After Nietzsche’s Beyond
Carl T. Dahlman1
Department of Geography, Miami University
Oxford, Ohio 45056, USA
Email: dahlmac@muohio.edu
Abstract
Nietzsche’s writing on nationalism raises a series of questions about how we
interpret his genealogical and constructivist insights in light of his often
mendacious cultural stereotyping. More importantly, the misinterpretations of his
work in the name of nationalism have required careful examination to ‘salvage’ his
work from the wreckage of his posthumous Nazi career. A close reading of
Nietzsche raises critical questions about modern political subjectivity. This piece
relates these questions to the methodological problem associated with studying
nationalist violence in the wake of Nietzsche’s academic revival. It argues that
Nietzsche’s desire to place his own subjectivity beyond the dilemmas of his day is
ethically incomplete. If we only understand oppression in terms of different
subject positions or personal subjectivity, then we fail to recognize the ethical
responsibility that inter-subjectivity makes possible through the act of bearing
witness to the oppression experienced by others.
Nietzsche wrote a lot about power but he was not much of a political
theorist, at least not in the formal sense. Yet everything he wrote about touches on
what we today think of as ‘the political’: religion, morality, and social philosophy.
That we recognize him today as important to social theory does not stem from any
formal philosophical construct but rather from his willingness to engage in the back
and forth of thinking through the problems facing the modern subject. He faced a
world of enormous uncertainties and tried desperately to understand himself by
1
Creative Commons licence: Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works
ACME: An International E-Journal for Critical Geographies 2010, 9 (1), 66-71
67
writing incisive critiques that often read at cross-purposes to each other. Yet his
attempt to move back and forth between places, friends, identities, and in and out
of social conventions appeared falsely to some as providing absolutes and fixity.
This partly explains how Nietzsche, a critic of German nationalism, was
resuscitated as a prophet of National Socialism, a posthumous career requiring
decades of careful rehabilitation. Perhaps we can now appreciate the moments in
which his insightful critique outpaced his times, and much of the last century, too.
The enormous energy and passion that have gone into re-reading Nietzsche is
indeed an important part of Europe’s post-war intellectual reconstruction, just as
bearing witness and building an ever closer union have been to healing the lines
that divided it. It is all the more striking to me, as someone who has studied
Europe’s latter-day genocides in the former Yugoslavia, that Nietzsche’s
rehabilitation has often set aside the uncomfortable questions – or rather questions
of our discomfort – about his writings on nations and the meaning of ‘good
Europeans,’ a persistent theme in Nietzsche’s writings that beckons to a postnational subjectivity and (some interpretations of) European integration (Emden,
2008).
What justifies his second life in the seminar room and fashionable journals
is that Nietzsche remains a pressing and discomforting presence in our
confrontation with political violence. Nietzsche is important not for the
questionable politics he was thought to serve but for his questioning the political in
modern life. I have frequently thought about his comments on nationalism since
my first trip to Bosnia-Herzegovina nine years ago. My confrontation with
nationalism raised complex and difficult ethical questions for me, however much I
might have thought, or rather wished, that nationalism was a ‘thing of the past.’
Nietzsche, too, recognized its troubling presence in modern life. In his work
Beyond Good and Evil (2000 [1886], § 241), Nietzsche argued that it is
nationalism’s own interest in strength and mastery that nevertheless leads a nation
into subservience to another: “how soon one stronger will become master over the
strong; also that for the spiritual flattening of a people there is a compensation,
namely the deepening of another people.” Yet, however critical Nietzsche is of
nationalism, his own claim to ‘reason’ still works through the categories of
‘peoples’ and races: “I could imagine that even within our quick-moving Europe,
some dull, sluggish races might need half-centuries to overcome these atavistic
attacks of fatherland-ism and attachment to the soil, and return to reason, that is to
say, to being ‘good Europeans’” (Nietzsche, 2000 [1886], § 241). Nietzsche’s
desire to transcend national categories surrenders their meaning to the nationalists
because he imagines a ‘good European’ is beyond bias and unreason.
After Nietzsche’s Beyond
68
Figure 1. The mass grave at Crni Vrh was reopened in 2003, eight years after the war.
One is struck by the resemblance between Nietzsche’s passivity to the
problem of nationalism in his time and the West’s passivity to the wars in
Yugoslavia during the 1990s. In effect, they both see nationalism as a political
problem that is overcome as nations develop/evolve sufficiently to join a new
Europe. This leitmotif is heard again in Nietzsche’s notion of political progress, of
“a tremendous physiological process” that yields an “evolving European”
(Nietzsche, 2000 [1886], § 242). This creative destruction of subject positions
clashes with the Foucauldian ethic of care and the recognition of nationalism as a
biopolitical construct. In short, we are left with the sense that Nietzsche’s attempt
to move beyond nationalist politics was really a movement back and forth within a
biopolitical definition of modern subjects that merely discarded one deadly politics
for another.
I thought of Nietzsche again while visiting the hollow crater of a mass
grave in eastern Bosnia (Figure 1). The grave had contained some of the missing
from the area where my collaborator and I were studying the aftermath of the
Bosnian war (Ó Tuathail and Dahlman, forthcoming). Located on the side of a
mountain named “Dark Peak,” it was, at the time, the largest mass grave opened in
Bosnia. There had been an accounting of what was found in the grave: 483 mostly
complete bodies, another 150 partial remains, 198 smaller body parts, and 122
ACME: An International E-Journal for Critical Geographies 2010, 9 (1), 66-71
69
artifacts. These had all been taken away for identification and proper burial,
leaving behind a gaping hole. It lay half full of water like an inverted tumulus, an
ignominious grave reflecting gray sky above. The yellow muck around the edge of
the pit pulled at my shoes and gave off a foul smell. After a few minutes of rather
unintentional meditation, perhaps shock, I was surprised to find myself thinking
about the abyss, about the new Europeans, about peoples and fatherlands. Later, I
felt disappointed at finding in that place an unreconstructed apparition of
Nietzsche’s questionable politics rather than God, pain, or something more directly
meaningful.
It was only later, upon seeing the victims’ remains in the morgue, that my
ambivalent reaction to that morbid aerie began to turn into thoughts about the
responsibility to bear witness, to call out the guilty. It was a relief to think “no,
Nietzsche doesn’t apply here… he got it wrong. One doesn’t have to remain
passive in the face of horror.” Yet I remain(ed) disturbed at my unexpected
encounter with Nietzsche and returned to Beyond Good and Evil (2000 [1886]) to
see what useful disruptions I might have missed in my earlier reading.
In chapter eight, “Peoples and Fatherlands,” Nietzsche presents us with a
discussion of problems that, one hundred years later, still apply to the conflict in
Bosnia and the strange disjuncture between nationalist violence and the apparent
progress of a unified Europe. Nietzsche writes about Europe’s preoccupation with
nation, a mania that he shares if only to try and best it. In expressing his skepticism
of German nationalism, Nietzsche moves back and forth between the category of
nationhood as a constructed thing and a biological presumption. He says, “The
German soul is above all manifold, of diverse origins, more put together and
superimposed than actually built” (Nietzsche 2000 [1886], § 244). This
momentary glimpse of a socially constructed nationhood then disappears when he
explains how it was “put together.” Nietzsche writes that this manifold quality is
“due to where it comes from… As a people of the most monstrous mixture and
medley of races, perhaps even with a preponderance of the pre-Aryan element, as
‘people of the middle’ in every sense, the Germans are more incomprehensible,
comprehensive, contradictory, unknown, incalculable, surprising, even frightening
than other people are to themselves” (Nietzsche, 2000 [1886], § 244). What
seemed at first insightful about nation gives way to Nietzsche’s greater tendency to
write poisoned pen letters to the culture he wished to estrange.
This back and forth from a critical position by which we might obliterate
nation – and move ourselves beyond good and evil – appears again in the same
chapter but with less ambiguity about Nietzsche’s assumptions: “What is called a
‘nation’ in Europe today, and is really rather a res facta than a res nata (and
occasionally can hardly be told from a res ficta et picta) is in any case something
After Nietzsche’s Beyond
70
evolving, young, and easily changed…” (Nietzsche 2000 [1886], § 251).2 These
critical moments lay bare “nation” as something with a genealogy, something
fashioned. But that same passage gives way to something less critical, more
uncomfortable, and ultimately disappointing as Nietzsche concludes that nation is
“…easily changed, not yet a race, let alone such an aere perennius as the Jewish
type.”3 Nation may be constructed, but other identities are not. Nietzsche is as
comfortable denouncing caterwauling Germanophiles as he is trading in the
currency of eternal racial and cultural typologies. We must be vigilent of his
mendacious indulgence of national and racial caricatures. At the same time, a
recognition of Nietzsche as a thinker working through his situation rather than
transcending it might provide a more critical position on identity that calls into
question not only his but also our passivity to nationalism, and the elusive hope for
‘good subjects,’ European or otherwise.
The post-war rehabilitation of Nietzsche, and his role in thinking about
modern subjectivity, has produced critical moments that bring us back to the
subject(s) of political violence. The moments beside the grave and in the morgue
were alienating – estranging and silencing – because it is an encounter with an
extreme form of difference. The violence that the war’s victims experienced was
part of a specific historical and social context that we cannot re-occupy or know –
we cannot move back and forth between subjects, per se. Kelly Oliver (2001)
argues that this impossible relation between subject positions is a major challenge
to overcoming the violence associated with nationalism and other forms of
violence. Seeking to recognize the subjects of oppression, in this case war’s
victims, fails because we are listening for an impossible testimony. Certainly, there
are eyewitnesses who survived, as well as the perpetrators themselves, but even
their testimonies and confessions are from different positions and reshaped by their
retelling (Cubilié, 2005). Oliver works with yet moves beyond Nietzsche, as well
as other thinkers, by suggesting that this difference in subject positions need not
give way to passivity. She argues that we must instead recognize oppression and
victimization through our shared subjectivities and our infinite capacity to make
meaning in the presence of difference, despite different subject positions. However
different our subject positions, our subjectivity allows us to carry responsibility for
witnessing oppression not by representing historical facts, per se, but by bearing
witness to the “truth about humanity and suffering that transcends those facts”
(Oliver, 2004, 81).
Witnessing, then, is an act not only of eyewitness testimony or our
recognition of the oppression of others, but an open encounter with their otherness,
a fundamentally ethical responsibility of the encounter. It is a back and forth
2
The Latin translates as “is really rather a thing man-made than a thing born (and occasionally can hardly be
told from a thing invented and painted).”
3
“Aere perennius” translates as “more lasting than bronze.”
ACME: An International E-Journal for Critical Geographies 2010, 9 (1), 66-71
71
movement that does not wait passively but rather allows us to move beyond subject
positions. Nietzsche was unable to do this because he did not recognize
subjectivity as having an ethical component towards the other, and so he became
self-referential. In contrast, witnessing is an obligation to recognize ourselves as
active agents in the re-presentation of oppression that results from a tension
between impossibly different subject positions and the possibility of bearing
witness. Oliver draws from psychoanalytic and phenomenological theory to create
a parallel between the encounter with the other and our encounter with ourselves.
Indeed, when we gaze into the abyss, it gazes back into us – to seek is to bear out.
This reflective understanding of subjectivity seeks to move beyond a theoretical
grammar that recognizes only either sameness or difference, and to bear out an
ethical obligation to the other by opening ourselves to a shared humanity. Bearing
witness, then, is an ethical responsibility to make meaning that, in Oliver’s
Nietzschean phrasing, “moves us beyond the melancholic choice between either
dead historical facts or traumatic repetition of violence” (Oliver 2004, 81).
Recognizing our own subjectivity in the work of bearing witness to oppression thus
exposes our own subject positions in ways that are discomforting, but productively
so if we are to responsibly make meaning after oppression.
References
Cubilié, Anne. 2005. Women Witnessing Terror: Testimony and the Cultural
Politics of Human Rights. New York: Fordham University Press.
Emden, Christian. 2008. The uneasy European: Nietzsche, nationalism and the idea
of Europe. Journal of European Studies 38(1), 27-51.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2000 [1886]. Beyond good and evil: Prelude to a philosophy
of the future. In, Basic Writing of Nietzsche. Translated by W. Kaufmann.
New York: The Modern Library.
Oliver, Kelly. 2004. Witnessing and testimony. Parallax 10(1), 79-88.
Oliver, Kelly. 2001. Witnessing: Beyond Recognition. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Ó Tuathail, Gearóid and Carl T. Dahlman. Forthcoming. Bosnia Remade: Ethnic
Cleansing and its Reversal. Oxford: Oxford University Press.