian society. They are as follows:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
duration,
flexibility,
exclusivity,
quality of title,
transferability,
divisibility.
Scott shows how, when just four of these characteristics are varied, the worth of a particular
property right can change, given that the amount of any of the characteristics can be observable,
measurable, and continuously variable. There is considerable attraction in this tabulation of
characteristics which Scott suggests to be a minimum when attempting to describe property rights
or interests which have been formed either by statute or even totally outside the common law.
However, these six characteristics require some analysis to explain their relevance to water
property rights if we are to be afforded the benefit of Scott’s initial research. It should be
remembered that his research was undertaken in the context of the development of individual
transferable fishing quotas as a property right. An interrogation of his description of each of the
six characteristics has been undertaken and is separately described below in the context of a test
for water property rights:
Duration
As regards duration, this first fundamental characteristic indicates the period usually in years that
the property right is held, and hence represents a profit or saving to the holder. Scott’s suggestion
that this characteristic should be measured in numbers of years may in the context of water
property rights have to be extended to a much longer time interval to be meaningful.
Flexibility
The second characteristic, flexibility is not specifically explained by Scott however it perhaps is
closely related to the sixth characteristic, divisibility, highlighting that a property right should be
susceptible to modification and/or alteration. In the context of water property rights, this aspect
will almost certainly be a product of the particular regional circumstances within which the water
entitlement and use occurs. In addition, water property rights are constrained ab initio by the
availability of the natural resource, and clearly it is conceivable that the full benefits of the right
may under certain circumstances be constrained.
Exclusivity
The third characteristic, exclusivity, is the inverse of the number of holders of the same or similar
property right. Clearly, a reduction in the exclusivity will reduce the profit or saving enjoyed by
the holder. This characteristic is directly relevant to water property rights.
21
Quality of Title
The fourth characteristic, quality of title, while not explained by Scott clearly refers to the
descending level of security as the tenure falls away from the optimum of notional freehold. The
water entitlement and usage regime currently operative under the Water Act 1912 (NSW) is a
threshold from which water property rights of greater quality of title can be constructed.
Transferability
The fifth characteristic, transferability, is the measurement of the market for the sale or leasing of
the particular property right. A high value would indicate that the demand reaches well beyond
the original acquiring group, and that the mere creation of a market and hence tradability in itself
enhances the value of the particular property right. In the context of water property rights, this
characteristic could also be referred to as tradeability, and relies heavily upon the amelioration of
current government constraints on transfers to other parties.
Divisibility
As regards the sixth characteristic, divisibility (which Scott sees as an aspect of transferability)
this has a number of facets. The property right may be capable of being shared between a number
of holders over one territory or the territory itself maybe subdivided and each new part held
separately. It may also be possible for the holder to divide his right on the basis of seasons or in
the case of fishing rights, on the basis of particular marine species.
In the context of water property rights, there will be limits to divisibility of access and usage,
beyond which the right becomes degraded, almost certainly uneconomic, and devalued.
Interestingly, perusal of recent commentary on the Water Management Bill reveals that a number
of these six fundamental characteristics of property rights have been identified, albeit in inchoate
form. For example, it is noted that ARMCANZ has suggested that within the principles for a
water property rights regime, inter alia:
[t]hat water entitlements be clearly specified in terms of:
rights and conditions of ownership tenure
share of natural resource being allocated (including probability of occurrence);
details of agreed standards of any commercial services to be delivered;
constraints to and rules on transferability; and
constraints to resource use or access.57
Further, ARMCANZ has suggested that such rights must evidence the following features for an
effective market to be created:
…in demand – the market will be effective when competition exists for a set of rights that are
limited in extent or availability;
57
ARMCANZ, 8.
22
well specified in the long-term sense – the market can interpret and depend on
rights really mean;
what the
exclusive – benefits and costs associated with the rights are attributed to the right holders;
enforceable and enforced – regulations and systems exist to ensure the rights are upheld; and
transferable and divisible – regulations and systems are in place to allow the transfer of
rights within defined limitations. 58
Importantly, ARMCANZ59 proposed that the tenure of water property rights should be perpetual,
and yet significantly attenuated this recommendation proposing that conditions of access be
subject to review to achieve acceptable levels of “planning certainty”60.
Therefore as previously noted by Denman61, regulation could if wished by government so
severely curtail these rights as to make the tenure a chimera.
Importantly, the Working Group on Water Resource Policy has reported to COAG that for
trading in water entitlements to be facilitated:
…governments will need to ensure that property rights to water are clearly defined and
specified in terms of ownership, volume, reliability, environmental flows and tenure.
Conversion factors will also need to be specified between different areas of surface and
groundwater systems and where catchments cross jurisdictional boundaries.62
There are clearly elements of the six fundamental features of property rights present in both of the
above writings, and are remarkably similar. It is posited that the six-point test as developed by
Scott is a suitable tool applicable to a broad range of circumstances when a new form of property
right is thought to have emerged.
Constraints on the Definition of Property Rights
It must be stressed that the notion of a “property right” is not a legal term, and the foregoing
discussion is not an attempt (nor should it be) to provide legal advice. Indeed, as this paper has
shown, there has been a long history of reluctance by the Courts to articulate what is “property”
or a “property right”.
It is clear that the form of tenure for a specific property right such as water should be driven by a
synergy of security and tradeability. Many permutations of tenure could doubtless be constructed
which, drawing upon the six fundamental characteristics of property rights identified by Scott,63
would result in a tenure which could be utilised in a system of property rights.
58
ARMCANZ, 4.
Ibid, 8.
60
ARMCANZ, 5.
61
Denman, 161.
62
The Working Group on Water Resource Policy, Report of the Working Group on Water Resource Policy
to the Council of Australian Governments (1993?) 11.
63
Scott
59
23
However, it is recognised that both security and tradeability require that the form of tenure is
capable of acting as collateral for a mortgaged based loan from a bank or other financial
institutions. From this line of reasoning, it can be concluded that the tenure must evidence
qualities which lenders are comfortable and familiar with.
Lenders are familiar with loans, which in the main are secured by way of a mortgage over
freehold land, specifically land which is held under the Real Property Act. This enables a lender
to have a registered first or second mortgage, or a caveat placed upon the public register of those
land titles issued pursuant to that Act.
Usually tenure is unlimited in time, and guaranteed by the Act. There is security of tenure at the
highest level, and the sale or transfer of the property rights held under this form of title can
readily occur subject only to a restriction that stamp duty and statutory charges be paid at the time
of sale or transfer.
While the utility accruing to the holder of the particular property rights is subject to restriction
from the usual range of planning development and environmental controls, the basic six
characteristics of a property right are not impugned. Clearly such a tenure would be the zenith for
any intending holder or mortgagee of new “property rights”, however the nature of some natural
resources is such that a perpetual tenure is unlikely to be granted by the Crown.
It therefore follows that a title for some property rights will be subject to a greater level of
restriction than would a usual “land-based” real property tenure, and also be evidenced in a grant
for a period of years rather than perpetuity. An analogy is the mineral rights granted under the
Mining Act 1992 (NSW) for specific minerals permitting both rights to prospect and mine.
Because the extraction of minerals is determined by the life of the ore body, these “property
rights” are granted or renewed for up to 21 years or longer with concurrence, and are secure. 64
Such rights may or may not impinge upon the “property rights” of the surface landholder, and
there may not necessarily be a nexus between the two holders of these quite different rights. Such
a situation has similarities to the proposal in the Water Management Act 2000 (NSW) where
water property rights and land are to be separated.
Conclusion
The increasing recognition of neophyte property rights in natural resources such as water and
biota has caused the notion of property rights to undergo fundamental change. As the angloAustralian legal system moves closer to an omnibus definition of property rights, this process has
already brought forth calls for a titling system for these new “property rights” which are
reminiscent of the Certificate of Title issued under the Real Property Act, subject to the
inescapable restrictions created by climate and other inherent natural risks.
64
David Farrier, Rosemary Lyster and Linda Pearson, The Environmental Law Handbook: Planning and
Land use in New South Wales, 3rd ed. (Sydney: Redfern Legal Centre Publishing, 1999) 339.
24
Such an approach attempts to enshrine a tenure for these emerging rights, such that compulsory
expropriation by the State cannot occur arbitrarily once the necessary tests as outlined by Scott
for a property right have been met. Indeed, the failure to guarantee security of tenure has been
recognised as the major shortfall of the Water Management Act 2000 (NSW) and its precursor,
the Water Act 1912 (NSW).
The importance of this line of reasoning cannot be overstressed, given that in North Sydney
Municipal Council-v-Boyts Radio and Electrical (1989) 67 LGERA 344 at 345, Kirby J. stated
that property cannot be arbitrarily expropriated, drawing upon previous decisions 65 and stating
that this principle is:
…an essential idea which is both basic and virtually uniform in civilised legal systems.
For this very reason, the development of strata titles as a distinctive property right in the early
1960’s resulted in amendments to the Real Property Act which were innovative in that a nexus
was created between air space and the Crown guarantee of title residing in land. There now is a
need for such an intellectual effort to occur afresh for the new emerging forms of property rights.
Such an endeavour will take place within a plurality of indigenous and non-indigenous rights and
interests, necessitating a rapprochement on managing such property rights. 66
History has shown that anglo-Australian land law can be amended to accommodate hitherto
unknown forms of property (i.e. stratum, community titles, limited term strata title of Crown
leaseholds), and it is the view of the authors that a well tested vehicle already exists wherein these
new property rights could be titled.
REFERENCES
Amery, Richard, Minister for Agriculture, and Minister for Land and Water Conservation,
(2000), Water Management Bill 2000, Second Reading speech, 31 October.
Agius Judson (2001) “Biodiversity Credits: Creating Missing Markets for Biodiversity”
Environmental and Planning Law Journal 18:5, 481-504.
Anderson, Perry. 1979.Lineages of the absolutist state, (London: Verso)
65
Dorrestijn-v-South Australian Planning Commission (1984) 59 AJLR 104
Already, indigenous management approaches such as those by the Gandangara peoples are evidence of
this rapprochement – see Healthy Rivers Commission of NSW Independent Inquiry into the Georges River
– Botany Bay System Final Report (Sydney: September 2001) 56.
66
25
ARMCANZ 1995 Water Allocations and Entitlements: A National Framework for the
Implementation of Property Rights in Water, Task Force on COAG Water Reform Occasional
Paper No.1 (Canberra: Standing Committee on Agriculture and Resource Management,
October.
Arrow, Kenneth J. 1996 “Foreword” in Rights to Nature: Ecological, Economic, Cultural, and
Political Principles of Institutions for the Environment, eds S Hanna, C Folke and K Maler
(Washington: Island Press)
Barzel, Yoram, 1997 Economic Analysis of Property Rights 2nd ed, Political Economy of
Institutions and Decisions series, (New York: Cambridge University Press)
Beale, Bob. 1998 “Depths of Despair”. The Sydney Morning Herald (6 June) 10s.
Bredhauer Jacqueline, 2000 “Tree Clearing in Western Queensland – a Cost Benefit Analysis of
Carbon Sequestration”, Environmental and Planning Law Journal 17:5, 383.
Chant, John, McFetridge, Donald, Smith Douglass and Nurick, John “The Economics of the
Green Society”, in Reconciling Economics and the Environment, eds. J. Bennett and W Block
(West Perth: Australian Institute for Public Policy)
Crase, Lin, Dollery Brian & Lockwood, Mike. 2000 “Towards an Understanding of Static
Transaction Costs in the NSW Permanent Water Market: An Application of Choice
Modelling”, unpublished paper submitted to Australian Journal of Agricultural and Resource
Economics
Denman, Donald. 1981 “Recognising the property right” The Planner 67(6)161
Ely, James W Jnr. 1998 The Guardian of Every Other Right: A Constitutional History of
Property Rights 2nd ed Bicentennial Essays on the Bill of Rights (New York: Oxford
University Press)
Fanfani, Amintore. 1939. Catholicism Protestantism and Capitalism. London: Sheed and Ward.
Farrier, David. Lyster, Rosemary and Pearson, Linda 1999The Environmental Law Handbook:
Planning and Land use in New South Wales, 3rd ed. (Sydney: Redfern Legal Centre
Publishing) 339.
Gray, Kevin & Gray, Susan F. 1998 “The Idea of Property in Land” in Land Law: Themes and
perspectives eds Susan Bright and John Dewar (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
Hargreaves A.D. & B.A. Helmore, B.A. 1963 An Introduction to the Principles of Land Law
Healthy Rivers Commission of NSW 2001 Independent Inquiry into the Georges River – Botany
Bay System Final Report (Sydney: September ) 56.
Information and Research Service of the Department of the Parliamentary Library 2000.
Bioprospecting and Regional Industry Development in Australia – Some issues for the
Committee’s Inquiry Paper prepared for the House of Representatives Standing Committee on
Primary Industries and Regional Services (Canberra)
Jefferies Rodney L , 1978 Urban Valuation in New Zealand Vol 1 (Wellington: New Zealand
Institute of Valuers.)
Lyster Rosemary (2001) “(De)regulating the Rural Environment” Environmental and Planning
Law Journal 18:5 445-468
Masson Sophie. 2001 “Here today, gone yesterday” The Sydney Morning Herald (14 October)
8S
26
Murray John F N. 1969 Principles and Practice of Valuation Sydney: Commonwealth Institute
of Valuers.
National Competition Council. 2001 Water Property Rights Background paper for 3rd tranche
assessment framework,(Canberra: March.)
NSW Irrigators Council (NSWIC) 2000. NSW Irrigators Council Submission to the Draft Water
Management Bill, roneo (Sydney).
Rost R O & Collins H G. 1984 Land Valuation and Compensation in Australia (Sydney:
Australian Institute of Valuers)
Scott, Anthony. Evolution of Individual Transferable Quotas as a Distinct Class of Property
Right edited version of a paper presented at the NATO Conference on rights-based fishing,
Reykjavik, June 1988 and the APPAM Conference 1989, (Seattle) January.
Sheehan J. 2000 “Assessing Compensation for Native Title: A Valuation Perspective” Pacific
Rim Property Research Journal (August 6 (1) 43-55.)
Sheehan J. 2001 Indigenous Property Rights in Water Paper presented at the inaugural
“Certificate in Water Property Rights” 5-day course conducted by the University of
Queensland in conjunction with the Australian Property Institute (QLD) (Brisbane: University
of Queensland) St Lucia 11 July.
Teh, Gim Leong and Dwyer, Bryan. 1992 Introduction to Property Law 2nd ed. (Sydney:
Butterworths)
The Working Group on Water Resource Policy, 1993? Report of the Working Group on Water
Resource Policy to the Council of Australian Governments.
Vargas Llosa, Mario, 2001.“Locally speaking, global is good” The Sydney Morning Herald (10
February) 3S
Veash, Nicole, 2000. “River of no Returns” The Australian Magazine (18-19 November) 40.
Weber, Max. 1974. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Translated by Talcott
Parsons. London: Allen & Unwin.
Zarsky Lyuba. 1996 “Economy and Ecology: Sustainable Development”, in Economics as a
Social Science: Readings in Political Economy, eds G. Argyrous and F. Stilwell (Sydney:
Pluto Press)
Paper presented at the Pacific Rim Real Estate Society (PRRES) conference, Christchurch New Zealand
January 2002.
TOWARDS A DEFINITION OF PROPERTY RIGHTS
John Sheehan* & Garrick Small #
* National Native Title Spokesperson, Australian Property Institute, National Secretariat 6 Campion
Street Deakin ACT 2600, and Member Land Tribunal, Level 9 Tank Street Brisbane. Queensland
4000.
Email : sarasan@ihug.com.au
# Senior Lecturer, University of Technology, Sydney, Property Studies Program.
Email: garrick.small@uts.edu.au
ABSTRACT
The notion of property rights has undergone fundamental change recently as a result of the
commodification of natural resources such as water and biota. All property rights result in
the conferral of three qualities or capacities, namely a management power, and ability to
receive income or benefits, and an ability to sell or alienate the interest.
However the transition from open access to property rights for natural resources has
drawn attention to just how we define whether “particular rights” are in fact property
rights. Property in the more familiar sense of land and buildings conveys a tenor of
regularity, constancy, and fixity – this is not so with the new forms of property which are
inherently sui generis.
As knowledge is gained as to the nature of these less familiar property rights accepted
truths regarding the notion of property rights are being shown to be only partial and
incomplete visions.
KEYWORDS
Property rights; property; water property rights; biota property rights
INTRODUCTION
Mario Vargas Llosa, a Peruvian novelist recently observed that while the discipline most closely
associated with globalisation is economics, other disciplines related to matters social, ethical and
cultural act as reminders that regional cultures remain surprisingly robust, pointing out that:
Page 1
2
[g]lobalisation will not make local cultures disappear; in a framework of worldwide
openness, all that is valuable and worthy of survival in local cultures will find fertile
ground in which to bloom.1
This is a poignant reminder that customs and laws of many societies have only undergone
incremental change throughout history, notwithstanding the sometimes violent precursors of such
change. Anglo-Australian land law is one such complex amalgam, and recent studies of its roots
in English custom and law reveal according to linguist Masson:
… a curious and most marvellous gift for mutability and metamorphosis, rooted in a rich,
complex and strange multilayered, multicultural history.2
Further, Masson observes of this legal transmogrification that:
[t]he violence and bloodiness of part of this [Norman] conquest which, unlike the earlier
Roman and Anglo-Saxon invasions, sought to extirpate an entire culture by destroying the
upper reaches of the conquered society and assimilating the rest by incorporating them
into a new system of law, are in many ways like the violent, bloody history of the frontier in
Australia, combined with the more peaceful installing of colonial administration..
Further,
[f]eudal Norman law, devised to firmly control both Norman lords and Anglo-Saxon
populace through a complex system of obligation and responsibility, was grafted onto
certain aspects of English law, which itself still had vestigial elements of both Roman and
Celtic laws. The genius of the Normans was ever in their syncretism.3
Inescapably property was of pivotal concern to those involved in conquest and dispossession, and
hence once acquired the value of property crystallised in the hands of the conquering Normans. In
keeping with other parts of Western Europe, the value of property was central to the maintenance
of civilisation. While the Norman lords held rights to the land and economic benefits, these were
conditional on service to the society. In particular, defense and civil order were funded from land
rents. Intermediate lords enjoyed property titles that were burdened by both rental obligations to
the higher lords, or the king, and service obligations to their vassals.
The connection between property ownership and obligation to the community was diluted over
time, despite the continuation of the formal feudal tradition of tenure. Land value emerged
explicitly as rental obligations to the sovereign and one's vassals were dissolved, leaving the
benefit of property liberated for personal enjoyment. It is the concept of economic value, often
1
Mario Vargas Llosa, “Locally speaking, global is good” The Sydney Morning Herald (10 February 2001)
3S
2
Sophie Masson “Here today, gone yesterday” The Sydney Morning Herald (14 October, 2001) 8S
3
Ibid
Commented [DGS1]: I think that you would benefit from
researching and reflecting further on this part of English
history.
Firstly, the culture each side of the channel was not as
dissimilar as recent English writers would like to imagine.
Both the Normans (named because they came to Gaul from
the north) and the Angles & Saxons were drawn from early
Germanic tribes, which meant that they shared a certain
primal cultural similarity. This is especially the case in the
ruling families of each. In addition, both were Christian and
shared much of the same understanding of society within that
religious framework, especially since St. Augustine of
Canterbury had linked the English closely to Europe five
centuries earlier.
Secondly, William was not an invading adventurer, but a
noble who for complicated reasons peculiar to the Middle
ages believed that he was not invading at all, but merely
taking over a birth right that had been denied him. That belief
explained his enthusiasm, the support he was able to muster
and also the acceptance his act received through the rest of
Christendom. This is not to say that the Saxons, especially the
former ruling class, did not resent his act. There later grew up
a kind of English mythology that has lauded the Germanic
spirit of the Angles and Saxons (& other pirate invaders) that
is somehow seen as the genesis of the superior quality of that
nation. This is usually pitted against the Roman culture that
crumbled (in the face of Germanic barbarian invaders) and
later European culture (William). The myth was useful when
England turned against European culture in the sixteenth
century and is symbolically evident in the pirate Francis
Drake who has become the hero of England and in many
ways one of the fathers of its empire.
Thirdly, the system of property and government that he
established was not novel in his time, despite being a better
refined form that England had previously seen. Feudalism
had been in existence as the dominant form of
political/economic organisation almost since the central
administration of Roman failed. William did reorganise it and
did put his men in the key positions. In some cases, his law
may have overturned native English practice, but not to a
significant degree, at least not to the degree necessary to
make the statement of the quote here.
Finally, the currently popular opinion of European (and
especially English) feudalism usually fails to take sufficient
account of the rationale justifying the apparent property
wealth of the nobility. Both poles of liberal thought today
entertain a vision of ancient feudal relationships that could
not have actually existed. These imagine ancient feudal lords
to be tyrants who created a system of property for the
oppression of the ordinary person. Under that model, kings
and their vassals used their property wealth to maintain an
unjust level of personal wealth and a standing army kept for
the purpose of suppressing the populace. There were some
corrupt lords, and they all tended to have a comfortable
lifestyle. However, their lifestyle was considered appropriate
because of the dignity of their station and the personal risks
and responsibilities that that they accepted. The income
differentials, especially in terms of net personal consumption,
between ancient kings and their people and contemporary
CEOs and the basic wage probably would make the kings
look poor. This is evident in the second part of the caricatue:
the purpose of the standing armies. While kings kept armies,
real battles in those days were mainly won by foot soldiers. ...
3
linked to its political implications of power, which tends to lie at the core of most discussions of
property rights, and as Ely observes in the North American context:
English common law provided the legal foundation for property ownership in the colonies.
Common law was customary law, deriving its authority from long-established usage. Royal
courts in England fashioned the common law into a body of rules that defined and
protected property rights…
The high value attached to landownership by the colonists is best understood in terms of
the English experience. In England, as in Western Europe generally, land was the
principal source of wealth and social status. Yet landownership was tightly concentrated in
relatively few hands, and most individuals had no realistic prospect of owning land.
Moreover, in theory no person owned land absolutely. All land was held under a tenurial
relationship with the Crown. Although there was a bewildering variety of tenure
arrangements, property ownership was conditional and involved continuing obligations to
a superior.4
Conceptually, property rights and the concept of value necessarily emerged as the twin liet motifs
of English property law, and its colonial American progeny. Anglo-Australian property law was
also a legal sibling of this tradition.
A Concept of Value for Property Rights
The modern concept of value, especially when given monetary expression, involves the potential
private allocation of worth to a particular parcel of land, usually as an estimate of its capitalised
future potentiality based on its current utility. The concept of ascribing monetary value to a
natural resource such as land has it roots according to Anderson in the:
…perdurable inheritance of classical antiquity. The Roman Empire, its final historical
form, was not only itself naturally incapable of a transition to capitalism. The very advance
of the classical universe doomed it to a catastrophic regression, of an order for which
there is no real other example in the annals of civilization. The far more primitive social
world of early feudalism was the result of its collapse, internally prepared and externally
completed.5
The transition between late Roman civilisation and the early Dark Ages was the atrophy of
property value. The estates of late Rome conferred great wealth on their owners, but this was of
little value in the face of civil decay. In the absence of civil government strong enough to enforce
private rights of property it was open to plunder by any party that had sufficient strength relative
to the owners. Feudalism was the result of fearful property owners surrendering formal title to
their property to military overlords in return for security. The overlords eventually appropriated
the mantle of government with formalised obligations to the community. While they technically
had title to property, its net value to them was low since it brought with it the onerous obligations
of providing security and other services now associated with the public sector. In that way, the
4
James W Ely Jnr. The Guardian of Every Other Right: A Constitutional History of Property Rights 2nd ed
Bicentennial Essays on the Bill of Rights (New York: Oxford University Press 1998) 10
5
Perry Anderson Lineages of the Absolutist State ( London: Verso 1979) 420.
Commented [DGS2]: John: I think that this quote is a little
oblique for our purpose. Historically, payment of money for
land goes back at least to Moasic times (see Leviticus 25).
The Romans no doubt had some trade in land, though I
suspect that such trade changed in nature during the course of
the empire. Even the early feudal period is probably not a
good time to cite for monetary trade in land - more tended to
change hands for military reasons.
4
value of property that existed in the civilised world of late Rome dissolved as private enjoyment
of property wealth was re-absorbed into the community in the person of the feudal lord. Value
began to re-emerge as the Dark Ages made its transition into the Middle Ages following the reign
of Charlemagne in the ninth century.
The re-civilisation of Europe created an arbitrage for the property-owning aristocracy since the
cost of providing defence and security fell as civil order returned. The aristocracy continued to
hold the land, but now with diminished effective obligations, which meant that it had a private
value to them. From this point, property once more meant private wealth, similar to the estates of
late Rome. The social sanction of its personal enjoyment and its economic potential for
concentration provided the fundamentals for the initiation of its capitalistic use in a way that late
Rome may have developed had civil order not failed. Marxist writers such as Anderson see
medieval Europe as a slow although inexorable transition to the “capitalist mode of production”,
although this phenomena appears however to have been unique to Europe because:
…the countryside of European feudalism also underwent an evolution that had no parallel
elsewhere. The extreme rarity of the fief system as a type of rural property…was never
known in the great Islamic states, or under successive Chinese dynasties, both of which
had their own characteristic forms of agrarian land tenure.6
The difference between the trajectory of feudalism in Europe opposed to other cultures was
largely connected with the unique evolution of commerce in Europe that was more quickly
extended into property. China, Japan, South America and Islam all displayed the intimate
connection of property and government that characterises feudalism. They also have histories
marked by the concentration of power, usually linked to property, that Marxist thought identifies
with capitalism. Unlike capitalism, that sanctions the commercial concentration of power, they
appropriated and held power directly using military or political means. While effective, that
approach was inferior to capitalism since it required Machiavellian discretion within the
appearance of holding property and power for an honourable purpose. European commerce was
signified by the elimination of the underlying ethic that made property a conditional right. This
ethical evolution at first proceeded discretely, but eventually flourished as Medieval ethics were
usurped by the social revolutions of the sixteenth century7. Anderson described this transition in
the European feudal notion of property rights as follows:
[t]he pure feudal mode of production was characterised by conditional private property in
land, vested in a class of hereditary nobles. The private or individual nature of this
landownership demarcated it, as Marx saw, from a whole range of alternative agrarian
systems outside Europe and Japan, where formal State monopoly of land, either original or
durable, corresponded to much less strictly ‘aristocratic’ possessing classes than knights
or samurai. But, once again, European development branched beyond that of Japan with
the transition from conditional to absolute private property in land, in the epoch of the
Renaissance.8
So, conditional private property in land was transformed to absolute private property with the
result according to Anderson being as follows:
6
Ibid 424
See Weber (1974) and Fanfani (1939)
8
Ibid
7
5
[t]he formula, however, contains a profound truth if applied in a somewhat different sense:
the transformation of one form of private property – conditional – into another form of
private property – absolute – within the landowning nobility was the indispensable
preparation for the advent of capitalism and signified the moment at which Europe left
behind all other agrarian systems. In the long transitional epoch in which land remained
quantitatively the predominant source of wealth across the continent, the consolidation of
an unrestricted and hereditary private property in it was a fundamental step towards the
release of the necessary factors of production for the accumulation of capital proper. The
very ‘vinculism’ which the European aristocracy displayed in the early modern age was
already evidence of the objective pressures towards a free market in land that was
ultimately to generate a capitalist agriculture.9
The transition of property from low value conditional to high value absolute/private paralleled the
rise in the merchant class to para-aristocracy. The period also saw the beginnings of the rise of
manufacturers to follow the steps of the merchants as challengers to landowners for private
wealth. Agricultural capitalism was overtaken by mercantile capitalism, industrial capitalism and
now financial capitalism as the most powerful visible forms of wealth control. As seen in the
failure of property after the decline of Rome, these can only exist in environments where civil
government has the strength and inclination to uphold the requisite property institutions. The
beneficiaries of property in early modernity recognised the importance of reinforcing civil
government as a means of securing their own position. Hence, private rights in property arose in
tandem with the emergence of ‘absolutist public authority’, where according to Anderson:
The increase in the political sway of the royal state was accompanied, not by a decrease in
the economic security of noble landownership but by a corresponding increase in the
general rights of private property. The age in which ‘Absolutist’ public authority was
imposed was also simultaneously the age in which ‘absolute’ private property was
progressively consolidated.10
These developments were paralleled by developments in social and ethical thought. Early postRoman feudalism of the Dark ages (500-800AD) was based on the equitable exchange of
property title for military protection and civil order. The Middle ages theory of property (800AD
to 1100AD) was based on an organic understanding of Christian society with the king as the
dispenser of the secular aspect of the will of God. The Medieval period (1100AD to 1500AD)
developed a more flexible concept of property based on human nature. In that theory of property,
the Aristotelian dual notion of private ownership with common use was developed. Feudalism
fulfilled the dual aspects of property. Being owned by the king, property could be efficiently and
responsibly managed, in a way that no socialist society has been able to match. However, the king
held title on the condition that its income was used appropriately for the welfare of the
community. This was the application of the benefit of property for the entire community, that is,
managed common use. The transition to absolutism required the development of the supposed
Divine right of kings that subtly released the king from this obligation by giving him absolute
authority over the use of the property with which he was entrusted. Absolute authority gave the
king the power to grant property absolutely to others thus giving freehold private enjoyment of
9
Ibid 425
Ibid 429
10
Commented [DGS3]: There were three pre-modern
economic institutions that distinguished it from capitalism.
These were 1. Property as obligation; 2. Just price; & 3.
Rejection of usury. Capitalism arose as a result of changes to
community attitudes of at least the first two, though inversion
of ethical sentiment towards all three was the hallmark of the
Renaissance. If you want to pursue this line in history we
should also discuss Weber's Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of
Capitalism of one of the other commentaries on the cultural
connection between the moral changes that flowed from the
religious changes of that century. Anderson's point about
Europe's unique trajectory towards capitalism compared to
other early feudal societies has more to do with fundamental
changes in European religious sentiments than a Marxist
would wish to admit. The reason why the Moslems did not
change was that their religion did not (and has not) change in
its economic ethics. China is similar, though in that case it
was more a matter of ethics based on paternal respect that
was not usurped till the twentieth century.
The notion of absolutism in the monarchy, or even the
aristocracy in general needs to be understood in the context of
this change. The pre-modern monarch (say 700AD, but
certainly 800AD, to 1500AD) was not absolute but held
power within Christian culture that generally understood that
the monarch's power was conditional exercising it consistent
with the will of God. After the sixteenth century that relation
was inverted in what is known as the principle of the divine
right of kings. That principle claimed that kings by nature did
the will of God, therefore they had no need to consider His
will in making judgements. This created the context for
absolutism that was manifested in
Marxist thought, built as it is on a conflict theory of human
relationships, has considerable difficulty recognising the
system of obligations that marked any of the feudal systems,
and hence is likely to miss the central dynamic of European
history, especially in contrast to other cultures.
6
property its ethical foundation. Once property could be unconditionally privately held, it acquired
value to the extent of the set of freehold rights that were granted.
Absolutism was primarily a political principle and was ushered in using a revised theory of
authority. It effectively dissolved the theoretical foundation for property as it had existed for the
previous millennia. The first attempts to rebuild a theory of property in an absolutist regime
followed the Medieval strategy of appealing to the nature of things. John Locke is often
considered the father of modern property theory when he reasoned:
"Though the Earth and all inferior Creatures be common to all Men, yet every Man has a
Property in his own Person. This no Body has any Right to but himself. The Labour of his
Body, and the Work of his Hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he
removes out of the State that Nature hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his Labour
with, and joyned to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his Property."11
Locke accepted that a man's labour was naturally his own and hence not to have title to it would
be a violation of natural justice. Since the farmer applies his labour to the land, if he did not have
title to the land, then his natural title to his labour would be uncertain. Hence, private property is a
necessary way to ensure natural justice. Locke's theory of property was consistent with his overall
vision of politics and economics, but it was flawed. His theory could only validate partial title,
based on the value of improvements. It would mean that a tenant clearing the virgin lands of a
landlord would gain title to them. Moreover, Locke was mute on how much labour one would
have to expend on property before title was warranted, on the contrary, he claimed:
"Thus the Grass my Horse has bit; the Turfs my servant has cut; and the Ore I have digg'd
in any place where I have a right to them in common with others, become my Property,
without the assignation or consent of any body" 12
The shortcomings of Locke's approach were recognised and later Enlightenment thinkers took
another approach at demonstrating the natural origins of absolute private property. Following the
revised notion of what constituted natural, the empiricists considered that human nature was
revealed by observing unconstrained human action. Hume went so far as to claim that nothing
more could be known of human nature than what was observed. On this basis, Hume's colleague,
Adam Smith, observed that private property was a fact of English society, and that it was
supported by English law. He emphasised the fact of possession and a legal/governmental
framework supporting a particular institution of property. In this way he could assert:
Property and civil government very much depend on one another. The preservation of
property and the inequality of possession first formed it, and the state of property must
always vary with the form of government.13
Legally sanctioned possession was the Enlightenment understanding of property, which led to
Smith's eighteenth century colleague, Lord William Blackstone, to summarise in his memorable
definition of property as:
11
Locke, John. 1693/1967. Two Treatises of Government. Edited by W. vonLeyden, critical edn.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Bk.2 Ch.V, n27]
12
ibid [II, ch V, n.28]
13
Smith, Adam. 1978. Lectures on Jurisprudence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ( p. 410)
7
"... that sole and despotic dominion which one man claims and exercises over the things of
the world, in total exclusion of the right of any individual in the universe." 14
This view of property has not changed appreciably since the eighteenth century, despite being
assailed by the socialists. It now tends to be justified more on the basis of supposed economic
efficiency than any recourse to the metaphysics of natures. It suits the absolutist approach, though
recent decades have seen the success of various appeals to soften the strong implications of
property being a despotic right.
With absolute private property, there emerged a concurrent need for definition of the territoriality
of the rights and interests within:
…[an] international state-system that defined and demarcated the continent as a whole.15
With this need for accurate definition, came the need for concomitant valuation of the worth of
the private property so defined. Murray usefully describes the concept of value, which has
emerged to deal with private property as follows:
Value in the economic sense means the benefit conferred by ownership, which includes not
only the possibility of exchange for other commodities, but all the satisfaction that may
arise from possession.16
Further, he states that the valuer:
…normally has to deal only with that concept of value which is known as “value in
exchange.” In other words he has to measure the market value; that is to say, the relativity
existing between the subject property and other properties and commodities.
The market value of land at a certain date may be defined as the amount of money that the
land would bring in the open market by voluntary bargaining between vendor and
purchaser, both willing to trade but neither of them so anxious to do so, that he would
overlook any ordinary business consideration. We must further suppose both to be
perfectly acquainted with the land, and cognizant of all circumstances which might affect
its value, either advantageously or prejudicially, including its situation, character, quality,
proximity to conveniences or inconveniences, its surrounding features, the then present
demand for land and the likelihood, as then appearing, to persons best capable of forming
14
Blackstone, Willian. 1979. Commentaries on the Laws of England: A facsimile of the First Edition of
1765-69. Edited by S. N. Katz. 4 vols. Chicago: Chicago University Press. (p. 2)
Ibid 431
16
John F N Murray Principles and Practice of Valuation (Sydney: Commonwealth Institute of Valuers),
1969
15
8
an opinion, of a rise or fall for what reason soever in the amount which one would
otherwise be willing to fix as the value of the property.17
This description of market value by Murray has it roots in a definition enunciated in Spencer v
The Commonwealth of Australia (1907) 5 CLR 418 at 441, where Isaacs J applied the following
test for market value:
To arrive at the value of the land at that date, we have…to suppose it sold then, not by
means of a forced sale, but by voluntary bargaining between the plaintiff and a purchaser
willing to trade, but neither of them so anxious to do so that he would overlook any
ordinary business consideration. We must further suppose both to be perfectly acquainted
with the land and cognizant of all circumstances which might affect its value, either
advantageously or prejudicially, including its situation, character, quality, proximity to
conveniences or inconveniences, its surrounding features, the then present demand for
land, and the likelihood as then appearing to persons best capable of forming an opinion,
of a rise or fall for what reasons soever in the amount which one would otherwise be
willing to fix as to the value of the property.
Jefferies usefully answers the question of what is value in the following way:
Value has many interpretations depending upon the definition and terminology used. There
can be different types of value, such as replacement value, sale value, loan value, market
value, insurance value….
For something to have value it must have utility, or be able to arouse desire for its
possession to satisfy some need through its possession or use. Mere usefulness or even
necessity on its own will not create value in an economic sense unless there is also the
element of scarcity. A common example is air, which because it is in free abundance does
not have a value in an economic sense, though having a very high utility. However, with
some modern buildings and structures, such as fully enclosed shopping complexes and
modern office blocks, specially conditioned air is supplied as part of a controlled
environment which certainly adds value to the space for leasing purposes.
For something to be valued it must also be negotiable in a market, having the purchasing
power to be exchanged for money.
Therefore to be valued, property must have utility and scarcity, which arouses the desire of
a purchaser who has the purchasing power and ability to acquire it and obtain its
possession.
Real estate, has the added characteristic of permanence compared with other consumer
goods which may be used up in satisfying the short-term needs or desires of the purchaser
with possibly some residual waste for disposal, Real estate is durable property which has
17
Ibid
9
the almost unique characteristic of extending the benefits of its ownership over very long
periods. The value of real estate arises out of its future benefits to the owner and therefore
its value is the present worth of the future utility to be enjoyed from its possession in the
future. As a result the value of real property must take into account the trends in the local
and general economy, and should reflect the degree to which the market recognises future
benefits. The utilities that real estate gives to an owner may include the anticipation that
there will be some benefit in the use and occupation of the property; some profit in its
rental; a potential for development into a higher and more intense use than present; or the
anticipation that the real value will increase and provide the owner with a capital gain.18
In applying these definitions of market value, a body of valuation theory and practice has
developed in Australia and New Zealand over the past century, and can be ascertained in classic
works such as Murray19, Jefferies20 and Rost and Collins21. Indeed, the activity of ascribing the
worth of property can be traced back to at least biblical times according to Murray22, who notes
that Ephron in selling his field to Abraham is quoted as saying:
My Lord, hearken unto me: the land is worth 400 shekels of silver; what is that betwixt me
and thee? (Genesis xxiii)
However, the body of valuation theory and practice has been garnered from an understanding that
the property rights to be valued are in the familiar guise of useful buildings constructed upon a
basic site. This familiar union of human product, fused to a natural, and primevally common,
resource blurs appropriate understanding of the underlying issues. There is a tenor of regularity,
constancy, and fixity in such property, all of which comes from the site alone, reflecting a
synergy of absolute private property, despotic control and enjoyment, territorial definition, and
economic/legal value .
The extent of property rights is always a positive human convention. The development of
absolute private property was a gradual accretion of private rights out of the public, or common
domain. Rights such as exclusive possession tend to be necessitated first by agricultural people.
The right to bequeath or sell land becomes a priority when either the land contains durable human
products or the culture sanctions the private enjoyment of land rent. The separation and exclusion
of certain rights to minerals within the land is a relatively recent development, driven by the
relative value of these things and the recognition by the state that they have a worth not to be
alienated lightly. Recent developments in urban organisation have necessitated focus on the right
to construct improvements and the control and sharing of that right through urban planning statute
and the use of easements.
The definition of land, a key component of the current property institution, is a human art that has
a long history. Geometry was first developed for land definition in Egypt and land surveying
grew as a specialisation of land administration in England parallel to the emergence of absolute
18
Rodney L Jefferies Urban Valuation in New Zealand Vol 1 (Wellington: New Zealand Institute of
Valuers, 1978) 5-1.
19
Murray 76
Jefferies 1-1
R.O. Rost & H.G. Collins Land Valuation and Compensation in Australia (Sydney: Australian Institute
of Valuers) (1984) 18
22
Murray 14
20
21
10
private property. Land definition is possible because of the fixed nature of land and is facilitated
by human artefacts, including fencing, buildings and other monuments This is not so with the
new forms of property rights which, due to the challenges that they present in terms of definition
and control, are inherently land property sui generis.
The commodification of natural resources such as water and biota, 23 and the recognition by the
High Court in 1992 of native title24 has resulted in changes to fundamental understandings of
property rights. 25 Indeed, the interplay between indigenous and non-indigenous rights and
interests has bought starkly into focus quite different values ascribed to property rights, all of
which are nevertheless expressions of worth. 26
All non-indigenous property rights result in the conferral of three qualities or capacities, namely a
management power, an ability to receive income or benefits and an ability to sell or alienate the
interest. In particular, the transition from open access to property rights for natural resources has
drawn attention to just how we define whether particular “rights” are in fact property rights.
Confounding this issue of transition is the long established pattern of self-regulation which
according to Arrow27 has resulted in the emergence of social institutions to meet this need,
namely:
…private property rights, frequently hard to define, on the one hand, and the supervision of
the state, on the other, [which] only begin to exhaust the list of social devices to balance
individual initiative with prevention of injury to others.
A test for property rights
In attempting to develop a test for property rights which accommodates new forms of “property”,
it is important that the paradigm within which this test is to operate is interrogated and
understood. To a large extent the development of a test for such property rights is an endogenous
enterprise pertaining to a particular culture, which to be meaningful in Australia must emerge
from the hegemonic epistemology of settled anglo-Australian land law.
Hence, any methodology used to value new forms of property rights, especially those in natural
resources, will depend on the use to which the resource is to be put, and the purpose of the
valuation. The likely reasons for attributing a value to such a property right has to do with
maximizing the economic benefit of the resource, balancing social any aspects, compensation for
loss of rights, access and the voluntary sale or purchase of property rights by private parties.
Rosemary Lyster “(De)regulating the Rural Environment” Environmental and Planning Law Journal
18:5 (2001) 447. See also Judson Agius “Biodiversity Credits: Creating Missing Markets for Biodiversity,
Environmental and Planning Law Journal 18:5 (2001) 490.
24
Mabo-v-Queensland(No.2) (1992) 175 CLR 1
25
Permits and licenses have in a number of cases been held to be property i.e. Dovey –v- The Minister for
Primary Industries (1993) 119ALR108; Western Mining Corporation-v-Commonwealth (1994)
121ALR661; Newcrest Mining (WA) Ltd –v- Commonwealth (1997) 147ALR42.
26
Lyster 455
27
Kenneth J Arrow “Foreword” in Rights to Nature: Ecological, Economic, Cultural, and Political
Principles of Institutions for the Environment, eds S Hanna, C Folke and K Maler (Washington: Island
Press, 1996) xiv
23
11
The ability of holders of property rights in natural resources to sell, or lease their rights is more
limited than holders of more widely encountered property rights such as freehold or leasehold. In
certain circumstances, property rights in natural resources may be inalienable, capable only of
surrender to the Crown.
In this paper, the notion of property rights in natural resources will be discussed in generic rather
than specific terms. Benefits are discussed in terms of their characteristics, rather than focusing
on the physical nature of the resource, an approach rooted in consumption theory requiring a level
of abstraction allowing the resultant advice to be applicable to a broad range of circumstances.
This prerequisite is especially important where there is regional variability in the use of natural
resources such as water, and possible regional changes over time to such rights. This approach
also accommodates the conceiving of different possible bundles of rights in natural resources as
“property”, and the different forms in which such rights may be held including exclusive and nonexclusive. This aspect will be developed later in this paper in the context of fundamental
characteristics, which must be evident for a property right to exist.
It is generally accepted in the literature that recognised grants of property define the range of
privileges and responsibilities of holders to specified rights in natural resources. It is generally
believed that such rights are either legal rights or economic rights, or both. 28 In attempting to
construct a test to determine whether a right is indeed a property right, it is important that the
different but necessarily interrelated notions of legal and economic rights are clearly understood.
When such rights are viewed as legal rights they involve an assignation by the State through
legislation, common law or other means (e.g. custom) to an individual, group of individuals or
organisation, of specified property rights that the State wishes to assign. Even when assigned,
there is the question of regulation which can be critical to the value of the legal rights, which as
Denman asserts lies in:
…the extent to which restraints can and should be imposed by the State on the use of the
private property rights…Restraint may be severe and curtail the absolute rights of property
to the near practical abolition of them; or the touch of the State power may be exceedingly
light and leave near absolute power with the holders of the private property right.
Political debate in these circumstances centres round the extent and nature of the restraint
to be imposed by the State over the exercise of property rights…29
However, regulation restraining the use of specified property rights is accepted as a necessary
feature of their continued existence in society, as explained in Mason-v-Tritton (1994) 34
NSWLR 572 where Kirby P. (at 592-593) stated:
28
29
Yoram Barzel, Economic Analysis of Property Rights, (New York: Cambridge University Press 1997) 3
Donald Denman, “Recognising the property right”, The Planner 67:6 (1981) 161.
12
…[i]n the ordinary case, control and regulation of the rights and privileges associated
with property ownership is consistent with continued property ownership. Indeed civilized
societies demand that proprietary rights and interests be highly regulated.
The new forms of “property”, especially water, show that for these to be provided as legal rights
they must now occur as a result of formal arrangements which derive from a subtle interplay
between constitutional law, legislation, common law and case law. There is nowadays almost no
recognition space in such formal arrangements for informal conventions and customs that may
have developed over time in relation to access and usage of natural resources. This fact is
highlighted by the inadequacies of water access rights in NSW which until recently relied heavily
on the good will of the Minister and his Department for any real security and duration of tenure 30.
Economic rights depend on, and are subsidiary to, the capacity of legal rights to permit and allow
the holder to enjoy as a benefit from the natural resource in question. In the past, the creation of a
market for rights in natural resources has been impeded by the inability of holders to alienate.
Over time, administrative structures for the allocation and use of such resources (in particular
water) have developed, permitting an understanding (albeit poorly developed), of the economic
worth of the resource notwithstanding the inchoate nature of these rights. This has also not
prevented their valuation.
However, it is clear that the conceiving of such property rights remains at best conjectural, and
possibly confused by sophistry. This is evidenced by the absence of a definition of “water
property rights” in the Water Management Act 2000 (NSW), notwithstanding assertions by the
Department of Land and Water Conversation (DLWC) that the new legislation would:
…maximize the specification and tenure of water entitlements whilst still being able to
manage adaptively.31
This omission was also evident in the Second Reading speech to the Bill where the Minister
merely stated that:
[i]t is the term of a plan that really helps to define water rights, and the period of 10 years
provides a much better basis for business confidence and investment. 32
Further, that:
30
The Water Management Act 2000 (NSW) repeals the Water Act 1912 (NSW), which licensed water users
and access for the majority of the last century.
31
DLWC, 13.
32
Richard Amery, Minister for Agriculture, and Minister for Land and Water Conservation, Second
Reading speech, Water Management Bill 2000, 31 October 2000, 3.
13
[t]he conditions of these water access licences will also be linked to the 10-year water
management planning cycle. These amendments are more consistent with the Council of
Australian Governments [COAG] requirement to specify water rights as clearly as
possible. They also provide more certainty for water users.33
This simplistic view of the security to be provided to water users has been criticised by Crase,
Dollery and Lockwood who point out that:
…successful water markets are predicated on the premise that “…buyers must feel
confident that they will receive and be able to use the right purchased…[and]…welldefined and enforced mechanisms and criteria must be in place to assure that users are
adequately compensated when their rights are confiscated or transferred to higher societal
preferences”…By way of contrast, the Water Management Bill would appear to do little to
allay the concerns of irrigators about the strength of their property rights in water.
…We contend that the attenuation of property rights in this form constrains the capacity of
the market to generate surplus by limiting the incentives to undertake trade. 34
Further, irrigation water users have in their submission to the NSW Government argued that the
legislation:
…completely lacks detail on the specification of water rights.
…[E]ntitlements [must be] backed by separation of water property rights from land title
and clear specification of entitlements in terms of ownership, volume, reliability,
transferability and, if appropriate, quality. 35
An inspection of the Water Management Act 2000 (NSW) suggests that there has been a
significant reluctance by the drafters of the legislation to provide detail as to the nature of water
property rights. Also, contrary to the Minister’s assertions in the Second Reading speech, it would
appear that the basic policy position for the implementation of water property rights proposed by
the Agriculture and Resource Management Council of Australia and New Zealand (ARMCANZ)
36
has not been adequately implemented.
33
Ibid.
Lin Crase, Brian Dollery & Mike Lockwood, “Towards an Understanding of Static Transaction Costs in
the NSW Permanent Water Market: An Application of Choice Modelling”, unpublished paper submitted to
Australian Journal of Agricultural and Resource Economics (2000), 4.
35
NSW Irrigators Council (NSWIC) NSW Irrigators Council Submission to the Draft Water Management
Bill, roneo (Sydney, 2000) 1.
36
ARMCANZ) Water Allocations and Entitlements: A National Framework for the Implementation of
Property Rights in Water, Task Force on COAG Water Reform Occasional Paper No.1 (Canberra: Standing
Committee on Agriculture and Resource Management, 1995) October.
34
14
Research by Chant et al37 into the efficiency of natural resource allocation shows that undesirable
socio-economic and environmental impacts can be ameliorated if property rights are well defined.
Based on the methodology of Coase, they claim that a “socially optimal result” can be achieved
once property rights have security and are tradeable. 38
In addition, it is argued that when such rights are clarified and enforced, the market place will
more readily provide the best allocation of property rights in natural resources. Furthermore,
when property rights are held exclusively it is argued that the rationing of natural resources
among competing users acts as a financial incentive to protect and use the asset because of the
exercise of such property rights, albeit within an environmental protection legislative framework
to prevent consequential adverse effects.
From the perspective of sustainable development, it is interesting that economists 39 argue that
natural resources must be now paid and accounted for. Natural resources such as water have
suffered damage because the cost has been traditionally borne publicly rather than privately.
From this line of inquiry, it can be concluded that the specification of water property rights will
create a market in water which provides incentives for greater stewardship by the holders of the
resource.
As stated earlier, it is suggested that the extent of the property rights of all holders should be
defined, together with the amount of resource (eg water) which should be reserved for
environmental and community purposes. It is argued by ARMCANZ that a property rights
framework in water would be created which incorporates environmental constraints within which
these rights can be traded.40
A fundamental flaw
It may seem prosaic in the extreme, but any discourse on “new property rights” ought to be
embarked upon from the standpoint that such rights must meet a defensible test of what a
property right is. If these property rights are to be meaningful to users, purchasers, and especially
the banks and financial organisations that will use these rights as collateral for mortgage-based
loans, then the test of whether they are indeed property rights is crucial.
In constructing such a test, it is essential to gain an appreciation of existing judicial considerations
of the notion of “property”. Starke J. in The Minister of State for the Army-v-Dalziel (1944) 68
CLR at 290 (Dalziel) indicated that such a definition:
John Chant, Donald McFetridge, Douglas Smith and John Nurick, “The Economics of the Green
Society”, in Reconciling Economics and the Environment, eds. J. Bennett and W Block (West Perth:
Australian Institute for Public Policy, 1991) 67, 69.
38
Chant, McFetridge, Smith and Nurick, 66.
39
Lyuba Zarsky “Economy and Ecology: Sustainable Development”, in Economics as a Social Science:
Readings in Political Economy, eds G. Argyrous and F. Stilwell (Sydney: Pluto Press, 1996) 173, 175.
40
ARMCANZ, 4.
37
15
…extends to every species of valuable right and interest including real and personal
property, incorporeal hereditaments such as rents and services, rights of way, rights of
profit or use in land of another, and chooses in action.
Starke J. (at 290) also comments that:
…to acquire any such right is rightly described as an acquisition of property.
This approach to constructing a definition of “property” has been further strengthened in a recent
decision Yanner-v-Eaton (1999) HCA 53 (unreported 7 October 1999) (Yanner), where the High
Court took the opportunity to contrast property in the conventional sense with the “property” or
“ownership” that the Crown asserts over natural resources.
The Court stated that:
The word “property” is often used to refer to something that belongs to
another….”property” does not refer to a thing; it is a description of a legal relationship
with a thing. It refers to a degree of power that is recognised in law as power permissibly
exercised over the thing. The concept of “property” may be elusive. Usually it is treated as
a “bundle of rights”.
But even this may have its limits as an analytical tool or accurate description, and it may
be…that “the ultimate fact about property is that it does not really exist; it is mere
illusion”.41
Also, the Court usefully stated that the common law position of natural resources was as follows:
At common law there could be no “absolute property”, but only “qualified property” in
fire, light air, water and wild animals42
Even previously accepted sovereign rights and interests over territory, such as sea lands, are no
longer viewed as completely settled. For example, in the recent decision in Commonwealth –vYarmirr (HCA unreported 11 October 2001) it was held by the majority that while the waters
around Croker Island where internationally recognised as part of the territorial sea of Australia,
such sea lands where not part of the original “territory” of England, and therefore not owned. 43
41
Yanner-v-Eaton (1999) HCA 53, at 8 per Gleeson CJ, Gaudron Kirby & Hayne JJ.
Ibid, 11.
43
The majority judges cited the decision in R.-v-Keyn (1876) 2 Ex D 63 (Keyn’s case)as authority for this
view that recognition does not necessarily result in ownership of territory.
42
16
Nevertheless, as stated earlier in this paper, “property” is generally understood as a titled right to
land or to exploit natural resources such as minerals. Commonly these property rights are referred
to by the terminology “real estate”, with its emphasis on the immoveable nature of the “property”
concerned such as land, buildings and minerals.
The range of interests that are classed as “property” while limited only by our imagination, has
however been restrained by the Courts of common law countries who have only recognised a few
kinds of interests in land, which are regarded as usual property rights. Some of these rights will
be readily recognised such as freehold and leasehold, however a few such as mining rights,
fishing rights, and water entitlements have also been recognised.
There has also been the very recent recognition of carbon as a property right, and legislation in
various states is developing this concept.44 The objective in recognizing carbon as “property” is:
…to provide secure title for carbon sequestration rights through registration on the land
title system. The practical effect of this will be that a carbon right attached to property will
be held separately from the land ownership, and the carbon right attached to land will be
viewable on a property title search, putting the world on notice of the obligations that flow
with that land.45
Even more recently, it has been suggested that the use of biota such as genetic botanicals may
have to be not only regulated but also recognised as property if they are to be conserved. It is
argued that the creation of such property rights would act as a “real economic incentive” 46 to
sustainably utilise these natural resources. The current enquiry into bioprospecting by the House
of Representatives Standing Committee on Primary Industries and Regional Services strongly
suggests that:
…[t]he regulation of access to biological resources for research and exploitation has been
problematical.47
However, a common feature of these property rights is that the interests in question are territorial,
in so much as the right is contained only within defined boundaries. This is commonly achieved
by way of a legal description of the boundaries, which have been defined by means of a cadastre.
In addition, these rights are also proscribed in so far as what activities can occur within the
territory48, the manner in which the right is to be paid for, and other obligations incurred or
limitations imposed.
44
Jacqueline Bredhauer “Tree Clearing in Western Queensland – a Cost Benefit Analysis of Carbon
Sequestration”, Environmental and Planning Law Journal 17:5 (2000) 389.
45
Ibid.
46
Nicole Veash “River of no Returns” The Australian Magazine (18-19 November 2000) 40. See also
Zarsky 173.
47
Information and Research Service of the Department of the Parliamentary Library Bioprospecting and
Regional Industry Development in Australia – Some issues for the Committee’s Inquiry Paper prepared for
the House of Representatives Standing Committee on Primary Industries and Regional Services (Canberra:
2000) 2.
48
Denman, 161.
17
Some of these usual property rights can be acquired outright, while some such as fishing rights
and water entitlements may be attached to rights that are held in a parcel of land adjacent or
nearby.
Common qualities or capacities of property rights
As previously stated, in varying degrees all “property rights” result in the conferral of three
qualities (or capacities):
1. a management power,
2. an ability to receive income or benefits, and
3. an ability to sell or alienate the interest.
The degree to which these three qualities are evident in a particular property right depends on the
mix of fundamental characteristics that the particular property right contains.
As stated earlier in this paper, an understanding of these fundamental characteristics is crucial to
ascertaining whether a particular right is a “property right”. There have been significant attempts
over the past few years by national governments to commodify natural resources, notably
fisheries. The history of subsidised open access to fisheries has led to the view of the American
Fisheries Society that:
…transferable fishing quotas are coming into being as a way of conferring property rights
on wild food (unfarmed) stocks in an effort to encourage more enduring harvests.49
This transition from open access to property rights for natural resources is reflected in increasing
attention by Australian courts to these less familiar forms of “property”. A notable example of
these judicial considerations is found in Minister for Primary Industry and Energy and Australian
Fisheries Management Authority-v-Davey and Fitti (1993) 119 ALR 108, where the Court was
asked inter alia whether the fishing capacity permitted for the Northern Prawn Fishery expressed
in “units of fishing capacity” was in fact “property” within the meaning of para.51(xxxi) of the
Australian Constitution which states that:
The Parliament shall, subject to this Constitution, have power to make laws for the peace,
order, and good government of the Commonwealth with respect to: …The acquisition of property on just terms from any State or person for any purpose in
respect of which the Parliament has power to make laws:
49
Bob Beale, “Depths of Despair”. The Sydney Morning Herald (6 June 1998) 10s.
18
In deciding whether the “units of fishing capacity” were property, it was noted by the Court that
the limits of operation of para.51 (xxxi) have not been determined precisely. However, the Court
drew upon the definition of property as discussed in the Dalziel case which was referred to earlier
in this paper, and noted that the approach in Dalziel was approved in Australian Tape
Manufacturers Association Ltd-v-Commonwealth of Australia (1993) 112 ALR 53 at 65.
The Court decided that the “units of fishing capacity” were property rights which were generated
by statute, and were “property” for the purposes of para.51 (xxxi).
Fundamental characteristics
It will be seen that existing judicial considerations of the notion of “property” fall short of
providing a defensible test of what a property right is. As stated previously, all property rights
have the three qualities or capacities of management, income/benefit and alienation, each in
varying combinations. At a more fundamental level, there are also characteristics which are
present in any property right, and which, depending on the blend and quality of the
characteristics, determines the relative influence of the three qualities or capacities outlined
earlier.
The concept of property rights arises from a need to address problems emerging from the actual
requirements of society. Nowhere more apparent is this seen than in the recent commodification
of increasingly valuable natural resources such as water, which in the conferring of a property
rights regime is hoped, in line with other resources such as fisheries to become more sustainably
used.50
There is a significant history in the literature of attempts to identify the fundamental
characteristics present in any property right. Hargreaves and Helmore 51 point out that the
foundations of modern Western property rights lie in the legal “world of the Middle Ages”,
however, like other branches of law, their present form is more dependent on the historical forces
of the intervening centuries. Despite the radical demise of the social obligations of Medieval
feudal property in the sixteenth century, the holder of property has never totally escaped a certain
remnant of duties to the community:
There has always been a thin trickle of public law which imposed duties upon landowners,
but these duties – mainly concerned with sanitation, from the old public nuisance to the
modern control by local government bodies of subdivision of land and building and the
duties imposed by statute on rural landholders…were not sufficient to disturb the emphasis
upon private rights as the essential feature of ownership.52
The despotic character of property probably reached its zenith in the eighteenth century, but since
then the laissez faire view that private property rights were almost absolute has waned to the point
that Teh & Dwyer could conclude:
50
Beale, 10s.
A.D. Hargreaves & B.A. Helmore, An Introduction to the Principles of Land Law (New South Wales)
(Sydney: The Law Book Co, 1963) 4.
52
Hargreaves & Helmore, 155.
51
19
[t]here is now general acceptance that property in land must be subject to restrictions in
the interests of preserving public safety, health, natural resources and social harmony.53
The value of a property right may be considered as the net private benefit of the particular
positive institution as it exists within a particular society. The benefit of the absolute right is
partially negated by the concurrent restrictions. This led Gray & Gray to point out that:
…there may well be graduations of “property” in a resource. The amount of “property”
which a specified person may claim in any resource is capable of calibration – along some
sort of sliding scale – from a maximum value to a minimum value…Far from being a
monolithic notion of standard content and invariable intensity, “property” thus turns out
to have an almost infinitely gradable quality.54
This view is of considerable interest in attempting to deduce those fundamental characteristics
that are present in any property right, in particular in natural resources such as water. It will be
observed that a “characteristics” approach has been adopted by the courts in some cases such as
Milirrpum & Anor v Nabalco Pty Ltd & The Commonwealth (1971) 17 FLR 141 when
attempting to ascertain whether a particular interest could be regarded as a property right. This
approach pivots on the identification of commonly encountered characteristics, namely:
The right to use
The right to alienate
The right to exclude
However, Teh and Dwyer note that this approach has been discredited as too limiting because
some forms of property rights may fail to exhibit some of these characteristics, while other
interests may exhibit the full range and yet not be true property rights.55
Given the above, a review of select literature for this paper suggests that a more comprehensive
tabulation of fundamental characteristics ought to provide a level of certainty such that a
meaningful discourse for property rights can be constructed.
A definition of property rights
Part of the difficulty in defining property rights within a particular society is the fact that they are
no more than a positive cultural artefact. The interesting question of what property should be is of
little relevance to commerce in property where the pivotal issue is where legally defensible
property rights are. Anthony Scott,56 (1986) described a comprehensive specification of
Gim Leong Teh and Bryan Dwyer, Introduction to Property Law 2nd ed. (Sydney: Butterworths 1992) 7.
Kevin Gray & Susan Francis Gray, “The Idea of Property in Land”, in Land Law: Themes and
perspectives eds Susan Bright and John Dewar (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998) 16.
55
Teh & Dwyer, 8.
56
Anthony Scott Evolution of Individual Transferable Quotas as a Distinct Class of Property Right edited
version of a paper presented at the NATO Conference on rights-based fishing, Reykjavik, June 1988 and
the APPAM Conference, Seattle, January 1989.
53
54
20
fundamental characteristics of a property right suitable for its inclusion in Western commercial
exchange. Scott outlined a test for property rights, which relies upon the identification of a
minimum of six fundamental characteristics, which he asserted to be present in any property
right. His characteristics are especially directed to the economic value of property rights, and as
such are applicable to societies such as the USA. As such they may be useful in developing a
definition of property rights suitable for contemporary Australian society. They are as follows:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
duration,
flexibility,
exclusivity,
quality of title,
transferability,
divisibility.
Scott shows how, when just four of these characteristics are varied, the worth of a particular
property right can change, given that the amount of any of the characteristics can be observable,
measurable, and continuously variable. There is considerable attraction in this tabulation of
characteristics which Scott suggests to be a minimum when attempting to describe property rights
or interests which have been formed either by statute or even totally outside the common law.
However, these six characteristics require some analysis to explain their relevance to water
property rights if we are to be afforded the benefit of Scott’s initial research. It should be
remembered that his research was undertaken in the context of the development of individual
transferable fishing quotas as a property right. An interrogation of his description of each of the
six characteristics has been undertaken and is separately described below in the context of a test
for water property rights:
Duration
As regards duration, this first fundamental characteristic indicates the period usually in years that
the property right is held, and hence represents a profit or saving to the holder. Scott’s suggestion
that this characteristic should be measured in numbers of years may in the context of water
property rights have to be extended to a much longer time interval to be meaningful.
Flexibility
The second characteristic, flexibility is not specifically explained by Scott however it perhaps is
closely related to the sixth characteristic, divisibility, highlighting that a property right should be
susceptible to modification and/or alteration. In the context of water property rights, this aspect
will almost certainly be a product of the particular regional circumstances within which the water
entitlement and use occurs. In addition, water property rights are constrained ab initio by the
availability of the natural resource, and clearly it is conceivable that the full benefits of the right
may under certain circumstances be constrained.
Exclusivity
The third characteristic, exclusivity, is the inverse of the number of holders of the same or similar
property right. Clearly, a reduction in the exclusivity will reduce the profit or saving enjoyed by
the holder. This characteristic is directly relevant to water property rights.
21
Quality of Title
The fourth characteristic, quality of title, while not explained by Scott clearly refers to the
descending level of security as the tenure falls away from the optimum of notional freehold. The
water entitlement and usage regime currently operative under the Water Act 1912 (NSW) is a
threshold from which water property rights of greater quality of title can be constructed.
Transferability
The fifth characteristic, transferability, is the measurement of the market for the sale or leasing of
the particular property right. A high value would indicate that the demand reaches well beyond
the original acquiring group, and that the mere creation of a market and hence tradability in itself
enhances the value of the particular property right. In the context of water property rights, this
characteristic could also be referred to as tradeability, and relies heavily upon the amelioration of
current government constraints on transfers to other parties.
Divisibility
As regards the sixth characteristic, divisibility (which Scott sees as an aspect of transferability)
this has a number of facets. The property right may be capable of being shared between a number
of holders over one territory or the territory itself maybe subdivided and each new part held
separately. It may also be possible for the holder to divide his right on the basis of seasons or in
the case of fishing rights, on the basis of particular marine species.
In the context of water property rights, there will be limits to divisibility of access and usage,
beyond which the right becomes degraded, almost certainly uneconomic, and devalued.
Interestingly, perusal of recent commentary on the Water Management Bill reveals that a number
of these six fundamental characteristics of property rights have been identified, albeit in inchoate
form. For example, it is noted that ARMCANZ has suggested that within the principles for a
water property rights regime, inter alia:
[t]hat water entitlements be clearly specified in terms of:
rights and conditions of ownership tenure
share of natural resource being allocated (including probability of occurrence);
details of agreed standards of any commercial services to be delivered;
constraints to and rules on transferability; and
constraints to resource use or access.57
Further, ARMCANZ has suggested that such rights must evidence the following features for an
effective market to be created:
…in demand – the market will be effective when competition exists for a set of rights that are
limited in extent or availability;
57
ARMCANZ, 8.
22
well specified in the long-term sense – the market can interpret and depend on
rights really mean;
what the
exclusive – benefits and costs associated with the rights are attributed to the right holders;
enforceable and enforced – regulations and systems exist to ensure the rights are upheld; and
transferable and divisible – regulations and systems are in place to allow the transfer of
rights within defined limitations. 58
Importantly, ARMCANZ59 proposed that the tenure of water property rights should be perpetual,
and yet significantly attenuated this recommendation proposing that conditions of access be
subject to review to achieve acceptable levels of “planning certainty”60.
Therefore as previously noted by Denman61, regulation could if wished by government so
severely curtail these rights as to make the tenure a chimera.
Importantly, the Working Group on Water Resource Policy has reported to COAG that for
trading in water entitlements to be facilitated:
…governments will need to ensure that property rights to water are clearly defined and
specified in terms of ownership, volume, reliability, environmental flows and tenure.
Conversion factors will also need to be specified between different areas of surface and
groundwater systems and where catchments cross jurisdictional boundaries.62
There are clearly elements of the six fundamental features of property rights present in both of the
above writings, and are remarkably similar. It is posited that the six-point test as developed by
Scott is a suitable tool applicable to a broad range of circumstances when a new form of property
right is thought to have emerged.
Constraints on the Definition of Property Rights
It must be stressed that the notion of a “property right” is not a legal term, and the foregoing
discussion is not an attempt (nor should it be) to provide legal advice. Indeed, as this paper has
shown, there has been a long history of reluctance by the Courts to articulate what is “property”
or a “property right”.
It is clear that the form of tenure for a specific property right such as water should be driven by a
synergy of security and tradeability. Many permutations of tenure could doubtless be constructed
which, drawing upon the six fundamental characteristics of property rights identified by Scott,63
would result in a tenure which could be utilised in a system of property rights.
58
ARMCANZ, 4.
Ibid, 8.
60
ARMCANZ, 5.
61
Denman, 161.
62
The Working Group on Water Resource Policy, Report of the Working Group on Water Resource Policy
to the Council of Australian Governments (1993?) 11.
63
Scott
59
23
However, it is recognised that both security and tradeability require that the form of tenure is
capable of acting as collateral for a mortgaged based loan from a bank or other financial
institutions. From this line of reasoning, it can be concluded that the tenure must evidence
qualities which lenders are comfortable and familiar with.
Lenders are familiar with loans, which in the main are secured by way of a mortgage over
freehold land, specifically land which is held under the Real Property Act. This enables a lender
to have a registered first or second mortgage, or a caveat placed upon the public register of those
land titles issued pursuant to that Act.
Usually tenure is unlimited in time, and guaranteed by the Act. There is security of tenure at the
highest level, and the sale or transfer of the property rights held under this form of title can
readily occur subject only to a restriction that stamp duty and statutory charges be paid at the time
of sale or transfer.
While the utility accruing to the holder of the particular property rights is subject to restriction
from the usual range of planning development and environmental controls, the basic six
characteristics of a property right are not impugned. Clearly such a tenure would be the zenith for
any intending holder or mortgagee of new “property rights”, however the nature of some natural
resources is such that a perpetual tenure is unlikely to be granted by the Crown.
It therefore follows that a title for some property rights will be subject to a greater level of
restriction than would a usual “land-based” real property tenure, and also be evidenced in a grant
for a period of years rather than perpetuity. An analogy is the mineral rights granted under the
Mining Act 1992 (NSW) for specific minerals permitting both rights to prospect and mine.
Because the extraction of minerals is determined by the life of the ore body, these “property
rights” are granted or renewed for up to 21 years or longer with concurrence, and are secure. 64
Such rights may or may not impinge upon the “property rights” of the surface landholder, and
there may not necessarily be a nexus between the two holders of these quite different rights. Such
a situation has similarities to the proposal in the Water Management Act 2000 (NSW) where
water property rights and land are to be separated.
Conclusion
The increasing recognition of neophyte property rights in natural resources such as water and
biota has caused the notion of property rights to undergo fundamental change. As the angloAustralian legal system moves closer to an omnibus definition of property rights, this process has
already brought forth calls for a titling system for these new “property rights” which are
reminiscent of the Certificate of Title issued under the Real Property Act, subject to the
inescapable restrictions created by climate and other inherent natural risks.
64
David Farrier, Rosemary Lyster and Linda Pearson, The Environmental Law Handbook: Planning and
Land use in New South Wales, 3rd ed. (Sydney: Redfern Legal Centre Publishing, 1999) 339.
24
Such an approach attempts to enshrine a tenure for these emerging rights, such that compulsory
expropriation by the State cannot occur arbitrarily once the necessary tests as outlined by Scott
for a property right have been met. Indeed, the failure to guarantee security of tenure has been
recognised as the major shortfall of the Water Management Act 2000 (NSW) and its precursor,
the Water Act 1912 (NSW).
The importance of this line of reasoning cannot be overstressed, given that in North Sydney
Municipal Council-v-Boyts Radio and Electrical (1989) 67 LGERA 344 at 345, Kirby J. stated
that property cannot be arbitrarily expropriated, drawing upon previous decisions 65 and stating
that this principle is:
…an essential idea which is both basic and virtually uniform in civilised legal systems.
For this very reason, the development of strata titles as a distinctive property right in the early
1960’s resulted in amendments to the Real Property Act which were innovative in that a nexus
was created between air space and the Crown guarantee of title residing in land. There now is a
need for such an intellectual effort to occur afresh for the new emerging forms of property rights.
Such an endeavour will take place within a plurality of indigenous and non-indigenous rights and
interests, necessitating a rapprochement on managing such property rights. 66
History has shown that anglo-Australian land law can be amended to accommodate hitherto
unknown forms of property (i.e. stratum, community titles, limited term strata title of Crown
leaseholds), and it is the view of the authors that a well tested vehicle already exists wherein these
new property rights could be titled.
REFERENCES
Amery, Richard, Minister for Agriculture, and Minister for Land and Water Conservation,
(2000), Water Management Bill 2000, Second Reading speech, 31 October.
Agius Judson (2001) “Biodiversity Credits: Creating Missing Markets for Biodiversity”
Environmental and Planning Law Journal 18:5, 481-504.
Anderson, Perry. 1979.Lineages of the absolutist state, (London: Verso)
65
Dorrestijn-v-South Australian Planning Commission (1984) 59 AJLR 104
Already, indigenous management approaches such as those by the Gandangara peoples are evidence of
this rapprochement – see Healthy Rivers Commission of NSW Independent Inquiry into the Georges River
– Botany Bay System Final Report (Sydney: September 2001) 56.
66
25
ARMCANZ 1995 Water Allocations and Entitlements: A National Framework for the
Implementation of Property Rights in Water, Task Force on COAG Water Reform Occasional
Paper No.1 (Canberra: Standing Committee on Agriculture and Resource Management,
October.
Arrow, Kenneth J. 1996 “Foreword” in Rights to Nature: Ecological, Economic, Cultural, and
Political Principles of Institutions for the Environment, eds S Hanna, C Folke and K Maler
(Washington: Island Press)
Barzel, Yoram, 1997 Economic Analysis of Property Rights 2nd ed, Political Economy of
Institutions and Decisions series, (New York: Cambridge University Press)
Beale, Bob. 1998 “Depths of Despair”. The Sydney Morning Herald (6 June) 10s.
Bredhauer Jacqueline, 2000 “Tree Clearing in Western Queensland – a Cost Benefit Analysis of
Carbon Sequestration”, Environmental and Planning Law Journal 17:5, 383.
Chant, John, McFetridge, Donald, Smith Douglass and Nurick, John “The Economics of the
Green Society”, in Reconciling Economics and the Environment, eds. J. Bennett and W Block
(West Perth: Australian Institute for Public Policy)
Crase, Lin, Dollery Brian & Lockwood, Mike. 2000 “Towards an Understanding of Static
Transaction Costs in the NSW Permanent Water Market: An Application of Choice
Modelling”, unpublished paper submitted to Australian Journal of Agricultural and Resource
Economics
Denman, Donald. 1981 “Recognising the property right” The Planner 67(6)161
Ely, James W Jnr. 1998 The Guardian of Every Other Right: A Constitutional History of
Property Rights 2nd ed Bicentennial Essays on the Bill of Rights (New York: Oxford
University Press)
Fanfani, Amintore. 1939. Catholicism Protestantism and Capitalism. London: Sheed and Ward.
Farrier, David. Lyster, Rosemary and Pearson, Linda 1999The Environmental Law Handbook:
Planning and Land use in New South Wales, 3rd ed. (Sydney: Redfern Legal Centre
Publishing) 339.
Gray, Kevin & Gray, Susan F. 1998 “The Idea of Property in Land” in Land Law: Themes and
perspectives eds Susan Bright and John Dewar (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
Hargreaves A.D. & B.A. Helmore, B.A. 1963 An Introduction to the Principles of Land Law
Healthy Rivers Commission of NSW 2001 Independent Inquiry into the Georges River – Botany
Bay System Final Report (Sydney: September ) 56.
Information and Research Service of the Department of the Parliamentary Library 2000.
Bioprospecting and Regional Industry Development in Australia – Some issues for the
Committee’s Inquiry Paper prepared for the House of Representatives Standing Committee on
Primary Industries and Regional Services (Canberra)
Jefferies Rodney L , 1978 Urban Valuation in New Zealand Vol 1 (Wellington: New Zealand
Institute of Valuers.)
Lyster Rosemary (2001) “(De)regulating the Rural Environment” Environmental and Planning
Law Journal 18:5 445-468
Masson Sophie. 2001 “Here today, gone yesterday” The Sydney Morning Herald (14 October)
8S
26
Murray John F N. 1969 Principles and Practice of Valuation Sydney: Commonwealth Institute
of Valuers.
National Competition Council. 2001 Water Property Rights Background paper for 3rd tranche
assessment framework,(Canberra: March.)
NSW Irrigators Council (NSWIC) 2000. NSW Irrigators Council Submission to the Draft Water
Management Bill, roneo (Sydney).
Rost R O & Collins H G. 1984 Land Valuation and Compensation in Australia (Sydney:
Australian Institute of Valuers)
Scott, Anthony. Evolution of Individual Transferable Quotas as a Distinct Class of Property
Right edited version of a paper presented at the NATO Conference on rights-based fishing,
Reykjavik, June 1988 and the APPAM Conference 1989, (Seattle) January.
Sheehan J. 2000 “Assessing Compensation for Native Title: A Valuation Perspective” Pacific
Rim Property Research Journal (August 6 (1) 43-55.)
Sheehan J. 2001 Indigenous Property Rights in Water Paper presented at the inaugural
“Certificate in Water Property Rights” 5-day course conducted by the University of
Queensland in conjunction with the Australian Property Institute (QLD) (Brisbane: University
of Queensland) St Lucia 11 July.
Teh, Gim Leong and Dwyer, Bryan. 1992 Introduction to Property Law 2nd ed. (Sydney:
Butterworths)
The Working Group on Water Resource Policy, 1993? Report of the Working Group on Water
Resource Policy to the Council of Australian Governments.
Vargas Llosa, Mario, 2001.“Locally speaking, global is good” The Sydney Morning Herald (10
February) 3S
Veash, Nicole, 2000. “River of no Returns” The Australian Magazine (18-19 November) 40.
Weber, Max. 1974. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Translated by Talcott
Parsons. London: Allen & Unwin.
Zarsky Lyuba. 1996 “Economy and Ecology: Sustainable Development”, in Economics as a
Social Science: Readings in Political Economy, eds G. Argyrous and F. Stilwell (Sydney:
Pluto Press)