Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 17, No. 1 (2019): 127–147
127
Do Thomists Have Rights?
Dominic Legge, O.P.
Dominican House of Studies
Washington, DC
In the standard account of the historical development of the idea of
natural rights, the watershed innovation is typically said to be the notion
that individual persons themselves “possess” rights: not only that we
judge something to be “right” by nature, in an objective sense (“objective
right” or “objective rights”), but that individual human subjects “have
natural rights” that they can maintain over against others (“subjective
rights”). Some view this development of the idea of subjective rights in
a positive light as the crucial foundation for contemporary doctrines
of human rights; others regard it as a corruption of classical theories of
justice and the beginning of the decay and decadence of contemporary
liberal regimes.1
For centuries, Thomists—those who lay claim to the principles and
heritage of St. Thomas Aquinas—have played a prominent role in this
history. In the early sixteenth century, Dominican Thomists like Francisco
de Vittoria, Domingo de Soto, and Bartolome de las Casas were instrumental in the development of a theory of natural rights that would serve
to limit the power of the Spanish crown and of colonial masters over the
natives of the new world. In the twentieth century, in the immediate aftermath of World War II, Jacques Maritain mounted a principled campaign
as a Thomist for the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. And contem1
For a moderate critique of the contemporary discourse that views rights as absolute, see Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse
(New York: The Free Press, 1991). Patrick Deneen has offered a more trenchant
critique along different lines in “Unsustainable Liberalism,” First Things, August/
September 2012, 25–31.
128
Dominic Legge, O.P.
porary interest in Aquinas’s approach to law and justice is increasing, as is
evident from several recent publications.2
Yet a lively debate has developed in recent decades over the Thomistic pedigree of subjective rights. Were these Thomists in fact faithful to the principles
of Thomas Aquinas?3 Is a doctrine of subjective rights found in Aquinas?4 If
not, is it an organic development from Thomas’s own views? Or can Aquinas’s
thought be used in a more general way to ground a theory of subjective natural
rights? To put it in the terms of Leo Strauss, does Aquinas truly belong in what
he terms the classic natural right tradition, or is Aquinas actually a precursor
and forerunner of the modern doctrine of natural rights? (In Natural Right
and History, Strauss himself seems to regard Aquinas as a liminal figure, still
within the classic tradition but sowing the seeds of its demise in post-Enlightenment modernity.5) The participants in the debate over these questions,
whether or not they think subjective rights are a positive development, generally take it for granted that the crucial shift is from a focus on duties based on
an objective sense of “what is naturally right, or just, or due” to a subjective
theory of “natural rights” that I “possess” as an individual person.
It is my claim that such questions miss the point and, worse, hide the
fact that, in the centuries after Aquinas, some putative Thomists diverged
in important ways from Aquinas’s own principles. The resulting (so-called)
Thomistic theories of natural rights involved a shift in perspective that has
2
3
4
5
For example, J. Budziszewski’s recent Commentary on Thomas Aquinas’s Treatise
on Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016) revives the medieval
practice of commenting, line by line, on the text of an eminent authority. That
something like this would be published by a major contemporary academic press
is a good indication of the growing appeal of scholarship on Aquinas in this area.
See also: Douglas Kries, The Problem of Natural Law (Lanham, MD: Lexington
Books, 2007); Russell Hittinger, The First Grace: Rediscovering the Natural Law in
a Post-Christian World (Wilmington, DE: ISI Books, 2003).
Alasdair MacIntyre criticizes Maritain’s putatively Thomistic argument for human
rights as “quixotic,” “an uncharacteristic lapse,” and producing “a conception of
rights alien to and absent from Aquinas’s thought” (Three Rival Versions of Moral
Enquiry: Encyclopaedia, Genealogy, and Tradition [Notre Dame, IN: University of
Notre Dame Press, 1990], 76).
Two prominent scholars on the history of natural rights disagree sharply on many
issues, but they agree in opining that Aquinas did not have such a doctrine: Michel
Villey, La formation de la pensée juridique moderne: cours d’histoire de la philosophie du droit (Paris: Montcrestien, 1975), and Brian Tierney, The Idea of Natural
Rights: Studies on Natural Rights, Natural Law, and Church Law, 1150–1625,
Emory University Studies in Law and Religion 5 (Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press,
1997), esp. 257–60.
Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1950), 163–64.
Do Thomists Have Rights?
129
worked much mischief in the domain of natural rights theory. Recovering
Aquinas’s own view is, I believe, quite important if we are to think aright about
a healthy political order. But contemporary commentators have generally
failed to recognize that some supposedly Thomistic theories are only Thomistic masquerades.
In order to bring this to view, I will first discuss what I consider to be the key
principles of Aquinas’s own account and how the distinction between objective and subjective rights is a relatively unimportant side issue compared to the
critical insight of Aquinas’s position: that law and justice, and consequently
any theory of natural rights, should always be understood in terms of an overarching order to the good. Then I will speak about how that key dimension
was eclipsed, first in the thought of late-medieval thinkers opposed to Aquinas
(like William of Ockham), and then in the thought of Francisco Suarez and
subsequent Jesuit and Jesuit-influenced Thomists. Finally, I will discuss how
the eclipse of this key dimension has widespread and damaging repercussions
and will attempt briefly to make the case that, if we wish to have natural rights
in a healthy political order, it is important to recover Aquinas’s central insight.
Thomas Aquinas on Law, Justice, and Ius
Did Thomas Aquinas recognize subjective natural rights? In essence,
the answer is yes. But focusing exclusively on this question obscures Aquinas’s understanding of the complex interrelationship among justice, law
(lex), right (ius), and the common good.
Let us start with justice. In his great synthetic Summa theologiae, Aquinas first discusses justice as an attribute of God. In doing so, he affirms
a key principle: justice always refers to a wise or reasoned ordering among
things. When we speak about justice in God, we are referring first of all to
the divine intellect, insofar as God’s intellect conceives the perfectly wise
plan by which all things are ordered to himself. Justice is only secondarily
in God’s will, insofar as, by his will, he acts according to the wise order he
has conceived.
Since the object of the will is the good as understood [by the intellect], it is impossible that God would will anything but the plan
[ratio] he conceives by his intellect, which is like a law of justice,
according to which his will is right and just. Hence what he does
according to his will, he does justly, just as we act justly when we act
according to the law.6
6
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae [ST] I, q. 21, a. 1, ad 2: “Cum bonum intellectum sit obiectum voluntatis, impossibile est Deum velle nisi quod ratio suae
130
Dominic Legge, O.P.
Here we are very far from later voluntaristic theories according to
which the decree of God’s will, which we are bound to obey, is the
ultimate root of justice and law. For Aquinas, law is not primarily
the expression of God’s will, but rather, the wisely ordered plan
of creation in God’s intellect is like the “law” that guides the
perfectly just willing of God. Law is an expression of reason, an
ordering according to reason, even in God. And so justice results
from rightly willing according to the wise or reasoned ordering of
all things to God.
This understanding of justice, order, and reason is echoed by Aquinas’s
famous definition of law as “an ordination of reason for the common good,
made by one with authority, and promulgated.” 7 Aquinas crafted this definition with care, intending it to account not only for human written laws
but also for natural law, divine positive law, and the eternal law in the mind
of God. Like justice, law designates for Aquinas an order of reason. It is a
rule and measure of acts not primarily because a subordinate is bound to
obey his superior, but because the law sets forth the ordered plan to attain
the end. Insofar as an act fails to conform to that plan, it does not conduce
to attaining the end, and so lacks the rectitude of order.
Later in the Summa theologiae, Thomas treats of justice in human
affairs. There, he speaks of it as a moral virtue in the soul by which man is
made good. That is, he treats human justice as part of a broader account
of how man is ultimately ordered to God within the complex network of
overlapping relationships he has with others, like his family, his neighbors,
his city, and so forth:
Justice by its essence implies a certain rectitude of order . . . insofar as
it implies a right order in man’s very act. And thus justice is held to be
a virtue, either as particular justice, which rightly orders man’s act in
relation to another individual man; or as legal justice, which rightly
orders man’s act in relation to the common good of a multitude.8
7
8
sapientiae habet. Quae quidem est sicut lex iustitiae, secundum quam eius voluntas
recta et iusta est. Unde quod secundum suam voluntatem facit, iuste facit, sicut et
nos quod secundum legem facimus, iuste facimus.”
ST I-II, q. 90, a. 4.
ST I-II, q. 113, a. 1: “Iustitia de sui ratione importet quandam rectitudinem
ordinis . . . secundum quod importat ordinem rectum in ipso actu hominis. Et
secundum hoc iustitia ponitur virtus quaedam, sive sit particularis iustitia, quae
ordinat actum hominis secundum rectitudinem in comparatione ad alium singula-
Do Thomists Have Rights?
131
This text brings into the foreground another key dimension of justice
for Aquinas: it implies a reasoned or wise ordering, and more specifically,
an ordering to the good, an ordering that makes man good.
At this point, we have identified three key elements in Aquinas’s
account of justice: it involves (1) an ordering (2) according to reason (3) to
the good. And with these elements in mind, we are now ready to take up a
key Latin term for theories of natural rights: ius.
Thomas’s says that ius is the object of justice. One is just when one
renders to another his ius. What does this mean? Ius is hard to translate
into English. Standard translations usually render it as “right,” but it can
also mean “the just thing,” or “what is due.” We could also say that ius is
“what is right,” or perhaps “the fair.” The term is drawn from the Roman
legal tradition, from Roman legal judgments: a judge would declare the
ius in a case. (That Aquinas uses this Roman term in an otherwise Aristotelian definition of justice provides a good example of how Aquinas
integrates and synthesizes Aristotle with the Roman and Augustinian
traditions.) Sometimes ius can even be translated as “law,” but that is not
quite correct, according to Aquinas. Especially when we are speaking of a
written law, he explains, the ius is the measure and the intelligible form of
a law in the same way that the artisan’s idea of the table he is going to make
is the mental exemplar and measure of what he carves in wood. And more
generally, law is a kind of expression of ius.9
Aquinas’s point is that we judge whether an action is just, or whether a
law is just, by reference to this objective measure or object of justice: have I
rendered to another his ius, that is, what is fair, what is due? This has led to
a misunderstanding, however. Aquinas certainly thinks that justice always
has this objective dimension of ius as the object of justice, as something
that expresses what is fair or equal in a given human relationship or set
of relationships, but this has led some to argue that Aquinas presents an
understanding of ius, and thus of “right” (or “rights”), as exclusively objective, or at least in a predominantly objective sense. This objective sense of
ius is then contrasted with later natural rights theories that begin to use
the term ius to designate a right or claim that belongs to an individual, one
that he can assert over against others. Here, the argument goes, we find the
origin of a modern understanding of subjective rights: rights as belonging
to a person, a kind of moral faculty that characterizes individual subjects.
9
rem hominem; sive sit iustitia legalis, quae ordinat secundum rectitudinem actum
hominis in comparatione ad bonum commune multitudinis.”
ST II-II, q. 57, a. 1, ad 2.
132
Dominic Legge, O.P.
Yet, if one accepts Aquinas’s account of ius as the object of justice, it
does not at all follow that ius cannot also be understood as a subjective
right, as a claim that one person has over against another. Indeed, this
is merely to reformulate Aquinas’s account from a different perspective.
The reason he emphasizes that ius is the object of justice and that it has an
objective character is to underline that what is due in a particular case does
not depend on the characteristics of the just man, but is rather a measure
external to him. This marks a significant distinction between justice and
the other moral virtues, which do depend on the subjective characteristics
of the person who possesses that virtue. You cannot judge whether a man is
temperate in eating unless you know what is the right measure of food for
him, and that measure will depend on his subjective qualities (for instance,
whether he is an offensive lineman on the college football squad or a sedentary professor who lives in the library), whereas you can judge that an act
is just simply by looking at whether one has rendered what is due, the ius.
This means that justice has a certain objective quality, because there is a
kind of “out-there-ness” to the ius, to “what is due,” that is a function of
the relationship or order between the parties and does not directly depend
on their personal qualities.10
Even so, it is entirely possible to speak about this objective ius from the
perspective of the person to whom it is owed, and even to suggest that a
person can make a claim for what is due to him—he has a “right” to it. This
is simply to regard the objective ius from the point of view of the person
to whom it is due. The objective “due” thus becomes a subjective claim or
right.11
My argument on this point cuts against the grain of most of the scholarship of recent decades on Thomistic natural rights. No less an authority
than Ernest Fortin, the eminent priest and Straussian, claims that the
notion of subjective rights based on natural law or natural justice is absent
10
11
Some additional qualifications are needed here. For example, for Aquinas, more
is due to one holding a particular office than to the average citizen. In the United
States, we recognize this in many ways: all in the courtroom stand when the judge
enters, whom they address as “your honor”; the president, even though he will
someday return to private life, is surrounded by honors and is “due” a personal staff
and an executive mansion in virtue of the office.
John Finnis makes this point quite persuasively, if briefly, in “Aquinas on ius and
Hart on Rights: A Response to Tierney,” Review of Politics 64 (2002): 407–10.
Jean Porter makes a similar argument at much greater length, specifically about
Aquinas’s conception of ius, in “Justice, Equality, and Natural Rights Claims: A
Reconsideration of Aquinas’s Conception of Natural Right,” Journal of Law and
Religion 30 (2015): 446–60.
Do Thomists Have Rights?
133
from, and even foreign to, Aquinas’s thought. Fortin concedes that the
research of Brian Tierney (a historian of natural rights) shows that, in
the century before Aquinas, canonists formulated subjective rights based
on positive law (like the Church’s canon law). But this is a far cry, Fortin
argues, from grounding subjective rights on natural law principles.12 For
his part, Tierney—whose scholarship is regarded as the standard historical
account of the development of subjective rights—accepts the dichotomy
between objective and subjective rights and regards Aquinas as a representative of the objective rights tradition, in opposition to both earlier and
later subjective rights proponents.13
In my view, both Fortin and Tierney are mistaken. In fact, if you read
beyond the narrow slices of the Summa theologiae that political theorists
are wont to consult, Aquinas very explicitly speaks of what is objectively
“due” to someone as a subjective ius or right that he possesses and can
assert. I have come across at least twenty-three different examples of
“subjective ius” in Aquinas.14 For example, he says that “free men . . . have
the right and capacity [ius et facultatem] in some cases to resist the precepts
of a king or prince.”15 In other words, the king’s just authority is limited,
and this same truth can be expressed as a right or faculty belonging to free
citizens. Elsewhere, Aquinas says that, in some matters, a free citizen has
a right of contradicting a ruler, ius contradicendi, which suggests a right to
contradict in speech or even oppose a ruler, as well as to refuse compliance
with the ruler’s commands.16 Aquinas also says that, if one has suffered
an injury, a private person “is able to prosecute his right [ius suum] in the
12
13
14
15
16
Ernest Fortin, “On the Presumed Medieval Origin of Individual Rights,” in
Collected Essays, ed. J. Brian Benestad, vol. 2, Classical Christianity and the Political
Order: Reflections on the Theologico-Political Problem (Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield, 1996), 243–64, esp. 246–47.
Tierney, The Idea of Natural Rights, 257–60. Annabel Brett offers a more nuanced
perspective when she identifies different types of subjective right that she contrasts
with the objective right tradition exemplified by Aquinas (Liberty, Right and
Nature: Individual Rights in Later Scholastic Thought [Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1997], 89–97; 123–24). Even so, the subjective–objective
distinction animates important parts of her analysis.
It is not clear in all twenty-three examples that a subjective ius would correspond
to what we would call a “right.” In some of these texts, ius might be translated as
“authority” rather than “right.” My point here is not that Aquinas has a full-fledged
enumeration of subjective rights, but that it is commonplace in his thought that an
ius would “belong to” a person who could assert or make a claim based on it.
Aquinas, De virtutibus, q. 1, a. 4: “Liberis . . . habent ius et facultatem repugnandi
quantum ad aliqua praecepta regis vel principis.”
ST I-II, q. 58, a. 2: “Liberis . . . habent ius in aliquo contradicendi.”
134
Dominic Legge, O.P.
tribunal of his superior.”17 In other contexts, Thomas speaks of an adopted
child having a right or ius in the adoptive family’s inheritance,18 of the
finder of buried treasure having a right in it,19 of a baptized person having
a right to receive the Eucharist, 20 of the Church as having rights [iura] that
should be defended against usurpation by civil rulers (referring explicitly
to Thomas a Becket and King Henry II of England),21 and even of certain
communities having a right to provide themselves with a king, and thus
also having the capacity to depose a king who becomes a tyrant.22 Many
of these are, in fact, quite close to what later theorists will label natural
rights.23
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
ST II-II, q. 40, a. 1.
ST I-II, q. 114, a. 3.
ST II-II, q. 66, a. 5, ad 2.
ST III, q. 67, a. 2.
Contra impugnantes IV, ch. 3.
De regno I, ch. 7.
In addition to the eight examples just cited, and the ninth discussed just below,
I have found fourteen other examples, across twenty-three different texts, of a
“subjective ius” in Aquinas: ST I-II, q. 96, a. 3 (to protect the right of one’s friend
[ius amici sui] may be a virtuous act of courage); I-II, q. 96, a. 4 (in some cases, a
man should “go the extra mile” by ceding his ius to avoid scandal or disturbance
); II-II, q. 87, a. 3 (a cleric with the care of souls has the right of receiving tithes
[ius accipiendi decimas] from those he serves); II-II, q. 100, a. 2, ad 5 (ius in a
bishopric or any other dignity or prebendary, acquired either through election or
provision); a. 4 (a right of patronage [ius patronatus]—that is, a right to present
clerics for an ecclesiastical benefice); III, q. 67, a. 6 (a cleric in certain cases has a
right of baptizing [ius baptizandi] those under his care); III, q. 57, a. 6, ad 3 (Christ
“acquired for himself and for us, in perpetuity, the right [ius] and the worthiness
of a heavenly dwelling-place”); De decem praeceptis, prol. (charity acquires for us
an ius to the inheritance of God, which is eternal life); Quodlibet II, q. 5, a. 1 (a
father has a right of governance [ius prelationis] over his children for the sake of
the good management of the household); In orationem dominicam, a. 5 (we take
away the ius of God when we prefer our will to his); Super Rom 13, lec. 1 (a king
has rights [iura] to receive tribute from his subjects); In orationem dominicam, a.
2 (a king has an ius in his reign even before that reign is declared); Super Rom 9,
lec. 3 (a king has rights [iura] in his kingship which he rightfully defends against
others); ST II-II, q. 12, a. 2 (the ius dominii of a prince to govern his subjects); I-II,
q. 105, a. 1, ad 5 (it is the king’s ius to draft young men into military service and
to take things from his subjects in order to secure the common good, though this
is often turned into an unjust usurpation by tyrants); I-II, q. 114, a. 1 (paternal ius
and lordly ius); II-II, q. 100, a. 4, ad 4 ( Jacob received a right of inheritance [ius
promogeniturae] by divine election; Super Heb 2, lec. 3 (the ius of primogeniture);
Super Rom 8, lec. 6 (a son has an ius in sharing in the inheritance); Super Matt 25,
lec. 3 (Marietti no. 2095; to take possession of an inheritance belongs to one with
an ius); ST III, q. 46, a. 3, obj. 3 (“the devil had no ius in man because he deceived
Do Thomists Have Rights?
135
One more notable example is worth mentioning because, in it, Aquinas
expressly argues that a right possessed by an individual is based on natural
law. It is found in one of his quodlibetal disputations at the University of
Paris. Quodlibet literally means “ask whatever you please,” and it was a
demanding academic exercise in which other members of the university
could publicly pose to Aquinas a question on any subject they liked, and
he would be expected to give a magisterial answer. In this case, a questioner
asked whether one may baptize Jewish infants even if their parents object.
Aquinas writes:
It would injure Jewish parents if their children were baptized
notwithstanding their objections, because it would violate their
right of parental governance [ius patriae potestatis]. . . . [The reason
is that] it is of natural right [de iure naturali] that a son is under the
care of his father until he gains the use of reason, and hence it would
be contrary to natural justice if, before a child has the capacity for
free choice [liberi arbitrii, the full capacity of free will in someone
who has attained the use of reason, normally around the age of
seven], he were taken away from his parents’ care, or if something
were ordered concerning him notwithstanding his parents’ objections. But after he begins to have the use of free choice, then he
begins to be his own [incipit esse suus], and he is then able to provide
for himself with respect to those things that concern observing
divine or natural law. At that point, he can consent to the faith
and be baptized even if his parents object, though he must not be
induced to accept the faith by coercion, but only by persuasion—yet
not before he has the use of reason.24
In this remarkable text, Aquinas speaks of the parents as suffering an
24
him by fraud”); Super Rom 8, lec. 1 (the devil has no ius regarding the innocent);
Super Ioan 14, lec. 8 (Marietti no. 1975) (because the devil attacked Christ, over
whom he had no right, he deserved to lose what he held justly).
Quodlibet II, q. 4, a. 2, sc and corp.: “Fieret autem Iudaeis iniuria, si eorum filii
baptizarentur eis inuitis, quia amitterent ius patriae potestatis in filios iam fideles.
. . . De iure naturali est quod filius, antequam habeat usum rationis, sit sub cura
patris; unde contra iusticiam naturalem esset, si puer ante quam habeat usum liberi
arbitrii, a cura parentum subtrahatur uel de eo aliquid ordinetur inuitis parentibus.
Postquam autem incipit habere usum liberi arbitrii, iam incipit esse suus et potest,
quantum ad ea quae sunt iuris diuini uel naturalis, sibi ipsi prouidere, et tunc est
inducendus ad fidem non coactione, set persuasione, et potest, etiam inuitis parentibus, consentire fidei et baptizari. Non autem ante quam habeat usum rationis.”
ST II-II, q. 10, a. 12, duplicates this text, nearly word for word.
136
Dominic Legge, O.P.
injury if they are deprived of their ius to raise and govern their children.
No positive law can contravene this right, in Aquinas’s view, because,
according to the order of nature, children are entirely under the care of
their parents until they attain the age of reason. Ius clearly has here a
subjective dimension that is grounded in the natural order of things, and
hence it pertains to the natural law: it is the ius of the parents to raise their
own children, and to violate this ius would do an injury to the parents.
Once the children reach the age of reason, Aquinas thinks the situation changes. Parents still have a right to care for their children, and
children still have to obey their parents with respect to the good ordering
of the household and their education in virtue.25 But as persons now fully
possessed of the use of reason and free will, children come into full possession of themselves, which means that they now enjoy the right to worship
God according to the judgment of their own minds, notwithstanding a
contrary wish of their parents.26 Indeed, this kind of possession of self is,
according to Aquinas, the ultimate root of the equality of justice between
human beings, and it is what makes it possible for us to be due something
in the proper sense of the word, to possess a “right” or ius.
It would not seem a great leap from Aquinas’s reasoning here to an
account of natural rights as belonging to persons in virtue of their nature
as free and rational creatures.27 This was precisely the sort of reasoning
that later Dominican Thomists did articulate in the controversies over the
enslavement of the indigenous peoples of the New World. Indeed, in the
very text I have been quoting, Aquinas expressly says that, even where the
civil law places a man in a state of servitude, he retains his right of parental
governance of his children, and also his right to determine how he himself
will worship God, because these derive from “the order of natural or divine
right [ius].”28 “Nor should anyone disrupt the order of natural right, by
which a son is under the care of his father.”29
This mention of order brings us back to the key dimension of Aqui25
26
27
28
29
Quodlibet II, q. 5, a. 1.
It is hardly surprising that Aquinas takes this position about parental authority,
since he himself, as a teenager, defied his parents and joined the then-fledgling
Dominican Order.
Porter emphasizes this aspect of Aquinas’s thought and argues that it is a feature
of Aquinas’s core commitment to our natural equality, which is grounded in our
“equality of status as free, self-directed rational agents” (“Justice, Equality, and
Natural Rights Claims,” 455–60).
Quodlibet II, q. 4, a. 2, ad 3.
Quodlibet II, q. 4, a. 2, ad 2: “Nec aliquis debet irrumpere ordinem iuris naturalis,
quo filius est sub cura patris.”
Do Thomists Have Rights?
137
nas’s account that I emphasized earlier. Aquinas never considers law, nor
justice, nor ius (the object of justice), as belonging to an individual person
abstracted from a wider teleological order. Rather, a subjective ius or right
is, for Aquinas, always a way of looking at how an individual belongs to a
larger order and is himself teleologically ordered, according to reason, to
a good.
This is true even of the right to worship God according to one’s
conscience, which belongs to individuals who have the use of reason and
free choice. For Aquinas, this right does not belong to them as pure or
absolute individuals, abstracted from the wider order in which man exists.
Rather, that subjective right is itself another way of expressing how man is
ordered to God. Man possesses reason above all so that he can be ordered
to God through it: “Man is ordered to God through reason, by which he
is able to know God. Hence a child, before he has the use of reason, is, by
natural order, ordered to God through the reason of his parents, to whose
care he is naturally subject.”30
Subsequent Thinkers
Let us now shift our focus from Aquinas to subsequent thinkers. The standard historical account generally accepted by all sides in the contemporary
debate over natural rights is that Aquinas lacked a doctrine of subjective
rights, and that the development of such a doctrine in later thinkers involved
a crucial shift from an objective sense of ius to a subjective one. Some praise it
and others decry it, but most agree that the shift from objective to subjective
marks a major change in approaches to law, justice, and rights. As we have
seen, however, Aquinas clearly does sometimes speak of an ius as a right or a
faculty of an individual derived from natural law or natural justice that he can
assert over against other individuals, or even against a civil ruler, the deprivation of which causes him injury, and which he can vindicate by making a legal
claim. To be sure, later thinkers develop a much more substantial account of
subjective rights than Aquinas has. Some also have a theory of natural rights
very different from his, but it is my claim that such theories are different not
because they shift from objective to subjective rights, but primarily because
they have lost sight of the truth that justice, law, and ius all depend on, and
are facets of, a wise or reasoned ordering of individuals to the good.
30
Quodlibet II, q. 4, a. 2, ad 4: “Homo ordinatur ad Deum per rationem, per quam
Deum cognoscere potest: unde puer antequam usum rationis habeat, naturali
ordine ordinatur in Deum per rationem parentum, quorum curae naturaliter subiacet; et secundum eorum dispositionem sunt circa ipsum divina agenda.”
138
Dominic Legge, O.P.
William of Ockham
In the history of moral theology, William of Ockham, the fourteenth-century Franciscan nominalist, is typically identified as the primary culprit
on this score. As we saw earlier, when Aquinas spoke of justice in God, he
held that the plan of God’s wisdom by which all things are ordered back to
God, a plan conceived by the divine intellect, is like a law for God’s willing:
God’s will is just because he always wills in accord with his wise plan of
order. Ockham reverses this because he thinks it denigrates God’s omnipotence to suggest any limitation on what God could will. He thus places
the divine will in the first and highest place, so that whatever God wills is
thereby necessarily just.31 Likewise, where Aquinas had defined law as an
ordination of reason for the common good (a definition that even applied
to divine law), Ockham understood law as ultimately rooted in God’s will,
as a function of God’s command.32
For Ockham, then, law and justice cease to have a reference to a plan of
order to the good and are principally matters of divine will or precept. The
divine will becomes a source and measure of justice, and even of reason—a
position nearly the direct opposite of Aquinas’s. Indeed, Ockham even
thinks that God could change what is just and right merely by changing his command: although God presently forbids us to hate, steal, and
commit adultery, and therefore these acts are wrong, they would be right
and meritorious if God were to command us to do them.33
These changes to the conception of justice and law are the backdrop to
Ockham’s transformation of the meaning of ius in his political writings.34
31
32
33
34
William of Ockham, In I sent., d. 17, q. 3: “Eo ipso quod ipse vult, bene et iuste
factum est” (Opera theologica, vol. 3, Scriptum in librum primum Sententiarum
(Ordinatio), distinctiones IV–XVIII, ed. Girardus I. Etzkorn [St. Bonaventure, NY:
St. Bonaventure University, 1977], 478].
Francis Oakley discusses this point in Ockham’s thought in “Medieval Theories of
Natural Law: William of Ockham and the Significance of the Voluntarist Tradition,” Natural Law Forum 60 (1961): 65–75.
Ockham, In II sent., q. 15 (Opera theologica, vol. 5, Quaestiones in librum secundum
Sententiarum (Reportatio), ed. Gedeon Gál and Rega Wood [St. Bonaventure, NY:
St. Bonaventure University, 1981], 352–53). God could even command the souls
in heaven to hate him, in which case it would be right for them to do so, according
to Ockham in In IV sent., q. 16 (Opera theologica, vol. 7, Quaestiones in librum
quartum Sententiarum (Reportatio), ed. Rega Wood, Gedeon Gál, and Romaldus
Green [St. Bonaventure, NY: St. Bonaventure University, 1984], 352). For Aquinas, such a view is nonsensical, since the beatitude of heaven consists in knowing
and loving God.
Armand Maurer’s judgment is correct (pace Tierney and other recent interpreters
of Ockham’s political thought on rights): Ockham’s political works should be read
Do Thomists Have Rights?
139
Whereas Aquinas had spoken of ius as the object of justice, or what is due
to someone in view of the complex ordering of individuals and communities to the good, such a conception of ius no longer makes any sense in
Ockham’s system of thought. Law and justice are principally matters of
precepts handed down from above, demanding obedience of the will. For
Ockham, the exterior act that one performs (such as eating, drinking,
dressing, writing, reading in a book, or riding), considered as a matter of
factual occurrence, is morally neutral.35 What gives it its moral character
is the will of the person who acts, namely, whether the person is actually
willing prudently to act in conformity with the divine will according to
the judgment of his or her conscience.36 Consequently, he conceives of ius
as a function of a positive grant of a privilege, a kind of positive enactment
by the will of the sovereign. For Ockham, therefore, most rights are positive rights had “by some enactment or human agreement.”37 Ockham does
acknowledge the existence of natural rights, ius “had from nature,”38 but
he seems to think of this along the same lines as a positive right: this ius
arises from a kind of divine grant by which God gives a privilege to man
that can be used as man sees fit. Thus, according to Ockham, in creating
man, God gave to him a certain dominion, a legitimate sphere of activity
and agency on matters not directly controlled by a precept of justice or
35
36
37
38
in continuity with his theological works (The Philosophy of William of Ockham
in the Light of Its Principles [Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies,
1999], 537). When one does so, one can see the deep coherence between them.
After all, Ockham was one of the most brilliant minds of the fourteenth century,
and one should expect that the core principles in one domain of his thought would
not be abandoned another.
Ockham, Opus nonaginta dierum 2, in A Translation of William of Ockham’s Work
of Ninety Days, vol. 1, trans. John Kilcullen and John Scott (Lewiston, NY: The
Edwin Mellon Press, 2001).
This is evident if one examines Ockham’s understanding of “actual prudence”
(which he distinguishes from “habitual prudence”). Actual prudence, on his view,
is something that “in no way is in our power,” but rather is generated in us, moment
by moment, by God. If God generates this actual prudence in you directing you
to do some act and you then will to do it, the resulting act is virtuous. But if, in
the midst of carrying out that act, God should cease to generate in you the actual
prudence telling you that this act is to be done but you continue to carry out the
act, your action is transformed from being virtuous into being vicious (Ockham,
Quaestiones variae, q. 8, a., in Opera theologica, vol. 8, Quaestiones variae, ed. Girardus I. Etzkorn, Franciscus E. Kelley, and Josephus C. Wey [St. Bonaventure, NY:
St. Bonaventure University, 1984], 409–20).
Ockham, Opus nonaginta dierum 61.
Ockham, Opus nonaginta dierum.
140
Dominic Legge, O.P.
divine command.39 It was here that Ockham located a person’s natural
ius, which he defined as a “licit power of a subject.”40 Within this sphere,
an individual can freely use, or not use, whatever belongs to him, his ius.41
In sum, then, order, reason, and the good have been displaced in
Ockham’s thought from the central role they played in Aquinas’s. For
Ockham, justice and law do not necessarily involve an ordering to the good
according to reason. Rather, they are matters of moral obligation: a precept
of the divine will calls for man’s will to obey. Consequently, ius is no longer
understood as a function of an ordering to the good, but rather is a feature
of the sphere of personal dominion granted to man by God, where man has
the licit power to act as he sees fit as long as he remains within the bounds
of the commands of God.
Francisco Suarez
It is important, however, that we not stop here, because some subsequent
figures—including those who oppose Ockham’s nominalism and claim to
be interpreting Aquinas’s thought—also lost sight of this crucial dimension
of St. Thomas’s thought. This is particularly the case with Francisco Suarez,
the great Jesuit who, in the early part of the seventeenth century, stands at
the origin of the distinctive Jesuit line of interpretation of Aquinas. (The
founder of the Jesuits, St. Ignatius of Loyola, had designated Aquinas as
the preferred theologian for his new society, and the Jesuits subsequently
adopted Aquinas as their principal teacher in “Scholastic theology.”42) In
1612, Suarez published his De legibus ac deo legislatore, a massive treatise
of moral and legal theory. As an obedient Jesuit, he consistently cites
Aquinas throughout, which might give the impression that he is simply
handing on and elaborating on the teaching of the Angelic Doctor. But he
in fact consistently alters the meanings of the terms of Aquinas, ultimately
producing a doctrine of law, justice, and rights that is different from the
great Dominican thinker in some notable ways.
At the start of his treatise, Suarez sets out to define law, lex. For Suarez,
the essence of law is not an ordination of reason to the common good, as
Aquinas taught. Rather, Suarez reframes it thus: “Law is a certain measure
39
40
41
42
Ockham, Opus nonaginta dierum 14: “complete power to subject and rule all
temporal things and power to use such things.” See also: Opus nonaginta dierum
2; Brett, Liberty, Right, and Nature, 65–66.
Ockham, Opus nonaginta dierum 61.
Brett, Liberty, Right, and Nature, 62–68.
See Andrés I. Prieto, Missionary Scientists: Jesuit Science in Spanish South America,
1570–1810 (Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press, 2011), 161.
Do Thomists Have Rights?
141
of moral acts, in the sense that such acts are characterized by moral rectitude through their conformity to law.”43 He then adds: “In the strict
sense of the term, only that is law which imposes an obligation of some
sort.”44 Entirely absent from Suarez’s initial definition is any reference to
an ordering to the common good. Law is first of all about moral precepts:
one’s actions are good when they conform to the commands of a superior.
As a result, even the terms “good” and “end” (which pepper Aquinas’s
discussion of law and justice) largely disappear from Suarez’s treatment,
replaced instead with the terms “right” and “wrong,”45 measures not of
whether an action produces the good or leads an actor to his proper end,
but rather of whether an actor’s will is conformed to the moral command
of his superior.
To be sure, Suarez does discuss the common good seventy-five pages later
in his treatise, in chapter VII. But his understanding of the common good is
far less robust than Aquinas’s, and it does not enter into the very definition
of law. Rather, having defined law as a binding moral rule that imposes an
obligation, he later adds, as a subsequent “characteristic condition,” that it
should be enacted for the sake of the common good.46 To put this another
way, the central element of law—that law imposes an obligation—is derived
from the will of the lawgiver who hands down the rule, whereas the fact
that a law is ordered to “what is good and necessary” pertains to the lawgiver’s intellect.47 And in the final analysis, Suarez affirms that the will of the
legislator is primary and that his act of intellect gives shape to what his will
has determined. Law, for Suarez, is therefore principally an act of the will of
the legislator: “Law . . . as it exists in the lawmaker himself, is the act of a just
and upright will, the act whereby a superior wills to bind an inferior to the
performance of a particular deed.”48
A similar transformation is also evident when Suarez examines the
meaning of ius. While he acknowledges that ius can designate the object of
justice, the true meaning of the word ius—its more strict and proper mean43
44
45
46
47
48
Francisco Suarez, De legibus 1.1.5. All quotations from the De legibus are taken
from Francisco Suarez, Selections from Three Works, ed. Thomas Pink, trans. Gwladys L. Williams, Ammi Brown, and John Waldron (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty
Fund, 2015).
Suarez, De legibus 1.1.7.
John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980),
46.
See Suarez, De legibus 1.1.7: “It shall be formulated particularly with reference to
that good.”
Saurez, De legibus 1.5.21.
Suarez, De legibus 1.5.24.
142
Dominic Legge, O.P.
ing—is, he says, “a certain moral power which every man has, either over
his own property or with respect to that which is due to him.”49 Suarez’s
definition differs from Aquinas’s not so much in the fact that ius can refer
to a subjective right or faculty, but rather in that ius no longer, for Suarez,
has any intrinsic reference to a wider order of relationships, nor is there any
reference to a teleological ordering to the common good. (For Aquinas, it
was precisely an individual’s place in a wider teleological order that gives
rise to the ius.)
What is more, Suarez reverses the relationship of ius and lex, or law. In
St. Thomas, ius is the just thing, the form of law, and thus the exemplar
according to which a written law is crafted. For Suarez, however, law is the
moral rule handed down by the will of a superior, and ius is the faculty or
moral power that an individual possesses in virtue of the law.
Drawing Conclusions: Do Thomists Have Rights?
Because Suarez’s teaching was so influential among Catholic natural
law thinkers, and especially among later Jesuit Thomists, contemporary
commentators often assume that Suarez offers standard Thomistic natural
law teaching. Fortin is a good example. He holds that the key break with
Thomistic natural law teaching—the line between classical natural right
and modern natural rights, if you will—is located not somewhere in the
three centuries between Aquinas and Suarez, but in the three decades
between Suarez and Hobbes.50
Yet, as I hope is now evident, Suarez’s account of law, justice, and rights
has a character fundamentally different from Aquinas’s, though not
because of a shift from an objective sense of ius to a subjective one. Rather,
the difference is twofold: (1) the loss of the recognition that law is fundamentally an ordination of reason to the common good, not the imposition
of an obligation by the will of a superior; and (2) the loss of the sense that
ius is a feature of the overarching teleological order to the good in which
the rational creature is placed, rather than a moral power of the creature
considered without reference to that order. Suarez may not be the source
of these changes (one might wonder whether William of Ockham bears
49
50
Suarez, De legibus 1.2.5.
Fortin, Collected Essays, 2:273: “The real ‘watershed’ in the history of the rights
doctrine is not to be located somewhere between Thomas and Suarez; it occurs
with Hobbes, who set the stage for all subsequent discussion of this matter by
denying that human beings are political by nature (something that Suarez and
Grotius never did) and by proclaiming the absolute priority of rights to duties.”
See also 2:248.
Do Thomists Have Rights?
143
some responsibility for them, or even Duns Scotus51), but he is a major
figure in their history. And it seems to me that these two changes together
constitute the mainspring of the development of modern theories of natural rights, with their strengths but also the notable weaknesses identified
by Strauss and others.
Should we try to return to the purity of the original Thomistic doctrine?
Jesuit Thomists after Suarez may have modern rights, but do Dominican
Thomists have rights? Can we formulate a Thomistic doctrine of rights
that would be plausible today?
I would like to answer by summarizing the essentials of what I take
to be Thomas’s position. The ius, or what is due to another, the object of
justice, depends, first, on the overarching order of the cosmos, which is
laid out according to God’s wisdom, and is therefore both intelligible and
teleological, and which is composed of persons endowed with reason and
free choice who are members of various communities that are themselves
arranged in hierarchical order. Then, second, this ius is a function of the
relationality that follows from the place that these persons have in this
order.52 Nor is this order an abstraction: it is the concrete, particular, historical order in which I find myself. Man comes into the world as the child of
parents, living in a human community, as a creature under God. He has
not himself created or generated this order. Consequently, man necessarily
and inevitably exists in an interlocking web of relationships, of belonging
as a part to other wholes: his family, his clan, his city, the whole human
race, the whole body of Christ, the whole of creation. These relationships
are not constituted by man’s choice. Rather, we could say that man is naturally and originally in these relationships.
Aquinas’s understanding of justice, and thus of rights, is therefore
quite different from the Enlightenment and post-Enlightenment accounts
derived from social contract theory, which postulate that man exists first
as a kind of independent individual in a primitive “state of nature,” and
therefore brings to the relationships he chooses to enter certain fundamen51
52
MacIntyre, for one, identifies Scotus as a seminal figure, a precursor to Ockham
and Kant, in the philosophical line of thought that accords primacy to the will
over the intellect, and consequently that sees natural law as a matter of obedience
to divine commands (Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry, 155).
On this theme generally, see Christopher A. Franks, “Aristotelian Doctrines in
Aquinas’s treatment of Justice,” in Aristotle in Aquinas’s Theology, ed. Gilles Emery
and Matthew Levering (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), 143–47. I got
from Franks the idea to conceive of justice as relational. Of course, Aquinas transforms this idea from Aristotle because he understands all men to be in relation to
God and to all other men in the civitas Dei.
144
Dominic Legge, O.P.
tal rights that are, in a sense, anterior to those relationships. Such theories,
whether we are speaking of Hobbes, Locke, or more recent authors like
John Rawls, tend to abstract from the concrete historical relationships
and, we might say, the initial conditions into which we are in fact born.
They aim at developing an account of the basic or fundamental rights
that human beings have purely in virtue of being human, such that justice
becomes, at least in part, granting what is due in virtue of those rights, and
so that individuals can then pursue whatever goods they deem worthy of
their choice.
For Aquinas, in contrast, the ultimate end of man is not a matter of
arbitrary choice, not even for God. The whole plan of divine providence
originates in God’s wisdom as an ordination of reason with respect to
the good. And so, we are born into the world as creatures who naturally
occupy a place in that order, and who are naturally ordered to a final end,
a good, that we do not choose. Neither are our relationships matters of
choice; we simply are in certain relationships: familial relations, relations
with our neighbors, membership in a larger political and civic community,
and so on. Justice thus has to do with our right ordering to the good that
we do not determine for ourselves. It is based on a reality outside of us, in
the order of relations in which we inevitably exist.
For a Thomist, then, rights are not properties of individuals as moral
monads. Nor can we find the source of rights in an abstract definition
of human nature, but rather by considering man as a rational and free
creature ordered to God and to the common good of the hierarchy of
communities to which he belongs. This allows us to see, then, how rights
are connected to justice, to teleology, and to the common good.
In relation to Justice: Rights are a way of looking at what is due, the ius or
iustum, insofar as it is due to someone who can then seek to have that “due”
vindicated. This is, in Thomistic terms, a “right.” Because of man’s nature,
we can draw certain conclusions about what man is, what man ought to
be, and therefore how we should treat other persons, since they are equal
to us insofar as they are human. Yet rights are not functions of individuals
as individuals, but rather of persons who belong in a hierarchy of ordered
wholes (families, cities, the whole human race, the whole cosmos), each of
which has its own common good.
In relation to Teleology and the Common Good: Law is teleological. It is
always ordered to the common good, either real or merely apparent. And
rights are likewise teleological: they affirm what is required for persons to
be rightly ordered to each other and to the political authority in view of the
common good. Thus, to respect the rights of another, to give him what is
due to him, not only pertains to his private good, but means acting in right
Do Thomists Have Rights?
145
relationship to the order of the whole, to the common good.
Indeed, Aquinas teaches that man’s ends are not arranged side-by-side
on a horizontal plane, but exist in an ordered hierarchy: he is ordered to
individual goods (like the good of his biological life), and then to higher
and nobler common goods (like the good life that he shares in a virtuous
family, a flourishing and friendly neighborhood, and a just city), and ultimately to God, the universal common good of the whole universe. Laws of
various kinds direct man toward these various levels of good. Rights can
therefore also be understood as a function of a just ordering of each person
toward the common good.
Note, though, how this view differs from a typical contemporary theory
of rights. In the classical Thomistic view, the end (the common good) and
the ordering of the community to that end are primary. Rights articulate
claims of justice in relation to the end. Consequently, rights are not absolute or unlimited claims, nor are they themselves the ultimate foundation
of or reason for our political community. Rather, rights always point to
something further and nobler than an individual or private good: the
common good of the whole. This is not to say, of course, that individual
rights must always bow before the demands of the political authority. To
the contrary, Aquinas holds that some rights are a function of the order of
man to a good that is prior to or transcends the political community (as we
saw him argue concerning the right of a parent to care for his child). But
even these rights do not stand on their own; rather, they stand in virtue of
their relation to a good.
Contemporary rights theorists might object that this classical Thomistic view subordinates the liberty that individual rights guarantee under the
common good in such a way that those rights will be endangered whenever
the government (or the majority) find them inconvenient. Is this not, they
would ask, precisely the reason why we should affirm the primacy of individual rights understood as anterior to political society and independent
of the common good? A complete answer to this objection would require
much longer treatment than can be provided here, but we can at least
identify the confusion about the common good hiding in such questions.
From Aquinas’s perspective, the common good is not something that
competes with the good of individuals, nor is it like other private goods
that are diminished when they are shared (e.g., more people invited to the
party means a smaller slice of cake for each). A common good is precisely
the kind of good that can be shared by many without diminishment, like
the good of victory for a sports team, or the good of justice in a city, or
the good of peace among states. To say that rights stand in relation to a
good, then, is not to say that some kind of alien or hostile “common good”
Dominic Legge, O.P.
146
trumps or even destroys the good of the individual. Rather, the common
good is a good for the individual, a good of a higher and nobler sort in
which the individual participates, and without which it is impossible to
have a full measure of human happiness. Human beings are ordered not
only to private goods like food and shelter but also to common goods
like justice, truth, civic friendship, and peace, and without at least some
measure of these common goods, they will neither flourish nor be truly
happy. As Aquinas puts it (paraphrasing Aristotle’s Politics), the city exists
“not only that men might live, but that they might live well.”53 That individuals have rights that they can assert, rights that the positive law should
recognize, pertains, therefore, not only to the private good of individuals,
but to the common good of the community: the “Blessings of Liberty”
(as the Preamble to the U.S. Constitution puts it) should not be thought
of as describing a merely private good, the individual property of discrete
individuals, but rather a dimension of the common good. It is part of the
common good that the community be just, that it recognize what is due to
its members, that it be governed by the rule of law, and that it be composed
of free citizens capable of directing their own lives by their own responsible choices. When the law acknowledges and protects the just right of a
citizen, it is doing something quite different from pork-barrel spending
that hands out material benefits (that is, essentially private goods) to the
favored clients of the ruler. Acknowledging what is due to individuals is (at
least in part) what makes a society just.
On this view, then, individual rights are not set over against the
common good, as if an increase in the common good necessitated a diminishment of individual liberty. Rather, that individuals be secure in their
liberties as citizens—that they “possess rights”—is precisely an aspect or
dimension of the common good, and the protection of those rights in
law is a means for securing the common good of a just republic. In all of
this, subjective rights are understood as a function of an overarching order
toward a good. To put it another way, rights are important (or even fundamental and indispensable) precisely because of the overarching primacy of
the common good and the place that each individual has in the order of
the whole.
Does this theory of rights offer a plausible alternative for our present
political culture? Whether it would win many votes in a popular election,
I will not presume to judge, but I think Aquinas would say that, no matter
what theory we construct, in actual fact, by the very nature of the case,
rights unavoidably and always are founded on some prior judgment about
53
Aquinas, In I pol., ch. 1.
Do Thomists Have Rights?
147
the good, either the good for individual persons or the good for the human
community. If that is true, then our epoch’s shrill and proliferating claims
of incompatible rights should tell us that, behind this camouflage, there is
a deeper and more radical disagreement about what is good. Our political
life can improve only if we bring this disagreement out into the open,
where we can have an honest debate about the true end of our common
life together.
There are some contemporary critics of the rights claims found in
classically liberal political regimes who view such rights as the product
of an Enlightenment mode of thought, containing a kind of poison pill
ultimately destructive of the justice of such regimes. On such a view, one
might argue that the American project was doomed to failure from the
start: we should not be surprised that expanding rights claims have become
the source of deep and enduring political conflict, and they are producing
a regime that is increasingly illiberal. This is the inevitable corruption and
self-contradiction of a regime built on a foundation of natural rights.
I hope it is evident that my argument is in a way the opposite of this
view. While it may be true that certain Enlightenment versions of rights
create mischief—namely, they set up insoluble political conflicts—it is not
clear that the notion of rights must necessarily produce this kind of situation. My claim is that, underlying all rights claims there is always an orientation to some good, and so there always remains a real possibility to have
a classical debate about how a community should order itself to the good.
In other words, a regime that recognizes natural rights has not necessarily
swallowed a poison pill, and a good Thomist can be a proponent of rights.
What is more, our present regime does not necessarily need radical surgery
to fix the problem. Rather, we need to recognize what is in fact already
there: that rights necessarily involve an ordering to the good. Once one sees
this, one can see how a regime like ours can be defended on Thomist terms.
So, in the end, do Thomists have rights? Yes. Does anyone else? Maybe
not, at least, perhaps not the kinds of rights that work for a healthy
N&V
political order.