Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
Technoscience rent: Towards a theory of rentiership KEAN BIRCH Senior Associate, Innovation Policy Lab, University of Toronto, Canada Associate Professor, Department of Geography, York University, Canada keanbirch@gmail.com Abstract Increasingly, a range of ‘things’ (e.g. infrastructure, data, knowledge, bodies, etc.) are configured and/or reconfigured as assets, or capitalized property. Accumulation strategies have changed as a result of this assetization process, which characterizes a particular form of technoscientific capitalism. Rather than entrepreneurial strategies based on commodity production, technoscientific capitalism is increasingly underpinned by rentiership, or the appropriation of value through ownership rights (e.g. intellectual property), monopoly conditions, and regulatory or market devices and practices (e.g. investment dispute courts, exclusivity agreements, etc.). While rentiership and rent-seeking are often presented as negative phenomena (e.g. distorting markets, unearned income) in both neoclassical and Marxist literatures – and much in-between – it is my intention in this paper to unpack rentiership as an increasingly constitutive politicaleconomic process underpinning technoscientific capitalism. Rather than being framed as a problematic ‘side-effect’ of capitalism, I argue that rentiership can help us to understand how different forms of value extraction are constituted by and come to constitute different forms of technoscience. This has significant analytical, political, and normative implications for understanding the relationship between science, innovation, and business (e.g. how do rentier rationales configure research agendas, how does innovation enable rentiership, what are the consequences for social equity, etc.). Introduction ‘Economic rents’ are the value that can be extracted from economic activity – broadly conceived – as the result of the ownership and control of a particular resource, primarily because of that resource’s (inherent or constructed) degree of productivity, scarcity, or quality. As a concept, economic rent has been primarily associated with the ownership and control of land. In fact, its starting point as a concept is in the 18th and 19th centuries – with the work of people like Adam Smith, Thomas Malthus, and David Ricardo – was centred on land ownership; some scholars sought to defend this ownership (e.g. Malthus), while others sought to highlight its negative impact on capitalist accumulation (e.g. Ricardo). During the 20th century, however, economic rent theory has been increasingly applied to other resources – including natural resources like oil, financial resources like capital, and, of most import to this article, intangible resources like knowledge – and it has been generally aligned with government ‘interference’ in the naturalized workings of the economy. Although it is an analytical concept, in seeking to explain the value that accrues in and as the result of particular socio-economic relations, economic rent is also implicitly a normative concept in that it is used to critique (and, on rare occasions, defend) those same socio-economic relations – however, see William Baumol (1990) for a more nuanced perspective. It is, moreover, interesting to note that this normative (and analytical) critique crops up across the political spectrum, from left-wing Marxist thinkers through to right-wing free market advocates – even if they might disagree about what constitutes rent, in contrast to other production ‘costs’ like interest (for capital) or wages (for labour). Recently, it seems like economic rent, and its adjectival equivalent ‘rent-seeking’, has moved to the centre of public debate. A growing chorus of academics, politicians, journalists, activists, and commentators have been analysing contemporary capitalism – especially its technoscientific version – through the lens of economic rent and rent-seeking. I provide only a few relevant examples here, but will highlight more throughout the article to illustrate my arguments. From the pro-capitalist side, the journalist Robert Colville (2017) – who used to work for the Daily Telegraph and now edits the CapX website, which is based at the Centre for Policy Studies – argues that “the structure of capitalism is increasingly tending towards monopoly … [and] because of the network effects involved, this tendency is particularly pronounced in tech”. From the anti-capitalist side, the academic Guy Standing (2016) argues that “Plutocratic corporations are patent hoovers, buying thousands of patents. It is a winner-takes-all market created by the regulatory apparatus, not market forces”. Numerous others raise similar issues relevant to science and technology studies (STS), including the privatization and commercialization of basic research (Stiglitz, 2014), network externalities of information technology (Jacobs, 2015), business models of new technology platform companies (Kaminska, 2016), ownership and use of personal data (Morozov, 2016), financial technology innovation (Bregman, 2017), and even the corporate control over tractors and their repairs (Koebler, 2017). All in all, rent and rent-seeking offer a ripe ground for STS scholars to engage in and with contemporary political economy; in fact, we might have something unique to offer in this regards, considering our focus on science, technology, and innovation. In light of all this concern, my aims in writing this article are twofold. On the one hand, there has been limited analytical development of the concept of economic rent – outside incremental adjustments in the dominant approaches – over recent decades, and next to none in the STS literature, despite the increasing public debate around the capture of scientific and technological rents (see above). There are, as usual, exceptions when it comes to STS (e.g. Fuller, 2002, 2016; Cooper and Waldby, 2014; Birch, 2017a, 2017b, 2017c; McGoey, 2017). It is, these exceptions notwithstanding, an opportune time to address this gap in our analytical toolkit, and that is my primary aim in this article. On the other hand, the more general (and incremental) analytical developments that have occurred are frequently conceptually burdened by a normative critique of rent and rent-seeking – or, my preference, rentiership (Birch, 2017a, 2017b, 2017c) – across different and distinct theoretical and political viewpoints. It is, for example, notable that both Marxist and neoclassical economic perspectives of rentiership are built on some sort of idealized notion of an economic process or logic that is then ‘distorted’ by economic rents or rent-seeking. For example, for Marxists rentiership distorts the labour process (or value of labour), exemplified by the notion of ‘unearned income’ (Sayer, 2015), while for neoclassical economists rentiership distorts ‘the market’ through government interference in the market’s naturalized functions and functionality (Congleton and Hillman, 2015). There is, in my view, room to develop the concept of rentiership in ways that go beyond these approaches, while necessarily building upon their insights and acknowledging their contributions. In order to address the above aims, I start the article with a discussion of the intellectual history of economic rent, going back to David Ricardo in the 19th century and working my way forward from there. This brief review, and unfortunately that is all it can be, provides an introduction to the key analytical approaches to thinking about rent and rent-seeking in order to pave the way for a more focused section on the specific relevance of rent to discussions of science, technology, and innovation in the field of STS. After that second section, I then seek to develop a theory of rentiership as a way to conceptualize it as a political-economic process specifically relevant for understanding modern, technoscientific capitalism. I end the paper by considering the theoretical, political, and normative implications that this reworking of economic rent has in relation to technoscientific research, development, and innovation. All told, my goal is for this article to contribute to the ongoing resurgence of interest in STS circles in issues around the changing political economy of research and innovation (e.g. Mirowski, 2011; Tyfield, 2012; Birch, 2013, 2017d; Hackett, 2014; Goven and Pavone, 2015; Tyfield et al., 2017). An Intellectual History of Economic Rent Economic rent is an analytical concept; it does not refer to the economic practices of ‘renting’ or ‘leasing’ resources or property. For example, Anne Haila (1990: 277) makes a useful distinction between “rent as a differential product” and “rent as a payment for the use of land [or other asset]”. It is important to make this point clear from the start since it can create confusion and it helps to avoid falling into the trap of conceptually conflating the two notions of ‘rent’, as some STS scholars have done in their work (e.g. Cooper and Waldby, 2014). As noted in the introduction, there are different approaches to analysing economic rent. For simplicities sake, these can be split between classical and neoclassical economics, Marxist political economy, and others. Obviously I can only provide a brief introduction to the intellectual history of economic rent in this article, considering the space available and the need to develop the rest of my argument, so I concentrate on the first two perspectives. There are, however, a number of more thorough overviews available for the interested reader (e.g. Haila, 1988, 1990; Zeller, 2008; Campling and Havice, 2014; Ward and Aalber, 2016). Economic rent has its intellectual origins in the work of classical political economists (Lackman, 1976). In particular, David Ricardo (1817[2001]) provided a thoroughgoing conceptualization of differential rent in relation to land ownership. As Ricardo (1817[2001]: 39) defined it: “Rent is that portion of produce of the earth, which is paid to the landlord for the use of the original and indestructible powers of the soil”; that is, the biophysical qualities and productivity of land (e.g. soil quality, rainfall, sunshine, etc.). Here, Ricardo argued that different economic rents – or ‘differential rent’ – accrue to different pieces of land depending on the aggregate prices of corn produced by said land. It is important to note the difference between differential rents and commodity prices. Namely, that value in the former case is constituted by the lowest productive unit (i.e. least productive piece of land), since more productive units accrue higher returns and therefore can command higher rent; in the latter case, value is constituted by the most productive unit (i.e. cheapest production process). Conceptually, differential rent was primarily concerned with the processes of production, rather than the exchange of commodities and their prices, in that raising productivity – and thereby reducing prices – does not reduce rent (Rigi, 2014). As such, Ricardo did not conceptualize rent as a determinant of price; rather, it reflected the transfer of profit from capitalist to property owner (Ward and Aalbers, 2016). Subsequently, economic rent was developed in different ways by heterodox political economists who stuck with the labour theory of value (e.g. Karl Marx, Henry George) and more orthodox economists who adopted notions of marginal utility (e.g. John Bates Clark, Alfred Marshall). I provide a chronology of the overlapping intellectual histories of rent theory below, but it is important to note that what I present here only goes so far. I am going to start with the more orthodox approaches and then move on to the heterodox approaches. Economic thinkers of a more orthodox bent, especially those influenced by the marginal revolution of the late 19th century, moved in different directions. Some, like Alfred Marshall (1890[1920], 1893), extended the concept of rent to other resources (e.g. technology, machinery) with fixed supply – which could be applied to most resources – by equating the ‘time value’ that said resources accrues during the period of their use with economic rents. Marshall (1893: 85) used the term quasi-rents here to reflect the fact that “value is found by capitalising their quasirent”, distinguishing it from other, ongoing forms of rent (e.g. land). Many orthodox economists, however, largely jettisoned economic rent as a differential concept after the marginal revolution. For example, Linsey McGoey (2017) argues that John Bates Clark – an American economist at the turn of the 20th century – developed the theory of marginal productivity as a direct response to the criticism of economic rent by campaigners like the American Henry George. According to McGoey: “A second repercussion of Clark’s notion is that his “law” essentially extinguishes the problem of illegitimate rent seeking by positing that under ideal market conditions, rent seeking cannot exist: all proceeds to capital owners are a natural reflection of the economic contribution they have made” (p.264). It is possible to identify the influence of both Marshall and Bates in the later work of Schumpeter. In The Theory of Economic Development, for example, Schumpeter (1934[2012]) specifically wrote that rent is “determined by the marginal productivity of land” (p.25). He was more interested, however, in the source of entrepreneurial profits than rents per se, although these profits bear a strong similarity to Marshall’s conception of quasi-rents.1 As a result, such entrepreneurial profits are often defined as Schumpeterian rents (e.g. Teece, 2003) and reflect Schumpeter’s argument that entrepreneurs “create new value by establishing new combinations of capital goods and new modes of organization” (Sautet, 2016: 2). A whole literature has emerged on this topic in business and management fields (e.g. Teece, 1986, 1998, 2006; Pisano, 1991), whose (perhaps marginal) influence on STS can be traced through innovation studies. Aside from the likes of Schumpeter and others working on innovation, entrepreneurship, and similar fields, the advent of marginalism seemed to mean that the concept of rent largely disappeared in mainstream economics until the 1960s and 1970s. Some, like Michael Hudson (2012), argue that mainstream economics simply did away with any separation between interest and rent (or unearned income) and profits (or earned income), while other argues that marginal utility shifted interest towards opportunity costs (Ward and Aalbers, 2016). Economic rent came back into the picture with the work of neoclassical economists like Gordon Tulloch (1967) and 1 It is interesting to note that Schumpeter (1950: 25) saw both Ricardian and Marxist rent theory as a means to theorize away the analytical need to address “Services of Natural Agents” in the “process of production and distribution”. Anne Krueger (1974), who sought to conceptualize it in terms of rent-seeking. This, however, had a very specific meaning that distinguished it from earlier notions of (differential) rent. For example, according to Krueger (1974: 291): “In many market-oriented economies, government restrictions upon economic activity are pervasive facts of life. These restrictions give rise to rents of a variety of forms, and people often compete for the rents. Sometimes, such competition is perfectly legal”. Generally speaking, this concept of rent-seeking is now used predominantly in the neoclassical sense to mean the interference of governments in the naturalized workings of a market or economy, especially at the behest of some vested interest (e.g. a business seeking to shore up a monopoly position). Examples of this perspective include the ProMarket blog run out of the Booth School of Business at the University of Chicago, as well as the use of the term ‘rentier state’ in political science (e.g. Beblawi and Luciani, 1987). When it comes to heterodox political-economic thinkers, it is probably impossible to provide a thorough outline in the space available, so this discussion will necessarily be truncated. While American thinkers like Henry George or Thorstein Veblen – writing at the end of the 19th century and beginning of the 20th century – are known for their critiques of rentiership (see Hudson, 2012; McGoey, 2017), my focus in this section will be on the Marxist perspective on economic rent. The conception of economic rent developed by Marx has lasted into the 21st century with a recent resurgence of interest (e.g. Felli, 2014; Rigi, 2014; Ward and Aalbers, 2016; Andreucci et al., 2017), although it languished somewhat in the late 20th century (Haila, 1988, 1990; Anderson, 2014; Christophers, 2016). While he built upon the work of Ricardo, Marx (1894[2010]) sought to distinguish between several different types of economic rent, which he outlined in Capital: Volume III. According to Harvey (1982[1999]), Haila (1988, 1990), and Ward and Aalbers (2016), for example, Marx theorized two forms of differential rent as well as monopoly rent and absolute rent. It is worth considering each of these in turn. First, differential rent is split between DR1 and DR2 (Marx 1894[2010]). Whereas DR1 reflected earlier political economist’s emphasis on land as the source of rent, DR2 reflected the investments made on land that increased its productivity (e.g. irrigation, tree clearing) or usefulness (e.g. buildings, infrastructure). The split in differential rent helps to separate land as a non-reproducible asset from land as an accumulation of past capital investments, usually over a long timeframe (Harvey 1982[1999]). In his updating and reworking of Marx, David Harvey (1982[1999]) adds a spatio-temporal twist to rent theory. On the one hand, Harvey defines rent as “the basis for various forms of social control over the spatial organization and development of capitalism” (p.337), including ‘absolute’ forms of space (e.g. biophysical qualities of land again) and ‘relational’ forms of space (e.g. circulation and location across space). On the other hand, his arguments reflect Marshall’s earlier claims about the need to incorporate a temporal frame into rent theory (see above). In particular, Harvey – like Marshall (1890[1920], 1893) – argues that some assets, especially land, are made more valuable, in rent terms, as the result of successive, sequential investments over time. Taking this spatio-temporal dimension into account helps to explain how a shop space in a train station accrues rent as the result of potential customer flows attracted to the station over time, but not resulting from an investment of the shop space owner; however, in differential terms it only accrues rent if there are other shops with lower customer flows. Second, in developing Marx’s theory, Harvey (1982[1999]) argued that there are two forms of monopoly rent, or MR1 and MR2. As a starting point, monopoly rent can be defined as arising from “the ownership of a tradable asset that is considered to be unique” (Rigi, 2014: 923). Harvey distinguished between (1) monopoly rent (MR1) created by the quality of the asset (e.g. land quality), and (2) monopoly (MR2) created by the rent itself (e.g. denial of access). Although they do not distinguish between two versions of monopoly rent like Harvey, Ward and Aalbers (2016: 5) highlight the difference between ‘classical’ and ‘modern’ examples of monopoly rent, where the former represents something like a “fine wine from a particular vineyard”, while the latter represents something like a “toll road that is the only viable route”. As such, these examples largely reflect Harvey’s conception of MR1 and MR2. Analytically speaking, Haila (1990: 278) argues that such monopoly rent depends on property rights, and is, therefore, different from differential rent, which “was conceived as being caused by technically and ahistorically determined production differentials and as existing independently of private property on land”. As a result, monopoly rent was often associated with pre-capitalist economic systems (e.g. feudal ownership) and seen as dysfunctional because it was a barrier to accumulation.2 However, this view has changed over the 20th century (Haila 1988, 1990). For example, Harvey and others have linked monopoly rent with finance capital, conceptualizing monopoly rent as claims on future revenues and, therefore, as endogenous to capitalism. However, the materiality of land (and other biophysical materials) matters here since land has a recurring use, being difficult to either destroy or use up (although not impossible), meaning that it provides can indefinite future claims whereas other assets cannot (e.g. machine). Finally, absolute rent is the last type of rent theorized by Marx. Generally speaking, it has received less attention, popular or academic, than either differential or monopoly rent, although there are examples of scholars theorizing it as a form of ‘monopoly class rent’ (e.g. Sørensen, 2000; Anderson, 2014). In the original Marxist sense, absolute rent reflects the arrangement of property relations in society, such that a particular society’s property rights create a social class that has the social right to limit access to assets and charge for their use. One relatively recent application of this notion is Aage Sørensen’s (2000) idea of ‘class as exploitation’ in which our ownership and control of access to any asset enables us to extract economic rents and determines our class position. According to Ward and Aalbers (2016), some Marxists critiqued the applicability of absolute rent outside the 19th century, preferring increasingly to theorize economic rent in specific terms rather than generic ones. For example, as Jäger (2003) notes, there seems to be little difference between monopoly rent and absolute rent, aside from the fact that the former is relevant for a specific asset, while the latter is applied generally to societal relations. 2 In a recent article, Geoffrey Hodgson (2017) points out that capitalism could only really take off when land was released from limitations on its transfer and sale, and could therefore be used as collateral; this contrasts with the notion that capitalism arose as the result of secure property rights. As such, it is possible that economic rents only emerge because of capitalism, rather than reflecting a feudal hangover. Prior to its use as collateral, the value of land was set by custom or whim; once it is released from customary restraints, it could be re-priced to reflect the expected returns from production. As this discussion of economic rent should illustrate, there are an array of concepts at play in the analysis of rentiership. I have only outline two key perspectives here, but want to mention a few more key concepts that could be relevant in any further conceptual developments. First, there is an old and longstanding interest in the figure of the rentier in heterodox discussions of economic rent. For example, people like Thorstein Veblen (1908), R.H. Tawney (1921), and John Maynard Keynes (1936) all argued that the separation of ownership from management had led to the rise of a class of people for whom property represented a significant income stream, but who did little work to merit said income. Tawney went so far as to argue that various rents represented a form of ‘improperty’. Second, the notion of ground-rent, which prefigures much of the rest of the discussion of rent theory, is an important concept in urban studies and planning. It refers to the “rent paid for the use of land” (Ward and Aalbers, 2016) and, following the work of Neil Smith (1979), has some to underpin much of the literature on gentrification, since it helps to explain the incentive to restrict access to an asset (e.g. land, buildings) in order to reduce the gap between currently ‘capitalized’ and ‘potential’ ground rent. For example, Tom Slater (2016) uses it in his recent analysis of ‘planetary rent gaps’ as a way to explain how international investors secure investment opportunities in global housing markets. Finally, Arvidsson and Colleoni (2012) suggest that there is a financial rent reflecting the capture of part of the global surplus of financial capital through regimes of shareholder value maximization. Similarly, Haila (2015) outlines forms of derivative rent, fiscal rent, and others in her book Urban Land Rent. While all these conceptions of rent are interesting, and indeed could be very relevant to STS, I have to limit myself to a manageable sub-set of them in this article. Technoscience Rent My aim in this section is to think through how economic rent might be relevant for an STS audience, especially one interested in understanding the political economy of technoscience. As Haila (1990: 277) notes, economic rent is conceived of as a “technical-economic phenomenon” as much as a “juridical relationship”. In this section, then, I discuss how rent-seeking, differential rent, and monopoly rent relate to extant STS literature. It is important, from the start, to frame this discussion in terms that broaden the applicability of economic rent theory from land alone to other resources and assets, especially those constituted as or by technoscientific knowledge and its outputs (Birch, 2017b, 2017d). Several STS scholars have started to engage with resources and assets as distinct analytical categories in STS, whether in terms of intangible assets like intellectual property (e.g. Birch and Tyfield, 2013; Lezaun and Montgomery, 2015; Martin, 2015), human capital (Cooper and Waldby, 2014), business models and valuation practices (e.g. Birch, 2017d; Muniesa et al., 2017), or new kinds of asset like personal data (Vezyridis and Timmons, 2017). As with previous extensions of economic rent theory beyond land (e.g. oil rentier states), this engagement with resources and assets as analytically interesting phenomena provides the means to deploy economic rent theory in another field of enquiry – in this instance STS. My aim in this section, then, is to outline how the concept of economic rent can be used to analyse different aspects of the technoscience-society relationship in existing STS theories and concepts. As such, my aim in this section is not to develop a wholly new analytical concept, which I leave to the next section where I seek to develop a theory of rentiership. I start this discussion by examining how the concept of rent-seeking is relevant to STS. It is notable that this concept is already evident in STS in the discussion of ‘regulatory capture’, especially in relation to the pharmaceutical sector. An example of this is John Abraham’s (2008) research on pharmaceutical regulation, along with colleagues likes Courtney Davis (e.g. Davis and Abraham, 2013). These scholars argue that the capture of regulatory agencies happens when they “regulate primarily in the interests of the industry, rather than the public interest”, and it happens through active lobbying and structural changes (e.g. ‘revolving door’) (p. 9). Even though they do not deploy the concept of rent-seeking specifically, their arguments reflect the concept outlined by the likes of Tullock and Krueger – namely, private organizations focus on lobbying government for policy and legislative changes, rather than focusing on research and development. A similar, although more specific analysis of rent-seeking, is evident in the work of Frohlich (2016: 4) when he argues that “Regulation, including standards setting, becomes a potential site for ‘rent-seeking’, where the state is ‘captured’ by private interests who seek thirdparty certification to protect their market”. As this would imply, lobbying and other policy and political interventions are constitutive of particular codes, standards, regulations, and certification (Busch, 2011), which end up not only imposing costs on certain parties and not others, but also configuring technoscience through the necessary pursuit of compliance. An example here, going back to Abraham’s work, is the pharmaceutical industry and the constitutive role played by regulations in pharmaceutical research and development programmes – that is, the pursuit of blockbuster drugs in order to ameliorate the high costs of regulatory testing (REF). Another example is where standards and their network externalities enable certain social actors – whether that be a single firm or even whole nation – can accrue rents on the basis of control over those standards (Teece, 1998). This is a point emphasized by Jim Balsillie, ex-CEO of Blackberry, in his discussions of the national benefits reaped by the USA as the centre of standards setting in information technology (REF). As with standards and regulations, intellectual property rights (IPRs) are another useful illustration of the relevance of economic rent theory to STS. Whereas standards might be conceived of as a form of rent-seeking, IPRs are closer to the concept of monopoly rent, as outline by Christian Zeller (2008) and others (e.g. Birch and Tyfield, 2013; Cooper and Waldby, 2014).3 At this point, it is worth considering the two versions of monopoly rent that Harvey (1982[1999]) identifies; namely, monopoly rent derived (1) from the qualities of an asset itself – its ‘quality’ or ‘specificity’ – or (2) from the denial of access to that asset (see Haila, 1990). Analytically speaking, then, IPRs would better reflect the latter definition, as property rights are a bundle of rights including rights of exclusion. I focus on this second form of monopoly rent here, but that does not mean the other form is not relevant.4 In legal terms, IPRs confer monopoly rights on their owners, including the (often temporary) right to returns on their 3 It is important to note that IPRs can reflect more than one form of rentiership: first, they represent monopoly rents accrued through monopoly rights (e.g. patents, copyright, etc.) to research and its outputs (Mirowski, 2011); second, they represent rent-seeking on the part of IPR creators and holders to extend or strengthen intellectual property protection by influencing policy-making (Tyfield, 2008); and third, they represent a particular property system underpinning a new innovation regime (Coriat et al., 2003). These three might necessary accompany – or coproduce – each other, as the evolution of the biotechnology industry since the 1970s largely illustrates (Slaughter and Rhoades, 2004). 4 An example of monopoly rent derived from the qualities of an asset itself, which is relevant to STS, could include the particular post-treatment qualities of certain biological materials (e.g. cell lines – see Waldby and Mitchell, 2006), or their specific biophysical materialities (e.g. energy content of different biofuel feedstocks – see Birch and Calvert, 2015). This form of monopoly rent can be equated with the neoclassical conception of ‘Schumpeterian rent’; for example, the well-known management theorist David Teece (2006) conceptualizes Schumpeterian rent as a reflection of the quality or specificity of an asset, rather than the degree of a firm’s market monopoly or control. investment – this is framed as an ‘entrepreneurial’ or ‘Schumpeterian’ rent in neoclassical terms (Teece, 1998). As Christopher May (2010: 4) puts it, IPRs reflect certain “legal benefits” including “the ability to charge rent for use”, as well as “the right to receive compensation for loss” and “the right to demand payment for transfer to another party through the market”. As such, IPRs represent ‘assets’ as defined by the International Accounting Standards Board (IASB), rather than commodities – see Birch and Tyfield (2013) and Birch (2017d) for an outline of the distinctive characteristics of assets versus commodities. According to Zeller (2008: 98), this form of monopoly rent is the “result of a systematic shortage of supply created by the property monopoly of the supplier of a key product [including knowledge], which encounters no direct competition from substitution goods.” He goes on to argue that knowledge monopolies, of relevance in STS debates, are distinct because: “In contrast to the differential rent, which arises due to differently favorably located or fertile pieces of land, no information differential rent can emerge, because every enclosed information is unique and is normally used in each case for the production of specific products”. There are numerous examples of these sorts of monopoly right relevant to STS. The example I draw on here is patenting and journal publishing in academia. These practices are increasingly debated in academia, where STS scholars – and many others – have raised concerns about the limitations placed by IPRs on access to knowledge (e.g. Drahos and Braithewaite, 2002; Hope, 2008; Hackett, 2014; Harvie et al., 2014). Access is constrained through IPRs like (a) patent rights and (b) copyright. The latter is clearly evident in the subscription fees charged by publishers to access journal articles, which has been defined as ‘knowledge rolls and rents’ by Martin Hall (2010). These IPRs limit the deployment of proprietary knowledge in finding solutions to broad social problems, since they necessitate some form of payment (e.g. license fee). As Hall notes, however, these IPRs should not be confused with ‘knowledge’ itself, which can be reproduced at marginal, if any, cost. In thinking through the implications of this for STS, it is important to remember that intangible assets – like patents, copyright, brands, and other IPRs – do not depreciate or deteriorate like tangible assets (e.g. machines, buildings, etc.), meaning that IPRs can represent an ongoing “source of revenue” because “rights over reproduction are constantly renewed resources [i.e. assets], offering the opportunity of perpetual income (in the form of rents) with negligible renewal or transactional costs” (Hall, 2010: 67). However, two issues might be worth addressing in future research. First, future revenue claims are not implicit in the characteristics of the intangible asset itself, in that future rents are not known when an intangible asset is enclosed by IPRs. This implies that rents are constructed as part of the process of assetization, not simply inherent to an asset. Second, therefore, the capture of monopoly rents is an (pro)active process, rather than a passive process associated with many notions of rentier states or ownership; it involves the management, policing, enforcement and reinforcement of property rights and their value by their holders as I have shown elsewhere (Birch, 2017d). The final form of economic rent I want to consider here is differential rent. It is probably the least amenable, analytically speaking. In STS terms, it might make sense, though, to conceptualize differential rent in terms of (a) moral economies of science (Kohler, 1994) and (b) varied forms of affective, cognitive, and/or immaterial labour (Boutang, 2011). In both cases, it is first important to consider how human activities and labour might be considered a form of rent or rent-seeking. Steve Fuller (2002) provides a useful starting point in this regard. He argues that the need to qualify for professional standing in knowledge communities – whether academic or legal or medical, etc. – can “be seen as a form of intellectual rent that is imposed on the student” (p.38). As Latour and Woolgar (1979) argued some time ago, knowledge production involves all sorts of credit, credibility, and credentials, which can (and probably should) be differentiated in our analysis – for example, citations vary widely between different researchers, which has significant impacts on the capacity of those different researchers to find employment, wages, grants, awards, etc. These issues raise questions about whose ideas are most influential (e.g. those who are already cited) and why (e.g. epistemic barriers to entry), which go beyond the description of the process itself. More recently, Fuller (2016) has expounded on these arguments in his book Academic Caesar by arguing that academics are increasingly tempted to secure the future of the university by “making the entry costs too high for newcomers [e.g. other knowledge producers or providers]” (p.48). As a result, it is more than worthwhile for STS to engage with the idea that intellectual ‘labour’ can be theorized in differential terms. First, I think that differential rent has particular resonance with STS debates around the ‘moral economy’ of science (Shapin, 1991; Kohler, 1994). As Kohler (1994: 12) outlines it, when applied to science the moral economy refers to the ‘moral conventions’ that regulate scientists, their activities, their access to equipment and materials, and their system of credit and rewards. Kohler goes on to note Shapin’s (1991) earlier work on the moral economy of 17th century scientists as well as Latour and Woolgar’s (1979) work on credit cycles in (more recent) laboratories. Others have drawn on this concept of moral economy to analyse how moral values and conventions regulate the “various kinds of exchange, including what rewards are appropriate” (Dussauge et al., 2015), noting that these values and conventions are contingent – that is, subject to change and contestation. Second, differential rent also has resonance with discussions of affective, cognitive, and immaterial labour, especially drawing on the work of autonomist Marxists (see Boutang, 2011), but also other inspirations (see Murphy, 2006; Vora, 2015). Here, it is possible to conceptualize what Veblen (1908) called ‘habits of life’ – that is, humour, love, friendship, loyalty, reputation, etc. – as social relations and dispositions that can be monetized and capitalized with the deployment of specific techno-economic arrangements, leading to the capture of differential rents depending on their qualities. In both of the cases I mentioned above, the relevance of differential rent to STS is probably most obvious in the analysis of the status of individual researchers, institutions, or broader communities (e.g. city, nation). On the one hand, status reflects the credit and credibility of social actors; for example, well-cited researchers extract rent as a result of the increasing ‘credit’ their higher visibility and epistemic centrality in their disciplines provides them (Fuller, 2016). At the same time, their status reflects a broader system of collective labour in which other, less well-cited researchers act as ‘prosumers’ who both produce and consume the credibility and reputation of the output of the more well-cited researchers – primarily through citation practices. The latter is important because it recognizes that knowledge production , and the credit system which currently underpins it, are social processes and that the ‘free’ labour of citers is highly differentiated, similar to advertising, branding, and other immaterial processes (Arvidsson and Colleoni, 2012). It is for this reason that people like Sørensen (2000: 1548) specifically argued that “larger rents provide an incentive for institutions of higher education to increase tuition costs”. At base, universities with higher status researchers can charge more tuition than those with lower status researchers, even though the status of all researchers is determined collectively by the citation (and other ‘moral’ practices) of every researcher. It is perhaps pertinent to end this section with a general comment about the theorization of economic rent and rent-seeking across the literature reviewed in the last two sections. I want to make three points worth emphasizing in any conceptualization of rentiership, the task I undertake next. First, and as noted in the introduction, rent and rent-seeking are as much normative notions as they are analytical. They are generally used to connote a negative economic phenomenon; as such, ‘rent’, throughout its intellectual history, has never been a ‘neutral’ concept. While this might not seem to be an issue in a field like STS where scholars such as Donna Haraway (1988) have explicitly invoked ‘situatedness’ as a critique of ‘objectivity’ claims, an almost universally negative perspective on rent necessarily closes down an array of social activities and subjectivities that we may actually want to support. For example, Steve Fuller (2002, 2016) has defined academic disciplines and scholarship as examples of rent-seeking; if we treat rentiership as wholly negative, then it raises the question of whether something like academia is also a problematic endeavour. Second, contemporary capitalism is very different from the eras in which many of the original rent theorists were writing (e.g. Marx, Ricardo, etc.). I again noted in the introduction that numerous contemporary writers argue that capitalism is increasingly characterized by a shift towards capital accumulation strategies driven by the ownership and control over resources and assets, rather than by the production of new goods and services. As Baumol (1990) noted, though, ‘entrepreneurial’ effort is driven by a variety of roles, some of which entail productive activities, some unproductive, and some entirely destructive. It is not, then, simply adequate to contrast, analytically or normatively, rentiership with entrepreneurship as different political-economic processes; instead, it is important to work out how rentiership fits in any wider analysis of (technoscientific) capitalism, as inherent and even necessary to capitalism. Finally, on an analytical level, the preceding discussion illustrates the extent to which rent theory, on whichever side of the political equation you fall, has been based on the assumption that there are such things as true or fundamental value – whether this reflects notions of earned labour or competitive markets – to which we can refer in calculating the excess represented by rent. In contrast, my preference has always been to theorize economies and markets as ‘instituted’ (Polanyi, 1957), and, increasingly, to theorize value as ‘managed’ (Birch, 2017d). However, where a market is instituted and value managed, it makes little analytical sense to theorize an excess over some primordial base. It is, in light of these concerns, necessary to do more than simply apply rent theory to the object of study in STS, as I have done in this section. It is vital to unpack rentiership as a concept and as a social process and practice in order to push the debate forward. Towards a Theory of Rentiership In the last section I sought to apply rent theory to STS as a way to illustrate its relevance to analyses of science, technology, and innovation. In this section, I develop a theory of rentiership – that is, an analytical conception of economic rent as a social process and practice – to bring together the diverse strands of rent theory I have already outlined. As a task, it is necessarily partial, in that this has to be the starting point for an ongoing theoretical and empirical examination of ‘actually existing’ rentiership. To summarize my theoretical claims briefly here, I conceptualize rentiership as a social process and practice involving a series of actions, practices, and transformations that, in the context of STS, enable the alignment of technoscientific knowledge production with the realization of returns from its commercialization, which can be separated by a significant period of time (e.g. 10-20 years). First, it involves the ‘thing-ification’ of technoscientific knowledge as part of the co-production of understandings of value and practices of valuation. Second, it involves turning that thing into an asset, or ‘assetization’ (Birch, 2017d), as a way to organize valuation and govern or manage value over time. Finally, it involves the extraction of value (i.e. rent) – or its ‘creation’ in business parlance – through the ownership and control provided by (a) government fiat, (b) monopoly control, and/or (c) the configuration of markets and technoscience. Any attempt to develop a theory of rentiership relevant for STS, however, has to start with an outline of knowledge, in a general and technoscientific sense. Arguably, knowledge – in all its contested wonder – represents a basic unit of analysis in STS (e.g. Bloor, 1976; Fuller, 1998). As diverse social science literatures emphasize, knowledge can be hard to pin down, it is difficult to codify, it is intangible, etc. However, it is important to stress that knowledge is not a ‘thing’ in our heads or on the page; rather, knowledge is a social process bounded by social practices, social actors, social values, social institutions, etc. (Fuller, 1998; Tyfield, 2012). Moreover, knowledge encompasses the learning and knowing of technical information as well as the learning and knowing of feelings and emotions (e.g. desires and dislikes), political, social, and economic values, incentives, and motivations (e.g. cultural tastes), relational states and dispositions (e.g. friendship), and much else besides – that is, it reflects Veblen’s (1908) ‘habits of life’ as much as any technical understanding of the world. As a result, knowledge has to be conceived of as more than atomistic and individual creativity or intellectual. A number of autonomist Marxists have specifically theorized these various ‘knowledge’ practices, relations, and identities as forms of ‘labour’, even though we do not earn a wage for them. Thinkers like Lazzarato (1997), Morini and Fumagalli (2010), and Boutang (2011), for example, argue that contemporary capitalism is underpinned by forms of ‘immaterial’, ‘affective’, and ‘cognitive’ labour. Now, my intention here is not to equate different forms of (knowledge) labour as analytically equivalent. In fact, Schumpeter (1959: 25) specifically argued that rent theories based on the LTV (e.g. Ricardo, Marx) make this theoretical assumption, and thereby ignore the specificities of the “Services of Natural Agents”. Such phrasing is obviously reminiscent of actor-network theory (ANT), highlighting the need to understand the social and techno-economic relations, arrangements, and entities that enable the monetization of knowledge, its capitalization in distinct organizational forms, and its capture through different forms of rentiership. First, knowledge has to be turned into a ‘thing’ – or, reified as a techno-economic object like a patent, or copyright, or similar intellectual property (IP) designation. Knowledge starts out as an ephemeral, distributed, and collective process, but it needs to be transformed into something that is alienable for it to have value. This ‘thing-ification’ of technoscientific (or any) knowledge follows from the distinction that Fuller (2013) makes between knowledge as a substance (is) and function (does). He argues that knowledge’s function is to replace something else, although this necessarily means a function of something rather than a substance. Fuller goes on to argue that the value of knowledge, therefore, has to be understood as “determined more by the cost incurred by lacking it than the benefit received from possessing it” (p.13); in this sense, the value of knowledge is better theorized in terms of positional goods, rather than public goods as argued by numerous economists of science (see Mirowski, 2011). Positional goods entail a zero-sum consumption in which the use of the good stops its use by another person, thereby sustaining the status of the first user and limiting its usefulness to other potential users. However, while this might be a useful way to think about the value of knowledge, it assumes that knowledge – really, its function – will be used up in consumption, which is not necessarily the case. In contrast, the transformation of knowledge into a thing – through IP rights, for example – ensures that knowledge is separated from its function, so that it can be alienated and exist as property, which has an expected ownership lifespan (e.g. 20 year patent right). As such, thing-ification entails a dual process in which our understandings of the value of knowledge (e.g. its status as a positional good) are always necessarily co-produced with how we can value knowledge (e.g. as an IPR). As this would suggest, it is important to unpack valuation practices alongside the positional status of knowledge. This is perhaps most evident, as a process, in the ongoing politicaleconomic transformation of academic science since the 1970s, especially in the USA, resulting from the expansion of IPRs across many technoscientific fields (Mirowski, 2011; Tyfield, 2012; Hackett, 2014). As Janet Hope (2008: 19) notes, such IPRs are really “private regulatory tools that enable their owners to order the market by fixing prices” and, as a result, they “encourage rent-seeking via the pursuit of unproductive property rights”. It is through the legal monopoly rights conferred by IPRs that knowledge is turned into a ‘thing’ (e.g. patent) and, simultaneously, can be valued as such because this makes it possible to value the expected future profits and rents that can be captured from the techno-economic configuration of markets. For example, Arvidsson and Colleoni (2012: 145) argue that the valuations of social media platforms like Facebook do not necessarily follow from calculations of advertising revenues, or “rational calculations as to the underlying performance of company assets”, but rather from the “ability to initiate and sustain a convention that enables a rational estimate of a company’s future financial performance” (i.e. continuing increases in share value). As should be evident, rentiership entails both understandings of value as an abstract concept – e.g. as financial opportunity cost (Chiappello, 2015) – and valuation practices that can turn these understandings into social processes. For example, Harvey (1982 [1999]) argued that geographical places can be conceptualized in monopoly rent terms, such as a location with many passers-by (e.g. train station). The location is more valuable, in retail terms, than one with fewer passers-by (e.g. residential neighbourhood), leading to higher rental charges for the first location, which then get passed on to consumers. It is important to note, however, that in this example the thing that is valuable is the number of people passing by the shop, not the land at that location. Second, and despite the normative language he still uses, rentiership might seem closer to what Baumol (1990) defined as ‘unproductive’ or ‘destructive’ entrepreneurship, rather than ‘productive entrepreneurship’. In order to avoid the normative connotations implied by these definitions, however, it might be best to think of rentiership as economic activity that does not entail the production of new goods and services (cf. Pike, 2015). Rather, and building on rent theory, rentiership is a process by which things are turned into assets, or resources in the production process (i.e. factors of production). As such, it reflects the growing interest in STS and cognate fields in the ‘assetization’ of knowledge, information, data, and suchlike (e.g. Birch, 2015, 2017; Martin, 2015; Birch and Muniesa, 2016; Muniesa et al., 2017; Vezyridis and Timmons, 2017). In contrast to commodification, assetization involves the creation of assets, which the International Accounting Standards Board (IASB) defines as “a resource controlled by the entity as a result of past events and from which future economic benefits are expected to flow to the entity”.5 As I have noted elsewhere (Birch, 2017c), technoscientific knowledge was reclassified as an ‘asset’ in the 2008 Systems of National Accounts (SNA), which is an international statistical standard produced by the United Nations; prior to this it was classified as an input into production.6 Assetization involves the conversion of a ‘thing’ into identifiable and alienable property, which has value both as a resource (i.e. intermediate input) and as tradable property. In relation to knowledge, research is transformed into an intangible asset as a result of things like intellectual property (IP – like a patent or copyright), organizational procedures and processes (e.g. database and software), reputation (e.g. brand), and ‘goodwill’ – the last of these represents the value of a business as a going concern (MacKenzie, 2009). Assets are interesting for a variety of reason (Boutang, 2011; Birch, 2017d), but most notably in the context of rentiership for how their value and valuation are organized, managed, and governed. In relation to knowledge, intangible assets – like IPRs – are often organized and constructed as monopolies in which legal restrictions (e.g. patent rights) inhibit the replication or imitation of knowledge resources; as such, rentiership involves the organization of limits and exclusions on the use of a resource or its copies (Zeller, 2008; May, 2010). As such, and this is crucial, knowledge can only be turned into an intangible asset through its identification and classification as a resource, which means finding ways to extract it from the freely and openly accessible knowledge ‘commons’ (Birch et al., 2017). According to Frase (2016), for example, a key defining feature of intangible assets (e.g. copyright) is the fact that exclusion and use rights are also follow-through rights that get extended in the sale of their copies (e.g. CD, DVD), thereby reinforcing monopolies despite the proliferation of copies. An interesting example, in this case, is the ongoing fight between US farmers and tractor manufacturer, John Deere, resulting from the latter’s attempt, through license agreements, to limit the ability of farmers to repair or modify their tractor’s software or electronic functions (Koebler, 2017). As mentioned above, this necessitates international standards like the SNA or IASB, but is also requires the legal extension and application of ownership rights to knowledge ‘assets’ and their ‘products’, whether the latter is given away for free or not. A key question to consider in this context is where the value of intangible assets lies. As several political economists argue (e.g. Nitzan and Bichler, 2009; Styhre, 2015; Bryan et al., 2017), much of the value of intangible assets rests in the valuation of asset holders (e.g. business organizations), rather than in the inherent qualities of the asset itself since intangible assets can be valued very differently by different people (Bryan et al., 2017). Consequently, in my previous work I stress the need to analyse the firm in STS debates about value (Birch, 2017d). With the above paragraph in mind, it is important to remember that the valuation of intangible assets is not a simple matter. Indeed, it involves a diverse array of political-economic knowledges, practices, and processes (Birch, 2017c, 2017d). Here, rentiership relates to the dynamic management of the earnings, or yield, of an asset over its lifespan – which is how Marshall (1890[1920]) defined quasi-rents. In technoscientific capitalism, the future earnings or yields of an asset are highly uncertain; for example, Hopkins (2012) provides an outline of these uncertainties in the biotech or life sciences sector. In part, uncertainty results from concerns about when a substitute might be found for an asset, when an asset might lose its appeal, and 5 6 https://www.iasplus.com/en/standards/other/framework https://unstats.un.org/unsd/nationalaccount/sna2008.asp when an asset might lead to a new product or service. The capitalization of a business – or asset – has become an important valuation practice in uncertain fields like biotech and information technology where there is limited profit data (Doganova and Eyquem-Renault, 2009). According to Muniesa (2012) and Muniesa et al. (2017), capitalization represents a political-economic epistemology and social practice which involves the discounting of future earnings in the present. Originally introduced in the early 20th century, it contradicted notions of inherent value prevalent in LTV approaches. Instead, it represents a way to calculate the value of future earnings – using a discount rate to work out their current value – and therefore the suitability of something for investment (Muniesa, 2012, 2014). As such, it involves a valuation based on future expectations rather than past work, meaning that it has created demand for a vast financial ecosystem – since valuations cannot be made through market exchanges when value I based on future expectations – comprising a range of political-economic experts who form part of the management and governance of value through their valuation judgements (e.g. brokers), valuation assessments (e.g. analysts), valuation monitoring (e.g. accountants), and so on (Birch, 2017d). Rentiership necessitates this active and ongoing organization, management, and governance of value, meaning that it is not a passive process; it can involve significant effort on the part of asset owners to manage the valuation decisions of investors. However, it means that financiers, investors, and others can make a valuation of something that has no historical precedence (e.g. profits), such that the timeframe between technoscientific ‘discovery’ (or, more likely, IP filing) and realization of value – which can be many years afterwards – are aligned with one another. Finally, rentiership is realized through different forms of value extraction, often still framed as value ‘creation’ in business circles. In each case, value extraction is enacted through the ownership and control of assets, whether bought or developed in-house, rather than the production of new goods and services. Here I discuss three forms of rentiership, although there are probably more: (a) government fiat, (b) monopoly control, and/or (c) the configuration of markets and technoscience. The first form of value extraction is government fiat. As stated earlier, my approach to analysing rentiership through a Polanyian lens (Polanyi, 1957), namely the idea that economies and markets are ‘instituted’ rather than natural or naturalistic. From this perspective, rentiership entails forms of government or quasi-government fiat, which includes the establishment of regulations, standards, and codes (Busch, 2011). This can happen in at least three ways: first, the presence and absence of regulations etc. can lead to the shifting of markets from one jurisdiction to another (e.g. stem cell tourism – Sleeboom-Faulkner and Patra, 2011; Rosemann, 2014); second, new regulations etc. can create new markets altogether (e.g. ethanol fuel standards – Birch and Calvert, 2015); and third, and most interesting here, new regulations etc. can both curtail existing markets and open new markets (e.g. greenhouse gas emissions – Lohmann, 2017). I want to focus on the last of these since it illustrates the impacts of government fiat most clearly. A helpful example of is the introduction of carbon markets, which Romain Felli (2014) theorizes as a form of ‘climate rent’. Felli argues that government (or quasi-government) fiat does not create “commodities” per se, but rather legally constituted “public entitlements to emit greenhouse gases” enacted through property rights (p.254). He goes on to call it an “administrative grant” representing a “barrier to production” which is the very thing “that makes them valuable” (p.266). As such, this form of government fiat reflects the Marxist notions of absolute rent in which ownership rights are first instituted and then distributed, protected, and enforced by the state, and provides an underlying logic to rentiership – namely, societal rules on the ownership and control of useful assets. Other examples of this form of rent extraction abound, including of land, of water, of culture, and so on (Andreucci et a., 2017). The second form of value extraction is monopoly, especially intellectual monopoly in regards to science, technology, and innovation – for example, IPRs like patents, copyright, etc. (Zeller, 2008). There is an important element of government fiat involved here also, but it is not necessarily a defining feature of monopoly control since monopoly rents can accrue as the result of the uniqueness or rarity of an asset as well. However, that being said, people like Fuller (2013) are quite clear that the value of knowledge is constituted by access, which means that stateinstituted IPRs do create monopolies. There are at least three reasons why IPRs are better theorized as monopoly control, rather than absolute monopoly represented by government fiat. First, IPRs represent very different socio-legal ‘things’ (e.g. patent, copyright, trade secret, trademark, etc.), which are configured in very specific ways to create specific exclusions. For example, Kang (2015) highlights the need to differentiate between types of property rights, including ‘use’, ‘fruits’, and ‘abuse’ rights. It is interesting to note that property rights over assets (cf. commodities) do not necessarily allow owners to destroy their asset (e.g. knowledge, land, customer base, etc.). On the other hand, they may extend use rights to copies of the asset. Second, IPRs entail a specific time frame (e.g. 20 year patent right) (May, 2010). Consequently, they do not represent a generic form of ownership encompassing the societal rules of the game or covering assets with perpetual lifespans (e.g. land). Third, increasingly, ownership rights, especially of assets, are governed as forms of investment (in assets) through corporate mechanisms like investor dispute panels, rather than through government sanction. Alongside IPRs, other forms of monopoly control are also possible, especially those based on the unique or special quality of an asset. General examples might include things like wine appellations or unique artwork (Harvey, 2002), although it is still pertinent in relation to technoscientific knowledge claims. The uniqueness and specificity of many research findings and their commercial potential, for example, are inscribed in the legal terminology of IPRs like patents (Pagano and Rossi, 2017). The final form of value extraction I want to outline results from the configuration of markets and technoscience. As noted above, the temporal nature of valuation practices in rentiership – exemplified by capitalization (Muniesa et al., 2017) – necessitate the techno-economic configuration of specific organizational forms – namely, the private business enterprise (Birch, 2017d). Considering the uncertainty of technoscientific commercialization, there are obvious limitations on the financing of innovation; that is, it needs to ensure that investors can receive their capital back before the realization of value in production events (e.g. selling products or services) (Hopkins, 2012). According to Pisano (2006), for example, the long timelines involved in biopharmaceutical development meant that biotech firms pursued research and business strategies based on monetizing knowledge in order to finance product developments. Such monetization of knowledge, however, is dependent on the configuration of knowledge markets through the reinforcement of IPRs as well as the emergence non-performing entities – or ‘patent trolls’ in more poetic language – which buy IP and then engage in litigation to extract value from their property rights (Chien, 2014). Rentiership, in this sense, can involve more than the simple assertion of government fiat or monopoly power. It also involves the configuration of markets and technoscience, exemplified in two examples here. First, work by Lazonick and Tulum (2911) shows that much of the financing that goes into the US biopharmaceutical sector is used to buy back shares, rather than increase research and development. As a consequence of the market pressures on managers to maximize shareholder value and avoid risky investments in long-term product development, Lazonick and Tulum argue that firms use capital to increase share values through financial means and outsource risky research to smaller firms. Second, and perhaps more interesting, are the Epipen and Daraprim drug cases (Glabau, 2016a, 2016b), although I focus on Daraprim for want of space. In 2015, the then CEO of Turing Pharmaceuticals, Martin Shkreli, was raked over the proverbial coals for raising the cost of Daraprim 5000%, from US$13.50 to US$750 (Glabau, 2016b). A lot of noise was made about FDA regulations giving Turing a monopoly on the drug; however, it had been off patent for some time so this did not seem to explain the case. Instead, Turing exploited FDA rules on market exclusivity provided by regulations on testing old drug to ensure their compliance with current regulations as well as convincing the previous rights holder to starve the market so no other company could get hold of any Daraprim tablets to run their own tests (Olson, 2015). It was not simply a case of government regulation or monopoly rights gone bad; instead, it was an active configuring of the market and technoscience in order to extract rents. Conclusion To follow! Analytical - Rent is not abnormal; rentiership is normal - Rentiership is active social practice STS - We need to develop new competencies We need to rejuvenate political economy, inside STS and outwith (we have a lot to contribute) Universities are at tipping point - How do we defend what we do - How do we fund what we do References Abraham, J. 2008. … Anderson, M. 2014. Class monopoly rent and the contemporary neoliberal city, Geography Compass 8(1): 13-24. Andreucci, D., Garcia-Lamarca, M., Wedekind, J. and Swyngedouw, E. 2017. ‘Value Grabbing’? A Political Ecology of Rent, Capitalism Nature Socialism, DOI: 10.1080/10455752.2016.1278027 Arvidsson, A. and Colleoni, E. 2012. Value in Informational Capitalism and on the Internet, The Information Society: An International Journal 28(3): 135-150. Baumol, W. 1990. Entrepreneurship: Productive, Unproductive, and Destructive, Journal of Political Economy 98(5): 893-921. Birch, K. 2013. The political economy of technoscience: An emerging research agenda. Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science 7(1): 49-61. Birch, K. 2015. We Have Never Been Neoliberal, Winchester: Zero Books. Birch, K. 2017a. Towards a theory of rentiership, Dialogues in Human Geography 7(1): 109111. Birch, K. 2017b. A Research Agenda for Neoliberalism, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. Birch, K. 2017c. Financing technoscience: Finance, assetization and rentiership, in D. Tyfield, R. Lave, S. Randalls and C. Thorpe (eds), The Routledge Handbook of the Political Economy of Science, London: Routledge, pp.169-181. Birch, K. 2017d. Rethinking value in the bio-economy: Finance, assetization and the management of value, Science, Technology and Human Values 42(3): 460-490. Birch, K. and Calvert, K. 2015. Rethinking 'drop-in' biofuels: On the political materialities of bioenergy, Science and Technology Studies 28(1): 52-72. Birch, K. and Muniesa, F. 2016. Call for papers: Turning things into assets, … Birch, K. and Tyfield, D. 2013. Theorizing the bioeconomy: Biovalue, biocapital, bioeconomics or …what?, Science, Technology and Human Values 38(3): 299-327. Boutang, Y.M. 2011. Cognitive Capitalism, Cambridge: Polity. Busch, L. 2011. Standards: Recipes for Reality, Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Chiapello, E. 2015. Financialisation of valuation , Human Studies 38(1): 13-35. Chien, C. 2014. Startups and Patent Trolls, Stanford Technology Law Review 17: 461-505. Christophers, B. 2016. For real: land as capital and commodity, Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 41(2): 134-148. Congleton, R. and Hillman, A. (eds) 2015. Companion to the Political Economy of Rent Seeking, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. Cooper, M. and Waldby, C. 2014. Clinical Labor, Durham: Duke University Press. Coriat, B., Orsi, F. and Weinstein, O. 2003. Does Biotech Reflect a New Science-based Innovation Regime?, Industry and Innovation 10(3): 231-253. Davis, C. and Abraham, J. 2013. Unhealthy Pharmaceutical Regulation, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Doganova, L. and Eyquem-Rrenault, M. 2009. What do business model do? Innovation devices in technology entrepreneurship, Research Policy 38: 1559-1570. Drahos, P. with Braithewaite, J. 2002. Information Feudalism, London: Earthscan. Dussauges, I., Helgesson, C-F. and Lee, F. (eds). 2015. Value Practices in the Life Sciences and Medicine, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Felli, R. 2014. On climate rent, Historical Materialism 22(3-4): 251-280. Frase, P. 2016. Four Futures: Life After Capitalism, London: Verso. Frohlich, X. 2016. The informational turn in food politics: The US FDA’s nutrition label as information infrastructure, Social Studies of Science, doi: 10.1177/0306312716671223 Fuller, S. 2002. Knowledge Management Foundations, Boston MA: Butterworth-Heinemann. Fuller, S. 2013. On commodification and the progress of knowledge in society: A defence, Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science 7(1): 6-14. Fuller, S. 2016. Academic Caesar, London: Sage. Glabau, D. 2016a. Pricing the EpiPen: Drug prices, corporate governance, and the financialization of biomedicine, Somatosphere, 12 September , available from http://somatosphere.net/2016/09/pricing-the-epipen-drug-prices-corporate-governance-and-thefinancialization-of-biomedicine.html (last accessed April 2017). Glabau, D. 2016b. Why does everyone hate Martin Shkreli?, Somatosphere, 14 January, available from http://somatosphere.net/2016/01/why-does-everyone-hate-martin-shkreli.html (last accessed April 2017). Goven, J. and Pavone, V. 2015. The bioeconomy as political project: A Polanyian analysis, Science, Technology and Human Values 40(3): 302-337. Hackett, E. 2014. Editorial: Academic capitalism, Science, Technology, and Human Values 39(5): 635-638. Haila, A. 1988. Land as a financial asset: The theory of urban rent as a mirror of economic transformation, Antipode 20(2): 79-101. Haila, A. 1990. The theory of land rent at the crossroads, Environment and Planning D 8: 275296. Haila, A. 2015. Urban Land Rent, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. Hall, M. 2010. Minerva’s owl. A response to John Houghton and Charles Oppenheim’s ‘The economic implications of alternative publishing models’, Prometheus: Critical Studies in Innovation 28(1): 61-71. Haraway, D. 1988. Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective, Feminist Studies 14(3): 575-599. Harvey, D. 1982[1999]. The Limits to Capital, London: Verso. Harvey, D. 2002. The Art of Rent: Globalization, Monopoly and the Commodification of Culture, Socialist Register 38: 93-110. Harvie, D., Lightfoot, G., Lilley, S. and Weir, K. 2014. Publisher, be damned! From price gouging to the open road, Prometheus: Critical Studies in Innovation 31(3): 229-239. Hodgson, G. 2017. 1688 and All That: Property Rights, the Glorious Revolution and the Rise of British Capitalism, Journal of Institutional Economics 13(1): 79-107. Hope, J. 2008. Biobazaar: The Open Source Revolution and Biotechnology, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. Hopkins, M. 2012. Exploring finding routes for therapeutics firms, in M. O'Neill and M. Hopkins (eds), A Biotech Manager's Handbook, Oxford: Woodhead Publishing, pp.131-155. Hudson, M. 2012. Veblen’s Institutionalist Elaboration of Rent Theory, Working Paper No. 729: Levy Economics Institute of Bard College. Available online at: http://www.levyinstitute.org/pubs/wp_729.pdf (accessed April 2017). Jäger, J. 2003. Urban Land Rent Theory: A Regulationist Perspective, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 27(2): 233-249. Keynes, J.M. 1936[1964]. The General Theory of Interest, Employment and Money, London: Macmillan. Kohler, R. 1994. Lords of the Fly, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Krueger, A. 1974. The Political Economy of the Rent-Seeking Society, American Economic Review 64: 291–303. Lackman, C. 1976. The Classical Base of Modern Rent Theory, The American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 35(3): 287-300. Latour, B. and Woolgar, S. 1979. Laboratory Life, London: Sage. Lazonick, W. and Tulum, O. 2011. US biopharmaceutical finance and the sustainability of the biotech business model, Research Policy 40(9): 1170–1187. Lazzarato, M. 1997. Lavoro Immateriale e Soggettivita, Verona: Ombre corte. Lezaun, J. and Montgomery, C. 2015. The pharmaceutical commons: Sharing and exclusion in global health drug development, Science, Technology and Human Values 40(1): 3-29. MacKenzie, D. 2009. Material Markets: How Economic Agents are Constructed, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Martin, P. 2015. Commercialising neurofutures: Promissory economies, value creation and the making of a new industry, BioSocieties 10(4): 422-443. Marx, K. 1894[2010]. Capital: Volume 3, Marxists.org, available online at: https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1894-c3/ (accessed April 2017). May, C. 2010. The Global Political Economy of Intellectual Property Rights, Oxford: Routledge. McGoey, L. 2017. The Elusive Rentier Rich: Piketty’s data battles and the power of absent evidence, Science, Technology & Human Values 42(2): 257-279. Mirowski, P. 2011. ScienceMart, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. Morini, C. and Fumagalli, A. 2010. Life put to work: towards a life theory of value, ephemera 10(3/4): 234–255. Muniesa, F. 2012. A flank movement in the understanding of valuation, The Sociological Review 59(s2): 24-38. Muniesa, F. 2014. The Provoked Economy, London: Routledge. Muniesa, F., Doganova, L., Ortiz, H., Pina-Stranger, A., Paterson, F., Bourgoin, A., Ehrenstein, V., Juven, P-A., Pontille, D., Saraç-Lesavre, B. and Yon, G. 2017. Capitalization: A Cultural Guide, Paris: Presses des Mines. Murphy, M. 2006. Seizing the Means of Reproduction, Durham: Duke University Press. Nitzan, J. and Bichler, S. 2009. Capital as Power, London: Routledge. Olson, W. 2015. That $750 Generic Pill Is a Pure Artifact of Regulation, Cato Institute, 29 September, accessed from https://www.cato.org/blog/750-generic-pill-pure-artifact-regulation (accessed April 2017). Pike, A. 2015. Origination, Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell Pisano, G. 1991. The governance of innovation: Vertical integration and collaborative arrangements in the biotechnology industry, Research Policy 20: 237-249. Pisano, G. 2006. Science Business, Boston: Harvard Business School Press. Polanyi, K. 1957. The economy as instituted process, in K. Polanyi, C.M. Arensberg and H.W. Pearson (eds), Trade and Market in the Early Empires, New York: The Free Press. Ricardo, D. 1817[2001]. On the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, Kitchener: Batoche Books. Rigi, J. 2014. Foundations of a Marxist theory of the political economy of information: Trade secrets and intellectual property, and the production of relative surplus value and the extraction of rent-tribute, tripleC 12(2): 909-936. Rosemann, A. 2014. Standardization as situation-specific achievement: Regulatory diversity and the production of value in intercontinental colaborations in stem cell medicine, Social Science and Medicine 122: 72-80. Sautet, F. 2016. Schumpeterian rents, in M. Augier and D. Teece (eds), The Palgrave Encyclopedia of Strategic Management, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp.1-3. Sayer, A. 2015. Why We Can’t Afford the Rich, Bristol: Policy press. Schumpeter, J. 1934. A Theory of Economic Development, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. Schumpeter, J. 1950. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, New York: Harper Perennial. Shapin, S. 1991. ‘A scholar and a gentleman’: The problematic identity of the scientific practitioner in early modern England, History of Science 29: 279-327. Slaughter, S. and Rhoades, G. 2004. Academic Capitalism and the New Economy: Markets, State, and Higher Education, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Sleeboom-Faulkner, M. and Patra, P.K. 2011. Experimental stem cell therapy: Biohierarchies and bionetworking in Japan and India, Social Studies of Science 41(5): 645-666. Sørensen, A. 2000. Toward a Sounder Basis for Class Analysis, American Journal of Sociology 105(6): 1523-1558. Styhre, A. 2015. Financing Life Science Innovation, London: Palgrave Macmillan. Sunder Rajan, K. (ed.) 2012. Lively Capital, Durham: Duke University Press. Tawney, R.H. 1921. The Acquisitive Society, London: Bell and Sons Ltd. Teece, D. 1986. Profiting from Technological Innovation: Implications for integration, collaboration, licensing and public policy, Research Policy 15(6): 285-305. Teece, D. 1998. Capturing Value from Knowledge Assets: The New Economy, Markets for Know-how, and Intangible Assets, California Management Review 40(3): 55-79. Teece, D. 2003. Essays in Technology Management and Policy, New Jersey: World Scientific Publishing. Teece, D. 2006. Reflections on “Profiting from Innovation”, Research Policy 35(8): 1131-1146. Tullock, G. 1967. The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies, and Theft, Western Economic Journal 5(3): 224-232. Tyfield, D. 2008. Enabling TRIPs : The pharma-biotech-university patent coalition, Review of International Political Economy 15(4): 535-566. Tyfield, D. 2012. The Economics of Science : A Critical Realist Overview (Volume 1 and 2), London: Routledge. Tyfield, D., Lave, R., Randalls, S. and Thorpe, C. (eds). 2017. The Routledge Handbook of the Political Economy of Science, London: Routledge. Veblen, T. 1908. On the nature of capital: Investment, intangible assets, and the pecuniary magnate, Journal of Economics 23(1): 104-136. Vezyridis, P. and Timmons, S. 2017. Understanding the care.data conundrum: New information flows for economic growth, Big Data and Society 4(1): 1-12. Vora, K. 2015. Life Support, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Waldby, C. and Mitchell, R. 2006. Tissue Economies: Blood, Organs and Cell Lines in Late Capitalism, Durham: Duke University Press. Ward, C. and Aalbers, M. 2016. Virtual special issue editorial essay ‘The shitty rent business’: What’s the point of land rent theory?, Urban Studies 53(9): 1760–1783. Zeller, C. 2008. From the gene to the globe: Extracting rents based on intellectual property monopolies, Review of International Political Economy 15(1): 86-115. Stiglitz: https://www.theguardian.com/business/2014/jun/09/why-learning-matters-innovationjoseph-stiglitz Standing, G. 2016. https://www.opendemocracy.net/guy-standing/we-must-combat-rentiercapitalism Colville, R. 2017. https://capx.co/taming-the-new-titans-of-tech/ Kaminska, I. 2016. https://ftalphaville.ft.com/2016/12/01/2180647/the-taxi-unicorns-new-clothes/ Koebler, J. 2017. https://motherboard.vice.com/en_us/article/why-american-farmers-are-hacking-theirtractors-with-ukrainian-firmware Morozov, E. 2016. https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2016/dec/04/data-populists-must-seizeinformation-for-benefit-of-all-evgeny-morozov?CMP=share_btn_tw Bregman, R. 2017. https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2017/mar/30/wealth-banks-googlefacebook-society-economy-parasites?CMP=share_btn_tw Malthus, T. 1815. http://socserv2.socsci.mcmaster.ca/~econ/ugcm/3ll3/malthus/rent