Choice Reviews Online
7/16/10 11:16 AM
Print
Full text
1.
45-4685
BF311
2006-5937 CIP
Social & Behavioral Sciences \ Psychology
Spivey, Michael. The continuity of mind. Oxford, 2007. 428p bibl index afp (Oxford psychology
series, 40) ISBN 0-19-517078-4, $69.95; ISBN 9780195170788, $69.95. Outstanding Title! Reviewed
in 2008apr CHOICE.
In this fascinating book, Spivey (Cornell Univ.) challenges the long-standing practice of focusing on
behavior as a sequence of perception, cognition, and action based on discrete stimulus-response events.
Instead, he argues for the continuity of "mental trajectories" and presents a theoretical, methodological,
and empirical overview of the flow of thought and action. In wonderful, lucid prose, Spivey presents the
conceptual tools for tracking cognitive processing and examines the temporal dynamics of
categorization, language comprehension, visual perception, action, and reasoning. The book is scholarly
(the bibliography spans 65-page and includes nearly 1,300 references) and demanding, but well worth
the effort. An invaluable resource for those interested in psychology, cognitive neuroscience, computer
science, philosophy, and related fields, this volume will serve both the present and the next generation
of cognitive scientists. Summing Up: Essential. Upper-division undergraduates, graduate students, and
researchers. -- G. B. Rollman, University of Western Ontario
© American Library Association. Contact
permissions@ala-choice.org for permission to
reproduce or redistribute.
http://www.cro2.org/printcontent.aspx
Page 1 of 1
8 of 8 people found the following review helpful:
Deep, great, diverse book, September 25, 2008
B
y psych reader
This review is from: The Continuity of Mind (Oxford Psychology)
(Paperback)
M. Spivey presents some deep material. The book is just filled
with evidence for a very core idea: Our understanding of the
mind should be based on continuous functions, and not on the
choppy file-copy concepts of a computer system (like the kind
I'm typing this on). The book taps into areas that span much of
what would satisfy very diverse interests: perception, language,
problem solving, consciousness, with neuroscience stuff
everywhere. And for any geeks, he supplies programming code
at the back of this book for you to run some of the theoretical
model systems he uses to demonstrate continuous theories. In
short, the book is deep and interesting and will entertain and
interest anyone interested in understanding the mind.
4 of 4 people found the following review helpful:
5.0 out of 5 stars
A New Psychology, October 3, 2009
B
y J. B. - See all my reviews
This review is from: The Continuity of Mind (Oxford Psychology)
(Paperback)
Ever since Jerry Fodor published the widely influential book The
Modularity of Mind in the 1980s, continuing from the cognitive
revolution in the 1950s and 1960s, the idea that the mind works
like a massively modular information processing system (namely,
a computer) has been extremely popular. More recently, popular
psychologists such as Steven Pinker have endorsed an easily
understood and largely popular computational theory of the way
that the mind works, which implicitly assumes tricky philosophies
such as the internalist view of the mind, and also is implicitly
assumed by evolutionary psychology, a largely nativist way of
looking at the way the mind has developed.
In The Continuity of Mind, Michael Spivey introduces what is
probably the most convincing account so far that the mind works
an entirely different way. He proposed, as others have before
him, that the mind is a continuous dynamical system embodied
in its environment, with perception and action being blurred in a
continuous cascade of "hungry" mental operations and actions.
It's easy to see that this view is much more complicated than the
straightforward modular account, but Spivey introduces the
mathematics and the nitty-gritty aspects of this fascinating
theory easily and without tripping over himself too much. He
argues for this embodied dynamical view of cognition with
convincing evidence from fields such as visual perception and
language, and finishes with hopeful hints that similarly
convincing evidence will soon emerge in fields such as reasoning
and decision making. The final two chapters on the book lay out
the implications that this new and exciting view of the mind has
for philosophy of mind at large, touching on concepts of free will,
consciousness, and government.
Spivey is eloquent and witty, and asserts his arguments with
respect for the history that he is building upon. Since this book
has come out, research has pointed to this embodied continuous
dynamical system view of the mind fitting in quite well with social
perception and decision making, and slowly people are beginning
to realize that this dynamical systems account of cognition isn't
quite as complicated and unintuitive as it has long been believed
to be. In fact, one of Spivey's most convincing arguments is that
this view of cognition is really much more valid
neurophysiologically than its modular counterpart. Many people
have argued for this view of cognition before, but Spivey's
execution is absolutely perfect and I have no doubt that this book
will be the centerpiece for a new study of how the mind works.!
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Nonlinear Dynamics, Psychology, and Life Sciences, Vol. 13, No. 1, pp. 151-154.
© 2009 Society for Chaos Theory in Psychology & Life Sciences
Book Review
The continuity of mind, by Michael Spivey. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2007. 427pp. ISBN 13: 978-0-19-517078-8.
Kudos to Spivey—the self-proclaimed “zombie scientist” -- for helping
stimulate the paradigmatic change needed in cognitive science. Spivey
forcefully argues: for the field to progress, cognitive researchers need to
acknowledge the wide-range of evidence for the continuous nature of mind, and
embrace a hybrid approach consisting of Nonlinear Dynamical Systems (NDS),
neural network (NN), ecological, and “embodied” perspectives.
Within each, numerous models may be used to describe changing
behaviors and cognitive states. Spivey narrows the possibilities by first,
providing an overview of tools for tracking mental trajectories, and breaks these
down (in Chapters 2, 3 and 4) into: conceptual, experimental, and simulation
categories. Spivey then spends much of the book focusing on: (a) the NDS state
space (i.e., attractor space) description of mental trajectories while carefully
stepping readers through various ways to visualize these trajectories, and (b) a
simple recurrence net (SRN) model, and how it captures key properties of
behavior.
Major themes of the book also include strong arguments against
cognitive modularity (Chapter 5), and the need for cognitive research focused on
temporal dynamics such as the many cited examples including work in:
categorization, language comprehension, visual perception, action, and
reasoning (Chapter 6). Later chapters include a unifying account of different
aspects of cognition, and a final swipe at modularity theories of cognition. In the
last chapter, Spivey entertains philosophical implications for consciousness, and
his self-identification with “zombie” agents.
Spivey”s focus on one version of recurrence analysis (SRN) has both
strengths and weaknesses. The strength is in its simplicity and thus accessibility
to wide audience. Two weakness: First, its short shrift given to the many other
very useful NDS tools that can be used to uncover the dynamical structure of
cognition. A future revision of this book might include a description of more
NDS tools, or at least provide an informed rationale for why one would choose
one approach over another. Pertinent here are considerations of dimensionality,
and why some NDS researchers focus on low dimensional, prominent features
of behavior (without attempting a link to biology) versus those choosing to study
high dimensional behavior through systematic study of subtle patterns of
behavioral variability (with the implicit acknowledgement of biological
151
152
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
NDPLS, 13(2), Aks
complexity underlying emergence of cognition). Many NN models, for example,
are better suited to high dimensional analysis by capturing complex interactions
and emergent dynamics resembling those of the brain system. Spivey briefly
notes importance of NN models, along with possible generating rules such as
predator-prey search examples (p. 321). Further discussion of resulting scaling
and power law behaviors would be very helpful along with the role they play in
cognitive and other behaviors.
A second weakness of SRN is in its key characteristic as a normalized
“local” network, having features subject to similar criticism to which Spivey
launches against mainstream cognitive science. SRN’s use of local averaging
across vectors ignores a key attribute of the human brain: its distributed
structure. Similarly, modification of synaptic weights “by hand” is a far cry from
(Spivey”s claim for) self-organization. Whether studying key dimensions of
overt behavior or the underlying complex system, common goal is to learn
whether essential dynamical structure emerges spontaneously from iteration of
these simple rules in a network of activated nodes.
Spivey might also consider: (a) The relation between SRN and other
low dimension descriptions of behavior such as simple differential equation
(e.g., logistic equation as in Ward and West (1998), or harmonic oscillator as in
Warren (2006). And (b) instead of collapsing to minimal-value functions in SRN
approach, the same resulting behavior, along with its pattern of variations, can
be described in terms of even simpler equations iterated over time to capture
interactive dynamics of brain’s neural populations (e.g., cellular automata or
self-organized criticality). The latter approach deliberately takes on the link
between brain and behavior, and the fact that it is a complex system.
Spivey defers to other sources on some of these issues (i.e., Ward,
2002), and to his credit, covers a vast array of research from the Cognitive
literature to show support for continuous nature of mind and how it is “situated”
(i.e., mediated) by both body and environment. Making the additional link to
NDS is what makes Spivey’s work unique, and arguably its greatest strength
aside from the excellent review of cognitive behaviors best described as
embodied and continuous.
My greatest reservation of the book is that its emphasis on continuity of
mind is overstated. The book’s objective may have been better served by placing
NDS or embodied cognition at the forefront. One apparent contradiction with
the continuity thesis may be found in Spivey’s occasional reference to process of
achieving stable mental states. These can easily be regarded as discrete states of
perception and cognition. Thus, when describing mind as a trajectory— both
continuous and discrete properties exist and can be accounted for in NDS
framework. In fact, building a case for NDS theory of mind would be expected
to include stable and unstable states as well as description of transitions brought
on by changes in control parameters. Shelhamer (2006) is a pertinent source, (an
unfortunate omission from Spivey”s book) illustrating excellent examples of
transitional states in eye-movement and other behaviors. To his credit, Spivey
acknowledges he may have overemphasized “continuous” nature of mind (p.
NDPLS, 13(1), Book Review
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
153
322), but does so as “to help pry loose [entrenched] assumptions of stable
representation.”
In addition to NDS theory of mind not requiring that mind be
continuous, it does not eliminate the need for functional-symbolic based
understanding of how the mind works. In contrast to conventional stage-based
theories of cognition and presumed linear (feed forward) sequence, research
now convincingly shows that graded transitions, feedback, and recurrence are
essential to high level cognition. Spivey describes this in a section on recurrence
and “warping” probabilities where members of population code pass activity
back and forth changing percent of activity until one set exceeds a threshold and
a decision (response) is made.
Similarly, symbol-based theories of cognition rely on improved
understanding of such transitional states. Spivey, however, trivializes this point
with his insistence on the continuity of mental states, and how discretization of
these states is either an illusory or artificial imposition. This focus on continuity
(mis)leads him to note that symbolic dynamics (SD) “may sound like an
oxymoron” (p. 112), but then counters this by (correctly) pointing out legitimate
SD approaches which implement symbols by neuronal assemblies. (Chapter 10
presents SD models from cognitive science such as Anderson’s ACT-R theory,
and Complex Systems such as Crutchfield’s deterministic model). Spivey insists
though that mental representations are not likely to resemble (or be converted) to
rule-based logic. However, this is exactly what might emerge from transitions
across different attractor states. Since symbols can be assigned and emitted by
different transitional states in a dynamical system this is likely a lucrative path
to our understanding of symbolic-rule characteristic of cognition.
Noteworthy are the entertaining linguistic gems sprinkled throughout
the book, These are quite revealing of Spivey’s expertise in cognitive linguistics
and his effort to “lay siege to the ivory tower of consciousness” and assert that
“everywhere that free will goes, it scorches the theoretical terrain.” One is left
wondering whether the “functionalist view of mind teeters on edge of Cartesian
dualism,” and is this in fact “Veja Du-alism all over again?” Many of these
perceptual-cognitive “lines in the sand” might be dissolved by seeing that
mental trajectories sometimes just “flirt with attractors…,” but do not reach
conscious reportability. At other times, “attractors warp into repellors”
permitting trajectory to continue on to new concepts.”
Overall, in his grand challenge to the “pandemic of homunculitis
ideas,” Spivey clearly and boldly expresses his ideas in a manner cognitive
psychologists can understand without getting bogged down in mathematics. No
doubt, impediments of inaccessibility arise from “modular” and “encapsulated”
nature of different disciplines, with their unique jargon and tools. Spivey’s
informal and “grounded” literary style—imbued with lots of clever metaphors
makes for an enjoyable read even if you disagree with the premise of his ideas.
Many are thought provoking and among these I am left pondering: Must one
really be a modularist to believe in free will? Or is the true state of our mentalbeing closest to that of a zombie?
154
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
NDPLS, 13(2), Aks
REFERENCES
Shelhamer, M. (2007). Nonlinear dynamics in physiology: A state-space
approach. Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific.
Warren, W. (2006). Dynamics of perception and action. Psychological Review,
113, 358-389.
Ward, L. M. (2002). Dynamical cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Ward, L. M., & West, R. L. (1998). Modeling human chaotic behavior:
Nonlinear forecasting analysis of logistic iteration. Nonlinear
Dynamics, Psychology, and Life Science, 3, 261-282.
-- Deborah J. Aks
Rutgers University
Center for Cognitive Science (RuCCS)
Psychology Bld. Annex
152 Frelinghuysen Road
Piscataway, NJ 08854-8020
Book Reviews
Michael Spivey
The Continuity of Mind
Oxford University Press. 2006. 448 pp. £43.00
ISBN 978-0195170788 (hbk)
Reviewed by Igor Aleksander
It used to be said that engineers either think in terms of ‘state spaces’
or they don’t. Those who do make aeroplanes fly and those who don’t,
sell them. In The Continuity of Mind psychologist Michael Spivey
argues that some such division now applies to those who attempt to
understand mind and brain. Either they embrace state spaces to study
the structure of mind or they remain bereft of an analytic understanding of their subject.
So what is state space and why does it suggest that there is something continuous about the mind? The words ‘mental state’ appear
often enough in psychological literature and folk psychology. It gets
assumed that a particular ‘thought’ is an experienced state as produced
by a state of the machinery of the brain (for example, the collection of
firing rates of neurons or the distribution of secretion of neurotransmitters in the brain). For Spivey, such states of mind, clearly
packaged in time as thoughts, do not exist. The machinery of the brain
just never stands still for long enough for an identifiable experience to
emerge. We may also be misled in thinking of pure states of mind
(such as the memory of that great sunset last night) because cognitive
scientists use the computer metaphor as a model of the relationship of
mind to body (as software to hardware). Computers jerk from state to
state as controlled by a master clock. So at any point in time the computer can be said to be in a briefly unchanging state both in term of its
hardware and its singular point in the execution of a program.
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14, No. 8, 2007, pp. 117–29
Copyright
(c) Imprint Academic 2005
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
118
BOOK REVIEWS
While nowadays this computer model of mind is pretty well dead
(simply due to the non-programmed emergent properties of the brain),
Spivey adds another twist to the killing process: there are no singular
states due to the continuously changing billions of parameters. Like
the flow of particles of lava down the side of a volcano, there is not
much point in looking for step-by-step processes, continuous analysis
is needed. The unsynchronised nature of the brain does not sustain the
notion of pure states of mind: whatever mind is, it has the nature of a
continuous flow rather than a sequence of beautifully formed states.
As an aside, did William James not make this point with the stream of
consciousness? Strangely, James does not feature in this book — but
he was not mathematically inclined, whereas Spivey is.
To unpack what Spivey suggests, we do need to understand some of
the state space analyses of dynamical systems of aeroplane designers.
Taking just the neurons in the brain - all 11 billion of them - and forgetting the little problem of how these contribute to conscious experience (a question Spivey accepts but does not address), we think of
each of these as having their own state of firing or intensity of firing.
In technical terms the neurons are the state variables of the brain and
(maybe indirectly) of the mind as the movement of the lava particles
are the state variables of the lava flow. Let’s take a toy problem: a system of only three neurons that can fire at a rate of anything between 0
and 10 (arbitrary units). We can visualise a 3-axis plot, one for the firing rate of each neuron. Then whatever is the instantaneous rate of
each, the state of the system can be plotted as a single point on this 3-D
graph. As the rate of the neurons changes, the point will move about in
this space. The space is a state space and the route taken by the point is
a state trajectory. One cannot visualise a plot for the brain with its billions of neurons, but the principles are the same. The total instantaneous firing of all the neurons is a point in a space with a vast number
of dimensions (unimaginable by ordinary mortals who would want to
visualise it, but never a problem for mathematicians who treat the
space as being abstract with no need to visualise it). Clearly in this
space there are state trajectories, that is, signatures of brain activity.
To translate this into mental experience requires the same arguments as used by those who refer to a ‘mental state’ as both experienced thought and its brain machinery support. Often, in dynamic
explanations, a ‘concept’ like the memory of Mother’s face is an
attractor in the state space. That is, state spaces can have areas which
are entered and not exited until a distractor input occurs and some
other attractor is entered. In Spivey’s scheme, state trajectories do not
hop randomly from attractor to attractor but are continuously
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
BOOK REVIEWS
119
controlled by input. Instead of attractors he has trajectories going
through funnels. So the morning thought to have breakfast, catch a bus
and get to work would, for Spivey, be a trajectory through breakfast,
bus and work funnels rather than being trapped in attractors related to
the same meanings. Both attractors and funnels are a result of physical
neuron plasticity that stores experience.
While the bulk of the book is aimed at persuading the reader to
think in terms of continuous mental state trajectories, the philosophical consequences are considerable. For example, Fodor-like ‘modularity of mind’ is not favoured, as trajectories are continuously
wafting in and out of a succession of meanings funnels for the individual. Also, free will is out as trajectories cannot avoid being influenced
by the funnels in state space. This may seem like freedom because the
state structure of funnels and their effects are not part of one’s consciousness: only the trajectories are. Trajectories can explore alternatives so that it is possible to experience and verbalise a trajectory as ‘if
I do A, X will follow’ where X might have some unwanted connotation. Another part of the trajectory might lead to ‘if I do B, Y will follow’. Say that Y is a better outcome then the organism might take the
better action B. The astute reader will have rightly anticipated that
Spivey has state space models for ‘better’ and ‘unwanted’ to clinch the
argument against free will. This is not as theologically traumatic as it
sounds — more a case of mathematical ‘non-determinism’ where
trajectories can represent that both A or B are allowed within some
specific state structure.
In many ways this book is an initial shot across the bows of many
cognitive scientists to alert them that the language of state trajectories
might become a lingua franca in brain and mind studies. It has been
this for engineers in the last 50 years with much benefit. So it is as an
engineer that I have a slight technical quibble with the ‘continuity’
part of Spivey’s argument. State trajectories need not be continuous.
They can have jumps (sometimes, mathematically called catastrophes) when the state variables have non-smooth characteristics. And
neurons surely fall into this class, possibly explaining the ‘Aha’
phenomenon. But no matter! All in all I feel that the book should be
widely read among mind scientists bringing forward the day that the
mind can be spoken of in a unified way.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005
For personal use only -- not for reproduction