The Naturalist versus Anti-Naturalist Debate
By Mark Bevira and Jason Blakelyb
(for The Routledge Handbook of Interpretive Political Studies, eds. Mark Bevir and R.A.W.
Rhodes)
aDepartment
of Political Science, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720-1950. Email:
mbevir@berkeley.edu
bDepartment
of Political Science, Pepperdine University, 24255 Pacific Coast Highway, Malibu,
CA 90263. Email: Jason.Blakely@pepperdine.edu
1
The Naturalist versus Anti-Naturalist Debate
Contrary to widespread belief, the naturalism and anti-naturalism debate in political
science is about philosophy not methods. Because this conflict is philosophical and not
methodological, political scientists are free to embrace whatever methods suit their research
purposes. That is, method pluralism can reign supreme over political science. But this method
pluralism does not imply that the naturalist/anti-naturalist debate is safely forgotten or somehow
resolved. On the contrary, the dueling philosophical assumptions facing off in this debate remain
of the greatest importance to the study of politics today. What are these dueling assumptions?
Naturalism is the assumption that explanations in political science should be formal,
ahistorical, and invariant like those often found in the natural sciences. The philosophic roots of
naturalism are found in the Vienna Circle, logical positivism, British empiricism, and early
analytic philosophy (Ayer, 1952, p. 48; Carnap, 1929, p. 331; Neurath, 1931, p. 48). By contrast,
anti-naturalism is the view that human beliefs and actions are expressive of meanings, making
political inquiry incompatible with the naturalist quest for formal, ahistorical, and invariant
explanations. The philosophic roots of anti-naturalism are found in German Romanticism,
phenomenology, idealism, and post-Wittgensteinian analytic philosophy (Dilthey, 1976;
Collingwood, 1946, pp. 285-288; Husserl, 1936; Winch, 1958). The purpose of this chapter is to
survey the naturalist/anti-naturalist debate as a specifically philosophical conflict, with particular
attention paid to how this conflict has generated anti-naturalist critiques and alternatives to the
study of politics. To this end, we have divided the chapter into three parts.
In the first part we survey the basic philosophical differences between naturalism and
anti-naturalism, looking at how each engenders rival ways of thinking about methods and
2
explaining political reality. In the second part of the chapter we will see how these philosophical
ruptures lead anti-naturalists to reject naturalist concepts. Specifically, where naturalists fashion
concepts meant to capture the reified and essential features of political life, anti-naturalists rebuff
any such reification and essentialism as distortions. The third and final part of the chapter then
explores how, although unified in their rejection of naturalism, anti-naturalists nevertheless
splinter into various schools of philosophic thought. Two of the most important are poststructuralism, as exemplified by Michel Foucault, and hermeneutics, as exemplified by Charles
Taylor.
One caveat, however, is necessary before commencing. Perhaps few political scientists
today would wish to identify as naturalists. Indeed, where once naturalism was openly
championed by the leaders of the discipline, the vogue today has shifted towards multi-methods,
as is evident in political science methodologists like John Gerring (2001; 2011), Gary Goertz
(2012), Robert Goodin (2009, pp. 9-12), Janet Box-Steffensmeier, Henry Brady, and David
Collier (2008, pp. 29-30), and Ann Chih Lin (1998) among others. In one sense, we strongly
support this shift towards method pluralism. However, an important proviso must be added:
namely, often multi-methods advocates assume that naturalists and anti-naturalists can carry out
a peaceful, untroubled coexistence so long as they adopt an ecumenical stance on methods (BoxSteffensmeier, Brady, and Collier, 2008, p. 30; Gerring, 2001, p. 9). Unfortunately, however, this
sunny vision of an untroubled peace misunderstands the basic distinctions of the naturalist/antinaturalist debate. For as we now hope to show, these two groups remain at odds at the most
fundamental philosophical level.
3
1. Naturalism and Anti-Naturalism
Naturalism and anti-naturalism are incompatible on the most basic philosophical level.
Where naturalists assume that explanations in the social sciences should be formal, ahistorical,
and invariant, anti-naturalists believe that these explanations must instead involve the
reconstruction of historically contingent meanings. Because the dividing issues in this debate are
philosophical and not methodological, naturalist political scientists may legitimately employ
what are sometimes thought of as “anti-naturalist” methods like ethnography, open-ended
interview questions, and close textual analysis. Likewise, anti-naturalists commit no faux pas
when they avail themselves of what are frequently considered “naturalist” methods like mass
surveys, polling, or large-N statistics.
Yet despite being able to share methods, naturalists and anti-naturalists also have very
different views of the very methods that are in principle available to both. In the case of
naturalists, the assumption that explanations are formal, ahistorical, and invariant often leads
them to treat methods as if they were logics of discovery. A method becomes a logic of
discovery whenever it is assumed that this method is a prerequisite to the practice of good
political science. For example, political scientists turn methods into logics of discovery when
they assume that a certain kind of statistical analysis or polling is necessary in order to conduct
sound research. A logic of discovery thus consists of the belief that a formal, invariant procedure,
rigorously carried out, secures scientific results.
By contrast, anti-naturalists do not think of methods as necessary procedures of
discovery. Instead, anti-naturalists tend to treat methods as heuristic techniques informing a
skilled craft. Consider the craft of fishing. A fisherman may use whatever techniques he prefers
4
for fishing provided the results are acceptable. Thus he may use a fishing pole, a net, a trap, a
spear, or even his bare hands. No matter what technique is used, the craft of fishing is developed
within the context of some tradition that provides heuristic techniques and rules of thumb. In
other words, fishermen can draw on a stock of knowledge that guides them in their craft.
Similarly, anti-naturalists hold that the practice of political science is foremost a craft.
This means political scientists may use whatever methods they wish so long as the results are
acceptable. Because skilled craftsmanship can always be creatively supplemented by ingenuity
or luck, anti-naturalists believe that no method can simply be treated as a mechanical procedure
or recipe for success. That is, in contrast to naturalists, anti-naturalists argue that no invariant,
formal set of steps can permanently replace the work of exercising a skill. Rather, anti-naturalists
hold that political scientists, like fishermen, also draw on traditions which instruct them in how
to skillfully employ whichever techniques suit their purposes (from reading texts to conducting
statistical research).
Thus, even though naturalists and anti-naturalists share methods, their philosophic
differences lead them to treat those methods differently. Where naturalists envision political
science research as guided by formal logics of discovery, anti-naturalists instead see it as
consisting of the heuristic techniques of a craft. But the philosophic difference between these two
camps runs much deeper than even this basic incompatibility. In this section we survey two
further ruptures between naturalism and anti-naturalism. First we will see that while naturalists
treat political reality as comprised of isolated atoms, subject to measurement and correlation,
anti-naturalists instead view it as composed of holistic webs of meaning. Second, we will
5
contrast naturalism’s search for explanatory causal laws with anti-naturalism’s attempt to
construct historical narratives.
i. Atomistic Units versus Holistic Meanings
One of the most important philosophic differences between naturalists and anti-naturalists
is that while the former atomize political reality into basic units that can then be correlated and
measured, the latter instead treat it as comprised of holistic webs of meaning. Let us look at each
of these two competing orientations in greater detail.
Naturalist political scientists often assume that inquiry consists of a process of isolating
units of political reality and correlating them to other such units. This process of atomization
allows naturalists to single out bits of reality that might then be found repeated across vastly
different contexts. For example, in their classic of behavioral political science, Gabriel Almond
and Sidney Verba (1965, pp. 307-315) treated certain beliefs—e.g., how much “pride” the
Italians versus the British felt for their respective governments—as isolated units that could be
measured, correlated, and compared across widely different cultures. As we will see below, this
picture of political reality as built out of basic, atomistic building blocks is directly tied to the
naturalist quest for formal, invariant laws (MacIntyre, 1978). But for now the key point is that
naturalist inquiry often consists of this attempt to breakdown political reality into measurable,
isolated units.
This stance puts naturalism directly at odds with the anti-naturalist view. For antinaturalists hold that human beliefs and actions should not be broken down into atomistic units,
6
but rather must be contextualized within wider networks of meaning (Taylor, 1985b). Political
reality, on the anti-naturalist view, is not comprised of atomistic properties but of holistic webs
of belief. Beliefs are holistic because they are always supported by further beliefs. Antinaturalists thus tend to treat human beliefs similar to the way literary scholars treat a passage
from a novel—that is, they interpret and contextualize it in light of the further meanings and
beliefs that inform it. The importance of this difference for political science will perhaps be
illuminated by an example.
Consider the case of an anti-naturalist who wishes to give an account of the political
slogan “el silencio es salud” (silence is health) which was commonly expressed by individuals
with authoritarian sympathies during Argentina’s Dirty War (Feitlowitz, 1998). At the most basic
level, the very meaning of el silencio es salud, requires some background knowledge of the
words and grammar of the Spanish language as well as the relevant historical and social
context—in this case, things like Argentine authoritarianism in the 1970s, practices of state
terrorism, the Cold War, and so on.
Of course, so far naturalists like Almond and Verba might well agree that such
background knowledge is necessary. However, what distinguishes the anti-naturalist approach is
the key claim that the very meaning of the slogan is dependent upon the particular webs of belief
that inform it. This crucial claim implies that meaning is not present in an isolated unit but is the
function of a holistic context. So, a man might repeat the slogan “silence is health” because of
his various beliefs about Argentina’s national security, the rowdiness of subversives, and the
need for the state to silence dissenters. By contrast, another individual might adopt this slogan
for very different reasons—for example, as expressing the ironic and cowardly view that
7
resisting evil is almost always futile and that surviving state terrorism in good health means
remaining silent. In this way, anti-naturalists conclude that explaining and understanding
particular meanings requires interpretively reconstructing the right context of beliefs and not
isolating and correlating atomistic facts.
Moreover, anti-naturalists hold that what is true of beliefs is also true of human actions—
namely, that they must be unpacked within a holistic context of belief. Here anti-naturalists
defend the thesis that actions are expressive of beliefs, a point often argued by drawing a basic
distinction between actions and movements (Geertz, 1973, pp. 6-7; MacIntyre, 1964, pp. 56-66).
A mere physical movement, anti-naturalists note, might be identical to an action. For instance,
the involuntary twitch of an eyelid may be indistinguishable from the wink of an eye. Yet the
difference between the two is vast because winking, as an action, is expressive of beliefs. A wink
might be a sign of flirting, a warning, an agreed upon code, a joke, or a salutation. Thus, properly
identifying actions requires linking them to the relevant web of beliefs that inform them.
Furthermore, anti-naturalists conclude that because political reality is made up of human beliefs
and actions, it is essentially expressive of holistic meanings. In other words, political reality itself
must be interpreted in a way analogous to the study of a text, and not treated as a collection of
isolated, repeating atoms.
This marks a basic philosophical incompatibility between these two camps. Where
naturalists attempt to subject political reality to a process of atomization, correlation, and
measurement, anti-naturalists instead contextualize and interpret beliefs and actions within
holistic webs of meaning. But this basic difference is in fact integrally related to a further
incompatibility—namely, how political scientists ought to explain political reality.
8
ii. Causal Laws versus Historical Narratives
Naturalist attempts to atomize political reality are usually part of a larger quest to
discover the formal causal laws explaining political life. In sharp contrast to this, anti-naturalists
view political reality as expressive of holistic meanings that must be explained through historical
narratives. Naturalists and anti-naturalists thus advance philosophically incompatible forms of
explanation: the one causal, ahistorical, and invariant; the other narrative, historical, and
contingent.
The naturalist attempt to explain politics in terms of general causal laws is evident in a
wide variety of schools, including not only certain versions of Marxism but also mainstream,
behavioral political science (Marx, 1859, pp. 388-391; Gunnell, 1975, pp. 65-67, 84). In its early
years, the behavioral movement often drew support for this view of explanation by appealing to
analytic philosophers like Carl Hempel (1965, p. 240; 1948) and A.J. Ayer (1952, p. 48) who
argued that every bona fide science required the establishment of general causal laws.
Explanation, on the view of these philosophers, consisted of finding the necessary causal
connections between two states of affairs, one antecedent and the other a consequent. Once a
necessary causal mechanism had been identified between two atomistic bits of reality a general
law could be formulated. Naturalists’ tendency to atomize political reality thus ties in directly to
their quest for correlating states of affairs in the hopes of discovering general causal laws.
This search for necessary, causal laws once again highlights the extent of the
incompatibility between naturalism and anti-naturalism. For we have already seen that anti9
naturalists view particular beliefs and actions as the result of the contingent reasons and beliefs
that support them. Yet viewing beliefs as the result of such contingent reasoning implies that
individuals could have reasoned differently, leading to other outcomes. In other words, the antinaturalist view is that beliefs and actions are the result of contingent reasons and not necessary
causal links. This means that as long as beliefs are understood as existing in light of other beliefs,
human behavior cannot be subsumed under determinate causal laws (Davidson, 2006).
Instead of causal laws, viewing beliefs as the result of contingent processes of reasoning
strongly implies that political science explanation is a form of historical narration. This is
because reconstructing contingent beliefs and reasons involves telling narratives or stories. Many
anti-naturalist philosophers have argued that human action is structured by narrative sequences
(Heidegger, 1953, pp. 292-304; Ricoeur, 1983-1985). The basic point here is that, human beliefs
and actions are not carried out in atomistic segments, but rather are integrated into a context of
goals, beliefs, and desires that relate the past, present, and future to one another. In this way,
human agency exists in a narrative stream that orders temporally remote episodes. Thus many
anti-naturalist philosophers maintain that human agency actually embodies a narrative and that
human beings are “a story-telling animal” that continually enacts stories (MacIntyre, 2007, pp.
216, 211-212; Taylor, 1985c). Political scientists must therefore fit beliefs and actions within
sequences of past, present, and future. Or, put more simply, they must construct narratives
(MacIntyre, 2007, p. 208).
However, an immediate caveat must be added to this exposition of the anti-naturalist
position. Namely, the anti-naturalist insistence on narratives does not negate method pluralism.
Rather, it only requires that whatever methods a political scientist selects (be it statistics, mass
10
surveys, or individual interviews), he or she must ultimately evoke narratives of contingent belief
and not necessary laws as explaining human behavior. Likewise, a similar caveat goes for the
naturalist position: namely, a commitment to causal laws doesn’t bar the use of ethnographic
research or close textual analysis. Thus we return to one of our major claims: the difference
between naturalism and anti-naturalism is philosophical and not methodological. Despite their
irreconcilable philosophic differences, both camps can avail themselves of whatever methods
they choose.
2. Against Naturalist Concept Formation
So far we have explored two philosophic ruptures between naturalism and antinaturalism, the first concerning atomism versus holism, and the second causal laws versus
narratives. We will now examine how these basic philosophic differences help drive the antinaturalist critique and rejection of naturalist concepts in political science.
Naturalists often either reify or essentialize political reality. This move reflects the basic
naturalist mission. That is, reification and essentialism reflect the naturalist hope of discovering
law-like explanations that are formal, ahistorical, and invariant. In what follows we look at
reification and essentialism each in turn, drawing on examples from contemporary political
science research. Approaching the topic in this way underscores our ongoing point that although
the naturalism/anti-naturalism debate is about philosophy and not methods, it nevertheless
remains of chief importance to the study of politics today.
11
i. Reification
Reification occurs when political scientists treat beliefs, actions, and practices as nonintentional objects that can break free of a single context of intentional meaning. Instead of
getting entangled in particular contexts of meaning, the appeal of reification is that it allows
political scientists to conceive of political reality as comprised of movable parts that can migrate
from context to context without distortion (a kind of movable furniture). Reification is thus
clearly related to the naturalist form of inquiry we explored above, which seeks to isolate bits of
reality that then form the basis for causal laws.
There are two general types of reification that are common to political science today. The
first is what might be called brute fact reification. This type of reification is the result of
stripping units of political reality of intentional meanings almost entirely in favor of brute
demographic, biological, or other such facts. The second kind of reification common to political
science is atomistic reification. Atomistic reification is the result of abstracting or otherwise
isolating intentional meanings from their original, holistic context. Once they have been
atomized, these concepts can be treated as independent variables. Let us look at each of these
forms of reification more carefully in light of contemporary political science.
Researchers of voter behavior often reify human identity by treating it as a brute fact. For
example, many American political scientists today believe there is a strong correlation between
the brute biological/demographic fact of age and the motivation to vote in presidential elections
(Kernell, Jacobson, and Kousser, 2011, pp. 496-497). The two political scientists who have done
the most to corroborate this claim are John Mark Hansen and Steven Rosenstone (1993, p. 128),
who together have gathered an impressive store of data in order to indentify the “causes” and
12
“personal determinants” of voter participation. Surveying American presidential elections from
1956 to 1988, Rosenstone and Hansen found that voter turnout among the oldest citizens was
twenty-nine percentage points higher than among the youngest. This led them to the general
conclusion that “as people grow older, their involvement in American politics deepens”
(Rosenstone and Hansen, 1993, pp. 136-137).
Rosenstone and Hansen’s research exhibits several of the features of naturalism we have
discussed so far. First, age is conceptualized as a reified, brute fact. This fact is then correlated
with another brute fact like the act of voting. After enough data has been aggregated the hope is
that basic causal or at least correlative patterns will emerge. In this way, the reified fact of age
plays an essential role in the attempt to causally predict voter behavior.
Anti-naturalists, by contrast, reject Rosenstone and Hansen’s reification of age on the
grounds that it neglects the intentions and beliefs of particular agents. Anti-naturalists note that
the political significance of age is always the result of a particular intentional context. Thus, they
would argue that although there is indeed the brute biological/demographic fact of being a
certain age, they would nevertheless insist that there is no brute fact as to the meaning or
significance of this for the motives and purposes of the agents in question. Rather, the
significance of age for voter behavior depends on the beliefs and intentions of particular actors.
Thus anti-naturalists might point to the existence of enclaves of elderly Americans that
are either highly apathetic or antagonistic to voting—for example, the last remnants of the “turn
on, tune in, drop out” ethos of the 1960s. Similarly, they might point to segments of American
youth that have become politically energized and enthusiastic voters. The purpose of such
counterexamples would be to show that there is no mere social fact of “being sixty-five” or
13
“being eighteen” that determines voter behavior. Instead, what is relevant to politics is how the
biological fact of age is interpreted by various different individuals and groups. That is to say,
the interpreted significance of age is crucial to its role within political explanation.
Of course, naturalist political scientists might respond to this line of critique by reifying
the concept of age in an atomistic way instead of reifying it as a brute fact. In other words, they
might adopt the second kind of reification discussed above in place of the first. Something like
this is what Rosenstone and Hansen actually do when they consider various possible hypotheses
for how aging determines voter turnout. After considering three possible hypotheses, Rosenstone
and Hansen settle on treating the meaning of age on the “life-experience hypothesis,” which
holds that “as people grow older … they accumulate information, skills, and attachments that
help them to overcome the costs of political involvement” (1993, p. 137).
This shift in analysis marks a turn towards atomistic reification because instead of
reifying age into a brute biological fact, stripped of meanings, age is instead reified as a freefloating meaning. That is, instead of an analysis of the particular beliefs and intentions of the
agents involved, Rosenstone and Hansen posit the “life-experience hypothesis” which endows
age with a single, free-standing meaning. This atomistic meaning is then treated as the cause of
higher levels of voter participation.
The anti-naturalist objection to this atomistic reification should now be clear. For
according to anti-naturalists, beliefs and actions are the result of particular intentions and reasons
held by agents. Yet Rosenstone and Hansen’s analysis gives the distinct impression that such
intentions can be neglected in favor of positing an atomistic and quasi-universal meaning to
growing older in America. Of course, none of this excludes the possibility that anti-naturalist
14
might accept Rosenstone and Hansen’s finding that older Americans voted in higher numbers
between 1956 and 1988. It is only that anti -naturalists would insist that all the work of
explanation was yet to be done. This is because anti-naturalists maintain that explanation
requires a narrative about the actual reasons why particular agents formed certain beliefs, and yet
this is precisely what they argue is elided by the naturalist correlation of reified concepts.
ii. Essentialism
Reification occurs when political scientists subtract the intentions of agents from political
concepts. Essentialism, by contrast, is the result of stripping political concepts of their contextual
and historical specificity. Freed of this specificity, essentialist concepts endeavor to express
historical and cultural constants, which in turn might be used as the basis for naturalist causal
explanations. Generally speaking, essentialism in political science takes two forms—“strong”
and “weak.” Where strong essentialism assumes a fixed core of common traits that must be
present for the concept to apply, weak essentialism allows for degrees of variation. Again we
will look briefly at each in light of contemporary political science research.
Strong essentialism occurs whenever political scientists assume a fixed core of features in
all cases where a concept might be legitimately applied (e.g., Sartori, 1984). This kind of
essentialism is widespread in political science today, but we will limit ourselves to observing it
in the study of “contentious politics” as conducted by Charles Tilly, Doug McAdam and Sidney
Tarrow. This research is worthy of singling out not only because of its widespread influence but
15
also because the very field of “contentious politics” is framed in such a way that it presupposes a
strong form of essentialism.
The concept of contentious politics is strongly essentialist in that it is meant to capture
the core features of otherwise heterogeneous political phenomena, including social movements,
strikes, revolutions, nationalism, and democratization to name only a few. According to Tilly,
McAdam, and Tarrow, what this seemingly disparate list of political phenomena share is a
nucleus of fixed features that make them all cases of contentious politics. These core features
include that they are “episodic,” “public,” and involve collective interaction between two
claimants at least one of which is a government (2001, p. 5). Contentious politics is in this way
defined using a logic of commonality, which allows political scientists to include or exclude
particular cases on the basis of whether or not they exhibit the core features. And while
McAdam, Tarrow, and Tilly express skepticism at the possibility of general laws, they
nevertheless preserve the naturalist hope that identifying the essential properties of political
contention will help them discover the recurring causal sequences behind political phenomena
(2001, pp. 345-346).
Take, for example, the criteria that all forms of political contention be episodic. True to
the logic of strong essentialism, this core feature is used by Tilly and company to exclude all
political phenomena that occurs with regularity. Thus, for instance, recurring actions like
elections, parliamentary debates, and associational meetings are all placed outside the bounds of
the concept of contentious political action. A similarly essentialist logic informs the criteria that
politically contentious politics be public. In this case, what is excluded are any actions occurring
inside “well-bounded organizations, including churches and firms” (McAdam, Tarrow, and Tilly,
16
2001, p. 5). And a similar point could be made about these political scientists’ criteria that all
contentious politics involve two claimants, at least one of which is a government.
Readers may have already guessed the anti-naturalist reasons for rejecting the strong
essentialism upon which the study of contentious politics rests. Because anti-naturalists believe
that actions are expressive of historically specific webs of belief, they are unlikely to accept a
supposedly universal class of action like that of political contention that transcends historical and
cultural meanings. Indeed, they would note that the attempt to posit such a universal class of
action only comes at the expense of neglecting the historically contextual meanings that inform
human beliefs. For anti-naturalists hold that human actions are expressive of contingent contexts
of meaning, and therefore are not the product of some nucleus of essential features. Thus, once
again, we arrive at the fundamental conceptual incompatibility between naturalist and antinaturalist approaches.
Of course, political scientists of a naturalist persuasion might still respond to the above
line of criticism by adopting a weak instead of strong form of essentialism. Indeed, weak
essentialism in political science often reflects the attempt to rectify the excesses of strongly
essentialism by allowing for variations of degree in terms of how present core features are in
particular empirical cases (e.g., Collier and Mahon, 1993). So where strong essentialism
struggles to account for the sheer nuance and complexity of political reality, weak essentialism
attempts to allow for greater flexibility while still retaining the basic essentialist premise that
human political life exhibits certain core features.
Weak essentialism plays a central role in what is considered by many to be among the
most solid scientific findings of modern political science—namely, democratic peace theory.
17
Democratic peace theory centers on the claim that two democratic regimes are dramatically less
likely to wage war on one another than other pairs of regimes. In a highly influential article, the
political scientists Bruce Russett and Zeev Maoz defended this thesis first by defining
democratic versus authoritarian regimes using weak essentialist concepts. Specifically, Russett
and Maoz adopted a numeric scale to create a continuum of how democratic versus authoritarian
a given regime might be in reality. On the basis of certain core criteria, like competitiveness of
political participation and constraints on the chief executive, Russett and Maoz devised a scoring
system in which minus 100 represented the most authoritarian regime and plus 100 the most
democratic (with plus 30 marking the lower threshold for classing regimes as democratic, and
minus 25 the upper threshold for marking them as authoritarian). As Russett and Maoz put it,
such a scale allowed that in empirical reality “a state can have mixed characteristics” where
“some features may be democratic at the same time that others are highly autocratic” (1993, p.
628). Yet the concepts of democratic and authoritarian regimes were also essentialist in that they
were defined by core features considered to migrate from context to context—an approach
Russett has since repeated (Russett and Oneal, 2001, p. 45). In short, the numeric scale allowed
for the complexity and nuance of actual empirical cases without giving up on the basic
essentialist logic.
Yet it is precisely the retention of this logic that renders weak essentialism vulnerable to
the same anti-naturalist line of critique. Namely, anti-naturalists would argue that once again
what drops out of weak essentialism is the particularity of historical context. But, anti-naturalists
would note, democracy and authoritarianism are not natural types with a recurring nuclei of
features. Rather, both democracy and authoritarianism are the result of historically contingent
meanings expressed in the beliefs, actions, and practices of particular societies. In this way,
18
political regimes are historically specific forms of meaning and not natural types. Interpreting the
meanings of particular regimes is thus much closer to studying literary or legal texts than to, say,
breaking down complex chemicals into the periodic table of elements.
The anti-naturalist critique of both reification and essentialism brings us to a further
question. Namely, what exactly are the anti-naturalist alternatives to concept formation? For
while we have seen that anti-naturalists believe explanation in the social sciences requires
narratives, it still isn’t clear what sorts of concepts such a narrative approach to the study of
politics implies. As we will now show, anti-naturalists are not entirely of one mind when it
comes to concept formation. We will conclude by surveying the two most important
philosophical schools of anti-naturalist thought.
3. Varieties of Anti-naturalism
Varieties of anti-naturalism share a rejection of naturalist concepts as reified and
essentialist. Likewise, they share certain philosophical affinities—such as holism and
contextualism—that lead them to deny the naturalist quest for causal laws built on atomistic units
of political reality. In this regard, there is considerable philosophical agreement among varieties
of anti-naturalism, which comprise their basic break from naturalism. However, these similarities
withstanding, important divisions nevertheless exist within the anti-naturalist response to the
naturalist challenge.
We will survey two particularly influential schools of anti-naturalist thought: poststructuralism and hermeneutics. Post-structuralism is part of a wider, post-modern turn which
19
encompasses theorists as diverse as Jacques Derrida, Jean-François Lyotard, and Jacques Lacan.
The sheer heterogeneity of this school means that we will have a better shot of understanding if
we restrict ourselves to one particularly influential strain. Foucault is probably the most
impressive and influential advocate of post-structuralism to date. As we shall see, Foucault’s
post-structural concepts are marked by hostility towards the human subject as well as quasistructural modes of explanation. By contrast, hermeneutics not only rejects Foucault’s poststructuralism, but also advances rival concepts that are more humanistic and historicist. Modern
defenders of hermeneutics have included Heidegger, Gadamer, and Paul Ricoeur. But we will
draw on the work of Taylor in particular, whose influence on these debates has grown
significantly in recent years. Picking the state of the art in these debates is especially important
because early varieties of phenomenology were not always free of naturalist commitments (e.g.,
Schutz, 1962).
i. Post-Structuralism
Post-structuralism is marked by hostility to the human subject. This hostility is clearly
evident, for example, in many of Foucault’s central concepts, which deemphasize the power of
individual agency. For instance, during his archaeological period, Foucault often argued that
individual human beliefs and actions were determined by fixed structures of meaning called
discourses or epistemes. As Foucault described it, the rules structuring a discourse or episteme
did not operate “in the mind or consciousness of individuals, but in discourse itself,” limiting “all
individuals who undertake to speak in this discursive field” (1972, p. 63). According to Foucault
this meant social science explanations should focus neither on “an individual, nor … some kind
20
of collective consciousness,” but on “an anonymous field whose configuration defines the
possible position of speaking subjects” (1972, p. 122). In other words, the concepts of discourse
and episteme pointed towards a social science in which explanation consisted of synchronically
locating individual beliefs and actions within the appropriate structures of meaning.
Thus, unlike the law-like explanations of naturalists, Foucault instead evoked synchronic
structures of meaning that purported to determine belief and action within their field. In this way,
Foucault’s archaeological mode of explanation was both anti-humanist and neglectful of
historical context. It was anti-humanist because it sought to eliminate the role of creative,
deliberative agents in favor of the power of impersonal quasi-structures. It was neglectful of
historical context because rather than attending to the particular webs of belief informing an
individual’s actions, Foucault posited frameworks of meaning that transcended the particularities
of individual beliefs.
The latter critique, in any case, was what drove the rejection of post-structuralism by
hermeneutic thinkers like Taylor. Taylor noted that the reduction of individual beliefs and
actions to concepts like discourse, episteme, or regime of power rendered actual historical
change very difficult to explain. Was Foucault suggesting that the disembodied discourses
themselves exhibited a kind of agency? That is, did post-structuralists believe epistemes and
discourses actually changed and evolved historically, independent of the actual individuals
involved? If so, Taylor argued, it was not at all clear how such an impersonal “purposefulness
without purpose” worked (1985a, pp. 169-170).
For his part, Foucault tried to account for this type of hermeneutic criticism by arguing
that discourses, epistemes, and regimes of power, were all characterized by their own kinds of
21
volatility and open-endedness. So he wrote that within a given regime of power there was
constant “tension” and “activity” such that a regime was never fully fixed or realized (Foucault,
1975, pp. 26-27). But unfortunately this response remained vulnerable to Taylor’s objections.
For even if one allowed that the concepts of discourse, episteme, and regime of power are
inherently volatile, this does not resolve what sort of agency such entities have apart from that
introduced by individuals. Indeed, in the final years of his life, Foucault himself appeared to
increasingly appreciate the importance of this criticism and the need for some role for human
agency in the study of social and political life (Foucault, 1983, p. 225).
Post-structuralism therefore faces the dilemma that it must adopt a more humanistic view
of agency if it is to explain historical change. Yet the latter would also require that it drop or
significantly remake its distinctive conceptual vocabulary of discourses, epistemes, and regimes
of power. That is, resolving this dilemma might mean abandoning some of the more original
elements of the post-structural project. Regardless of how post-structuralists respond to this
problem going forward, an alternative that allows for individual human agency is presently
offered by hermeneutics.
ii. Hermeneutics
Hermeneutics conceives of humans as the creative source of the beliefs, actions, and
practices that comprise political reality. Taylor (1985c), for instance, has argued that human
beings are “self-interpreting animals” able to creatively articulate, modify, and change their
beliefs. The fact that humans are self-interpreting means they cannot be reduced to explanation
22
by impersonal laws or quasi-structures. But neither does it mean that individuals are entirely
autonomous when it comes to belief and action. Rather, hermeneutic theorists insist that
individuals exhibit a kind of situated agency, in which they retain creative capacities while
nevertheless existing against the backdrop of some tradition of inherited beliefs and practices.
Thus the concept of tradition (unlike post-structural notions of episteme or power) allows for
individual agency without denying the active role of a larger social inheritance (Gadamer, 1960,
II.1; Taylor, 2011, p. 34).
According to hermeneutic theorists, political scientists can explain individual beliefs and
actions by referring both to traditions and the ability of agents to reason creatively in light of
dilemmas. Traditions can be used by students of politics to explain continuities in belief and
practice. So, political scientists might explain the beliefs and actions of individuals by arguing
that they inherited them from a particular tradition. Dilemmas, by contrast, can help explain
changes in belief. Because humans hold beliefs for particular reasons, those beliefs can change
whenever the supporting beliefs are invalidated or in some other way challenged. Dilemmas, in
this regard, are any beliefs that create pressure on an existing web of beliefs. Political scientists
can thus employ dilemmas and traditions in tandem to explain how individuals creatively
respond within a world of shared meanings, beliefs, and practices.
It is important to add that the concepts of dilemma and tradition do not commit
hermeneutic theorists to the view that all actions and beliefs are rational or must be taken at face
value. To the contrary, according to Taylor, hermeneutic explanation is by its very nature critical
as “there can’t be explanation without a judgment of truth or validity” (Taylor, 1995, p. 153).
The reason for this is that if an agent offers reasons for acting that appear deluded or otherwise
23
distorted, then a hermeneutic theorist must search for an alternative explanation for that agent’s
actions. Such alternative explanations might include evoking pathologies (e.g., disease or injury)
but it might also require identifying cases of repression or self-deception. Hermeneutic theorists
conceptualize such acts of self-deception in terms of unacknowledged or hidden motives. Such a
hidden motive might consist of any repressed belief, desire, or need that leads an individual to
form a web of inauthentic or rationalizing beliefs (e.g., Taylor, 1985d, pp. 4-6). A brief example
will help illustrate how this works from a hermeneutic perspective.
Consider the case of Nazi, “Aryan physics,” which was advanced by otherwise worldclass physicists like Philipp Lenard and Johannes Stark. Presumably some distortion of rational
belief was going on in this case. Most likely, the development of Aryan physics by these two
famous scientists was driven by an irrational unwillingness to accept the contributions of Jewish
physicists like Einstein. So, where Lenard and Stark might have thought Aryan physics was
simply another way of saying “good” or “proper” physics, a hermeneutic student of politics
might argue that their beliefs and actions are instead explained by an irrational form of
ideological distortion.
Hermeneutics thus appears to offer an approach to the study of politics that is equally
humanistic and critical. And yet this school of thought is often criticized for being unable to
move beyond small-scale analysis of individual beliefs in order to explain politics at a general
level (Box-Steffensmeier, Brady, and Collier, 2008). However, this latter criticism represents a
basic misunderstanding of the hermeneutic position. For as we noted above (in part one), antinaturalist approaches are not tied to any one level of analysis. Taylor (2007), for one, has used a
hermeneutic approach to offer an account of political life at the most general level—narrating
24
nothing less than the civilizational shift toward secularism in the modern era. Thus it would
appear that in addition to being humanistic and critical, hermeneutic approaches are not limited
to small-scale research.
There is, in this sense, a certain playfulness in hermeneutic approaches. For, unlike
naturalists, hermeneutic theorists need not privilege a single level of description. Rather, because
they believe there are multiple true ways of describing human actions, hermeneutic students of
politics don’t have to treat political reality as though it were reducible to a single level of truly
scientific description (Davidson, 2006, pp. 24-25). This, of course, runs against the tendency we
observed in naturalist political scientists like Tilly and Russett. For where the latter presuppose
some privileged, essential core to, say, a politics of contention or democratic peace,
hermeneutics insists that researchers can instead pragmatically choose their level of description
given the wider purposes of their project.
In short, hermeneutic theorists believe there are multiple true stories that can be told
about political reality, not just one scientifically official account. This means the hermeneutic
study of politics, like the analysis of a literary or legal text, can legitimately take on various
forms depending on the purposes of the interpreter. This once again returns us to some of the
fundamental differences between hermeneutics and the naturalist presuppositions informing
much of political science. For, the entire logic of naturalism presses towards the discovery of a
universal, invariant language of explanation, while hermeneutics seeks historically contingent
stories.
25
Conclusion
We have tried to show how the basic ruptures between naturalism and anti-naturalism are
philosophical and not methodological. One such rupture can be seen in the naturalist tendency to
treat methods as logics of discovery versus the anti-naturalist preference for treating methods as
the techniques of a craft. Another set of ruptures is evident in naturalism’s inclination towards
atomism and causal explanations versus anti-naturalism’s championing of holism and narrative
explanations.
We also saw that fundamental differences of philosophy are what fuel the anti-naturalist
critique and rejection of naturalist concepts in political science. So, anti-naturalists draw on their
philosophical assumptions in order to argue that naturalist political science is distorted by
reification and essentialism. In place of naturalism, anti-naturalists have offered a number of
philosophic alternatives. Two of the most important are post-structuralism and hermeneutics.
Post-structuralism advocates an anti-humanist conception of political science, while
hermeneutics favors a humanistic vision of the study of political life. Both reject naturalism.
Because the conflict between naturalism and anti-naturalism is ultimately about
philosophy and not methods, methodological pluralism can and should reign within political
science research. None of this serves to keep the peace between these two battling factions. For
in the naturalism/anti-naturalism debate the price of suing for a false peace is conceptual
confusion and muddle—and the latter, whatever the outcome of future exchanges, is something
no side should desire.
26
Reference list
Almond, G. and Verba, S. (1965) The Civic Culture. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.
Ayer, A. (1952) Language, Truth, and Logic, 2nd edn. New York: Dover Publications.
Box-Steffensmeier, J., Brady, H., and Collier, D. (2008) ‘Political Science Methodology’, in
Box-Steffensmeier, J., Brady, H., and Collier, D. (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Political
Methodology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 3-34.
Carnap, R., Hahn, H., and Neurath, O. (1929) ‘Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener
Kreis’, in Sarkear, S. (ed.) The Emergence of Logical Empiricism. Reprint, New York: Garland
Publishing, 1996, pp. 321-340.
Chih Lin, A. (1998) ‘Bridging Positivist and Interpretivist Approaches to Qualitative Methods’,
Policy Studies Journal 21:1, pp. 162-180.
Collier, D. and Mahon, J. (1993) ‘Conceptual “Stretching” Revisited: Adapting Categories in
Comparative Analysis’, American Political Science Review 87(4), pp. 845-855.
Collingwood, R. (1946) The Idea of History. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davidson, D. (2006) ‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes’, in Lepore, E. and Ludwig, K. (eds) The
Essential Davidson. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 23-36.
Dilthey, W. (1976) Selected Writings. Translated by H.P. Rickman. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Feitlowitz, M. (1998) A Lexicon of Terror: Argentina and the Legacies of Torture. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Foucault, M. (1983) ‘The Subject and Power’, in Dreyfus, H. and Rabinow, P. (eds.) Michel
Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2nd edn. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, pp. 208-226.
Foucault, M. (1975) Discipline and Punish. Translated by Alan Sheridan. Reprint, New York:
Vintage Books, 1995.
Foucault, M. (1972) The Archaeology of Knowledge. Translated by A. M. Sheridan Smith.
Reprint, New York: Vintage Books, 2010.
Gadamer, H. (1960) Truth and Method. Translated by Joel Weinscheimer and Donald G.
Marshall. Reprint, New York: Continuum, 2004.
Geertz, C. (1973) The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books.
27
Gerring, J. (2001) Social Science Methodology: A Criterial Framework. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Gerring, J. (2011) Social Science Methodology: A Unified Framework, 2nd edn. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Goertz, G. and Mahoney, J. (2012) A Tale of Two Cultures: Qualitative and Quantitative
Research in the Social Sciences. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Goodin, R. (2009) ‘The State of the Discipline, the Discipline of the State’, in Goodin R (ed.)
Oxford Handbook of Political Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gunnell, J. (1975) Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry. New Jersey: General Learning
Press.
Heidegger, M. (1953) Being and Time. Translated by Joan Stambaugh. Reprint, Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1996.
Hempel, C. and Oppenheim, P. (1948) ‘Studies in the Logic of Explanation’, Philosophy of
Science 15, pp. 135-175.
Hempel, C. (1965) ‘The Function of General Laws in History’, in Aspects of Scientific
Explanation. New York: The Free Press, pp. 231-243.
Husserl, E. (1936) ‘Vienna Lecture’ and ‘The Attitude of Natural Science and the Attitude of
Humanistic Science’, in Carr, D. (ed.) The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental
Phenomenology. Reprint, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1970, pp. 269-300, 315334.
Kernell, S., Jacobson, G., and Kousser, T. (eds.) (2011) The Logic of American Politics, 5th edn.
Washington, DC: CQ Press.
McAdam, D., Tarrow, S., and Tilly, C. (2001) Dynamics of Contention. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
MacIntyre, A. (1964) ‘A Mistake About Causality in Social Science’, in Laslett, P. and
Runciman, W.G. (eds.) Philosophy, Politics and Society. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 48-70.
MacIntyre, A. (1978) ‘Is a Science of Comparative Politics Possible?’, in Against the Self Images
of the Age. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 260-279.
MacIntyre, A. (2007) After Virtue, 3rd edn. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Maoz, Z. and Russett, B. (1993) ‘Normative and Structural Causes of Democratic Peace, 19461986’, American Political Science Review 87(3), pp. 624-638.
28
Marx, K. (1859) ‘Preface to A Critique of Political Economy’, in McLellan, D. (ed.) Karl Marx:
Selected Writings. Reprint, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977, pp. 388-391.
Neurath, O. (1931) ‘Physicalism: The Philosophy of the Viennese Circle’, in Cohen, R. and
Neurath, M. (eds) Philosophical Papers: 1913-1946. Reprint, Boston: D. Reidel Publishing
Company, 1983, pp. 52-57.
Ricoeur, P. (1983-1985) Time and Narrative, 3 vols. Translated by Kathleen McLaughlin and
David Pellauer. Reprint, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984-1988.
Rosenstone, S. and Hansen, J. (1993) Mobilization, Participation, and Democracy in America.
New York: Macmillan.
Russett, B. and Oneal, J. (2001) Triangulating Peace. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Sartori, G. (ed.) (1984) Social Science Concepts: A Systematic Analysis. Beverly Hills, CA:
Sage.
Schutz, A. (1962) ‘Concept and Theory Formation in the Social Sciences’, in Emmet, D. and
MacIntyre, A. (eds) Sociological Theory and Philosophical Analysis. Reprint, New York:
Macmillan Company, 1970, pp. 1-19.
Taylor, C. (1985a) ‘Foucault on Freedom and Truth’ in Philosophy and the Human Sciences:
Philosophical Papers 2. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 152-184.
Taylor, C. (1985b) ‘Interpretation and the Sciences of Man’, in Philosophy and the Human
Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 15-57.
Taylor, C. (1985c) ‘Self-Interpreting Animals’, in Human Agency and Language: Philosophical
Papers 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 45-76.
Taylor, C. (1985d) ‘Introduction’, in Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers 1.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1-12.
Taylor, C. (1995) ‘Comparison, History, Truth’, in Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, pp. 146-164.
Taylor, C. (2007) A Secular Age. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University.
Taylor, C. (2011) ‘Understanding the Other: A Gadamerian View on Conceptual Schemes’, in
Dilemmas and Connections. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, pp.
24-38.
Winch, P. (1958) The Idea of a Social Science. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
29