Constitutional Stickiness
Ozan O. Varol∗
Continuity is a striking hallmark of the constitutional world. Empirical
evidence shows that many constitutional amendment and replacement
processes counterintuitively produce relatively little change in substance.
During constitutional makeovers, existing provisions frequently “stick,”
even where they are arbitrary, suboptimal, or anachronistic.
This paradox, which I call “constitutional stickiness,” has been
neglected in the scholarship. American constitutional theorists have
largely assumed that Article V’s high threshold for amendment is the
primary culprit for lack of formal constitutional change and that
significant alterations might follow with a lower threshold. With mounting
calls by the states for a constitutional convention, this assumption has also
prompted concerns about a “runaway convention” that could drastically
alter the substance of the U.S. Constitution.
This Article challenges that assumption. Drawing on rational-choice
theory and behavioral law and economics, it provides the first theoretical
analysis of constitutional stickiness in descriptive and normative terms.
Even with low amendment thresholds, the constitutional status quo exerts
significant historical weight and the constitutional starting points
constrain future choices in specific and systemic ways. The existing
constitutional configurations therefore often depend, quite arbitrarily, on
the historical starting point, rather than a rational assessment of all
alternatives. As a result, relatively insignificant events in a country’s early
∗
Copyright © 2016 Ozan O. Varol. Associate Professor of Law, Lewis & Clark
Law School. For helpful comments, I thank Erin Delaney, Rosalind Dixon, David
Fontana, Tom Ginsburg, Vicki Jackson, Richard Kay, Jeremy Kidd, David Landau,
David Law, Russell Miller, Christopher Schmidt, Mark Tushnet, Kathy Varol, Mila
Versteeg, and the participants at workshops and conferences held at the Clough
Center for the Study of Constitutional Democracy at Boston College Law School, the
Center for the Constitution at James Madison’s Montpelier (the Montpelier
Roundtable in Comparative Constitutional Law), as well as participants in the 2014
SEALS Annual Meeting. For outstanding research assistance, I thank Kelsey Benedick,
Katherine Davis, Elisabeth Rennick, Philip Thoennes, and Lynn Williams. I am also
grateful to the Editors of the UC Davis Law Review (particularly Gokalp Gurer) who
provided expert editorial assistance.
899
900
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
constitutional history can have an enormous impact, whereas more
dramatic events that occur later — such as a revolution or a major
constitutional convention — are much less consequential than assumed.
Ultimately, the Article aims to reorient the normative focus of
constitutional scholarship to oft-neglected temporal and sequential
considerations.
TABLE OF CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 901
I. A THEORY OF CONSTITUTIONAL STICKINESS ............................. 909
II. THE CAUSES OF CONSTITUTIONAL STICKINESS.......................... 915
A. Rational Choice ................................................................. 915
1. Benefits of Constitutional Change ............................. 917
2. Costs of Constitutional Change ................................. 925
a. Costs of Drafting ................................................... 925
b. Costs of Negotiation and Ratification ..................... 928
c. Implementation Costs ............................................ 931
B. Behavioral Law and Economics ......................................... 937
1. Status Quo Bias ........................................................... 938
2. Anchoring Bias ........................................................... 947
3. Availability Heuristic .................................................. 948
4. Hedonic Adaptation ................................................... 951
5. Excessive Veneration of the Constitution .................. 952
III. NORMATIVE IMPLICATIONS OF CONSTITUTIONAL STICKINESS ... 954
CONCLUSION....................................................................................... 960
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
901
INTRODUCTION
American constitutional theory suffers from a normative bias.
Scholars have been preoccupied with analyzing the normative
implications of various constitutional provisions at particular
moments of interest and how to alter them for the better.1 Implicit in
these normative explorations is an assumption of a world where
constitution-makers can produce meaningful changes, correct errors
in the original design, and attain certain ideals — as long as they are
unencumbered by a high bar for constitutional amendment. This
assumption has produced a prevailing view that Article V’s high
threshold for constitutional amendment is the primary culprit for lack
of formal constitutional change and that significant alterations might
follow with a lower threshold.2 With mounting calls by the states for a
1 See David S. Law, Constitutions, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF EMPIRICAL LEGAL
RESEARCH 376, 376 (Peter Cane & Herbert M. Kritzer eds., 2010) [hereinafter
Constitutions] (noting that “constitutional scholarship has long been predominantly
normative in character”); Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Constitutional Constraints, 97 CALIF.
L. REV. 975, 977 (2009) (noting the normative orientation of constitutional theorists);
John Ferejohn, The Politics of Imperfection: The Amendment of Constitutions, 22 LAW &
SOC. INQUIRY 501, 526 (1997) (noting that normative scholarship can “create false
visions of constitutional possibilities”); Daryl J. Levinson, Parchment and Politics: The
Positive Puzzle of Constitutional Commitment, 124 HARV. L. REV. 657, 659 (2011)
(“Constitutional lawyers and theorists have . . . focus[ed] instead on normative
issues . . . .”).
2 See Bruce Ackerman, The Emergency Constitution, 113 YALE L.J. 1029, 1031,
1077 (2004) (noting that Article V represents “a formidable obstacle course” to
amendment); John Ferejohn & Lawrence Sager, Commitment and Constitutionalism, 81
TEX. L. REV. 1929, 1954 (2003) (“[Article V’s] resistance to change is what cements
the external, institutional commitments of the Constitution in place.”); William E.
Forbath, The Politics of Constitutional Design: Obduracy and Amendability — A
Comment on Ferejohn and Sager, 81 TEX. L. REV. 1965, 1979-80 (2003) (“The
overbearing obduracy of the unamended Article V diminished the jurisgenerative
politics of the New Deal moment, and deprived us of new constitutional texts — texts
on which citizens and courts could have rested claims to extend and deepen our
constitutional commitments in ways we would prize.”); Aziz Z. Huq, The Negotiated
Structural Constitution, 114 COLUM. L. REV. 1595, 1665 (2014) (noting that political
actors are unable to amend the U.S. Constitution due to “exorbitant transaction costs”
stemming from Article V); Michael J. Klarman, What’s So Great About
Constitutionalism?, 93 NW. U. L. REV. 145, 149 (1998) (“The supermajority
requirements of Article V unduly privilege the status quo . . . .”); Sanford Levinson,
How the United States Constitution Contributes to the Democratic Deficit in America, 55
DRAKE L. REV. 859, 874 (2007) (arguing that Article V’s requirements make
constitutional amendment “almost impossible by the difficulties placed in its path”);
David A. Strauss, The Irrelevance of Constitutional Amendments, 114 HARV. L. REV.
1457, 1459 (2001) (“It is only a slight exaggeration to say that [informal
amendments] are the only means of change we have.”).
902
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
constitutional convention,3 this assumption has also prompted
concerns about a “runaway convention” that could drastically alter the
substance of the U.S. Constitution.4
This conventional wisdom is appealing in principle. After all,
constitution-makers have the authority to rewrite the constitution or
some of its provisions from scratch and pick from a rich menu of
options in global constitutional models.5 Indeed, in cases of
constitutional replacement, constitution-makers are specifically
charged with replacing the existing constitution with a new one,
presumably because the status quo suffers from significant
shortcomings. Without a high threshold for constitutional amendment
— such as that imposed by Article V — substantial, substantive
changes should follow.
Yet even a casual survey of constitutional replacement and
amendment processes around the globe reveals that many
counterintuitively produce relatively little change in constitutional
substance.6 That anecdotal observation is confirmed by the empirical
3 On some accounts, Michigan became in March 2014 the thirty-fourth state to
request a constitutional convention, which meets the two-thirds majority required by
Article V. Stephen Dinan, Balanced Budget Convention Gains Steam as Congressman Calls
for Official Evaluation, WASH. TIMES (Apr. 1, 2014), http://www.washingtontimes.
com/news/2014/apr/1/balanced-budget-convention-gains-steam-congressman. Although
many states, including Michigan, have sought a convention for the limited purpose of
proposing a balanced budget amendment, scholars disagree on whether states have the
authority to restrict the subject matter of constitutional conventions. Compare Walter E.
Dellinger, The Recurring Question of the “Limited” Constitutional Convention, 88 YALE L.J.
1623-24 (1979) (arguing that limited subject matter conventions are not authorized by
Article V), with Michael B. Rappaport, The Constitutionality of a Limited Convention: An
Originalist Analysis, 28 CONST. COMMENT. 53, 56 (2012) (arguing that states can call for
limited or unlimited conventions).
4 See, e.g., Gerald Gunther, The Convention Method of Amending the United States
Constitution, 14 GA. L. REV. 1, 4 (1979) (finding unpersuasive the claim that a
convention limited to a single narrow subject “won’t get out of hand”); Michael B.
Rappaport, Reforming Article V: The Problems Created by the National Convention
Amendment Method and How to Fix Them, 96 VA. L. REV. 1509, 1528-31 (2010) (“A
runaway convention is not merely a theoretical possibility . . . .”); see also Laurence H.
Tribe, Issues Raised by Requesting Congress to Call a Constitutional Convention to
Propose a Balanced Budget Amendment, 10 PAC. L.J. 627, 635 (1979) (contending that
“[h]owever democratic an Article V Convention might be in theory, such a
convention would inevitably pose enormous risks of constitutional dislocation”).
5 See Jon Elster, Constitutionalism in Eastern Europe: An Introduction, 58 U. CHI. L.
REV. 447, 468-71 (1991) [hereinafter Constitutionalism].
6 See, e.g., Arend Lijphart, Democratization and Constitutional Choices in CzechoSlovakia, Hungary and Poland: 1989–1991, 4 J. THEORETICAL POL. 207, 208 (1992)
(noting that changes to “fundamental constitutional structure” are rare in established
democracies); Adam M. Samaha, Dead Hand Arguments and Constitutional
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
903
evidence, which shows that constitutions exhibit high serial similarity
across time.7 On average, an 81% match exists in constitutions preand post-replacement, and a 97% match between a constitution preand post-amendment.8 Even in transitions from one regime type to
another or in constitution-making processes following exogenous
shocks such as a revolution or war — when one might expect tectonic
constitutional shifts9 — the resulting constitutional changes are often
relatively minor.10 The recent post-revolutionary constitution-making
process in Egypt, for example, produced a constitution that looks
remarkably similar to its predecessor.11 In the United States, as Alison
Interpretation, 108 COLUM. L. REV. 606, 627 (2008) (noting the persistence of
bicameralism in state legislatures in the United States even after Supreme Court
decisions weakened the justification for state senates).
7 See ZACHARY ELKINS ET AL., THE ENDURANCE OF NATIONAL CONSTITUTIONS 56-57
(2009); Tom Ginsburg & James Melton, Innovation in Constitutional Rights 6 (draft for
presentation at N.Y.U. Workshop on Law, Econ. & Pol., 2013) [hereinafter Innovation],
available at http://www.law.nyu.edu/sites/default/files/upload_documents/November%
2019%20Ginsburg%20Melton%20Innovation%20in%20Constitutional%20Rights%20.pdf
(“The set of institutions adopted in the very first constitution in a country’s history tends to
be very sticky . . . .”); see also Tom Ginsburg & James Melton, Does the Constitutional
Amendment Rule Matter at All? Amendment Cultures and the Challenges of Measuring
Amendment Difficulty 16 (Coase-Sandor Inst. for Law and Econ., Working Paper No. 682,
2014) [hereinafter Amendment Cultures], available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/
papers.cfm?abstract_id=2432520 (finding that “the vast majority of constitutional
amendments result in few [constitutional] changes”).
8 ELKINS ET AL., supra note 7, at 57. As Elkins et al. define those terms, an
amendment occurs when constitutional designers follow the amendment rule in the
existing constitution and a replacement occurs when the constitutional designers
disregard it. Id. at 55.
9 See, e.g., András Sajó, Preferred Generations: A Paradox of Restoration
Constitutions, in CONSTITUTIONALISM, IDENTITY, DIFFERENCE, AND LEGITIMACY:
THEORETICAL PERSPECTIVES 335, 341 (Michel Rosenfeld ed., 1994) (“After a major
revolution, there is neither a serious willingness nor any real possibility to return to
the status quo ante . . . .”).
10 See, e.g., Kathleen Thelen, How Institutions Evolve: Insights from Comparative
Historical Analysis, in COMPARATIVE HISTORICAL ANALYSIS IN THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 20910 (James Mahoney & Dietrich Rueschemeyer eds., 2003) [hereinafter How
Institutions Evolve] (“[F]requently, particular institutional arrangements are incredibly
resilient and resistant even in the face of huge historic breaks . . . .”); Thandika
Mkandawire, Crisis Management and the Making of “Choiceless Democracies,” in STATE,
CONFLICT, AND DEMOCRACY IN AFRICA 119, 125 (Richard Joseph ed., 1999)
(“Democratic states that are built on the ruins of authoritarian rule often retain some
of the previous state’s institutions, which linger on due to social inertia and structural
rigidities.”).
11 See, e.g., John Mukum Mbaku, Providing a Foundation for Wealth Creation and
Development in Africa: The Role of the Rule of Law, 38 BROOK. J. INT’L L. 959, 1042-45
(2013) (arguing that the recent revolutions in Egypt and Tunisia produced only
“regime changes” and did not significantly alter the governmental structure); Samer
904
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
LaCroix explains, the Constitution of the Confederate States (which
seceded from the Union) displayed surprising continuity with the U.S.
Constitution, including some of the most contested constitutional
provisions of the pre-war period.12
I call this phenomenon “constitutional stickiness.” Drawing on
rational-choice theory and behavioral law and economics, this Article
offers the first theoretical analysis of how the path of constitutional
history constrains future constitutional paths in specific and systemic
ways. Studies of path dependence have spanned numerous other
fields, such as technological standards,13 the economy,14 political
science,15 sociology,16 the common law,17 intellectual-property
Atallah, Egypt’s ‘New’ Constitution: Repeating Mistakes, AL JAZEERA (Jan. 14, 2014, 9:33 AM),
http://www.aljazeera.com/indepth/opinion/2014/01/egypt-new-constitution-repeatingmistakes-201411255328300488.html (arguing that the 2014 Egyptian Constitution
“repackage[s] the old” constitution).
12 Alison L. LaCroix, Continuity in Secession: The Case of the Confederate
Constitution, in NULLIFICATION AND SECESSION (Sanford Levinson ed., forthcoming Feb.
2015) (manuscript at 2), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2571358 (noting that
the Confederate Constitution “duplicated some of the most contested language of the
pre-war period, including several clauses that suggested a relatively powerful
central . . . level of government with a robustly powered Congress”).
13 See, e.g., Paul A. David, Clio and the Economics of QWERTY, 75 AM. ECON. REV.
332, 332-33 (1985) [hereinafter Clio]. But see S.J. Liebowitz & Stephen E. Margolis,
Path Dependence, Lock-in, and History, 11 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 205, 205-06 (1995)
(criticizing the application of path dependence to technological standards).
14 See, e.g., W. BRIAN ARTHUR, INCREASING RETURNS AND PATH DEPENDENCE IN THE
ECONOMY 33-34 (1994).
15 See, e.g., Scott E. Page, Path Dependence, 1 Q.J. POL. SCI. 87, 88 (2006); Paul
Pierson, Increasing Returns, Path Dependence, and the Study of Politics, 94 AM. POL. SCI.
REV. 251, 251 (2000) [hereinafter Increasing Returns]; Kathleen Thelen, Historical
Institutionalism in Comparative Politics, 2 ANN. REV. POL. SCI. 369, 384 (1999)
[hereinafter Historical Institutionalism].
16 See, e.g., James Mahoney, Path Dependence in Historical Sociology, 29 THEORY &
SOC’Y 507, 507-08 (2000).
17 See, e.g., Oona A. Hathaway, Path Dependence in the Law: The Course and Pattern
of Legal Change in a Common Law System, 86 IOWA L. REV. 601, 603 (2001); see also
Clayton Gillette, Lock-in Effects in Law and Norms, 78 B.U. L. REV. 813, 813-814
(1998); Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 457-58
(1897); Matthew Tokson, Judicial Resistance and Legal Change, 82 U. CHI. L. REV. 901,
902-04 (2015). In a famous passage, Holmes explained the path dependency of the
common law:
The life of the law has not been logic: it has been experience. The felt
necessities of the time, the prevalent moral and political theories, intuitions
of public policy, avowed or unconscious, even the prejudices which judges
share with their fellow-men, have had a good deal more to do than the
syllogism in determining the rules by which men should be governed.
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
905
institutions,18 corporate governance and contracting,19 adjudication,20
law and economics,21 and social norms,22 among others. Yet, despite
the salience of path dependence in constitutions, the academic
commentary has surprisingly failed to examine it in systematic and
theoretical terms.23 This Article fills that scholarly void.
The study of constitutional stickiness reveals important insights as
well as troubling conclusions for contemporary constitutional theory.
Constitutional provisions carry significant historical weight, and the
starting point often constrains future choices. Even where the initial
constitutional choice is suboptimal or anachronistic, that choice has a
profound effect on current behavior. As a result, a constitutional
provision that has gained an arbitrary historical advantage may be
OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES, JR., THE COMMON LAW 1 (1881).
18 See, e.g., Paul A. David, Intellectual Property Institutions and the Panda’s Thumb:
Patents, Copyrights, and Trade Secrets in Economic Theory and History, in GLOBAL
DIMENSIONS OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS IN SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY 19, 23, 28
(Mitchel B. Wallerstein et al. eds., 1993).
19 See, e.g., Lucian Arye Bebchuk & Mark J. Roe, A Theory of Path Dependence in
Corporate Ownership and Governance, 52 STAN. L. REV. 127, 129-30 (1999); Marcel
Kahan & Michael Klausner, Path Dependence in Corporate Contracting: Increasing
Returns, Herd Behavior, and Cognitive Biases, 74 WASH. U. L.Q. 347, 348 (1996);
Michael Klausner, Corporations, Corporate Law, and Networks of Contracts, 81 VA. L.
REV. 757, 762-64 (1995); Amir N. Licht, The Mother of All Path Dependencies: Toward
a Cross-Cultural Theory of Corporate Governance Systems, 26 DEL. J. CORP. L. 147, 14950 (2001).
20 See, e.g., Richard H. Fallon, Jr., The “Conservative” Paths of the Rehnquist Court’s
Federalism Decisions, 69 U. CHI. L. REV. 429, 434-36 (2002); Lawrence Friedman, Path
Dependence and the External Constraints on Independent State Constitutionalism, 115
PENN ST. L. REV. 783, 789 (2011); Michael J. Gerhardt, The Limited Path Dependency of
Precedent, 7 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 903, 905-06 (2005); Alain Marciano & Elias L. Khalil,
Optimization, Path Dependence and the Law: Can Judges Promote Efficiency?, 32 INT’L
REV. L. & ECON. 72, 73 (2012); Richard A. Posner, Past-Dependency, Pragmatism, and
Critique of History in Adjudication and Legal Scholarship, 67 U. CHI. L. REV. 573, 583-88
(2000).
21 See, e.g., Mark J. Roe, Chaos and Evolution in Law and Economics, 109 HARV. L.
REV. 641, 643-44 (1996).
22 See, e.g., Dan M. Kahan, Gentle Nudges v. Hard Shoves: Solving the Sticky Norms
Problem, 67 U. CHI. L. REV. 607, 607-08 (2000).
23 There are a few articles that mention in passing, with no systematic analysis, the
possibility of path dependence in constitutional structures. See, e.g., H. Kwasi
Prempeh, Presidential Power in Comparative Perspective: The Puzzling Persistence of
Imperial Presidency in Post-Authoritarian Africa, 35 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 761, 819-20
(2008) (noting that executive-legislative relations in contemporary Africa “reflect
strong elements of path dependency”); Samaha, supra note 6, at 625-27 (suggesting
that culture and path dependence can serve as sources of constitutional stability);
Lawrence B. Solum, Constitutional Possibilities, 83 IND. L.J. 307, 312-14 (2008) (citing
the difficulty of replacing constitutions as an example of path dependency).
906
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
retained in future design processes. An alternative constitutional
provision may not be adopted even when its benefits are obvious.
Conversely, the objective flaws of an existing constitutional provision
may not necessarily lead to its amendment or replacement.
Constitutional provisions may thus reflect arbitrary historical
selection, rather than a comprehensively rational assessment of the
costs and benefits presented by alternatives.24 Constitutions may end
up where they are because they happened to start there, not because
that starting point enjoys a distinct normative advantage.
Constitutional stickiness calls into question the prevailing
orthodoxy25 in the United States that Article V’s high threshold for
constitutional amendment is the primary culprit for lack of formal
constitutional change. As a result of the rational-choice and behavioral
mechanisms discussed below, constitutional provisions can — and
often do — stick even absent significant external restraints on
constitution-makers, such as high amendment thresholds. This analysis
suggests that any constitutional changes that either a lower amendment
threshold or a major constitutional convention may generate would be
much less significant than the legal scholarship assumes.
Constitutional stickiness can be especially problematic since
Constitution 1.0 of most countries is a beta version that can benefit
from a comprehensive makeover.26 Even if the designers of
Constitution 1.0 happen to stumble upon optimal provisions from the
start, over time, those optimal provisions may become anachronistic
and suboptimal as society evolves.27 As a result of constitutional
stickiness, however, these increasingly obsolete constitutional
provisions can become increasingly difficult to alter. After repeated
commitments to the existing constitutional path, “the road not taken,”
to quote the poem by Robert Frost, grows increasingly distant and
difficult to reach.28
Constitutional stickiness also amplifies the salience of earlier events
and dampens the significance of later ones.29 Counterintuitively,
relatively insignificant events in a country’s early constitutional history
can have an enormous impact, whereas more dramatic events that
See Gillette, supra note 17, at 817.
See Samaha, supra note 6.
26 ELKINS ET AL., supra note 7, at 15.
27 Id.
28 See Paul Pierson, Not Just What, but When: Timing and Sequence in Political
Processes, 14 STUD. AM. POL. DEV. 72, 75 (2000) [hereinafter Not Just What].
29 See id.
24
25
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
907
occur later may be much less consequential.30 It is therefore a mistake
to assume that large-scale events — such as the Arab Spring or a major
constitutional convention in the United States — will necessarily
produce large constitutional waves.
But constitutional stickiness is not necessarily undesirable from a
normative perspective. In some cases, there will be multiple
constitutional paths that produce an optimal result. That a
constitutional trajectory has been locked into one path does not
necessarily render it inefficient or suboptimal. In addition,
constitutional stickiness can generate significant societal benefits, such
as promoting constitutional stability, facilitating consensus building
during constitutional design, and impeding constitutional change
towards a less optimal configuration. But ultimately, as this Article
argues, constitutional stickiness can also become a straitjacket that
leads to the retention of inferior constitutional configurations where
the optimal outcome is their amendment or replacement.
In addition, constitutional stickiness is neither inevitable nor
irreversible. If it were, the United States would not have experienced
significant constitutional transformations as it transitioned from the
Articles of Confederation to the U.S. Constitution, nor would South
Africa as it adopted a democratic constitution after the end of
apartheid. Although constitutional stickiness is a strong force to
contend with, it is sometimes possible to reverse the initial
constitutional path, go back, and take an alternative path. Moreover,
even where the initial path cannot be completely reversed, changes
might still occur, but in a bounded fashion constrained by the path
initially forged. My primary aim in this Article is to explain stickiness
where it occurs, not to argue that constitutions inevitably exhibit that
phenomenon. I also consider the conditions under which
constitutions are likely to be less sticky and analyze the relative
stickiness of different constitutional alterations. This analysis sheds
light on the sources of potential disruptions that can foment largescale constitutional changes.31
This Article’s focus is on the stickiness of the provisions in the
written, formal constitution (i.e., the “large-c” constitution).32 To be
See id.
See id. at 78 (discussing large scale institutional development in general political
processes through “self-reinforcing processes” that have “distinct trajectories” because
of different historical events at their inception).
32 See Law, Constitutions, supra note 1, at 377 (contrasting the large-c constitution
to the small-c constitution, the latter of which refers to the “de facto, unwritten,
uncodified, or informal constitutions”).
30
31
908
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
sure, constitutional provisions can also be transformed informally
through interpretation by relevant judicial, political, and social actors,
without any formal changes to the constitutional text.33 For example,
the authorities of the federal government in the United States have
expanded significantly since the adoption of the U.S. Constitution
with little corresponding change to the constitutional text. Likewise,
the right to privacy, which is not expressly recognized in the
constitutional text, was adopted through interpretation by the U.S.
Supreme Court.34 These informal changes can obviate the need for
formal constitutional amendments, reducing the significance of textual
stickiness.
Despite the significance of informal alterations, the formal
constitution is undoubtedly important. Setting aside normative
debates about judicial philosophy and the appropriateness of
“updating” constitutions through interpretation, not all constitutional
provisions are amenable to updating through informal means.
Constitutional drafters may want to adopt provisions that require
specificity — for example, the establishment of an electoral system. In
a world where constitutions are becoming increasingly more detailed
and specific, it is not possible to informally update many provisions
absent brazen disregard for the constitutional language.35 Even with
respect to less specific constitutional provisions, the text provides the
starting point for interpretation and either constrains or influences the
available interpretive paths.36
The Article proceeds in three parts. Part I sets out a basic theory and
definition for constitutional stickiness. Part II turns to its causes and,
drawing on both rational-choice theory and behavioral law and
economics, explains the confluence of factors that can produce
33 See GABRIEL L. NEGRETTO, MAKING CONSTITUTIONS: PRESIDENTS, PARTIES, AND
INSTITUTIONAL CHOICE IN LATIN AMERICA 18 (2013) (“Adaptation . . . can take place by
the introduction of formal alterations, by old rules being interpreted in new ways, or
by the development of informal rules and practices that transform the meaning of
existing institutions.”).
34 See Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 485-86 (1965).
35 See Brannon P. Denning & John R. Vile, The Relevance of Constitutional
Amendments: A Response to David Strauss, 77 TUL. L. REV. 247, 275 (2002) (“If the
nation is to continue with a written constitution that contains the specificity of some
of the provisions of the existing document, there will be times when, absent flagrant
disregard for constitutional language, some amendments will be required as defects
become apparent, or changes are desired.”).
36 In fact, many of the rational-choice and behavioral mechanisms discussed in
this Article can also cause stickiness in judicial interpretations of the Constitution. See
also supra note 17 (summarizing the scholarship on path dependency in judicial
decisions).
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
909
constitutional stickiness. As to rational choice, where the costs of
transition to alternative constitutional configurations are high relative
to benefits, suboptimal constitutional configurations can endure
despite rational behavior by constitution-makers. I then apply
behavioral research to consider how cognitive limitations and biases
that lead individuals to act irrationally can contribute to constitutional
stickiness. Specifically, I analyze the status quo bias, anchoring bias,
availability heuristic, hedonic adaptation, and excessive veneration of
the constitution. Part III turns from the descriptive to the normative
and analyzes the normative implications of constitutional stickiness.
I.
A THEORY OF CONSTITUTIONAL STICKINESS
The layout of the modern computer keyboard is called “QWERTY”
by reference to the first six letters of its top line. This layout first
appeared in typewriters. Before the adoption of the QWERTY
arrangement, the typewriter suffered from a defect: the keys would
jam if the user typed too quickly.37 The QWERTY layout was designed
specifically to slow down typing speed so as to prevent mechanical key
blockage.38 In addition, for marketing purposes, the letters that
comprise the word “TYPEWRITER” were placed on the first line of the
keyboard to permit salespersons to efficiently demonstrate how the
machine operates by quickly typing the brand name — Typewriter.39
These purposes were obviated by later technological developments,
such as the ball-point typewriter and computer keyboards, which do
not cause mechanical key blockage.40 Yet, despite the apparent
availability of superior, more efficient, and more ergonomic layouts,
the QWERTY arrangement has “stuck.”41 The initial adoption of the
QWERTY keyboard prompted manufacturers to create software and
hardware compatible with that keyboard layout, which in turn
reinforced it.42 In addition, the increasing numbers of QWERTYSee David, Clio, supra note 13, at 333.
See Jürgen Beyer, The Same or Not the Same — On the Variety of Mechanisms of
Path Dependence, 5 INT’L J. SOC. SCI. 1, 2 (2010).
39 See David, Clio, supra note 13, at 333.
40 Beyer, supra note 38, at 2; Marciano & Khalil, supra note 20, at 76.
41 See Beyer, supra note 38, at 1-2; Posner, supra note 20, at 583; see also Marciano
& Khalil, supra note 20, at 76 (“[T]he most appealing and seemingly more efficient
alternative to QWERTY is the Dvorak Simplified Keyboard (DSK).”). But see S. J.
Liebowitz & Stephen E. Margolis, The Fable of the Keys, 33 J.L. & ECON. 1, 2-3 (1990)
[hereinafter Fable of Keys] (disputing the supposed inefficiency of the QWERTY
arrangement).
42 See David, Clio, supra note 13, at 335-36.
37
38
910
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
trained typists encouraged employers to buy QWERTY machines, and
the value of QWERTY training for employees increased with every
employer who did so.43
This is a classic illustration of path dependence. The concept was
first introduced by economic historians interested in trajectories of
technological development.44 Although the term has assumed multiple
meanings,45 in common parlance, path dependence refers to “an
outcome or decision [that] is shaped in specific and systematic ways
by the historical path leading [up] to it.”46 Path dependence, as I use
the term here, is more than a broad, vague claim that “history
matters.”47 I use the term in a narrower sense where each stage of
historical development constrains the next stage in the temporal
sequence and stimulates movement in the same direction.48 The past
narrows the choices available in the future and links decision making
through time.49
Consider an example from evolutionary biology.50 Evolution, like
constitutions, must contend with existing configurations. Although
evolutionary processes result in the “survival of the fittest,”51 the
See id.
See Thelen, How Institutions Evolve, supra note 10, at 219.
45 See Tom Ginsburg et al., Libertarian Paternalism, Path Dependence, and
Temporary Law, 81 U. CHI. L. REV. 291, 292-93 (2014).
46 Hathaway, supra note 17, at 604. As Margaret Levi explains:
43
44
Path dependence has to mean, if it is to mean anything, that once a country
or region has started down a track, the costs of reversal are very high. There
will be other choice points, but the entrenchments of certain institutional
arrangements obstruct an easy reversal of the initial choice. Perhaps the
better metaphor is a tree, rather than a path. From the same trunk, there are
many different branches and smaller branches. Although it is possible to
turn around or to clamber from one to the other — and essential if the
chosen branch dies — the branch on which a climber begins is the one she
tends to follow.
Margaret Levi, A Model, a Method, and a Map: Rational Choice in Comparative and
Historical Analysis, in COMPARATIVE POLITICS: RATIONALITY, CULTURE, AND STRUCTURE 28
(Mark Irving Lichbach ed., 1997).
47 Hathaway, supra note 17, at 604; Pierson, Increasing Returns, supra note 15, at
252 (distinguishing the broader and narrower conceptions of path dependence).
48 Pierson, Increasing Returns, supra note 15, at 252.
49 See DOUGLASS C. NORTH, INSTITUTIONS, INSTITUTIONAL CHANGE, AND ECONOMIC
PERFORMANCE 98-99 (James Alt & Douglass North eds., 1990).
50 In providing this example, I do not mean to suggest that evolution in biology
and law are identical phenomenon. The example is meant to illustrate the existence of
similar path-dependence mechanisms in diverse fields.
51 CHARLES DARWIN, THE ORIGIN OF SPECIES 94 (Charles W. Eliot ed., 1909).
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
911
species that do survive are far from perfect.52 The panda’s thumb is a
prominent example. The “thumb” functions as a thumb, but it is not a
thumb from an anatomical perspective.53 The panda’s thumb is an
enlarged bone that developed from the radial sesamoid, a small
component of the wrist.54 The design of the thumb is clumsy and, to
quote Stephen Gould, “wins no prize in an engineer’s derby.”55 It
cannot move like a thumb, but it presents a workable solution to a
recurring problem in the life of a panda: it allows the panda to strip
leaves from bamboo shoots, its primary food source.56 If one were
designing the panda from scratch, the optimal design of the thumb
might look very different. But the panda’s thumb as it exists today was
the best that evolution could do given the limited options provided to
it by the historical development of the panda’s anatomy.57
Similar arbitrary starting points can also constrain later choices in
constitutional design. Consider the Necessary & Proper Clause in
Article I, Section 8 of the U.S. Constitution. Significant as it is today,
the framers did not precisely know the Clause’s purpose.58 The
Constitutional Convention records do not state a precise justification
for the Clause.59 Nor do the records otherwise indicate that the Clause
resulted from a bitter compromise between the Federalists and the
Anti-Federalists.60 The inclusion of the Clause can be traced to Charles
Pinckney’s suggestion that Congress be authorized “to make all laws
for carrying the foregoing powers into execution.”61 But the
Committee on Detail did not explain its acceptance of Pinckney’s
suggestion nor its addendum of the phrase “which shall be necessary
and proper” into Pinckney’s proposal.62 The Constitutional
Convention appears to have perceived these additions as “mere
rhetorical flourish” and unworthy of debate, which suggests that the
Convention was unaware of the significance that the Clause would
See Hathaway, supra note 17, at 616.
See STEPHEN JAY GOULD, THE PANDA’S THUMB 22-23 (1980).
54 Id. at 22.
55 Id. at 24.
56 Id. at 21-24.
57 See id. at 22-24.
58 Mark Graber, Unnecessary and Unintelligible, in CONSTITUTIONAL STUPIDITIES,
CONSTITUTIONAL TRAGEDIES 43, 46 (William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Sanford Levinson eds.,
1998).
59 See id.
60 See id.
61 Id.
62 Id.
52
53
912
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
later assume.63 In Federalist No. 44, James Madison essentially admits
that the Clause was pointless, writing, “Had the Constitution been
silent on this head, there can be no doubt that all the particular
powers requisite as means of executing the general powers would have
resulted to the government, by unavoidable implication.”64 The
Necessary & Proper Clause might be considered the legal analogue of
the panda’s thumb, a once-insignificant part that evolved to serve a
momentous function.
Although the panda lacks the luxury of redesigning its thumb,
constitutions can be rewritten from scratch. Yet starting points in
constitutional design can, and often do, exert substantial historical
weight on subsequent choices. I call this phenomenon “constitutional
stickiness.” Without constitutional stickiness, each constitutional
choice would be made in isolation65 and previous constitutional
choices would have no effect on current options.66 With constitutional
stickiness, however, past constitutional configurations constrain later
decisions, displaying what mathematicians call a “sensitive
dependence on initial conditions.”67
Constitution-makers are humans, and humans make errors with
regularity. Some of these errors can even generate payoffs. A polity can
learn from the undesirable consequences of suboptimal constitutional
provisions and amend them. But stickiness may impede constitutional
change and freeze in place norms that will continue to generate
undesirable consequences. In other words, constitutional stickiness
can inhibit the changes that should result as constitution-makers learn
from their predecessors’ errors.
Although stickiness particularly resists the removal or amendment
of existing constitutional provisions, the addition of new provisions
can also generate stickiness because addition alters the status quo. For
example, the addition of a federal system of government changes what
was a non-federal state to a federal state. Likewise, the grant of
additional authorities to the executive branch can alter the existing
constitutional power balance between the legislature and the
See id.
THE FEDERALIST NO. 44 (James Madison), available at http://avalon.law.yale.edu/
18th_century/fed44.asp.
65 See Page, supra note 15, at 107.
66 See id.
67 See JON ELSTER, ULYSSES AND THE SIRENS: STUDIES IN RATIONALITY AND
IRRATIONALITY 47 (1979) (“[P]references are always relative to a past history of
choices.”); Liebowitz & Margolis, Fable of Keys, supra note 41, at 3; Page, supra note
15, at 91, 107.
63
64
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
913
executive. Stickiness can therefore resist all types of constitutional
alterations — whether by removal, amendment, or addition.
Constitutional stickiness is a variable phenomenon and can be
divided into three gradations in decreasing order of strength. First,
constitutional stickiness, at its sturdiest, can make it prohibitively
difficult to alter an initial constitutional choice. Second, even where
the initial constitutional choice can be altered, that choice can still
constrain the options available to future constitution-makers.68 In
other words, the initial choice can limit or narrow available future
paths. Constitutional change might continue, but bounded by the path
initially forged. Constitution-makers may take their bearings from the
existing constitutional norms, with the past provisions serving as a
baseline for departure and shaping their mental models.69
For example, despite the significant changes that the U.S.
Constitution introduced, it also retained many features from the
Articles of Confederation.70 The Interstate Compact Clause, the
Privileges and Immunities Clause, and the Extradition Clause, among
others, all had their origins in the Articles of Confederation.71
Likewise, the Constitution gave Congress all of the authorities it had
under the Articles of Confederation, and neither the Virginia Plan nor
the New Jersey Plan sought to remove them.72 In describing the
authorities of Congress, the Constitution also adopted the language
and structure of the Articles of Confederation.73
The post-World War II German Constitution, otherwise known as
the Bonn Constitution or the German Basic Law, provides another
illustration. Although its drafters agreed to reject all semblance of
68 As Carl Schorske explains in a different context, “when men produce
revolutionary changes, they screen themselves from their own frightening innovations
by dressing themselves in the cultural clothing of a past to be restored.” CARL E.
SCHORSKE, THINKING WITH HISTORY: EXPLORATIONS IN THE PASSAGE TO MODERNISM 88
(1998).
69 See Beyer, supra note 38, at 3.
70 Ernest J. Brown, Politics and the Constitution in the History of the United States,
67 HARV. L. REV. 1439, 1441 (1954) (reviewing WILLIAM WINSLOW CROSSKEY, POLITICS
AND THE CONSTITUTION IN THE HISTORY OF THE UNITED STATES (1953)) (noting that the
U.S. Constitution “borrowed and carried forward from the text of the Articles of
Confederation not only ideas and concepts but even, in many instances, the very
wording, verbatim or only slightly adapted, of phrases or whole clauses”).
71 Eric M. Freedman, Why Constitutional Lawyers and Historians Should Take a
Fresh Look at the Emergence of the Constitution from the Confederation Period: The Case
of the Drafting of the Articles of Confederation, 60 TENN. L. REV. 783, 793 n.35 (1993).
72 See Calvin H. Johnson, Homage to Clio: The Historical Continuity from the
Articles of Confederation into the Constitution, 20 CONST. COMMENT. 463, 473 (2004).
73 Id. at 474.
914
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
continuity with the Nazi past, they still looked to their previous
constitution for guidance and found elements to incorporate into the
new constitution.74 They abolished the provisions of the previous
constitution that appeared most to blame for the rise of fascism, but
retained other, more palatable portions.75
Another example appears in the successive iterations of the Egyptian
Constitution. The 1971 Constitution required half of the members in
the legislature to be “workers and farmers,” a remnant of the country’s
socialist past.76 Although the provision had become anachronistic
when the Arab Spring arrived, the 2012 Constitution retained it.77 The
drafters of the 2014 Constitution also retained the provision, though
they modified it by requiring the state to grant only “appropriate
representation” to workers and peasants in the first House of
Representatives to be elected after the Constitution was ratified.78
Third, constitutional stickiness might be completely overcome.
Stickiness significantly resists fundamental alterations, but does not
make them impossible.79 The drafters of the U.S. and Bonn
Constitutions, to return to those examples, retained some features of
their previous constitutions but also achieved significant
transformations. As I describe in the next Part, switching
constitutional paths is encumbered by a confluence of factors that may
— but need not — lead to the retention of existing constitutional
configurations.80
The analysis in the next Part also suggests that, all things being
equal, some constitutional alterations will generate more stickiness
than others. For example, the removal of existing provisions will tend
to be more difficult than the addition of new ones. With some
exceptions, alterations to structural provisions will also be more
burdensome than changes to negative-rights provisions. I discuss why
in the next Part.
74 Kim Lane Scheppele, A Constitution Between Past and Future, 49 WM. & MARY L.
REV. 1377, 1402 (2008).
75 Id. at 1402-04.
76 Nathan J. Brown & Kristen Stilt, A Haphazard Constitutional Compromise,
CARNEGIE ENDOWMENT FOR INT’L PEACE (Apr. 11, 2011), http://carnegieendowment.
org/2011/04/11/haphazard-constitutional-compromise; see also CONSTITUTION OF THE
ARAB REPUBLIC OF EGYPT art. 87, 11 Sept. 1971, as amended, 22 May 1980, 25 May
2005, 26 March 2007.
77 Brown & Stilt, supra note 76.
78 CONSTITUTION OF THE ARAB REPUBLIC OF EGYPT art. 243, 18 Jan. 2014.
79 See
Beyer, supra note 38, at 4 (discussing how “path-dependent
institutionalization” restricts but does not prevent change).
80 See id. at 3-4.
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
II.
915
THE CAUSES OF CONSTITUTIONAL STICKINESS
The previous Part provided a basic theory of constitutional
stickiness. This Part turns to its causes. Because many constitutionmaking processes are opaque, it is prohibitively difficult to
disaggregate the multiple factors that produce constitutional
stickiness. In addition, constitutional design is highly variable, so
different combinations of factors will be at work in different contexts.
As a result, in this Part, I necessarily paint with a somewhat broad
brush and discuss, drawing on rational-choice theory and behavioral
law and economics, how a confluence of variables can generate
constitutional stickiness. My goal here is not to create a behavioral
model of constitutional design but rather to identify the mechanisms
that contribute to constitutional stickiness.
Section A first analyzes the causes of stickiness, applying a costbenefit analysis and traditional rational-choice assumptions. Section B
then explains how behavioral biases and limitations may contribute to
the stickiness of constitutional provisions. Although traditional law
and economics often conflicts with behavioral law and economics, in
the Sections that follow, I will show how rational-choice mechanisms
and behavioral biases may complement and reinforce each other to
cause constitutional stickiness.
Before I proceed, two introductory points are in order. As I
discussed above, constitutional stickiness is variable. Different types of
constitutional alterations generate different costs and biases, which in
turn produce varying degrees of resistance to change. I consider the
salience of each type of cost and cognitive limitation with respect to
different constitutional alterations in detail below. In addition, in
discussing why constitutional provisions stick, I remain agnostic about
whether certain constitutional configurations are more optimal than
others. Optimality is a relative concept and a constitutional norm that
is optimal in one context may be suboptimal in the other. In fact, as I
discuss in Part III, constitution makers often confront more than one
constitutional path that can lead to an optimal equilibrium.
A. Rational Choice
I begin this Section with a theoretical premise based on rationalchoice theory: Constitution-makers are self-interested actors who seek
to minimize costs and risks and maximize personal payoff.81 At first
81 See, e.g., Robert J. Barro, The Control of Politicians: An Economic Model, 14 PUB.
CHOICE 19, 19 (1973) (assuming that a public officeholder acts “to advance his own
916
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
blush, constitutional stickiness might appear antithetical to rational
choice. After all, if there is a superior alternative available to the
constitutional status quo, one may assume that the rational course is
to adopt it. Nevertheless, where the costs of adopting even
demonstrably superior constitutional alternatives are high relative to
their benefits, the constitutional status quo can endure. Put
differently, if individuals are rational actors, they can retain
constitutional provisions that are suboptimal from a societal
perspective but that maximize their individual payoff.
A methodological limitation should also be noted at the outset.
Constitution-makers are not monolithic entities that follow a uniform
code of “rational” conduct. Depending on context, constitutional
design may bring together heterogeneous actors such as politicians,
judges, academics, religious leaders, and individual citizens, among
others, with divergent personal attributes and incentives. The
assumptions associated with rational-choice theory may not apply
equally to all of these individuals, some of whom, for example, may be
motivated in their decision making by considerations of the greater
public good even where it contradicts their self-interest.82 In addition,
constitutions are sometimes imposed by outsiders — as in the case of
Japan after World War II — who may have different sets of incentives
than domestic constitution-makers.83 Further, the costs and benefits
interests, and these interests do not coincide automatically with those of his
constituents”); Donald J. Boudreaux & A.C. Pritchard, Rewriting the Constitution: An
Economic Analysis of the Constitutional Amendment Process, 62 FORDHAM L. REV. 111,
113 (1993) (noting the assumption in public-choice analysis that “government actors
and interest groups rationally pursue their own self-interests in the same way that
private actors do in the marketplace”). This theoretical premise is also consistent with
the strategic-realist theory of law and constitution-making. Under that theory,
domestic institutions are the product of political bargains, and laws and constitutions
reflect the self-interest of political elites. See Ran Hirschl, The Strategic Foundations of
Constitutions, in SOCIAL AND POLITICAL FOUNDATIONS OF CONSTITUTIONS 157-58 (Denis J.
Galligan & Mila Versteeg eds., 2013). But see BRUCE ACKERMAN, THE FUTURE OF
LIBERAL REVOLUTION 48-54 (1992) (arguing that, during constitution-making periods,
the relevant actors are motivated primarily by long-term principles, rather than shortterm partisan interests).
82 Note, however, any facially impartial arguments by constitution-makers in favor
of the greater public good may be a strategic façade for a direct statement of their
personal interest. See Jon Elster, Arguing and Bargaining in Two Constituent Assemblies,
2 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 345, 421 (2000) (noting “the simple fact of political life that selfinterest is often dressed up in impartial garb”).
83 See Zachary Elkins et al., Baghdad, Tokyo, Kabul: Constitution Making in Occupied
States, 49 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1139, 1140-41 (2008) (discussing the inclusion of U.S.
institutions in Japan’s Constitution drafted largely by American authorities in 1946);
Benedikt Goderis & Mila Versteeg, The Transnational Origins of Constitutions: An
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
917
discussed below are distributed unequally across different actors who
will make different cost-benefit calculations.
Despite these limitations, rational choice can help identify some of
the causes of constitutional stickiness and the likely responses by
constitution-makers. I also recognize the objections levied against
rational-choice theory by scholars of behavioral law and economics.
Later in the Article, I relax these traditional rational-choice
assumptions and apply behavioral research to analyze why
constitutional stickiness may occur.
This Section proceeds as follows. In Subsection 1, I first consider the
incentives of constitution-makers. I examine how constitutional
stickiness may result where constitution-makers derive few benefits
from constitutional change. In Subsection 2, I analyze how the costs of
constitutional change can preserve the status quo even where
constitution-makers benefit from constitutional alterations.
1.
Benefits of Constitutional Change
Collective-action problems often cause stickiness in technological
standards. People will be reluctant to switch to a different standard
where they lack assurances that a sufficient number of others will also
do the same.84 For example, an individual American may be reluctant
to abandon the imperial system and adopt the metric system if she is
uncertain whether the rest of the community will also make the
switch. Change may be beneficial if made by the entire community,
but without a community-wide adoption, the optimal choice might be
to retain the imperial system. This problem results in part from the
absence of a centralized authority that can mandate simultaneous
change.85 For example, if legislation were adopted mandating or
incentivizing the use of the metric system, the imperial system may be
abandoned by a sufficient number of users. This, in turn, may alter the
status quo and create a new equilibrium.86
Empirical Analysis 5-6 (Apr. 2011) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://
www.law.uchicago.edu/files/files/Versteeg_April2011[2].pdf (describing the imposition
by outsiders of constitutions in over thirty former British colonies, as well as in Japan,
Micronesia, Germany, Afghanistan, and Iraq, among others).
84 Gillette, supra note 17, at 819-20.
85 See id. at 820.
86 In 1975, Congress enacted the Metric Conversation Act, which established the
U.S. Metric Board to “coordinate and plan the increasing use of the metric system in
the United States.” The United States and the Metric System: A Capsule History, NAT.
INST. OF STANDARDS & TECH., (May 2002), http://www.nist.gov/pml/wmd/metric/
upload/1136a.pdf. The American public largely ignored the Metric Board’s proposals,
918
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
Unlike technological standards, constitutions are designed by a
centralized authority, such as a constituent assembly, that can direct
simultaneous change and move the polity to a new constitutional
equilibrium (subject to a ratification process). The existence of this
central authority decreases the uncertainty partially responsible for
locking in suboptimal technological standards.87 After the constitution
drafted by the central authority is ratified, the entire polity will move
to a new constitutional equilibrium.
The ability to change, however, does not necessarily yield change.88
As Tom Ginsburg and James Melton observe in a forthcoming paper,89
constitution-makers are unlike commercial businesses that derive
significant benefits from innovation. Although path dependence has
been documented in consumer products as well,90 competitive
pressures may prompt the replacement of suboptimal products with
more optimal alternatives.91 For example, a sleeker, more
technologically capable cellular telephone, might attract more
customers than an older, inferior design. In a competitive market, the
iPhone 6 will outsell older cell phone models that resemble giant
walkie-talkies, the iPod will outsell the Walkman, and the XBOX 360
will outsell the Gameboy.
In contrast, even a casual survey of constitutions around the globe
reveals many ancient relics that, in a competitive market, would have
been replaced by superior alternatives. The Electoral College, which
has outlived its usefulness, and the twenty-dollar threshold for the
Seventh Amendment right to a jury trial are good examples from the
U.S. Constitution. For several reasons, unlike the market for consumer
products and services, the market for constitution-making is not
particularly competitive.92
As an initial matter, unlike commercial businesses that profit from
innovation, many constitution-makers lack a pecuniary interest in the
constitutional provisions they draft.93 For example, the adoption of an
establishment clause is unlikely to generate any economic benefits for
an individual constitution-maker. The value derived from the
which were not mandatory, and the Board was disbanded in 1982. Id.
87 See Gillette, supra note 17, at 824.
88 See id.
89 See generally Ginsburg & Melton, Innovation, supra note 7 (stating that
“constitution-makers have relatively few incentives to innovate”).
90 See David, Clio, supra note 13, at 332-36.
91 Pierson, Increasing Returns, supra note 15, at 260.
92 See Ginsburg & Melton, Innovation, supra note 7, at 3-4.
93 Id. at 3.
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
919
separation of religion from government will not, in most cases, be
pecuniary. To be sure, there are exceptions. McGuire and Ohsfeldt’s
quantitative work, following Charles Beard’s famous thesis,94 finds
support for the proposition that economic interests had some effect on
voting behavior both at the Philadelphia Constitutional Convention of
1787 and the state ratifying conventions.95 But these pecuniary
benefits, even where they exist, will often be less salient than the
pecuniary benefits present in the economic marketplace. Unlike
constitutional design, the economic marketplace provides individuals
with clear entitlements to income from particular property rights and
thus provides strong incentives to care about the long-term value of
their economic assets.96
In addition to pecuniary benefits, reputational benefits, which can
provide incentives to change in commercial products, are also likely to
be slim in constitutional design.97 Constitution-makers are often
anonymous bits of a large institution and, as a result, few obtain
meaningful recognition for innovative constitutional policies.98 Most
do not attain the ranks of James Madison or Alexander Hamilton99 and
are lost to obscure history books or dusty records of constitutional
conventions. In addition, many constitution-design processes are
opaque, making it difficult to credit a single constitution-maker or
even a group of constitution-makers for an innovative constitutional
norm.100 Where reputational benefits are important for constitution-
94 See CHARLES A. BEARD, AN ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF THE
THE UNITED STATES 73, 149-51 (1913).
CONSTITUTION
OF
95 See Robert A. McGuire & Robert L. Ohsfeldt, Economic Interests and the
American Constitution: A Quantitative Rehabilitation of Charles A. Beard, 44 J. ECON.
HIST. 509, 517 (1984).
96 Paul Pierson, The Limits of Design: Explaining Institutional Origins and Change,
13 GOVERNANCE 475, 481 (2000).
97 See Ginsburg & Melton, Innovation, supra note 7, at 3.
98 See id.
99 Id.
100 For example, it still remains open to serious debate which political group in
Egypt — the Muslim Brotherhood or the non-Islamists — was responsible for adding
a clause to the 2012 Egyptian Constitution that promised the consultation of the
Islamic institution al-Azhar on questions of Islamic Law. See CONSTITUTION OF THE
ARAB REPUBLIC OF EGYPT art. 4, 30 Nov. 2012; Clark Lombardi & Nathan J. Brown,
Islam in Egypt’s New Constitution, FOREIGN POLICY (Dec. 13, 2012), http://mideast.
foreignpolicy.com/posts/2012/12/13/islam_in_egypts_new_constitution (“Brotherhood
members of the Constituent Assembly insist that they were not behind this language
and indeed that it was non-Islamists who pushed al-Azhar into the document.”).
920
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
makers, the opacity of constitutional design may hamper any
individual motives for adopting innovative constitutional changes.101
Of course, constitution-makers will have the necessary incentives to
adopt constitutional changes where change generates tangible benefits
for them. For example, members of political parties with a popular
candidate for president may advocate popular elections for the
executive, regardless of the constitutional status quo.102 Conversely,
the other parties may attempt to limit executive powers and support
presidential elections by the parliament.103 During the 1919–21
constitution-making process in Poland, the conservative Parliament
created a weak executive in the Constitution, in part because it was
widely expected that the socialist Joseph Pilsudski would be elected
president.104 Likewise, members of small political parties may favor
proportional representation in elections, whereas large parties may
insist on a first-past-the-post system,105 regardless of the existing
constitutional configurations.106 Smaller states in a federal system may
advocate equal representation in the federal government, whereas the
larger states may oppose it, as was the case in the U.S. Constitutional
Convention.107
In constitutional-design processes following a fundamental shift in
political power, the newly empowered group may also derive benefits
from changing the constitutional configurations that benefited their
political rivals. For example, the post-apartheid South African
Constitution introduced significant changes as political power shifted
to the African National Congress during the country’s transition from
apartheid to a more pluralistic democracy.108 Constitution-makers that
cooperate with interest groups or constituents by constitutionalizing
their preferences can also receive rewards in the form of votes,
See Ginsburg & Melton, Innovation, supra note 7, at 4-5.
Elster, Constitutionalism, supra note 5, at 474-75.
103 Id.
104 Id. at 475.
105 First past the post is a winner-take-all system, where political office is awarded
to a single candidate that receives the most amount of votes. Mark Tushnet, 1937
Redux? Reflections on Constitutional Development and Political Structures, 14 U. PA. J.
CONST. L. 1103, 1104 (2012).
106 See Jon Elster, Forces and Mechanisms in the Constitution-Making Process, 45
DUKE L.J. 364, 378 (1995) [hereinafter Forces and Mechanisms].
107 Id. at 379.
108 See Richard J. Goldstone, The South African Bill of Rights, 32 TEX. INT’L L.J. 451,
451-52 (1997) (describing the major changes in the post-apartheid South African
Constitution, including the addition of a justiciable bill of rights and the
establishment of a new constitutional court to enforce those rights).
101
102
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
921
campaign contributions, and assistance with election efforts.109 All
things being equal, this interest will be more salient for public
officeholders who serve on the constitution-making body since they
will have a vested interest in election or reelection to the
government.110
Constitution-makers may also have incentives to adopt changes
where it is too costly to retain the status quo.111 For example, various
pathologies in state constitutions and the Articles of Confederation
spurred significant alterations in the U.S. Constitution.112 The
constitutional drafters for the French Fifth Republic moved to a semipresidential system to prevent the parliamentary chaos that led to the
collapse of the Fourth.113 And, as noted above, the drafters of the postWorld War II German Basic Law abandoned many features of the
Weimar Constitution blamed for permitting the rise of fascism.114
These past constitutional disasters can prompt constitution-makers to
abandon or amend the culpable constitutional provisions.
Importantly, however, constitution-makers can also receive rewards
for preventing constitutional change, which can contribute to
constitutional stickiness. Constitution-makers will have strong
incentives to retain constitutional provisions and institutions that
benefit them or their constituents. In the United States, recent
attempts to adopt constitutional amendments to abolish the Electoral
College or overturn the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in Citizens
United v. Federal Election Commission115 may have failed in part for this
reason. The proposed Equal Rights Amendment — which would have
protected gender equality in the U.S. Constitution — also failed in part
because some state lawmakers opposed the amendment to undermine
their opponents or to broker political deals that benefit them.116
See Gillette, supra note 17, at 830.
Cf. Christine Jolls et al., A Behavioral Approach to Law and Economics, in
BEHAVIORAL LAW AND ECONOMICS 13, 32 (Cass R. Sunstein ed., 2000) (contending that
legislators always have an interest in obtaining their own reelection, and that interest
will encourage them to respond to their constituents).
111 NEGRETTO, supra note 33, at 45 (“[U]nder certain conditions, the costs of
replacing or amending constitutions may be lower than the costs of leaving these
structures unreformed.”).
112 See Elster, Constitutionalism, supra note 5, at 477.
113 Id.
114 See id.
115 558 U.S. 310, 365 (2010).
116 See Donald T. Critchlow & Cynthia L. Stachecki, The Equal Rights Amendment
Reconsidered: Politics, Policy, and Social Mobilization in a Democracy, 20 J. POLICY HIST.
157, 161-62 (2008).
109
110
922
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
Likewise, in Poland, even though the upper house of the Parliament
had lost its raison d’être, it was retained in its post-communist
Constitution, primarily because the upper house had a veto on the
Constitution and would not vote to abolish itself.117 In addition, all
relevant groups order their conduct around existing constitutional
configurations and can also have a vested interest in retaining them.
That, in turn, can lead interest groups and constituents to pressure
constitution-makers to refrain from adopting alternative constitutional
provisions, even where they are more optimal than the status quo.
Global pressures, in the form of diplomatic, military, or financial
carrots or sticks, can also motivate constitution-makers to adopt
changes. For example, David Law has argued that globalization can
create an incentive for countries to compete in a race to the top in
constitutional innovation.118 Specifically, Law argues that constitutionmakers will face growing incentives to adopt economic and human
rights provisions to attract investors and elite workers.119 Likewise, the
adoption of judicial review can provide legal assurances to foreign
investors by protecting property rights and ensuring economic
stability, especially in regimes with some level of government
corruption.120 For that reason, the World Trade Organization
(“WTO”) requires judicial supervision in trade-related areas, the
establishment of which can convince a skeptical international
community to invest in a state.121 Constitution-makers can also adopt
standardized constitutional models in an effort to signal good
intentions and become a part of the international community.122
Although these global pressures can serve as a potential source of
constitutional changes, they may not necessarily result in the
predictable evolution of legal norms.123 Countries may instead turn to
117 See Andrzej Rapaczynski, Constitutional Politics in Poland: A Report on the
Constitutional Committee of the Polish Parliament, 58 U. CHI. L. REV. 595, 615 (1991).
118 David S. Law, Globalization and the Future of Constitutional Rights, 102 NW. U. L.
REV. 1277, 1282 (2008).
119 Id. But see Ginsburg & Melton, Innovation, supra note 7, at 4 (expressing
skepticism about the claim that globalization can prompt constitutional innovation
since “[i]n a world of territorially defined nation states, populations are not able to
‘vote with their feet[,]’ emigrating freely to jurisdictions offering attractive rights
packages”).
120 Ozan O. Varol, Stealth Authoritarianism, 100 IOWA L. REV. 1673, 1692 (2015).
121 Id.
122 Mila Versteeg, Unpopular Constitutionalism, 89 IND. L.J. 1133, 1183 (2014).
123 See Thelen, Historical Institutionalism, supra note 15, at 394.
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
923
existing domestic institutions to respond to global pressures,124 as
opposed to altering the constitutional status quo.125
But even where constitution-makers derive benefits from change,
these benefits may not be realized immediately and can take time to
accrue.126 Although some constitutional choices generate immediate
benefits, the consequences of many constitutional changes are often
revealed in the long term as the new provisions are interpreted and
enforced. Yet constitution-makers, especially politicians, will be more
interested in short-term results and thus heavily discount long-term
effects.127 Unlike a far-sighted commercial investor interested in the
financial benefits of a long-term investment, elected officials tend to be
more focused on the short term and the next election cycle.128 In
contrast to the long-term (and therefore less certain) benefits from
many instances of constitutional change, the costs associated with
constitutional changes are typically incurred in the short run.129 For
example, the establishment of a federalism system may require
immediate, costly, and burdensome measures, but its consequences
may not be revealed for a long period of time. Where the costs of
constitutional change are incurred immediately but their benefits may
be realized in the long term — and by someone else — constitutionmakers may have little incentive to invest in significant changes.130
In addition, in cases where constitution-makers participate in the
design process only temporarily, it can be difficult to lengthen their
time horizons by monitoring and sanctioning their behavior. Setting
aside cases where the elected legislature drafts the constitution,
members of a typical constituent assembly are elected or selected only
for the purpose of writing a constitution. Unlike agents in an
employment relationship — who might have strong incentives to
Id.
In addition, diffusion studies show that, despite the global informational flow
generated by globalization, innovations tend to spread primarily to countries in close
regional proximity. KURT WEYLAND, BOUNDED RATIONALITY AND POLICY DIFFUSION 19
(2007).
126 See Pierson, Increasing Returns, supra note 15, at 261 (contending that many
complicated political decisions “only play out in the long run”); cf. Boudreaux &
Pritchard, supra note 81, at 117 (contending that interest groups incur costs of
constitutional amendments up front, but do not see benefits right away).
127 See Pierson, Increasing Returns, supra note 15, at 261.
128 See id.
129 See id. (discussing how politicians frequently discount the long-term effects of
major political decisions because the nature of electoral politics encourages politicians
to focus more on short-term effects).
130 See id.
124
125
924
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
perform well over a long time horizon to retain employment or obtain
a promotion — the employment of these constitution-makers
automatically terminates at the end of the design process. The
consequences of their constitutional choices, however, may not be
revealed during the course of their employment or even within their
lifetime. Even where consequences become apparent earlier, it may be
difficult, as noted above, to assign individual responsibility to
constitution-makers for specific constitutional choices where the
drafting occurs in a complex, collective, and often opaque, bargaining
process. These factors, in turn, can make it difficult to monitor and
sanction constitution-makers and incentivize them to care about the
long-term consequences of their choices.131
The lack of monitoring and sanctioning mechanisms might also
suggest, however, that constitution-makers will be unencumbered to
pursue constitutional changes. After all, even if their constitutional
adventures produce undesirable consequences, they may escape
accountability. Yet the empirical data on stickiness contradicts this
conclusion.132 Although the absence of monitoring and sanctioning
mechanisms may prompt some constitution-makers to abandon the
handcuffs of the past, as a result of the costs and cognitive biases
discussed below, existing constitutional provisions still serve as
powerful anchors, producing varying degrees of stickiness.
And even where constitutional change generates immediate benefits,
alterations still may not occur. Where constitutional change benefits
one group, it may harm another, which may stymie its adoption by
holding out during the design process. Especially where the
constitutional alteration concerns a particularly contentious issue,
consensus may be prohibitively difficult to achieve because political
groups benefit from maintaining a distinct position on such issues,
decreasing the likelihood of defections by individual constitutionmakers.133 Even groups that are harmed by the constitutional status
quo may prefer not to oppose the existing arrangements if the costs of
attempting to renegotiate or altogether abandon the constitutional
order are higher than the costs of retaining the status quo.134 In the
United States, the Anti-Federalists, as Daryl Levinson explains, “rather
quickly came to accept a constitution they had vehemently opposed,
131 See Versteeg, supra note 122, at 1180 (noting that “the experts that write the
constitutions often do so in relative insulation from democratic pressures”).
132 See supra note 7 and accompanying text.
133 Cf. Rosalind Dixon & Tom Ginsburg, Deciding Not to Decide: Deferral in
Constitutional Design, 9 INT’L J. CONST. L. 636, 656 (2011).
134 Levinson, supra note 1, at 712.
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
925
in large part because of the calculation that even a bad law was better
than lawlessness.”135
2.
Costs of Constitutional Change
Simply put, changing existing constitutional provisions can be
expensive. All things beings equal, continuing down the same
constitutional path will cost less than changing it, at least in the short
term.136 What is more, unlike benefits of constitutional change —
which, as noted above, often accrue in the long term — constitutional
change can impose significant transition costs immediately.137 These
costs can be divided into three categories: costs of drafting, costs of
negotiation and ratification, and costs of implementation. I consider
each in turn below.
a.
Costs of Drafting
Adhering to the constitutional status quo often reduces the
workload of a constitution drafter. Especially where constitution
drafters must complete the design process in a relatively short period
of time, as they often do,138 retaining existing constitutional provisions
saves them precious resources by allowing them to build on the
foundations constructed by earlier designers. To be sure, some
constitutional provisions are relatively easy to adopt through imitation
of global or regional models, which lowers the drafting costs.139 For
example, constitution-makers can copy, with little immediate costs,
individual rights adopted in other influential constitutions or
international human rights treaties. Britain’s former colonies in Africa,
upon gaining independence, adopted the exact same boilerplate bills
of rights.140 These bills of rights, in turn, were modeled on the
European Convention on Human Rights and Fundamental
Id.
See Gerard Alexander, Institutions, Path Dependence, and Democratic Consolidation,
13 J. THEORETICAL POL. 249, 254 (2001); Hathaway, supra note 17, at 607.
137 See Alexander, supra note 136, at 254.
138 See infra text accompanying notes 256–64.
139 See Versteeg, supra note 122, at 1180 (suggesting that constitution-makers’
adoption of universal rights and ready-made constitutional model explains
constitutions’ disconnect from popular values); see also VICKI C. JACKSON,
CONSTITUTIONAL ENGAGEMENT IN A TRANSNATIONAL ERA 40 (2009) (“[M]any foreign
constitutions drafted since World War II rely on international human rights
instruments (or on other constitutions that relied on these instruments) as archetypes,
leading to parallel rights-protecting provisions.”).
140 Versteeg, supra note 122, at 1188.
135
136
926
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
Freedoms.141 Even with readily available constitutional models,
however, constitution-makers may retain existing provisions to avoid
formulation errors, ease drafting, and benefit from the available
judicial interpretations of existing provisions.142
There are also information costs associated with changing the status
quo at the drafting stage. Information costs refer to the costs of
obtaining information about the consequences of a constitutional
choice. Knowledge is often at a significant premium in constitutionmaking. Constitution-makers lack perfect, or even good, foresight,
especially since there is often a lack of sustained expertise in
constitution-drafting assemblies. Many constitution-makers have
never written a constitution before and will not do so again.143 What is
more, the consequences of a new and untested constitutional norm are
usually revealed only through the passage of time.144 A new
constitutional provision may prove to be unworkable in practice or
produce undesirable substantive outcomes. Despite sustained efforts
by scholars, the academic literature has produced little guidance on
the consequences of constitutional choices.145 The parties at the
bargaining table therefore often cannot predict which groups will be
advantaged and disadvantaged by particular configurations. The
drafters may also be uncertain about their own normative preferences
and the acceptability of those preferences to the polity.146 Faced with
such uncertainty, many constitution-makers, as Kim Lane Scheppele
explains, “turn to history to find models to follow, ideas to plunder,
and guides to steady themselves in their own troubled times.”147 If the
existing provision has been in place for some appreciable duration,
Id.
Cf. Kahan & Klausner, supra note 19, at 350 (discussing how using a standard,
commonly used contract term has many benefits, including “avoidance of formulation
errors, ease in drafting, [and] availability of judicial rulings on the validity and
interpretation of the term”).
143 Ginsburg & Melton, Innovation, supra note 7, at 4.
144 See Dixon & Ginsburg, supra note 133, at 644.
145 See Ginsburg & Melton, Innovation, supra note 7, at 5.
146 For example, Alexis de Tocqueville, who was elected to the Constituent
Assembly following the 1848 revolution in France, openly admits his sense of doubt:
“But what preyed most on my hopes and my nerves throughout the nine years spent
in public affairs, and what still remains the most frightful memory of that time, was
the constant doubt in which I was forced to live about what was best to do each day.”
Scheppele, supra note 74, at 1399.
147 Id. at 1398; see also Elster, Constitutionalism, supra note 5, at 476 (“In most
Eastern European countries today, there is a tendency to look to the precommunist
constitutions as sources of inspiration.”).
141
142
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
927
constitution-makers should have much better information about it
than a novel provision.
Uncertain judicial construction of novel constitutional provisions
can also increase information costs. In many constitutional systems,
the provisions drafted by the constitution-making body will be
interpreted by a separate institution, the judiciary.148 The judicial
construction of new constitutional provisions might introduce a great
deal of uncertainty into the constitution-design process and increase
information costs, which might dissuade the constitution-makers from
incurring the costs of deviating from the more certain constitutional
status quo.
Information costs might be reduced, at least to some extent, by
examining the implications of any untested constitutional provisions
adopted by other nations. The data provided by such comparative
examination, however, may be highly context dependent.
Constitutional norms appropriate for one context may be
inappropriate for another for a multitude of historical, cultural,
political, or legal reasons.149 If a constitutional norm has not been
implemented and tested in that particular country, that norm might
produce consequences difficult to forecast at the time of its adoption.
In addition, similar constitutional norms can be interpreted drastically
differently by the relevant judicial, political, and social actors in
different contexts.150
Although high information costs may stymie constitutional changes,
information costs will not always be high. Where the constitutional
designers are adequately equipped with satisfactory levels of
information and are reasonably confident about their normative
preferences and the acceptability of those preferences to the polity,
they can rationally adopt novel constitutional norms.151
148 See David S. Law & Mila Versteeg, The Evolution and Ideology of Global
Constitutionalism, 99 CALIF. L. REV. 1163, 1199 (2011) [hereinafter Global
Constitutionalism] (noting that by 2006, 87% of constitutions had either de jure or de
facto judicial review).
149 See Michel Rosenfeld & András Sajó, Introduction, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF
COMPARATIVE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 1, 14-15 (2012) (Michel Rosenfeld & András Sajó
eds., 2012) (noting that the nexus between identity and norms is an important factor
in the creation of constitutions).
150 See Vicki C. Jackson, Comparative Constitutional Law: Methodologies, in THE
OXFORD HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW, supra note 149, at 71
(noting that “[c]onstitutions are made and then interpreted in complex and distinctive
historical contexts”).
151 See ROBERT A. DAHL & CHARLES E. LINDBLOM, POLITICS, ECONOMICS, AND WELFARE
84 (1953) (arguing that a greater amount of knowledge and confidence in preferences
928
b.
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
Costs of Negotiation and Ratification
Negotiating and ratifying a constitution are often delicate exercises
in consensus building. The process ordinarily brings together
representatives from major facets of the polity to agree to a document
that will be acceptable to most citizens and respond to their needs.
These groups will often have competing visions for the document and
will disagree, and do so vehemently, over its content. The framers of
the U.S. Constitution, for example, passionately disagreed, among
other things, about the constitutional role of the federal government
vis-à-vis the states, the necessity of a Bill of Rights, and the question of
slavery. Recent efforts at constitution drafting across the Arab World
also revealed deep conflicts about state-religion relations, judicial
review, the constitutional rights of women and minorities, and the
freedom of speech and assembly. As constitutional passions increase,
so do decision costs, which refer to the costs associated with reaching
a constitutional decision.152 Although some passion is necessary to
jump start the constitutional-design process and provide the requisite
motivation to take action, excessive passion can make consensus
building, especially on controversial provisions, prohibitively
difficult.153
As a general matter, decision costs are likely to be higher for altering
entrenched provisions as opposed to retaining them.154 The
phenomenon of legislative inertia is well-documented in the
literature.155 Legislative inertia often freezes bad laws in place because,
as Neal Katyal puts it, “it is so much harder to get legislatures to do
something than it is to get them not to do something.”156 The
legislative inertia phenomenon is even more salient in constitutional
design. The mere labeling of a political issue as constitutional, as
opposed to legislative, raises the stakes involved because constitutions
are perceived as supreme and durable instruments. That, in turn,
enable larger and rational amounts of change).
152 Samaha, supra note 6, at 612.
153 Dixon & Ginsburg, supra note 133, at 642.
154 Levinson, supra note 1, at 708 (“Maintaining coordination around the existing,
and therefore focal, order will always be much easier than attempting to recoordinate
around some alternative constitutional regime.”).
155 Cf. Russell Korobkin, Behavioral Economics, Contract Formation, and Contract
Law, in BEHAVIORAL LAW AND ECONOMICS, supra note 110, at 123-25 (finding support
for the inertia hypothesis in the context of contract drafting).
156 Neal Katyal, Sunsetting Judicial Opinions, 79 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1237, 1240
(2004) (emphasis added).
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
929
makes it more difficult to adopt alterations.157 Even in nations where
the constitutional amendment rule sets a much lower threshold than
Article V of the U.S. Constitution, ratifying a constitutional
amendment is still costlier than legislation. For example, in New
Zealand, where the Constitution may be altered through an ordinary
legislative act, documents that enjoy constitutional status tend to be
more costly to amend or repeal.158 Likewise, in the United Kingdom,
where the Parliament is not legally constrained by a codified
constitutional text, a claim that legislation raises constitutional
concerns often has the effect of “raising the temperature of the
debate,”159 which can stymie its adoption.
In addition, constitutional design usually takes the form of a
bilateral monopoly.160 That is, the parties at the bargaining table have
no available alternative negotiating partners yet they also have an
incentive to hold out.161 In the world of constitutional design, which
entrenches one group’s preferences into a durable document, finishing
second does not count for much. When the stakes are high, the parties
to the constitutional bargain may be more reluctant to yield and more
likely to hold out for a better bargain.162 Holding out, in turn, prevents
constitutional change and results in retention of the status quo.
Two recent constitution design processes are illustrative. For
example, sharp divisions over the replacement of Turkey’s
parliamentary system with a presidential one was at least partially
responsible for derailing the country’s recent constitution-making
process.163 Although all major political parties agreed that the existing
157 See JANET L. HIEBERT, LIMITING RIGHTS: THE DILEMMA OF JUDICIAL REVIEW 3
(1996) (discussing the debate over adoption of the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms, “described as the single most important innovation of the constitutional
changes of 1982”); Stephen M. Griffin, The Nominee Is . . . Article V, in
CONSTITUTIONAL STUPIDITIES, CONSTITUTIONAL TRAGEDIES, supra note 58, at 51-52.
158 See JON ELSTER, ULYSSES UNBOUND: STUDIES IN RATIONALITY, PRECOMMITMENT, AND
CONSTRAINTS 101 & n.28 (2000); Julian N. Eule, Temporal Limits on the Legislative
Mandate: Entrenchment and Retroactivity, 1987 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 379, 394 n.61
(noting that, even under legislation-like amendment procedures, “there remain moral
and political restraints on the legislative alteration of constitutional doctrine”).
159 ERIC BARENDT, AN INTRODUCTION TO CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 30 (1998).
160 Ginsburg et al., supra note 45, at 337.
161 Id. at 337-38.
162 See Dixon & Ginsburg, supra note 133, at 639.
163 See Gulsen Solaker, Hopes Fade for a New Turkish Constitution, REUTERS (Nov. 18,
2013, 1:23 PM), http://www.reuters.com/article/2013/11/18/us-turkey-constitutionidUSBRE9AH0OV20131118 (reporting that the creation of a presidential system was
“[o]ne of the most contentious issues” facing the drafters); see also Ozan Varol,
Constitution-Making in Turkey: Towards a Presidential System?, I-CONNECT (Dec. 3, 2012),
930
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
constitution should be amended significantly, the ruling party’s
insistence on a presidential system — which many argued would spur
authoritarian governance in Turkey — brought the drafting process to
a halt.164 Likewise, disagreement during the 2010 constitution-making
process in Kenya on whether and how to regulate abortion was almost
sufficient to defeat the entire constitution-making process.165
Even where the constitution-making body is able to agree on the
constitutional alterations, there are also decision costs associated with
the ratification of a constitutional change.166 The often arduous process
for ratification, and the preferences of the body that will ratify the
constitutional changes, will constrain the constitution-making body’s
proposals.167 Ratification often requires a popular referendum, a
supermajority of the legislature, or both,168 which render constitutional
alterations significantly more costly than legislation.169 Ratification also
often involves costs associated with organizing elections, articulating
the proposals to the public, and mobilizing political and public
support.170 In Canada, for example, two sets of proposed constitutional
amendments — the 1987 Meech Lake Accord and the 1992
Charlottetown Accord — failed ratification. The Meech Lake Accord
failed to be ratified by its June 1990 deadline, despite initially high
levels of public approval, overwhelming support in the House of
Commons (242–16), and ratification within one year by eight of the ten
provinces.171 The Charlottetown Accord was defeated in a public
http://www.iconnectblog.com/2012/12/constitution-making-in-turkey-towards-apresidential-system (discussing how the proposal of replacing the parliamentary system in
Turkey with a presidential system without checks and balances caused controversy).
164 See Solaker, supra note 163.
165 Dixon & Ginsburg, supra note 133, at 659.
166 Decision costs may vary with the type of alteration at issue. For example, all
things being equal, a constitution that contains an expansive array of rights will tend to
enjoy more popular support in a referendum than a constitution that adopts relatively
few rights. See Versteeg, supra note 122, at 1168; see also Daniel Lansberg-Rodriguez,
Wiki-Constitutionalism, THE NEW REPUBLIC (May 25, 2012), http://www.
newrepublic.com/article/politics/75150/wiki-constitutionalism (“Latin American leaders
have discovered that, by packaging ever-longer lists of promises and rights alongside
greater executive functions, they can make a new constitution appealing enough to the
masses that they will vote for it in a referendum.”).
167 See Elster, Forces and Mechanisms, supra note 106, at 374.
168 See id. at 366-67.
169 See Boudreaux & Pritchard, supra note 81, at 117.
170 NEGRETTO, supra note 33, at 45.
171 Christopher P. Manfredi, Institutional Design and the Politics of Constitutional
Modification: Understanding Amendment Failure in the United States and Canada, 31
LAW & SOC’Y REV. 111, 123 (1997).
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
931
referendum even though it also initially enjoyed high levels of public
support and obtained the assent of important political elites.172
Decision costs will be much lower where a unified group dominates
the constitution-making process and has the ability to unilaterally
impose outcomes.173 With sufficient institutional authority and
popular support, a dominant group can adopt self-interested changes
to the constitutional status quo without the consensus of opposition
groups.174 This trend has been fairly common in Latin America.175 For
example, during the 1949 constitution-making process in Argentina,
the dominant party was able to alter the constitutional status quo to
increase its institutional influence and weaken the competitiveness of
the opposition.176 More recently, the Fidesz party in Hungary, armed
with the requisite two-thirds parliamentary supermajority for
constitutional amendments, implemented sweeping constitutional
changes intended to stack the constitutional deck in its favor and
undermine political opposition.
c.
Implementation Costs
Some constitutional norms also require large set-up or
implementation costs, which can stymie their adoption. Where set-up
costs for a new constitutional path are high, constitution-makers,
operating within budgetary strictures, will have a strong incentive to
remain on the same trajectory.177 All things being equal, the addition
of positive rights will cost more than the addition of negative rights,
assuming that the positive right is not a “sham” provision that will go
unenforced in practice.178 For example, the adoption of a positive right
to government-sponsored health care would require the government
to establish a comprehensive health-care system for all citizens, which,
if faithfully implemented, can be quite costly. In contrast, negative
rights tend to cost less than positive rights, providing more room for
change in this area.
Changes to structural provisions will often generate higher
implementation costs than the addition of individual-rights provisions.
Id. at 132.
See NEGRETTO, supra note 33, at 109.
174 Id. at 113.
175 Id.
176 Id. at 113-14.
177 See Pierson, Increasing Returns, supra note 15, at 254.
178 See generally David S. Law & Mila Versteeg, Sham Constitutions, 101 CALIF. L.
REV. 863, 916 (2013) (noting that positive rights can be costly to implement, harder
to uphold, and easier to violate).
172
173
932
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
To be sure, the line between structural provisions and individualrights provisions can be elusive since it is possible to interpret many
rights provisions in structural terms.179 For example, the adoption of
an individual right to a criminal defense attorney at the public’s
expense may require the establishment of supporting institutional
structures, such as a public defender’s office, which can also generate
significant costs. As a general matter, changes to structural provisions
— such as an electoral system or federalism — often require
corresponding changes to complementary institutions far more
extensive than rights provisions, making rights provisions less
expensive to add.180 For example, any alterations to the Electoral
College in the U.S. Constitution would require numerous changes to
party platforms, election commissions, and federal and state electoral
laws and regulations, which contributes to its stickiness. The
empirically demonstrated global trend towards “rights creep” —
which refers to the increasing number of constitutions that have
adopted an increasing number of individual rights — supports the
theory that the addition of individual-rights provisions will be less
costly than changes to structural provisions.181 But where individual
rights (such as a right to health care or criminal defense attorney)
require supporting structures, their addition can impose similarly high
implementation costs and generate stickiness.
Self-reinforcement can also increase implementation costs for
several reasons. In this context, self-reinforcement means that the
adoption of the original constitutional norm foments a set of forces
and complementary institutions that reinforce and strengthen the
stickiness of the original norm.182 As Kathleen Thelen explains, “once
179 See Ozan O. Varol, Structural Rights (Jan. 10, 2016) (working paper) (on file
with author).
180 As I explain below, however, the removal of existing individual-rights
provisions can be quite difficult as a result of the endowment effect.
181 See Zachary Elkins et al., Getting to Rights: Treaty Ratification, Constitutional
Convergence, and Human Rights Practice, 54 HARV. INT’L. L.J. 61, 63 (2013) (finding
that both the number of rights included in national constitutions and the number of
national constitutions with rights has increased steadily); Law & Versteeg, Global
Constitutionalism, supra note 148, at 1195 (documenting that “[o]ver the last six
decades . . . the number of rights in the average constitution has crept upward”); cf.
Rosalind Dixon, Constitutional Non-Redundancy (Jan. 10, 2016) (working paper) (on
file with author) (“The average length of national constitutions is now roughly 20,000
words; 50 years ago it was 16,000 words; and 100 years ago, it was 11,000 words.”).
182 See Page, supra note 15, at 88. Self-reinforcement follows a different logic from
reactive sequence arguments. As James Mahoney explains, “[w]hereas self-reinforcing
sequences are characterized by processes of reproduction that reinforce early events,
reactive sequences are marked by backlash processes that transform and perhaps
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
933
a particular path is chosen, actors adapt to the existing institutions in
ways that push them further along the trajectory.”183 Once initial steps
are taken down a particular path, the costs of switching to another,
previously plausible alternative increase and the path not taken
becomes progressively remote.184
Some constitutional arrangements can create what Douglass North
calls “the interdependent web of an institutional matrix” by requiring
complementary organizations and support networks.185 As the
concomitant matrix of laws, institutions, and expectations expands,
the alteration of the provision grows costlier over time. Consider a
polity that has created a constitutional guarantee of health care by the
government. To effectuate that guarantee, the polity will need to
construct government hospitals, hire doctors, nurses, and other
hospital staff, and purchase medical equipment. Over time, these
complementary bodies will develop specialized skills and expand
relationships with other institutions, which in turn reinforces their
own stability and generates increasing benefits and powerful
inducements to remain on the same constitutional path.186 A
constitutional right to government-sponsored health care may also
lead employers to not offer health-care benefits, which also reinforces
the initial choice of a government-sponsored health care system. As a
result, altering this constitutional right would generate significant
implementation costs by requiring the reconfiguration of settled
expectations and complementary institutions.
In addition, political parties, interest groups, and other political and
social actors often shape their agenda to fit various aspects of the
constitutional structure, such as federalism or the electoral system.187
The groups that have invested in and benefited from these structures
will be deeply committed to preserving and expanding them.188 For
example, the U.S. Constitution has prompted the development of a
large array of institutions, such as a central bank, ministries, interest
reverse early events.” Mahoney, supra note 16, at 526; see also Pierson, Not Just What,
supra note 28, at 85 (noting that in reactive sequences “action and reaction shift the
system in a new direction, but not one that reinforces the first move”).
183 Thelen, Historical Institutionalism, supra note 15, at 392 n.27.
184 Pierson, Increasing Returns, supra note 15, at 251; Thelen, Historical Institutionalism,
supra note 15, at 392 n.27.
185 NORTH, supra note 49, at 95.
186 See Pierson, Increasing Returns, supra note 15, at 255, 259.
187 Levinson, supra note 1, at 713.
188 Id. at 713.
934
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
groups, and legislative committees.189 These complementary
institutions have also established their own constituencies who might
resist any attempts to significantly modify the constitutional
arrangements that prompted their creation.190
In addition to supporting the interests of their intended
constituents, some constitutional institutions can also empower
subordinate groups or the initial losers of the constitutional bargain.191
Where divergent segments of society begin to obtain leverage from
existing constitutional configurations, these configurations will tend
to collect greater political support over time.192 For example, although
the Anti-Federalists vehemently resisted the adoption of the U.S.
Constitution, they eventually came to accept it in part because they
emerged victorious in the 1800 elections and began to benefit from the
constitutional scheme of government.193 Where the initial losers of the
constitutional bargain begin to benefit from it, however, selfreinforcement may not tell the whole story.194 Instead of wholly
embracing these initial constitutional configurations, as selfreinforcement would suggest, the losers may turn these institutions
into objects of ongoing political contestation, which, in turn, may
transform them over time.195 Increasing the size of the existing
constituency for a particular constitutional norm or configuration can
also foment conflict over its meaning and goals, introducing new
pressures for change.196 Although these modifications may not happen
through formal alterations of the constitutional text, informal,
subterranean changes may ensue through the re-interpretation of the
existing provisions.
Self-reinforcement can also result because of the learning that takes
place after a constitutional system has adopted a particular norm.
Brian Arthur refers to this phenomenon as “learning effects,” which
occur when knowledge “gained in the operation of complex systems
also leads to higher returns from continuing use.”197 The production
of a body of constitutional law on a particular provision can generate a
positive feedback loop, permit all relevant actors in the legal system to
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
ELKINS ET AL., supra note 7, at 20.
Id. at 20.
Cf. Thelen, How Institutions Evolve, supra note 10, at 216.
See Levinson, supra note 1, at 715.
Id. at 713.
Cf. Thelen, How Institutions Evolve, supra note 10, at 231.
See id.
See id.
ARTHUR, supra note 14, at 112-13.
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
935
carry out their tasks more effectively, and, up to a point, increase the
pay-off for additional movement in the same constitutional path.198
For some constitutional provisions, the learning effects may be trivial,
but for others, they can be quite substantial.199
Consider, for example, the Necessary and Proper Clause in the U.S.
Constitution. As discussed above, although the Clause was thought to
be an insignificant addition to the Constitution, its adoption has
prompted thousands of judicial opinions interpreting it. Judges have
accumulated experience over time after deciding cases that invoke the
Clause and passed that accumulated experience onto future
generations through reasoned judicial opinions.200 In addition,
constitutional lawyers have developed expertise in the Clause. Law
schools and law school textbooks have incorporated cases that educate
students on the Clause. Where these learning effects are salient for
constitution-makers — because, for example, they happen to be
judges, lawyers, or law professors — they can contribute to the selfreinforcement of the constitutional status quo.
In contrast, the introduction of novel constitutional provisions may
impose costs on the legal system. The amendment or replacement of
an existing constitutional provision would require the abandonment of
some or all of the existing legal expertise on that provision and require
the development of a new body of doctrine intended to effectuate it.201
That, in turn, would require judges, lawyers, and other relevant actors
to adapt to the new provision. Novel provisions may also increase
constitutional litigation since the applicable law is likely to be more
uncertain after the adoption of a new constitutional provision.202
Therefore, even if an alternative constitutional norm might appear
superior, the costs that would be imposed on the legal system from its
replacement may result in its retention.203
The costs on the legal system might be lowered, to some extent, by
constitutional borrowing. If another polity has adopted the same
constitutional norm, the legal system can borrow some portions of the
See Pierson, Not Just What, supra note 28, at 77.
See Kahan & Klausner, supra note 19, at 351.
200 See Hathaway, supra note 17, at 627-28.
201 Cf. RICHARD A. POSNER, HOW JUDGES THINK 145 (2008) (“Adherence to precedent
[limits the judicial workload] both directly, by reducing the amount of fresh analysis
that the judges have to perform, and indirectly, by reducing the number of appeals,
since the more certain the law, the lower the litigation rate.”).
202 Cf. id. at 144-45 (discussing how judicial precedent begets stability).
203 The costs imposed on the legal system will not be as salient for constitutionmakers who are not part of the relevant legal community affected by the constitutional
alterations.
198
199
936
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
already developed jurisprudence, reducing some of the costs
associated with generating a new body of constitutional doctrine. This
is a function of positive feedback, which means that a choice generates
positive externalities204 if that choice is also made by other people.205
In the constitutional context, borrowing can permit the use of another
legal system’s already developed jurisprudence on a constitutional
provision. Although some constitutional borrowing may occur, the
wholesale adoption of a foreign system’s jurisprudence would be
highly unlikely. And even where borrowing occurs, the legal system
will still incur some costs in adapting to the foreign jurisprudence and
modifying it to fit the domestic context. As a result, even with the
possibility of borrowing, transition costs will be much less for the
retention of the status quo than the adoption of a constitutional norm
that exists in another legal regime.
Constitutional decisions also create negative externalities206 with
respect to time and money.207 The more resources a constitutional
provision requires, the greater its impact will be on future
constitutional choices. For example, the creation of a constitutional
right to education might require a substantial amount of resources,
which can create negative externalities with respect to future
constitutional rights. If the polity has spent its available resources on
enforcing the constitutional right to education, it may lack adequate
resources for a constitutional right to health care.
***
In sum, where the costs of constitutional change exceed its expected
benefits, the constitutional status quo will stick. Adherence to the
constitutional past can therefore be rational even where superior
alternatives are available. Where the benefits of constitutional change
exceed the costs, however, one would expect alterations to occur
under rational choice theory. Yet, constitutional provisions may stick
even where the benefits of change outweigh its costs. I explain why in
the next Section.
204 A positive externality is a benefit awarded to a third party who did not pay for
it. See N. GREGORY MANKIW, PRINCIPLES OF ECONOMICS 199 (6th ed. 2012).
205 Page, supra note 15, at 88.
206 A negative externality is a cost imposed on a third party who did not choose to
incur that cost. See MANKIW, supra note 204, at 196.
207 See Page, supra note 15, at 111-12 (explaining that time and money create
negative externalities).
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
937
B. Behavioral Law and Economics
In the previous Section, I applied rational-choice theory to explain
how constitutional stickiness may occur despite rational behavior by
constitution-makers. Rational choice admittedly does not fully capture
the entire complexity of the incentives and motivations of
constitution-makers.208 It also neglects the suboptimal choices that
constitutional drafters make as a result of their cognitive limitations
and biases, which can result in inaccurate perceptions of the relevant
costs and benefits and deviations from comprehensive rationality.209
Simply put, human judgment is not perfect.210 Important research in
behavioral law and economics has challenged the “rational actor”
model of traditional economics in favor of a more nuanced view of
decision-making termed bounded rationality.211 This line of research
shows that cognitive biases and heuristics cause individuals to “form
confident opinions based on inadequate or badly biased information
and then hold to these opinions in the face of substantial
disconfirming data.”212 This does not mean that human behavior
randomly fluctuates around rational judgments.213 Rather, behavioral
research shows that human beings exhibit certain systematic biases,
which permits predictive analysis. In this Section, I examine several
systematic biases and cognitive limitations that may affect constitution
makers during the design process to produce constitutional stickiness:
status quo bias, anchoring bias, availability heuristic, hedonic
adaption, and excessive veneration of the constitution.
At this juncture, two methodological caveats are in order. First, the
biases and limitations I discuss here are neither inevitable nor
invariable. Nor will they uniformly affect the heterogeneous actors
208 See Richard H. Pildes & Elizabeth Anderson, Slinging Arrows at Democracy:
Social Choice Theory, Value Pluralism, and Democratic Politics, 90 COLUM. L. REV. 2121,
2143 (1990).
209 See WEYLAND, supra note 125, at 11; Russell B. Korobkin & Thomas S. Ulen,
Law and Behavioral Science: Removing the Rationality Assumption from Law and
Economics, 88 CALIF. L. REV. 1051, 1069 (2000); Cass Sunstein, Introduction, in
BEHAVIORAL LAW AND ECONOMICS, supra note 110, at 3 [hereinafter Introduction].
210 Norbert L. Kerr et al., Bias in Judgment: Comparing Individuals and Groups, 103
PSYCHOL. REV. 687, 687 (1996).
211 Christopher Buccafusco & Cristopher Jon Sprigman, The Creativity Effect, 78 U.
CHI. L. REV. 31, 33 (2011) (describing the erosion of the “rational actor” model “in
favor of a more nuanced and empirically robust view of human decision-making as
‘boundedly rational’”).
212 ROBERT BOYD & PETER J. RICHERSON, CULTURE AND THE EVOLUTIONARY PROCESS
168 (1985).
213 Kerr et al., supra note 210, at 687.
938
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
involved in constitutional design. In some settings and for some of the
relevant actors, some of these biases and limitations may have low or
zero salience. Where appropriate, I discuss when these biases and
limitations are likely to be of low significance and how they can affect
various public and private actors differently.
Second, there are also undeniable behavioral differences in individual
decision-making and group decision-making, such as a constitutionaldesign process. Despite sustained efforts, behavioral research has not
produced a simple, coherent answer to the question of whether group
judgments are more or less biased than individual judgments.214 As a
result, for the purposes of this Section, I generally assume that the
biases discussed here are equally effective in the context of group
decision-making and, where available, I discuss behavioral research that
documents these biases in group decision-making.
1.
Status Quo Bias
The status quo bias refers to a behavioral preference for the current
state of affairs.215 The bias results from a preference for inaction when
decision-makers are presented with multiple choices.216 In addition to
preferring the status quo, people tend to be biased against novel ideas
that generate uncertainty about their consequences.217 The bias can
affect both private actors and public decision-makers charged with
overhauling the constitution. As a result of the status quo bias, they
might be reluctant to alter pre-existing constitutional provisions and
214 Id. at 692-93 (surveying the empirical literature); id. at 714 (“At best, our
analyses offer an existence proof that collective rationality can sometimes be superior
to individual rationality, but they also suggest that over a large and plausible region of
relevant parameter space, group decision making actually exacerbates the biases
observed in individual decisions.”).
215 See William Samuelson & Richard Zeckhauser, Status Quo Bias in Decision
Making, 1 J. RISK & UNCERTAINTY 7, 8 (1988).
216 See Ilana Ritov & Jonathan Baron, Status Quo and Omission Biases, 5 J. RISK &
UNCERTAINTY 49, 49 (1992).
217 Jennifer S. Mueller et al., The Bias Against Creativity: Why People Desire but
Reject Creative Ideas, 23 PSYCHOL. SCI. 13, 13 (2012) (“Uncertainty is an aversive state
that people feel a strong motivation to diminish and avoid.” (citations omitted)); see
also Eric F. Rietzschel et al., The Selection of Creative Ideas After Individual Idea
Generation: Choosing Between Creativity and Impact, 101 BRIT. J. PSYCHOL. 47, 65
(2010) (“[P]eople appear to have a strong preference for ideas they believe can and
should be adopted, and . . . seem to believe that this is incompatible with the selection
of original ideas.”).
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
939
demand a great deal to justify departures even where the optimal
outcome is their amendment or replacement.218
From a behavioral perspective, existing constitutional provisions
enjoy a first-mover advantage. The prevailing orthodoxies in the
existing constitutional order occupy an “almost monopolistic
position.”219 The repeated application of existing constitutional
provisions elevates them to a higher position.220 Competing
constitutional norms may thus be perceived as presumptively
undesirable.221 Take, for example, the choice between a presidential
system and a parliamentary system. The U.S. Constitution establishes
a presidential system, which has remained in place since its adoption.
As a result, the presidential system has come to occupy a unique
position in the minds of both private actors and public decisionmakers, similar to first-movers in consumer products such as CocaCola, Kleenex, and Xerox.222 The market for regime types in the
United States is thus skewed towards the dominant product
(presidentialism), which, in turn, reinforces the position of
presidentialism, making it difficult to dislodge and replace with an
alternative form of government.223 Even where a search for a novel
constitutional idea is prompted by inadequacies in the existing
constitutional order, the status quo bias will skew the search in favor
of provisions compatible with existing constitutional norms.224
218 See Samuelson & Zeckhauser, supra note 215, at 8 (“Faced with new options,
decision makers often stick with the status quo alternative, for example, to follow
customary company policy, to elect an incumbent to still another term in office, to
purchase the same product brands, or to stay in the same job.”); Sunstein,
Introduction, supra note 209, at 4; Russell Korobkin, The Status Quo Bias and Contract
Default Rules, 83 CORNELL L. REV. 608, 675 (1998) (“Because individuals tend to prefer
the status quo to alternative states, they are likely to prefer the default [contract] term,
whatever it may be, to other options, all other things being equal.”).
219 Eoin Carolan, Diffusion of Ideas and Comparative Law 11 (2012) (unpublished
manuscript), available at http://law.mc.edu/files/7113/3397/7796/Carolan.pdf; see also
Levinson, supra note 1, at 708 (“[J]ust by virtue of its status quo position, the existing
constitutional order will enjoy a special salience that conceivably preferable
alternatives will lack.”).
220 See Carolan, supra note 219.
221 See id.
222 Marvin B. Lieberman & David B. Montgomery, First-Mover Advantages, 9
STRATEGIC MGMT. J. 41, 46 (1988).
223 See Carolan, supra note 219, at 12.
224 See id. at 15. Alison LaCroix invokes a similar rationale in describing why the
Confederate Constitution showed strong continuity with the U.S. Constitution: “The
words of the [U.S.] Constitution, its ways of framing questions, and indeed its very
structure dominated the American consciousness to such a degree that even
secessionists could not escape it.” LaCroix, supra note 12, at 1.
940
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
But where the dominant product suffers from a negative association,
the status quo bias may be less salient since public and private actors
are less likely to ascribe normative desirability to existing
constitutional provisions. The drafters of the post-World War II
German Basic Law were able to discard those constitutional provisions
that appeared most to blame for the rise of fascism in large part
because of the evils associated with the dominant constitutional
products of the Nazi past. For example, the vote of no confidence in
the pre-World War II Weimar Constitution was constrained
significantly in the post-World War II Basic Law since the instability
caused by the frequent use of the vote was blamed, at least in part, for
the rise of the Nazi Party.225 Likewise, the new Egyptian Constitution
limits states of emergency to three months and requires the consent of
the Parliament,226 which was most likely motivated by the abuse of the
executive emergency power under the Mubarak regime. In other cases,
however, the strength of the status quo bias may dominate any
negative associations with the constitutional status quo. Although the
drafters of the Egyptian Constitution limited executive declaration of
emergency, they nevertheless retained the presidential system, which
many commentators at least partially blamed for the country’s
authoritarian past.
One can hypothesize seven factors that affect the salience of the
status quo bias in constitutional design. First, all things being equal,
the salience of the bias may increase with the lifetime of the
constitutional provision at issue. For example, a constitutional
provision that has been in place for twenty-five years may be more
likely to stick than a provision adopted two years prior to the
constitution-drafting moment. Under this hypothesis, the status quo
bias will tend to be particularly strong with respect to the U.S.
Constitution, which has not been replaced since it went into force in
1791. The status quo bias may also be more salient for provisions that
have been retained in successive constitutional-design processes.
These provisions may be perceived as having withstood the test of
time despite repeated opportunities to amend or discard them and
therefore may be more difficult to displace.
Second, the perceived degree of departure of the proposed
constitutional norm from the status quo is also relevant to the salience
of the status quo bias. If the novel constitutional provision is
225 See GRUNDGESETZ FÜR DIE BUNDESREPUBLIK DEUTSCHLAND [GRUNDGESETZ] [GG]
[BASIC LAW], May 23, 1949, BGBl. arts. 67–68 (Ger.).
226 CONSTITUTION OF THE ARAB REPUBLIC OF EGYPT art. 154, 18 Jan. 2014.
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
941
compatible with the existing constitutional order, that can bolster the
adaptability of the new provision and decrease the salience of the
status quo bias. Conversely, if the new provision represents a marked
departure from the constitutional status quo, that can increase the
salience of the status quo bias and hamper attempts to adopt the new,
markedly different provision.227
Third, behavioral studies show that the strength of the status quo
bias increases with the number of available alternatives.228 Put
differently, the more alternatives that people confront, the more likely
they are to retain the status quo. Constitution-makers often have
numerous choices available to them in designing constitutions. Even
seemingly limited alternatives such as the tripartite choice between
presidentialism, parliamentarism, and semi-presidentialism conceal
many complexities. In a recent paper, Cheibub, Elkins, and Ginsburg
demonstrate that these traditional categories show great internal
heterogeneity across time and space, presenting constitution-makers
with numerous options in allocating powers between the legislature
and the executive.229 Confronted with copious alternatives,
constitution-makers might opt for the status quo.
Fourth, the endowment effect and loss aversion may also increase
the salience of the status quo bias.230 The endowment effect refers to
the empirical finding that people tend to overvalue things (including
rights and privileges) that they already own.231 Loss aversion, a
corollary to the endowment effect, refers to the human tendency to
fear losses more than gains.232 Under the endowment effect and loss
aversion, those who benefit from the constitutional status quo will
value those benefits more highly than those who would benefit from
227 See EVERETT M. ROGERS, DIFFUSION OF INNOVATIONS 243 (5th ed. 2003); Carolan,
supra note 219, at 15 (“[A]n idea which involves little or no innovation is more likely
to be adopted than one that genuinely involves a departure from previous practice.”).
228 See Daniel Kahneman et al., Anomalies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion, and
Status Quo Bias, 5 J. ECON. PERSP. 193, 198 (1991).
229 Jose Antonio Cheibub et al., Beyond Presidentialism and Parliamentarism, 44
BRIT. J. POL. SCI. 515, 516-17 (2014).
230 See Kahneman et al., supra note 228, at 194 (illustrating the relationship
between the endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias).
231 See Buccafusco & Sprigman, supra note 211, at 31; Steffen Huck et al., Learning
to Like What You Have — Explaining the Endowment Effect, 115 ECON. J. 689, 689
(2005); Kahneman et al., supra note 228, at 194.
232 Ginsburg et al., supra note 45, at 321; Kahneman et al., supra note 228, at 19798 (“One implication of loss aversion is that individuals have a strong tendency to
remain at the status quo, because the disadvantages of leaving it loom larger than
advantages.”).
942
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
constitutional change.233 As a result, even where a constitutional
alteration would produce a net social benefit, one might expect those
who benefit from the constitutional status quo to invest more in
retaining it than those who would profit from constitutional change.234
This theory is supported by the empirical evidence, which shows that
individual rights, once introduced, tend to maintain their popularity
over time.235
All things being equal, under the endowment effect and loss
aversion, the removal of existing provisions will be more difficult than
the addition of new provisions. That is because where new provisions
do not result in a loss of existing constitutional rights or privileges,
their addition does not implicate the endowment effect or loss
aversion. The result changes, however, where the design process
resembles a zero-sum game. In other words, if the gain of one group
from the addition of a constitutional provision results in a loss to
another group, then the endowment effect and loss aversion can
support the entrenchment of the status quo. For example, several
commentators have argued that the provision of constitutional rights
to crime victims would undermine the constitutional rights of criminal
defendants.236 Likewise, in several states in the United States, the
recent proposed addition of a state constitutional right to engage in
farming and ranching practices generated significant resistance from
animal rights groups.237
See Gillette, supra note 17, at 827.
See id. at 827-28.
235 Elkins et al., supra note 181, at 72 (finding only four rights with a negative or
flat trajectory over time: “the right to bear arms, the right to citizenship of those born
in the state’s jurisdiction (jus soli citizenship), intellectual property rights, and the
right to a jury trial”).
236 See, e.g., David E. Aaronson, New Rights and Remedies: The Federal Crime
Victims’ Rights Act of 2004, 28 PACE L. REV. 623, 672 (2008) (“From the defendant’s
perspective, providing crime victims a significant participatory role in criminal
proceedings echoes back to injustices of the colonial period when alleged crime
victims played a dominant role in criminal prosecutions through a system of private
prosecution.”).
237 Julie Bosman, Missouri Weighs Unusual Addition to Its Constitution: Right to Farm,
N.Y. TIMES (Aug. 2, 2014), http://www.nytimes.com/2014/08/03/us/missouri-considersadding-right-to-farm-to-state-constitution.html; Ryan Sabalow, Indiana Senate Kills ‘Right to
Farm’ Amendment, INDY STAR (Feb. 24, 2015), http://www.indystar.com/story/news/
2015/02/24/indiana-senate-kills-right-farm-amendment/23944627. Several other design
features have also been described as zero-sum games in the literature. See, e.g., A.C.
Pritchard & Todd J. Zywicki, Constitutions and Spontaneous Orders: A Response to Professor
McGinnis, 77 N.C. L. REV. 537, 538-39 (1999) (stating that the structural constraints of the
U.S. Constitution were intended to “pit government actors in a zero-sum game”); Barbara
Bennett Woodhouse, The Constitutionalization of Children’s Rights: Incorporating Emerging
233
234
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
943
Although the endowment effect and loss aversion bolster the
salience of the status quo bias, over the lifetime of a constitution, the
initial coalition that lobbied for the adoption of a constitutional norm
may dissipate.238 Depending on the time that has elapsed, the coalition
for whose benefit the provision was adopted might no longer exist and
efforts to recreate it might fail.239 In such cases, the endowment effect
and loss aversion may not result in constitutional stickiness. The
Prohibitionists are a good example of a group that coalesced only
temporarily.240 Although they successfully lobbied for the adoption of
the Eighteenth Amendment, which established Prohibition, they were
unable to stop its repeal thirteen years later due in part to the
temporary nature of their alliance.241
Fifth, the composition of the constitution-drafting body can also
affect the salience of the status quo bias. Constitution-makers are often
selected because they played a historical role in the event that gave rise
to the new constitution-making process.242 In the United States, for
example, many framers had served in the Continental Army or as
officials for the Confederation or the Continental Congress.243 These
constitution-makers, selected for their historical roles, can be more
prone to turn to history than to the future when making constitutional
choices.244 Likewise, judges, who have spent their careers interpreting
and applying the status quo, may be more affected by the status quo
bias during constitutional design than law professors who are rarely
awarded tenure for publishing articles arguing that the status quo is
“just fine as it currently exists.”245
Demographic factors can also be relevant.246 For example, ordinary
citizens serving on a constitution-making body may be less loyal to the
status quo than career politicians.247 Likewise, age can also play a role.
Several behavioral studies have found a significant positive age effect
Human Rights into Constitutional Doctrine, 2 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 1, 8 (1999) (arguing that the
constitutionalization of parental rights erected barriers to constitutionalization of children’s
rights).
238 See Gillette, supra note 17, at 828.
239 See id.
240 Boudreaux & Pritchard, supra note 81, at 119.
241 See id.
242 Scheppele, supra note 74, at 1379.
243 Id. at 1407 n.9.
244 Id. at 1379.
245 Gillette, supra note 17, at 824.
246 A comprehensive behavioral assessment of these factors is beyond the scope of
this Article.
247 See Ginsburg & Melton, Innovation, supra note 7, at 12.
944
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
on loss aversion — older participants were more loss averse and
therefore potentially more susceptible to the status quo bias.248
Younger constitution-makers may be less wedded to the status quo
since their innovative powers are at their peak and they have much
less to cite from their own history to address the challenges of the
present.249 Behavioral research reaches mixed conclusions on the
effects of education and income on the status quo bias. Although some
studies found that loss aversion decreases with higher levels of
education,250 others did not find a significant effect.251 The results are
also mixed with respect to the effects of high income.252
Sixth, time pressure can also increase the salience of the status quo
bias. Although no study has examined the effects of time pressure on
constitution drafting, behavioral research generally shows that severe
time pressure negatively affects individuals’ ability to generate novel
solutions to problems and reduces the quality of decisions. It also
encourages “closing of the mind”: individuals discount available
alternatives, fail to thoroughly process relevant information, and
refrain from critical probing.253 Further, individuals are more likely to
rely on heuristics when making decisions under severe time pressure,
which also inhibits change.254 The creativity-inhibiting effects of time
pressure have also been documented in group-negotiation settings.255
248 Katrine Hjorth & Mogens Fosgerau, Loss Aversion and Individual Characteristics,
49 ENVIRON. & RESOURCE ECON. 573, 586-87 (2011); Simon Gächter et al.,, IndividualLevel Loss Aversion in Riskless and Risky Choices 17 (CeDEx Discussion Paper Series,
Working Paper No. 2010-20, 2010), available at http://hdl.handle.net/10419/49656;
Eric J. Johnson et al.,, Exploring the Nature of Loss Aversion 19 (IZA Discussion Papers,
Working Paper No. 2015, 2006), available at http://hdl.handle.net/10419/33324. But
see Ye Li et al., Complementary Cognitive Capabilities, Economic Decision Making, and
Aging, 28 PSYCHOL. & AGING 595, 607 (2013) (finding that older participants were
slightly less loss averse than younger participants, although this difference was not
statistically significant).
249 See Posner, supra note 20, at 592.
250 Hjorth & Fosgerau, supra note 248, at 588; Gächter et al., supra note 248, at 17-18.
251 Johnson et al., supra note 248, at 19.
252 Id. at 17-19 (finding that individuals with higher incomes were more loss
averse). But see Hjorth & Fosgerau, supra note 248, at 586-87 (finding no significant
effect of income on loss aversion).
253 Martin G. Kocher & Matthias Sutter, Time Is Money — Time Pressure, Incentives,
and the Quality of Decision-Making, 61 J. ECON. BEHAV. & ORG. 375, 378 (2006); see
also Anne Edland & Ola Svenson, Judgment and Decision Making Under Time Pressure:
Studies and Findings, in TIME PRESSURE AND STRESS IN HUMAN JUDGMENT AND DECISION
MAKING 27, 30 (Ola Svenson & A. John Maule eds., 1993).
254 Carsten K.W. De Dreu, Time Pressure and Closing of the Mind in Negotiation, 91
ORGANIZATIONAL BEHAV. & HUM. DECISION PROCESSES 280, 282 (2003). See generally
Amos Tversky & Daniel Kahneman, Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases,
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
945
Constitution-making is a frustratingly long process that often must
be condensed, due to internal and external pressures, to a short time
frame.256 Ginsburg, Elkins, and Melton observe that, of the eighty-six
constitutions for which data is available, 50% were drafted in six
months or less and over 25% were drafted in less than four months.257
The polity’s perceived need to reach a swift constitutional resolution
of immediate concerns may lead to the imposition of internal time
restraints on constitutional drafters. Political agreements may stipulate
a time limit for the constitutional-design process in order to establish a
basic framework for governance, as was the case in Kenya, Nepal,258
and most recently, Egypt.259
In addition to domestic pressures, foreign occupiers, anxious to
terminate their involvement in a constitutional reconstruction, may
also impose external time restraints on the design process.260 For
example, international actors, including the United States and the
United Nations, required the constitution-design process in
Afghanistan to be completed within two years — a formidable
challenge in a society emerging from twenty-five years of civil war.261
Similarly, United Nations officials required the constitutional drafting
185 SCI. 1124 (1974) (discussing the systematic errors that result from reliance on
heuristics).
255 See De Dreu, supra note 254, at 291; Janice R. Kelly & Joseph E. McGrath,
Effects of Time Limits and Task Types on Task Performance and Interaction of FourPerson Groups, 49 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 395, 404-05 (1985) (finding that
time constraints reduce the quality of performance, including originality and
creativity, in a group essay writing task); Kocher & Sutter, supra note 253, at 388
(“Our results suggest that time pressure has . . . a negative effect on the quality of
decision-making in an interactive context as well.”); Rick van der Kleij et al., Effects of
Time Pressure and Communication Environment on Team Processes and Outcomes in
Dyadic Planning, 67 INT’L J. HUM.-COMPUTER STUD. 411, 420-21 (2009) (finding that
time pressure reduced the quality of teams’ written planning); Michael A. West,
Sparkling Fountains or Stagnant Ponds: An Integrative Model of Creativity and Innovation
Implementation in Work Groups, 51 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 355, 365, 379 (2002)
(reviewing the literature that finds time restraints to impede creative problem solving
in group settings).
256 Dixon & Ginsburg, supra note 133, at 642-43.
257 Ginsburg & Melton, Innovation, supra note 7, at 5.
258 See Dixon & Ginsburg, supra note 133, at 643.
259 See sources cited infra note 264 and accompanying text.
260 See Dixon & Ginsburg, supra note 133, at 642-43 (discussing how the United
States pushed for a swiftly completed constitution in Iraq).
261 J. Alexander Thier, Big Tent, Small Tent: The Making of a Constitution in
Afghanistan, in FRAMING THE STATE IN TIMES OF TRANSITION: CASE STUDIES IN
CONSTITUTION MAKING 535, 558 (Laurel Miller ed., 2010).
946
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
in East Timor to take place within ninety days.262 The United States
occupation in Iraq likewise forced a rushed constitution-design
process, which was completed in less than six months through a
process that excluded Sunni factions.263
These temporal restraints on the constitutional-design process often
do not permit sufficient deliberation over the adoption of novel
constitutional norms and impede constitutional change. Several
commentators have argued, for example, that the domestic time
constraints imposed on the 2012 constitution-drafting process in
Egypt contributed to the retention of many suboptimal provisions
from the previous constitution.264 In addition, temporal restraints —
which, as noted above, impede information gathering and processing
— can increase even further the high information costs associated
with new and untested constitutional provisions.265
Seventh, many constitution-drafting moments occur following a
revolution or transition from one regime type to another, where the
status quo bias is likely to be particularly salient. Revolutions tend to
produce outbreaks of nostalgia.266 In the political and social turmoil
that a regime transition produces, many wistfully harken back to the
socially and economically stable days of the former regime.267 Change
may be costly, difficult to comprehend, and questionable.268 As
262 Louis Aucoin & Michele Brandt, East Timor’s Constitutional Passage to
Independence, in FRAMING THE STATE IN TIMES OF TRANSITION: CASE STUDIES IN
CONSTITUTION MAKING, supra note 261, at 254.
263 See Vicki C. Jackson, What’s in a Name? Reflections on Timing, Naming, and
Constitution-Making, 49 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1249, 1273 & n.61, 1275 (2008).
264 See, e.g., Saïd Amir Arjomand, The Islam and Democracy Debate After 2011, 20
CONSTELLATIONS 297, 308 (2013) (arguing that the abrupt closure of the inconclusive
constitutional debate resulted in the retention of many provisions from the old
constitution); Yasmine El Rashidi, Egypt: The Rule of the Brotherhood, N.Y. REV. BOOKS (Feb.
7, 2013), http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2013/feb/07/egypt-rule-brotherhood
(discussing the drafting process of the Egyptian Constitution and noting that the head of
the Constitutional Assembly actively pushed for the swift completion of the document).
265 See supra Part II.A.2.a (discussing information costs).
266 SVETLANA BOYM, THE FUTURE OF NOSTALGIA xvi (2002).
267 GUILLERMO O’DONNELL & PHILIPPE C. SCHMITTER, TRANSITIONS FROM
AUTHORITARIAN RULE: TENTATIVE CONCLUSIONS ABOUT UNCERTAIN DEMOCRACIES 4
(1986) (“Compared to periods of ‘order’ which characterize the high point of
authoritarian rule, the uncertainty and indirection implied in movements away from
such a state create the impression of ‘disorder.’ This impression some compare
nostalgically with the past, while overlooking or regretting the transition’s revival of
precisely those qualities which the previous regime has suppressed: creativity, hope,
self-expression, solidarity, and freedom.”).
268 Levinson, supra note 1, at 691, 708; Adam Przeworski, Democracy as a
Contingent Outcome of Conflicts, in CONSTITUTIONALISM AND DEMOCRACY 59, 75 (Jon
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
947
“revolution fatigue” sweeps over the nation,269 inherited institutional
structures may appear normatively superior to theoretical
alternatives.270 For example, according to an August 2013 nationwide
survey of Egyptians by the Pew Research Center’s Global Attitudes
Project, 80% of Egyptians believed that the country was worse off
following Mubarak’s ouster.271 A constitution drafted in this
environment may be prone to entrenching existing provisions as
opposed to adopting novel alternatives. The relative insignificance of
the changes to the Egyptian and Tunisian Constitutions following
their revolutions in 2011 largely support that theory. Thus, even in the
aftermath of a revolution — when one might expect tectonic
constitutional shifts — the status quo bias, along with the other biases
to which I now turn, can stymie constitutional changes.
2.
Anchoring Bias
The anchoring bias, which is related to the status quo bias, refers to
a tendency to insufficiently adjust one’s judgments up or down from
an initial starting value.272 Under the anchoring bias, initial reference
points influence, or “anchor,” judgments.273 After these anchors are
established, final judgments are influenced in the direction of the
anchor.274 For example, when asked to estimate various numerical
values — such as the percentage of African countries in the United
Nations or the likelihood of nuclear war — people give significantly
higher or lower estimates if they are first asked whether the value is
greater or less than some arbitrary high or low value, compared to
people who are asked to estimate the value without a starting point.275
Elster & Rune Slagstad eds., 1988) (“[T]he authoritarian power apparatus may resist
the transition to democracy even when the forces within the civil society upon which
the regime rests are willing to try their chances under democratic conditions.”).
269 See Michael Slackman, When a Punch Line Is No Longer a Lifeline for Egyptians,
N.Y. TIMES (Apr. 5, 2011), http://www.nytimes.com/2011/04/06/world/middleeast/
06cairo.html.
270 See Levinson, supra note 1, at 691.
271 Mohamed Younis, Egyptians See Life Worse Now than Before Mubarak’s Fall,
GALLUP (Aug. 16, 2013), http://www.gallup.com/poll/164015/egyptians-life-worsemubarak-fall.aspx.
272 S. Plous, Thinking the Unthinkable: The Effects of Anchoring on Likelihood
Estimates of Nuclear War, 19 J. APPLIED SOC. PSYCHOL. 67, 67 (1989); Tversky &
Kahneman, supra note 254, at 1128.
273 Tversky & Kahneman, supra note 254, at 1128-30.
274 See Plous, supra note 272, at 67-68; Tversky & Kahneman, supra note 254, at
1128.
275 Tversky & Kahneman, supra note 254, at 1128.
948
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
The anchoring bias is robust even when people are aware of the bias,
they are paid to be accurate in their estimations, they are familiar with
the subject matter, the anchors are outrageously high or low, or an
expert claims that the given anchor point is not an accurate
estimate.276 The anchoring bias has also been documented in the legal
context. For example, several scholars have observed that sentencing
guidelines and prosecutorial sentencing demands serve as influential
anchors in judicial decision-making.277 Studies have also found that
the anchoring bias affects federal magistrate judges278 and bankruptcy
judges.279
The anchoring bias can also affect constitution-makers. In the
context of constitution-making, the existing constitutional provisions
serve as the “anchors” or the initial reference points.280 As a result of
the anchoring bias, constitution-makers may be reluctant to alter
existing constitutional provisions. And even where changes occur, the
anchoring bias can skew them in the direction of the anchor — i.e.,
the constitutional status quo.
3.
Availability Heuristic
As Jon Elster aptly observes, “the task of constitution-making
generally emerges in conditions that are likely to work against good
constitution-making.”281 With some exceptions,282 constitutions are
ordinarily written in the aftermath of a war, revolution, economic or
social crisis, or other exceptional circumstances.283 The constitutional
reconstructions following the 2011 Arab Spring exemplify the
turbulent conditions under which constitution-makers often must
See Plous, supra note 272, at 68, 83-85.
Birte Englich & Thomas Mussweiler, Sentencing Under Uncertainty: Anchoring
Effects in the Courtroom, 31 J. APPLIED SOC. PSYCHOL. 1535, 1538 (2001); Nancy
Gertner, What Yogi Berra Teaches About Post-Booker Sentencing, 115 YALE L.J. POCKET
PART 137, 138 (2006).
278 See Chris Guthrie et al., Inside the Judicial Mind, 86 CORNELL L. REV. 777, 778
(2001).
279 Jeffrey J. Rachlinski et al., Inside the Bankruptcy Judge’s Mind, 86 B.U. L. REV.
1227, 1236 (2006).
280 Cf. Kahan & Klasuner, supra note 19, at 363 (arguing that standard contract
terms may anchor contracting parties).
281 Elster, Forces and Mechanisms, supra note 106, at 394.
282 Id. at 370 (noting the exceptional case of Sweden’s 1974 constitution drafting,
which occurred in unexceptional circumstances).
283 Id. at 370-71.
276
277
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
949
operate. These turbulent circumstances create ripe conditions for the
availability heuristic to stymie constitutional change.
Under the availability heuristic, people tend to overestimate the
seriousness of a risk if the risk is readily available or easy to recall.284
The observed frequency and the salience of the risk affect the strength
of the heuristic.285 First, if a particular hazard has occurred recently,
people will tend to believe that it has a higher probability of
reoccurring in the future.286 For example, the number of people who
purchase earthquake insurance increases in the immediate aftermath
of a major earthquake.287 Conversely, residents of flood plains are less
likely to purchase flood insurance if floods have not occurred in recent
memory.288 Second, if the hazard at issue is particularly salient, the
availability bias will be more pronounced.289 The salience of the
hazard, in turn, increases if it is particularly dramatic or is widely
publicized.290
The availability heuristic can contribute to constitutional stickiness
in post-conflict constitutional design. Affected by the availability
heuristic, constitution-makers and the public alike may overestimate
and overreact to newly recognized threats generated by the chaotic
post-conflict moment, however unlikely their recurrence may be.291 A
constitution drafted in these tumultuous moments (or in their
immediate aftermath) may therefore focus on the short-term societal
needs of achieving economic and social stability at the expense of
other constitutional goals.292 The drafters may shun experimentation
with novel constitutional norms and retain preexisting provisions
believing that established institutions and norms will better promote
stability. In contrast, the adoption of untested constitutional
provisions may destabilize the polity because they have the potential
to generate unknown and perhaps undesirable consequences.
284 Sunstein, Introduction, supra note 209, at 5; Cass R. Sunstein, What’s Available?
Social Influences and Behavioral Economics, 97 NW. U. L. REV. 1295, 1300-01 (2003)
[hereinafter What’s Available]; see also Tversky & Kahneman, supra note 254, at 1127.
285 Jolls et al., supra note 110, at 37.
286 Id.
287 Sunstein, What’s Available, supra note 284, at 1301; Jolls et al., supra note 110,
at 37 (“The same phenomenon may occur in other areas of regulatory law; an example
here is the move toward heavy regulation of school bus safety in the wake of media
coverage of school bus accidents in which children were killed.”).
288 Sunstein, What’s Available, supra note 284, at 1301.
289 Jolls et al., supra note 110, at 37.
290 See id.
291 Ozan O. Varol, Temporary Constitutions, 102 CALIF. L. REV. 409, 428-29 (2014).
292 Id.
950
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
Exasperated by social and economic turmoil, the public also may
lobby primarily for constitutional provisions that promote stability,
which, in turn, may lead constitution-makers to misperceive the
benefits of altering the status quo.
Consider, for example, the preventive-detention provisions in the
Indian Constitution. The Constitution was drafted after the end of
British colonialism and during a conflict-laden period in Indian
history marked by an armed rebellion in Telangana and violence with
Pakistan over contested territories.293 Although fully aware of the use
of preventive detention as a tool for tyranny by the British, the
Constituent Assembly rejected due process protections for detainees
and allowed the use of preventive detention.294 The Constitution
permitted extrajudicial detention without charges to prevent future
crime as a legitimate law enforcement tool.295 Preventive detention
was perceived as a necessary evil to safeguard the new state at its
conflict-laden transitional moment, but its preservation in a durable
constitution allowed later government officials to use the provision to
suppress opposition, long after the security threats that necessitated
preventive detention dissipated.296
All things being equal, establishing consensus on existing provisions
will be less costly than securing agreement on novel provisions.
Significant changes may unnecessarily prolong the design process,
which may detract attention from other pressing societal concerns. At
times, conflict over novel constitutional provisions can derail the
entire constitution-design enterprise,297 which may further destabilize
the polity. To avoid these consequences and achieve a swift resolution
of contentious constitutional questions, the drafters may retain the
constitutional status quo.
In some cases, however, the availability heuristic can prompt the
adoption of novel provisions. First, achieving stability may require
constitutional alterations. For example, even where a preexisting
constitution does not contain any emergency powers, the post-conflict
constitution may authorize government officials to declare
emergencies in times of national crisis to ensure stability.298 Second, as
293 Hallie Ludsin, Peacemaking and Constitution-Drafting: A Dysfunctional Marriage,
33 U. PA. J. INT’L L. 239, 259 (2011).
294 See INDIA CONST. art. 22, § 3(b); Ludsin, supra note 293, at 259.
295 See INDIA CONST. art. 22, § 3(b); Ludsin, supra note 293, at 259.
296 Ludsin, supra note 293, at 260.
297 See supra notes 166–72 and accompanying text.
298 Cf. Gabriel L. Negretto & Jose Antonio Aguilar Rivera, Liberalism and
Emergency Powers in Latin America: Reflections on Carl Schmitt and the Theory of
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
951
a result of the availability heuristic, a constitution-maker may
selectively recall only those events that are particularly vivid for her.
For example, if a constitution-maker has experienced discrimination
in the past, she might lobby for novel constitutional policies to
eradicate discrimination. Although the availability heuristic can result
in individual motivations to lobby for novel constitutional policies, it
is less likely to prompt the entire constitution-making body to adopt
changes, where the most recent and salient societal concerns are the
achievement of social and economic stability. Finally, the availability
heuristic can also prompt constitutional change where constitutional
designers emulate “available” global constitutional models or
constitutional provisions adopted in temporal and geographical
proximity.299
4.
Hedonic Adaptation
Hedonic adaptation, which refers to the human capacity to adapt to
unpleasant circumstances,300 may also contribute to constitutional
stickiness. Behavioral research shows that, despite dramatic events
such as a disability, human beings have a tendency to recover fairly
quickly and recapture their pre-event level of happiness.301
Although hedonic adaptation is neither inevitable nor invariable
across different individuals,302 where it occurs, it may contribute to
constitutional stickiness. Due to hedonic adaptation, relevant public
and private actors may adapt to the constitutional status quo, leading
to a belief, correct or incorrect, that the existing constitutional
Constitutional Dictatorship, 21 CARDOZO L. REV. 1797, 1803-04 (2000) (noting that
emergency provisions were adopted in many Latin American constitutions, including
in Chile, Argentina, Mexico, and Colombia, in the mid-nineteenth century after a lack
of legal mechanisms to address emergencies led to problems of constitutional
legitimacy and gave authoritarian leaders opportunities to seize power).
299 See WEYLAND, supra note 125, at 6.
300 See John Bronsteen et al., Hedonic Adaptation and the Settlement of Civil Lawsuits,
108 COLUM. L. REV. 1516, 1527-28 (2008) [hereinafter Hedonic Adaptation]; Shane
Frederick & George Loewenstein, Hedonic Adaptation, in WELL-BEING: THE FOUNDATIONS
OF HEDONIC PSYCHOLOGY 302, 311-20 (Daniel Kahneman et al. eds., 1999).
301 Bronsteen et al., Hedonic Adaptation, supra note 300, at 1517; Daniel Kahneman
& Richard H. Thaler, Anomalies: Utility Maximization and Experienced Utility, 20 J.
ECON. PERSP. 221, 230 (2006) (“[A]s the new state loses its novelty it ceases to be the
exclusive focus of attention, and other aspects of life again evoke their varying
hedonic responses.”).
302 Bronsteen et al., Hedonic Adaptation, supra note 300, at 1530-31; see Ed Diener
et al., Beyond the Hedonic Treadmill: Revising the Adaptation Theory of Well-Being, 61
AM. PSYCHOLOGIST 305, 311-13 (2006) (finding that individuals vary significantly in
their rate of adaptation).
952
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
arrangements are functioning reasonably well. As a result, they may
retain the status quo even where the adoption of alternatives would
lead to a more optimal outcome.303 This is not to suggest, however,
that an equilibrium that results from hedonic adaptation is necessarily
suboptimal. Hedonic adaptation, even to suboptimal constitutional
configurations, can increase societal happiness and welfare.304
5.
Excessive Veneration of the Constitution
Another behavioral factor associated with constitutional stickiness is
the societal veneration of the constitution. Constitutional veneration
varies across both time and space,305 producing dramatically divergent
prevailing cultural attitudes about resistance to constitutional change.
In some nations, such as the United States, large portions of the public
treat their constitutions as a sacred text306 that should remain
untouched except in matters of profound significance.307 In other
nations, constitutions are of little normative significance and are
frequently amended and discarded.308
Although stickiness can be correlated with the societal veneration of
the constitution, I do not suggest a one-directional causal relationship
where constitutional veneration causes stickiness. The causation arrow
may point in the opposite direction as well because the society may be
more likely to revere a constitution that has remained relatively
unchanged. In other words, it is equally plausible that causation is
bidirectional, in that the stickiness of the constitution and the societal
reverence for it mutually bolster each other.
Although a detailed examination of the cultural factors that produce
societal veneration of the constitution are beyond the scope of this
Article, I will include some preliminary thoughts here. The veneration of
the constitution may stem from a veneration of the generation that
drafted it. As Thomas Jefferson wrote in 1816, future generations “ascribe
to the men of the preceding age a wisdom more than human, and
See Ginsburg et al., supra note 45, at 324.
Id. at 324 n.69.
305 See Ginsburg & Melton, Amendment Cultures, supra note 7, at 13-14.
306 See Thomas C. Grey, The Constitution as Scripture, 37 STAN. L. REV. 1, 17 (1984)
(noting the “well-attested phenomenon of American constitution-worship”); Sanford
Levinson, “The Constitution” in American Civil Religion, 1979 SUP. CT. REV. 123, 12324 (1979).
307 Ginsburg & Melton, Amendment Cultures, supra note 7, at 13.
308 Id.
303
304
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
953
suppose what they did to be beyond amendment.”309 Max Weber refers to
this quality as charismatic authority, which he defines as follows:
[Charisma is] a certain quality of an individual personality by
virtue of which he is considered extraordinary and treated as
endowed with supernatural, superhuman, or at least
specifically exceptional powers or qualities. These are not
accessible to the ordinary person, but are regarded as of divine
origin or as exemplary, and on the basis of them the individual
concerned is treated as a “leader.”310
Out of enthusiasm, despair, or hope, later generations may recognize
the charismatic authority of earlier political leaders,311 and the
posterity of these leaders may continue to look to their principles and
ideals for guidance. That, in turn, may produce a reluctance in future
generations to alter the superior constitutional ideals of the past.
This phenomenon is in part a function of monumentalistic historywriting that glorifies the past at the expense of the present.312 In his
famous essay, On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life,
Friedrich Nietzsche argues that the study of history can undermine
our ability to meet the challenges presented by the modern world. Of
the several criticisms he lodges against historical sense, one is
particularly relevant to constitutional stickiness. Nietzsche contends
that the study of history can belittle the present and make us feel like
“latecomers.”313 He ascribes to old age “an appropriate senile
occupation, that of looking back, of reckoning up, of closing accounts,
of seeking consolation through remembering what has been,” rather
than what can be.314 Selection bias also plays a role: It leads us to
compare “the best of the past with the average of the present” since
the best of the present has yet to be sorted from the average.315 As a
result, we might feel inferior to the quasi-divine leaders of the past. If
the principles and ideals of these foregone leaders are crystallized in a
written constitution, those principles may tend to stick and trump the
309 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Samuel Kercheval (July 12, 1816), in 10 THE
WRITINGS OF THOMAS JEFFERSON 1816–1826, at 37, 42 (Paul Leicester Ford ed., 1899).
310 MAX WEBER, 1 ECONOMY AND SOCIETY: AN OUTLINE OF INTERPRETIVE SOCIOLOGY
241 (Guenther Roth & Claus Wittich eds., 1968).
311 See id. at 242.
312 Posner, supra note 20, at 590.
313 FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE, UNTIMELY MEDITATIONS 83 (Daniel Breazeale, ed., R.J.
Hollingdale, trans., 1997); Posner, supra note 20, at 576.
314 NIETZSCHE, supra note 313, at 109.
315 Posner, supra note 20, at 590.
954
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
ideas produced by what the society views as the inferior, short-sighted
political leaders of later generations.
In modern United States, for example, large swaths of the public hold
the founding generation in especially high regard. American children
are taught to admire their forefathers from the very early stages of their
education and literary works about the founders consistently top
national bestseller lists.316 Over the years, values espoused by the
founders have, according to Jamal Greene, “acquired a presumption of
rightness within our political culture.”317 The reverence of the founding
generation in the United States has contributed, at least in part, to the
stickiness of most provisions in the U.S. Constitution, which remain
formally unaltered. The veneration of the founding generation, and the
Constitution they drafted, also suggests that even absent the high
amendment threshold in Article V, many provisions in the U.S.
Constitution would prove to be rather sticky.
***
In sum, constitutional stickiness can also result from imperfect
human judgment. As a result of the cognitive biases and heuristics
discussed in this Section, constitution-makers can retain the
constitutional status quo even where the optimal outcome would be
its amendment or replacement.
III. NORMATIVE IMPLICATIONS OF CONSTITUTIONAL STICKINESS
Having described the causes of constitutional stickiness, this Part
turns to the normative question: Is constitutional stickiness
undesirable? As an initial matter, constitutional provisions may not
stick. Where the costs and the salience of the biases I described above
316 See Tom Donnelly, Our Forgotten Founders: Reconstruction, Public Education, and
Constitutional Heroism, 58 CLEV. ST. L. REV. 115, 117 (2010) (listing works about the
founding generation that have been on national bestsellers lists); Richard S. Kay,
“Originalist” Values and Constitutional Interpretation, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL’Y 335,
337 (1996) (“The constitutional Founders still seem to enjoy a regard, if not
reverence, that has not significantly diminished over time, an attitude evidenced in
popular culture, as well as in Supreme Court opinions.”); see also Michael Kirby,
Constitutional Interpretation and Original Intent: A Form of Ancestor Worship?, 24 MELB.
U. L. REV. 1, 2 (2000) (characterizing the American fascination with “original intent”
of the Constitution as a form of legal “ancestor worship”).
317 Jamal Greene, Selling Originalism, 97 GEO. L.J. 657, 713 (2009); see also
LaCroix, supra note 12, at 16 (“Examining the Confederate Constitution demonstrates
the degree to which nineteenth-century Americans were constitution worshippers —
not only the U.S. Constitution, but constitutions in general.”).
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
955
are sufficiently low, constitution-makers can break from the
constitutional past and forge new paths. As discussed above, although
prior decisions can still influence future choices, it may not block them.
Where stickiness occurs, its normative consequences depend on the
nature of the sticky provision. As relevant here, three types of
provisions may stick: (1) an optimal provision; (2) a suboptimal
provision that would be inefficient to change today; and (3) a
suboptimal provision that can be corrected efficiently. I analyze each
in turn below.
First, even where a constitutional provision sticks, that provision
might happen to be optimal (though, perhaps, not exclusively
optimal). Some constitutional choices are as good as — if not better
than — other alternatives. For example, a decision to adopt a
constitutional right to freedom of religion might cause stickiness with
respect to that right. But the costs and benefits of that right might have
been fully appreciated and foreseen through a rational decisionmaking process by the initial constitution-makers. As a result, the
initial adoption of that right may lead to an optimal outcome, even if it
produces stickiness. In addition, it is possible for a suboptimal
provision to become optimal over time as a result of societal evolution
and adaptation.
Importantly, constitutions do not always — or even frequently —
change for the better. At first blush, one may conclude that
constitutional stickiness will inevitably impede the development of
superior constitutional standards since unrestricted markets are
assumed to generate more optimal outcomes.318 Yet markets can also
be dominated by powerful interest groups whose interests deviate
from the furtherance of the public good.319 Constitutional design is no
exception. For example, in constitution-making processes that occur
without effective political pluralism and opposition, the opportunity is
ripe for powerful groups to capture the constitution-design process
and stack the constitutional deck in their favor. In Venezuela,
President Hugo Chavez was able to seize unilateral control over the
constitution-design process, producing a constitution that
marginalizes opposition groups and creates a competitive
authoritarian regime.320 The constitution-making processes in Russia,
318 Cf. Gillette, supra note 17, at 816 (noting the “assumption that unfettered
markets inherently generate more efficient equilibria”).
319 See id.
320 See David Landau, Constitution-Making Gone Wrong, 64 ALA. L. REV. 923, 940
(2013).
956
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
Belarus, and Kazakhstan also produced similar results.321 In these
circumstances, stickiness can resist constitutional changes towards
less optimal configurations.
Japan provides another illustration. Adopted after Japan’s defeat in
World War II, the 1947 Japanese Constitution includes a provision,
Article 9, which renounces war and prohibits the maintenance of a
military and other “war potential.”322 Most recently, Prime Minister
Abe reinterpreted Article 9 to allow collective self-defense (i.e., aiding
allies under attack when Japan itself is not threatened). Large swaths
of the public vigorously oppose the relaxation of the pacifist ideals of
Article 9, fearing a return to pre-World War II militarism and a
renewal of the traumas of war.323 I reserve any normative judgments
about the validity of these competing arguments, but simply note that
the stickiness of Article 9 appears to be impeding change towards what
wide segments of the public view as a proposed move to a less optimal
constitutional framework.
Second, constitutional stickiness can generate a suboptimal outcome
that would be inefficient to change today. Initial constitutional choices
may turn out to be inferior to other alternatives.324 If constitution-makers
had known what we know now, they would not have made that choice.
This problem can occur in many contexts outside of constitutional
design. For example, a company’s decision to hire Employee X today may
foreclose the hiring of Employee Y tomorrow, even where Employee Y
would have been preferable to Employee X.325 Similarly, in the
constitutional-design context, a federal system of government may have
been perceived to be optimal, but the passage of time can reveal that
choice to be suboptimal.326 In addition, external societal conditions might
change, rendering suboptimal a norm that was optimal at the time of its
adoption. The Electoral College is a good example. The result of bitter
debate and uneasy compromise, the Electoral College has outlived its
usefulness, a consequence the founders did not foresee. As Akhil Amar
321 See William Partlett, The Dangers of Popular Constitution-Making, 38 BROOK. J.
INT’L L. 193, 209-23 (2012).
322 NIHONKOKU KENPŌ [KENPŌ] [CONSTITUTION], art. 9, para. 2 (Japan).
323 See Matthew J. Gilley, Japan’s Developing Military Potential Within the Context of
Its Constitutional Renunciation of War, 14 EMORY INT’L L. REV. 1681, 1694-95 (2000).
324 See Liebowitz & Margolis, Fable of Keys, supra note 41, at 3; Gillette, supra note
17, at 823.
325 Gillette, supra note 17, at 813-14.
326 See Liebowitz & Margolis, Fable of Keys, supra note 41, at 3.
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
957
puts it, the Electoral College “was a brilliant eighteenth-century invention
that makes no sense today.”327
In this second category, although a more optimal alternative exists,
it would be inefficient to change the status quo. Put differently, the
costs of adopting the superior alternative are higher than its benefits.
Although the initial constitution-makers should, in hindsight, have
chosen a different constitutional path, it would be too costly to alter it
now. The suboptimal arrangement may therefore rationally persist.
Even though change is inefficient in this second category, it still has
significant normative implications. Although the status quo rationally
persists, it would have been more optimal to adopt an alternative
initially. In other words, the retention of the constitutional status quo
should not necessarily imply a determination that the status quo is
optimal. The acknowledgement that an existing provision is
suboptimal, yet inefficient to change, can generate important signaling
effects for both the domestic polity, as well as foreign polities
searching other constitutions for provisions to borrow. In addition,
the costs and benefits of constitutional change can fluctuate. Although
the costs of changing the status quo may exceed the benefits today,
that cost-benefit calculus may change in the future, permitting
efficient constitutional alterations. Finally, recognizing that initial
design choices can lock-in suboptimal configurations that would be
inefficient to subsequently alter can force constitution-makers to pay
closer attention to preliminary design choices. Although most nations
already have written constitutions and therefore will not engage in the
design process for the very first time, some nations still forge new
constitutional paths by adopting new provisions with no roots in the
old document. In those circumstances, the second category of
stickiness carries significant potential normative weight.
Third, constitutional stickiness may generate a suboptimal result
that can be corrected efficiently, yet remain uncorrected. Unlike in the
second category, here, the benefits of adopting a superior
constitutional alternative exceed its costs and therefore change is
efficient from a rational-choice perspective. But a suboptimal
provision may persist because of a combination of cognitive
limitations and biases that impede rational decision-making by
constitution-makers. In this category, constitutional stickiness may
prove to be a straitjacket that prevents modern generations from
adequately confronting novel challenges or correcting serious
327 Akhil Reed Amar, A Constitutional Accident Waiting to Happen, 12 CONST.
COMMENT. 143, 143 (1995).
958
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
constitutional errors, even where it would be efficient to do so.328 For
example, Egypt’s powerful presidency — which many commentators
argued was at least partially to blame for the country’s authoritarian
past — proved to be rather sticky and was retained in all
constitutional makeovers that Egypt experienced following Hosni
Mubarak’s overthrow.329
Even where constitutional stickiness prevents optimal changes,
however, it can still produce some tangible benefits. Stickiness can
reduce decision costs and promote consensus building by taking
contentious questions off the bargaining table. As discussed above, all
things being equal, the decision costs of retaining existing
constitutional norms are lower than bargaining over novel provisions.
In other words, constitution-makers are more likely to agree to retain
existing constitutional norms than adopt novel provisions. The
reduction of decision costs, in turn, can prevent endless, destructive
conflict over constitutional choices that has the ability to derail the
entire constitutional design enterprise, which, in some cases, may
generate disastrous consequences.
Stickiness can also promote constitutional stability and continuity.
Constitutions often need to be grounded in historical institutions to
succeed. Madison, for example, famously resisted Jefferson’s
suggestion that “the earth belongs always to the living generation” and
that the constitution should thus be rewritten by each successive
generation.330 Madison argued that negotiation and lobbying in the
drafting of each successive constitution may lead to factionalism and
undermine continuity and stability.331 Constitutional stability, in turn,
facilitates the settlement of disputes when they arise and encourages
328 In a separate paper, I analyze several strategies that constitution-makers can
employ to diminish stickiness where it produces undesirable results, including
vagueness, layering, logrolling, temporary constitutions, and non-constitutional
means. See Ozan O. Varol, Remedying Constitutional Stickiness, 37 NAT’L J. CON. L. __
(forthcoming 2016).
329 See Bruce Ackerman, To Save Egypt, Drop the Presidency, N.Y. TIMES (July 10, 2013),
http://www.nytimes.com/2013/07/11/opinion/to-save-egypt-drop-the-presidency.html.
330 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to James Madison (Sept. 6, 1789), available at
http://press-pubs.uchicago.edu/founders/documents/v1ch2s23.html; Letter from James
Madison to Thomas Jefferson (Feb. 4, 1790), available at http://press-pubs.uchicago.
edu/founders/documents/v1ch2s24.html.
331 See Jacob E. Gersen, Temporary Legislation, 74 U. CHI. L. REV. 247, 254-55
(2007); David A.J. Richards, A Theory of Free Speech, 34 UCLA L. REV. 1837, 1840
(1987) (“Madison argued that the reflective values institutionalized in a properly
designed republic are least compromised by oppressive democratic factions if the
written constitution is understood on all sides as an enduring charter of just
government subject to amendment only by extraordinary procedures.”).
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
959
beneficial reliance and investment, allowing relevant public and
private actors to organize their conduct around existing constitutional
configurations.332 Constitutional change has the potential to disrupt
these expectations and cause socioeconomic turmoil.333 In some cases,
it is better for a constitutional rule to be settled than to be settled
correctly.334 As Aristotle argued, instability in law can undermine the
rule of law since the citizens’ habits of obedience to a stable set of
rules give law its power.335 Stability may also avoid frequent attempts
to change the existing constitutional configurations, which may lead
to deadweight losses.336
***
In sum, constitutional stickiness is not always undesirable.
Although stickiness can prevent the adoption of superior alternatives,
it also has the potential to generate tangible benefits in terms of
consensus building, continuity, and stability. Whether these benefits
are outweighed by the benefits of changing the constitutional status
quo is a highly context-dependent question to be evaluated on a caseby-case basis.
332 See David Hume, Of the Original Contract, in DAVID HUME, ESSAYS: MORAL
POLITICAL, AND LITERARY 465, 476 (Eugene F. Miller ed., Liberty Fund rev. ed. 1987)
(“[A]s human society is in perpetual flux, one man every hour going out of the world,
another coming into it, it is necessary, in order to preserve stability in government,
that the new brood should conform themselves to the established constitution . . . .”);
Elster, Constitutionalism, supra note 5, at 471 (“The constitution will lose many of its
desirable properties — notably that of inspiring confidence and creating a climate in
which investors are willing to make long-term investments — if everyone expects that
it will be continually revised.”); David L. Shapiro, The Role of Precedent in
Constitutional Adjudication: An Introspection, 86 TEX. L. REV. 929, 942 (2008).
333 See Robert N. Clinton, Original Understanding, Legal Realism, and the
Interpretation of “This Constitution,” 72 IOWA L. REV. 1177, 1262-64 (1987) (noting
that constitutional stability has “political, social, and economic importance” and is
necessary to support societal and economic growth and the legitimacy of the
government); Levinson, supra note 1, at 712 (“The absence of constitutional stability
— leaving nothing but chaos, economic stagnation, civil war, and vulnerability to
external conquest — will be enormously costly to most if not all.”).
334 See Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., 285 U.S. 393, 406 (1932) (Brandeis, J.,
dissenting) (“[I]n most matters it is more important that the applicable rule of law be
settled than that it be settled right.”).
335 ELKINS ET AL., supra note 7, at 17.
336 Boudreaux & Pritchard, supra note 81, at 126.
960
University of California, Davis
[Vol. 49:899
CONCLUSION
In the famous and oft-misunderstood poem, The Road Not Taken,
Robert Frost describes a traveler’s choice between two roads that
diverge in the woods. The poem is often misinterpreted as a testament
to individualism and self-determination because, in the final lines of
the poem, the traveler asserts that he took the road “less traveled by”
and “that has made all the difference.” A close inspection of the poem,
however, reveals important nuances that are often overlooked. The
two roads, Frost writes, had been worn “really about the same” and
both paths “equally lay in leaves no steps had trodden black.” In other
words, neither path was more or less traveled, and the traveler’s
choices were just about equal, his evaluation in hindsight
notwithstanding.337 In addition, had the traveler chosen the path that
was more traveled on, that also could have “made all the difference.”338
Like the traveler in Frost’s poem, constitution-makers often face
divergent paths as they design constitutions. In this Article, I discussed
how the taking of one path can reinforce further movement along the
same path and foreclose others. A combination of rational-choice and
behavioral mechanisms can lock-in the constitutional status quo,
creating constitutional stickiness. Where the costs of constitutional
change exceed the benefits, previous constitutional choices may persist
despite rational behavior by constitution-makers. Constitutional
designers can also fall prey to their own cognitive biases and, similar to
the traveler in Frost’s poem, continue to follow the path they took,
believing, in hindsight, that the chosen path was superior to all others.
This, in turn, challenges the prevailing orthodoxy in the United States
that Article V’s high threshold for constitutional amendment is the
primary culprit for lack of formal constitutional change and that
significant changes might follow if the threshold were lowered or a new
constitutional convention were called.
The Article also discussed the normative implications of constitutional
stickiness. There is often no single optimal path in constitutional design.
The constitutional roads ahead of the designers, though divergent, may
be “really about the same.” Even where two constitutional roads differ,
they may both lead to optimal outcomes for the polity. But where a
suboptimal path locks in its travelers at the expense of more optimal
337 Matthew Hollis, Edward Thomas, Robert Frost and the Road to War, GUARDIAN
(July 29, 2011), http://www.theguardian.com/books/2011/jul/29/robert-frost-edwardthomas-poetry.
338 Id.
2016]
Constitutional Stickiness
961
alternative paths, constitutional stickiness can be a strong and
unwelcome force to contend with in constitutional design.
The study of constitutional stickiness carries major implications for
contemporary constitutional theory. It suggests that constitutional
scholarship has misplaced its focus on synchronic normative
explorations of constitutional substance. In drawing attention to the
significance of oft-neglected temporal and sequential elements in
constitutional design, the study of constitutional stickiness promises
to open new frontiers in constitutional theory.