Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
Abstract: Offering an account of morality which builds on Hume’s argument for sentimentalism (the notion that our moral judgments are fully and completely explainable as emotional dispositions, the sentiments we have towards things), Prinz argues that emotions are not only necessary but sufficient for moral judgment and that this sort of account is all that’s needed to entirely explain our moral intuitions. He further adds that the relativism implied by this sort of account is not inherently damaging to moral belief and discourse. Contrary to his view I suggest that the implied relativism of an entirely sentimentalist account is actually fatal to moral belief and to the discourse by which we implement it and thus undermines the very kind of account Prinz wants to give. If we agree with Prinz that there can be no “transcendental” moral position in any sense of that term, then we can have no moral beliefs at all in the sense in which moral beliefs matter—as a means of providing a basis for determining the right and wrong courses of action for anyone capable of thinking about such things.
Praxis Filosófica, 2017
The purpose of this paper is to critically review Prinz’s constitution model. According to commonly suggested models, moral judgment is the result of specific cognitive processes that are intuitive, emotional or rational. According to Prinz, sentimentalist views argue that such judgments are caused by emotions. In contrast, he argues that moral judgment is constituted, not caused, by them. I will expose Prinz’s argument to support his proposal and outline some inconsistencies of it.
ethic@: An International Journal For Moral Philosophy (ISSN 1677-2954), 2013
Jesse Prinz (2006, 2007) claimed that emotions are necessary and sufficient for moral judgments. First of all, I clarify what this claim amounts to. The view that he labels emotionism will then be critically assessed. Prinz marshals empirical findings to defend a series of increasingly strong theses about how emotions are essential for moral judgments. I argue that the empirical support upon which his arguments are based is not only insufficient, but it even suggests otherwise, if properly interpreted. My criticism is then extended to his sentimentalist theory, that accounts for how emotions are integrated into moral judgments. The central problem is that Prinz’s view fails to capture the rational aspect of moral evaluation. I make this failure explicit and defend that some version or other of neosentimentalism is a more promising route.
presented at the 2008 Australasian Association of Philosophy Meetings, Melbourne
presented at the 2008 Australasian Association of Philosophy Meetings, Melbourne
In Evolution, Human Behaviour and Morality: The Legacy of Westermarck, 2017
Postmodern Openings, 2021
Moral sentimentalism can be defined as the philosophical theory according to which emotions are the source of our value judgements, in general, and of our moral judgements, in particular. It follows that, from a historical and conceptual point of view, moral sentimentalism has emerged and developed in opposition to moral rationalism, according to which reason allows us to formulate and understand value judgments from a psychological point of view and is also the source of our axiological knowledge from an epistemic point of view. In this article we present the theoretical issues related to the sentimentalist approach to morality and evaluative judgments, starting from the diverse theories of the classical representatives of sentimentalism, Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Hume and Smith, and especially the three theses they defended: psychological perspective, the theory of moral sense and the theory of moral feelings. I also argue that the first moral sentimentalism emerged from the confron...
Prolegomena, 2013
This essay shows that a moral sense or moral sentiments alone cannot identify appropriate morals. To this end, the essay analyzes three defenses of Francis Hutcheson's, David Hume's, and Adam Smith's moral sense theories against the relativism charge that a moral sense or moral sentiments vary across people, societies, cultures, or times. The first defense is the claim that there is a universal moral sense or universal moral sentiments. However, even if they exist, a moral sense or moral sentiments alone cannot identify appropriate morals. The second defense is to adopt a general viewpoint theory, which identifies moral principles by taking a general viewpoint. But it needs to employ reason, and even if not, it does not guarantee that we identify appropriate morals. The third defense is to adopt an ideal observer theory, which draws moral principles from sentimental reactions of an ideal observer. Yet it still does not show that a moral sense or moral sentiments alone can identify appropriate morals.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
For moral sentimentalists, our emotions and desires play a leading role in the anatomy of morality. Some believe moral thoughts are fundamentally sentimental, others that moral facts make essential reference to our sentimental responses, or that emotions are the primary source of moral knowledge. Some believe all these things. The two main attractions of sentimentalism are making sense of the practical aspects of morality, on the one hand, and finding a place for morality within a naturalistic worldview, on the other. The corresponding challenges are accounting for the apparent objectivity and normativity of morality. Recent psychological theories emphasizing the centrality of emotion in moral thinking have prompted renewed interest in sentimentalist ethics.
2006
This volume includes essays presented at the conference on Emotions and Rationality in Moral Philosophy held at the Universities of Neuchâtel and Bern in October 2005. The authors of this volume share the Humean insight that the ‘sentiments’ have a crucial role to play in elucidating the practice of morality. In a Humean fashion, they warn us against taking an intellectualist view of emotions and reject the rationalist account of morality.
SHS Web of Conferences
The idea that we must free ourselves from the mastery of our emotions in order to act morally has been challenged over the past decades as Kant scholars have turned to the Metaphysics of Morals and the Critique of Judgment to regain the centrality of emotions in this tradition. I want to expand the claim about the positive role of emotions in Kant’s moral theory by arguing that certain emotional states should be understood as having an even more fundamental role, namely, as an empirical condition for morality. Therefore, I will show that the structure Kant provides to explain the human mind conceives of our moral experience as relying on what he calls lower faculty of feeling. After sketching Kant’s approach to cognition, I will show how some feelings are indissociable from the human moral experience – and notably, from the ability to act in accordance with our predispositions. I will discuss textual evidence for this view and explain that, although Kant himself failed to devise an ...
Észak-magyarországi Stratégiai Füzetek, 2024
Scientific Culture, 2022
Non-Intrusive Methodologies for Large Area Urban Research, 2023
DOĞU AVRUPA TARİHİ Yeni Bulgular ve Yaklaşımlar , 2023
Cieli dipinti. Soffitti lignei nell'Europa meridionale fra Medioevo e Rinascimento, 2022
Bericht der Römisch-Germanischen Kommission 101/102 (2020/2021), 2023
Body, Movement and Dance in Psychotherapy, 2007
REFLEXIONES EN TORNO AL DERECHO PROCESAL CONSTITUCIONAL (2012). A. Giacomette dir. CCDPC / Universidad El Bosque: 75-99, 2012
Travaux du Muséum National d'Histoire Naturelle "Grigore Antipa", 2010
FEMS Microbiology Ecology, 2000
Proceedings of The 5th IIAE International Conference on Industrial Application Engineering 2017, 2017
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 1997
Archeologia e Calcolatori 35.1, 2024, 447-472., 2024
Research in Nursing & Health, 2018