Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Democracy in the Digital World - Wilson Gomes.pdf

Democracy in the digital world: History, issues and themes, 2018
In times of crisis of representation the question of what kind of democracy can be achieved through the expansion of new technologies emerges with renewed vigor. Is it direct democracy or yet another appendage of representative democracy? Is it democracy as understood by classical liberals, libertarians or communitarians? Is it deliberative or participatory electronic democracy? In the first book of the Digital Democracy series, Professor Wilson Gomes draws on ten years of research on the subject to present a historical cross section of the idea of electronic and digital democracy, addressing themes such as transparency, public sphere, participation and political deliberation. PhD in Philosophy and coordinator of the Center for Advanced Studies in Digital Democracy of the Federal University of Bahia (Ufba), Gomes divides his book into three periods: "1970-1995 - The origins of the idea of electronic democracy – Teledemocracy"; "1996-2005 - The consolidation of the idea of digital democracy"; and "2006-2015 - The state of digital democracy". As Gomes summarizes: "The history of the idea that it was possible to improve democratic processes through information technology can naturally go a long way back, as the invention and, above all, the massification of new communication media have always been accompanied by renewed hopes for improvement in democracy and public life...Read more
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS The manuscripts that originated this book were generously discussed by researchers at the Center for Advanced Studies in Digital Democracy and Electronic Government of the Federal University of Bahia. I am very grateful to Dilvan Azevedo, Rodrigo Carreiro, Maria Paula Almada, Lucas Reis, Tatiana Dourado, Eurico Matos, Pedro Mesquita, Maria Dominguez, Robson Carneiro, Isabele Mitozo and Samuel Barros for the criticisms, corrections and suggestions offered. CONTENTS Presentation Preface Introduction Chapter 1 1970-1995: The origins of the idea of electronic democracy – teledemocracy To democracy via technology Teledemocracy as a project The dimensions of digital democracy Registering public opinion Information, data Debate, discussion, horizontal communication Decision making Chapter 2 1996-2005: the consolidation of the idea of digital democracy Digital democracy takes off The impact of technology on democracy: the controversy on the effects The phase of models of democracy Facing the last resistances Chapter 3 2006-2015: the state of digital democracy A new internet Themes and trends in recent years New trends in digital democracy To conclude References About the author Credits S INCE THE LATE 1990s, with the spread of the internet, words such as interaction, collaboration, exchange, recombination and sharing have come not only to organize the grammar of digital networks but also to influence the social dynamic itself. It is a set of expressions related to forms of production and distribution of information and knowledge that uncover new scenarios, demanding reflexive efforts to understand its effects on communication and culture, as well as on education, economy and politics. Today, the reach of the digital connection networks in a country of continental dimensions such as Brazil is evident. If, on the one hand, internet promotes an unprecedented enhancement in remote interactions and an exponential increase in access and production of content, on the other hand, there is a fierce dispute over attentions (and accessions) in its environment, which are increasingly narrowed to a limited range of platforms, sites and applications. With the growing use of networks in the country, issues such as freedom, human rights, social equality, censorship, gender and race populate the daily life of virtual forums, often providing alternatives to the type of approach developed in traditional media such as radio, the TV and the written press. This is due, among other factors, to the relativization of the division between those who dictate and those who consume information, as this boundary is currently being erased. Since the expansion of the network leverages the multiplication of data volume and its corresponding dissemination in the public sphere, and it also stimulates the participation of an increasing number of people in the discussions on subject matters of common interest, we should ask ourselves about the real impact, in the public eye, of this way of circulating information and voices. In this sense, it is promising to create a collection that aims to bring together Brazilian authors dedicated to thinking about the dynamics of digital connection networks, investigating their influence on the direction of democracy. Edited by the sociologist and PhD in Political Sciences Sergio Amadeu da Silveira, the Digital Democracy series invites researchers from the field of digital culture to scrutinize, from different approaches, the recent history of this ambivalent relation. Within this series, the book Democracy in the Digital World: History, Issues and Themes, by Wilson Gomes, guides us more securely through the history of this democracy so distinctively designed by the contemporary world. An itinerary, in the author’s own words, to follow the formation of a new, transformative idea, whether regarding its meandering uniqueness or the historical meaning of many terms used for comprehension on broader scale. With a clear and direct language, the Digital Democracy series also seeks to awaken the interest of researchers in the area of technology and communication, as well as that of a more comprehensive readership, who are surrounded in their daily life by permanently connected technological devices. This publication in digital format makes use of a support capable to expand the possibilities of accessing studies about central aspects of contemporary life. In this way, it reinforces the role of reading as a key feature in education conceived on an emancipatory basis, using digital technology as a tool propitious for a critical, inventive and renewing social space. Danilo Santos de Miranda Regional Director of Sesc São Paulo L IVES CONNECTED IN HIGH-SPEED data flows through georeferenced devices. In the past it would have sounded like fiction. Today it sounds like a trite description, a commonplace. Our everyday life is teeming with information technologies that have come to mediate much of our social interaction. Technological hopes thrive and become marketing ploys, creating loyalty to and passion for the brands of big corporations that sell state-of-the-art gadgets. But the technology leaps unveil scenarios of risks and dystopias. The fear of automation, algorithmic prediction, artificial intelligence or corporate control over human beings has produced research and fiction. In order to discuss the complex relationship between technology and democratic societies, from the human and social sciences point of view, we now launch the Digital Democracy series, featuring works that address topics closely linked to the expansion of technologies, such as hacker culture, intellectual property, algorithms and democracy. The series includes reflections on the implications of digital technologies – especially cybernetic (Wiener) – in societies that can be called of control (Deleuze), in an informational (Castells), surveillance (Zuboff) and platform-based (Srnicek) capitalism, delimited by a neoliberal order (Laval, Dardot). In this volume, one of the most important of the series, the professor and researcher Wilson Gomes has successfully gathered, both critically and creatively, theoretical approaches to digital democracy, from the origins of the concept in the 20th century to our days, analyzing notions of the disputes and solutions envisioned for the obstacles and possibilities stemming from the appearance of newer, more agile and more pervasive technologies. It is, therefore, an indispensable reading for anyone who researches, studies or takes an interest in the subject, since, despite the theoretical rigor, it was written to be read and understood by non-specialists. The journey narrated by Gomes is one worth following. I find it particularly striking how people once believed and placed their hopes in television as a means to organize the participation of the society. Today, teledemocracy may seem farfetched, but it shows that over time technologies have kindled the hopes of people who seek to overcome or solve issues of social power relations through technique. One of the main legacies of modernity. Scrutinizing the theories of digital democracy, the author discusses political participation in digital networks, the so-called e-deliberation, the structuring of the public sphere vis-à-vis the internet, the obstacles to and advances of etransparency and the digital divide as one of the limits of the democratic process. While attempting to stick to the main theme, Gomes could hardly fulfill his mission without addressing or mentioning online political participation and the issues of digital governments and parliaments. This book thus fills a gap in the scientific literature on digital democracy. In somber times, of serious crisis and doubts about the democratic conditions of our country, it makes us reflect beyond the possibilities of digital technologies to improve the quality of democracy, political representation and processes of deliberation and participation. It is opportune to remember that digital technologies are a product of cybernetics, the science of communication and control. The internet is a network in which the digital traces left by its users are aggregated and analyzed by data brokers that identify them and sell them to marketing companies. Online social networking had focused the attention of connected citizens of both genders and hosted major clashes of electoral disputes in Western democracies in the second decade of the 21st century. Intriguingly, heated debates have emerged on the corrosion of democracies in technologically mediated environments due to the opacity of the algorithms and codes that control them, the speed of the so-called fake news, adherence to post-truth rituals, in short, the huge concentration of traffic in few technological platforms. In this sense, the issues raised by Wilson Gomes may help us understand the ambivalent role played by technologies in democracies. Sergio Amadeu da Silveira T HIS BOOK INTENDS TO PROVIDE AN ITINERARY to help readers understand the development of the idea of digital democracy, which is the conception according to which technological resources, projects based on communication technologies and even personal and social experiences in the use of communication and information technologies can be employed to produce more democracy and better democracies. The history of the idea of digital democracy is the history of the implementation of e-democracy in projects and experiments, but also, unintentionally, of the social uses of technology. Moreover, it is also the history of the public talk, in political environments or in the media, in the form of discourses, publications and debates, about what technology could or should do for – or against – democracy. Finally, it is the history of academic or scientific attention to e-democracy, of the bibliography on the subject from the first formulations to contemporary developments, of the formation and consolidation of lines and trends of research, of the constitution of the scientific field of digital democracy. The three elements are fairly well documented and, owing to the very brevity of this history, the memory of the entire journey is still largely available. But the study of academic attention provides the most promising path for two reasons. Firstly, materials such as articles, chapters, books, works in conference proceedings and papers are more reliable, more abundant and more available in their complete format. Scientific discourse is obliged to be systematic, careful and comprehensive, which cannot be said of the other two types of materials. Secondly, scientific publications reflect, address and often have as subject, throughout the entire history, the projects and public debate on digital democracy. The opposite is not true, since experiments and debates in the public sphere, for example, do not necessarily reflect the state of the art of research and, as they are focused on responding to specific functions, they hardly keep in view the current e-democratic issues as a whole. Therefore, the reconstruction of the history of the idea of digital democracy in its broader lines is directly based on the academic attention given to the theme in the last 45 years. And, indirectly, on the public debate and experiments carried out over those years, since they are reflected in scientific attention. The material used consists of a collection of little over two thousand titles gathered and classified by me in the last ten years, mainly in English and Portuguese1, and which comprises, under any metric used, the main literature of the area of digital democracy. When necessary I partly drew on another collection, gathered in the same way, with around 2,500 titles, from the areas of digital government and online politics2. This enabled the design of a graphic representation of the area (its themes, its trends), which, presented in a timeline, reveals the course of the conception of digital democracy from its origins to our days. Thus it was possible to provide readers desiring an overview of this subject with a fairly reliable map and chronology about the origins, trajectory and future directions of digital democracy, as well as the history of its main issues, debates and questions. The chronological approach, in the format of a history of the issue, is actually an innovation in the case of digital democracy, a theme often subjected to systematic discussions on general problems or particular questions, and, to the best of my knowledge, no other book adopts such an approach. Do readers therefore deserve an explanation as to why I did not simply address the main themes and most decisive discussions of digital democracy, drawing mainly on the current state of affairs? A lot of uncertainty has prevailed in the area, which still produces considerable damage when adequate links are not established between concepts, problematizations and viewpoints adopted at a given moment and the state of affairs at that precise moment. A proper understanding of the state of affairs, which means one that considers changes over time, involves understanding: • the technology standard adopted at a given moment; • the stage of development, innovation and social use of technology at that precise moment; • the specificities of the discussion developed in that context, the “parties” and interests involved; • the intellectual benchmarks considered by the authors of a given moment. That is why it is different understanding, for example, a proposition of electronic democracy when somebody has cable television in mind; or of cyberdemocracy in a society that is discovering home computers; or of digital democracy in a society of the internet of things, big data and social media. In the same tone, a discussion of technology-based democracy in a context in which democratic theory is most concerned with participatory democracy cannot be similar to one in which deliberative democracy exerts considerable attraction on the imagination of democratic minds. I start out from the hypothesis that in order to make more refined distinctions, fairer and more adequate analyses or appropriate reconstructions of problems it is important to at least once link the issues, themes and discussions to the historical contexts in which they are inserted. Being a short book, its course is also naturally brief. But it tried to be faithful to the topography of the area and the trajectories therein contained. In addition, it was conceived as an introduction to e-democracy, to present the subject to a non-specialist reader, but who is interested in acquiring a practical grasp of digital democracy. I hope I have succeeded in that purpose. I must say that even for me, who have been working since 2001 in a field that only actually started in 1996, it was important to try to formulate a reconstruction of the history and produce a reliable map of what, after all, happened in this brief, extremely fast and definitely intense twenty-year span of digital democracy − which, not accidently, was the one that swept us up in the 20th century and launched us into the whirlwind of innovations of the new century. Digital democracy is the offspring of the turn of the millennium and naturally reflects the dizzying speed it inherited from that moment. In this sense, a pause to locate ourselves on the map, understand where we came from and decide where we want to go seems to be not only important but necessary. I sincerely hope readers will appreciate the map provided by this small book. This volume is divided into three parts, each corresponding to one of the periods in the history of digital democracy. • The first is the formative period of the idea of democracy via technology, from the first formulations of the 1970s to the period of the great debate on teledemocracy between the late 1980s and the middle of the following decade. The second and third parts address digital democracy in its strictest sense, over the period that extends until the present, when hopes for e-democracy are based on internet technologies. • The second part is longer and features the debates, the themes, the typical issues of the 1996-2005 decade, the turn of the millennium when the idea of digital democracy was consolidated. Debates, themes and issues that will definitely mark the field, so far. • The third part is shorter and addresses the problems, changes and trends typical of the last eleven years up to our times. It examines the behavior of the themes of the previous decade, discusses the new themes and points out future trends and gaps to be filled in digital democracy studies and projects. This section will be shorter, mainly because it is largely an unfolding of the trends, conceptions, and premises established in the great debates at the turn of the millennium. Lastly, an important conceptual explanation to properly introduce readers to the universe of interactions between democracy and technology. An attempt is made in this book to restrict the subject matter to the field of digital democracy and its new and traditional themes. In an earlier publication (Gomes, 2016a), I believe I have shown that e-democracy has become, especially from the turn of the century onwards, part of the broader field dealing with the impact of technology on public life. TABLE 1 The field of digital politics, democracy and state Online politics Digital democracy • Campaign and elections • Theory of digital democracy • Digital government • Political participation • E-Participation Digital state • Governance • Participation and cooperation • News and politics • Politicians, parties and institutions • Internet and society • Political discussions • E-Deliberation and the public sphere • E-Transparency • Digital divide • Delivery of public services • Open government and open data • Smart cities • Digital parliament In Table 1, digital democracy lies precisely in the middle, between the subfields of online politics and digital government (or state). The interfaces between digital democracy and the other two fields are quite significant, above all because e-democracy was born first and provides most of the social legitimacy on which the entire larger area is grounded. In other words, digital governments must be efficient, economical and modern, but they also have to be democratic; politics happens almost entirely online, but remains committed to the normative horizon of liberal democracy, at least in our societies. These are intersections, not confusions or indifferences: each area has its particularities, aspects, dimensions, purposes. And its own themes. I resorted to such interactions here whenever relevant, but it should be clear that I did not presume the themes and problems related to digital government or online politics to be automatically part of the digital democracy repertoire. 1 Nevertheless, there is also literature available in Spanish, Italian, French, and German. 2 This is a collection of metadata, treated on the Mendel platform, resulting from a permanent project of the Center for Advanced Studies in Digital Democracy and Electronic Government (CEADD) of the Federal University of Bahia, the main laboratory of the National Institute of Science & Technology in Digital Democracy (INCT.DD). It is widely believed that it would be impossible for millions of people to have the kind of participatory democracy available to the members of small communities such as the Greek polis, New England towns, and Israeli Kibbutzim. In contemporary modern societies, there are no effective means by which large groups of citizens, whether dispersed across the country or clustered in a single community, can regularly interact among themselves or with their leaders. […] At last there is a basic conception of the attributes needed to create a technological system that will allow a large number of citizens, dispersed throughout their communities and throughout the nation, to dialogue with each other regularly and to form their positions on public issues as a group. Amitai Etzioni To democracy via technology T HE NOTION OF DIGITAL DEMOCRACY1 did not emerge all at once, but it was developed step by step. The idea that technology could be useful to build more democratic societies was gradually constructed over at least 45 years. Much changed during this span of time, starting with the designation of the phenomenon, called successively electronic town meetings (Etzioni, 1972), teledemocracy (Arterton, 1987), electronic democracy (Varley, 1991), virtual democracy (Hacker; Todino, 1996), cyberdemocracy (Ogden, 1994), computer democracy (Buchstein, 1997), and digital democracy (Hale; Musso; Weare, 1999). Not to mention a large number of adjectives and nouns whose mere association with the word “democracy” sufficed to express the same idea: online, technology, new technologies, information and communications technologies (ICTs), web, etc. Obviously, the choice of the word associated with “democracy” bestows on it a specific meaning (Porebski, 2002): the “distance” (as in “distance education”), the cybernetics, the electronic technologies, the online connection, the means of transmission. Moreover, it took some time to reach a solid consensus on the elements addressed and hence referred to by the idea of digital democracy and, consequently, by its experiments, applications, tools, devices, institutions and functions. In different historical phases, for example, different means of communication prevailed, but between the telegraph and the permanently connected smartphone lies a huge difference of scope and meaning. It is one thing to think of mechanisms of televoting; it is quite another to consider big data and open government data. Thirdly, the very idea of democracy is a complex notion; it can be polysemous and admits a considerable dose of legitimate pluralism, even at the most rigorous and sophisticated conceptual level. Thus the main issues of digital democracy were long treated as if all that mattered was the kind of democracy to be delivered through technology. Is it direct democracy or yet another appendage of representative democracy? Is it another version of majoritarianism (in the sense of a society in which the majority can oppress and assert its dominance on the minority by sheer force of numbers) or is the emphasis now placed on consensus building? Is it the democracy as understood by classic liberals, libertarians and communitarians, or is it deliberative or participatory electronic democracy? If that were not enough, added to the intrinsic multidimensionality of theories of democracy are difficulties regarding which democratic aspects or dimensions will be addressed in the definition adopted. Are we interested in: • Giving people the chance to make political decisions directly? • Being consulted, i.e. being heard and considered, by the political system? • Interacting with elected representatives? • Participating? Deliberating? • Cooperating with the government? • Legislating? We have furthermore to consider how rigorous we want to be: is it ultimately about improving liberal democracy, supplementing current representative democracy or changing it profoundly and permanently through a technological revolution per se? Finally, we should have to admit that the notion that technologies of communication and information may have a relevant democratizing effect on governments and parliaments, on political activity and on public life in general; the notion that technologies have the potential to transform the political process with democratizing purposes and offer new solutions to traditional obstacles to the implementation of democracy is not new, but took a long time to acquire the features it has today. It goes back to a time when, for example, speaking of communication technologies brought to mind something very different from our current referent of the term, generally a piece of equipment with a screen, some kind of input device (which may be the actual screen), some kind of processor and internet connection. As Thierry Vedel put it, despite the young age of this ethat serves as a suffix for democracy, “electronic democracy [...] has a standing history of several decades, of which the current discussion focusing on online media is only the most recent extension”2. The history of the idea that it was possible to improve democratic processes through information technology can naturally go a long way back, as the invention and, above all, the massification of new communication media have always been accompanied by renewed hopes for improvement in democracy and public life. For many people, the principle that any important change – and for the better – in the quality of public life necessarily entails a reassessment of democracy itself is consistently true. So it was with the printing press and the sudden genuine possibility of spreading the printed word and “democratizing” access to books, but also, successively, with the telegram, the telephone, the radio, the cinema, the television, and even the fax machine. “Democratizing” could well mean “massifying,” reaching a wider audience beyond face-to-face, restricted audiences, but also instructing new audiences about political issues, offering more, up-to-date inputs to form public opinion and inform debate, endowing parties and political factions with channels of expression, providing citizens with new and more efficient ways of access to political authority etc. Our story begins in the 1970s, more than twenty years before the internet became a relevant social experience, when speculation starts on the future intersections between democracy and technology, now materialized in a few concrete experiments. The academic attention enjoyed by the theme at the time, still sparsely scattered in few publications, consists either of general speculation about the effect of “new technologies” (cables, satellites, interactive television, computers, fax, video conferencing) on democracy or the review of experimental projects, usually carried out by academics and members of social organizations, aimed at democratic participation via electronic technologies (de Sola Pool, 1973; Doty; Zussman, 1975; Etzioni, 1972). The main focus is citizen participation. The political and democratic model, in turn, was derived from the “town meetings”3 held by residents of villages and towns in the golden age of New England’s “Tocquevillean” democracy (which, in turn, replicated the Greek agora model) (Etzioni, 1992). In the 1980s, the volume of publications doubles and academic attention to the subject deepens. There is a clear decision to consider interactive cable television as the main technology in question, with other technological resources (computers, telephones, fax) playing second fiddle. Experiments thrive, headed by organizations and social movements, but also carried out by companies, almost all based on cable TV and focused on citizen participation. A theoretical approach to the contribution of technology to democracy in this period basically addresses (or promotes) the polarization between advocates of teledemocracy (or supporters of democracy via technology) and skeptics, critics or detractors, whether of the proposal of teledemocracy or of the idea that technology is able promote or modify current democracy. Between 1990 and 1995, the amount of material published matches that of the entire previous period, indicating that academic attention to the subject has now been consolidated. The conceptual discussion is basically an extension of what had been debated in the preceding decade, though with greater coherence and initial attempts to organize the field of debate (Dutton, 1992). A considerable difference now looms on the horizon: as the debate about the possibilities and limits of teledemocracy still reverberates in the period, the discussion on democracy and technology increasingly sees the technology of preference, cable television, fading away in the rear mirror, while home computers with internet connection firmly establish themselves as the technology of the future. Teledemocracy still lies at the core of the discussion, but already terms like electronic democracy (Varley, 1991) and cyberdemocracy (Ogden, 1994) start to emerge, indicating that eyes are turning to other technologies. Teledemocracy as a project The first phase in the history of the “electronic” democracy idea is anchored in the term “teledemocracy.” The expression gains conceptual muscle in the 1980s, extends throughout the 1990s and, sporadically, over the following decade. The golden age of teledemocracy is the 1980s and the first half of the 1990s, when experiments mushroomed and rhetoric about the democratic promises of electronic technologies peaked. But criticism was equally fierce, especially in the late 1980s and in the 1990s. It should be noted, finally, that this is basically an American experience, despite having marked the history of electronic democracy worldwide, either as an example of experiences or as a counterexample in alternatives to e-democracy. The term, like all others that succeeded it, expresses what is considered essential in the new quality of democracy based on electronic technologies, especially the prefix tele-, in the etymological sense of “at a distance” and in the most immediate sense of the relation with telephone and television. What technology can best offer to democracy, therefore, has to do with what can be done at a distance, putting people in contact with one another or with political authorities. At all stages in the development of the history of the idea of democracy based on technologies – and therefore also in the case of teledemocracy – three processes unfold at the same time: a) experiments specially designed to explore the democratic possibilities of the new technology; b) a strong increase of rhetoric, reflected in media and political discourses, about the impact of technology on democracy; c) academic debate in which terms are treated conceptually and concerns take on the form of conceptual problems4. Experiments with teledemocracy generally include: • opinion polls (or projects of a general plebiscitary nature); • “televoting,” registering votes by electronic means; • and meetings between citizens and elected representatives to discuss and solve problems, now at nationwide level through electronic town meetings (Etzioni, 1992), events held via teleconferencing and interactive cable television. One example of experiments and initiatives of democracy via electronic technologies is the so-called Minerva project, developed by the German-IsraeliAmerican professor Amitai Etzioni, then based at the Center for Policy Research in New York, and documented in an article from the early 1970s (Etzioni, 1972). Apparently, the term teledemocracy had not even been coined yet, but the idea is of “an electronic technology that will allow masses of citizens to have discussions with each other, and which will enable them to reach group decisions without leaving their homes or crowding into a giant hall.”5 This “system of participatory democracy” is based on different technologies, depending on the number of people reached: for groups of up to thirty people, automated telephone teleconferencing systems would suffice, but for small communities (up to 2,000 people) interactive cable TV would be the most adequate medium, while medium-sized communities (6 to 40 thousand) would need to rely on a combination of radio, satellite television and telephones. Finally, meetings of a national or international scope would need to be based on networks connecting cables, shortwaves, television stations or satellites. It should be noted that, despite the integration of multiple technologies, cable television (and its interactive possibilities) was the technology standard that most stirred people’s imagination, already present in every home, school, church, city council and political club in the US. An example of a typical electronic poll of the early 1980s was the interactive television service called QUBE, of the Warner-Amex cable company, whose purpose was to give governments a quick feedback on what people thought about public policies and other specific subjects of public interest. QUBE was adopted by many city administrations in the United States to conduct unofficial “electronic referendums” on local issues. All citizens needed to do was push buttons on a console placed on top of the TV to register their vote, which was collected every six seconds by the company’s computer. It didn’t work out for different reasons such as operational costs, low participation rates and the impossibility of having a scientifically constructed sample, among others, but it enjoyed some success during its short period of existence. And it fired imaginations. Regarding the rhetoric about the use of electronic technologies to aid democracy, or even to replace existing democracy, two main types of material make important contributions: a) the public discourse present in mass media, generally stemming from influential politicians or newspaper, magazine and television columnists; b) the “futurologies”, publications that attempt to identify and interpret trends in the contemporary social environment and predict their impact on a more or less imminent future. The highlight of the first type of public discourse occurred during US election campaigns of the 1990s, when political rhetoric finally buys the idea of technologies at the service of the renewal of democracy. First with the model of Ross Perot’s earliest formulation in 1992, and his electronic town hall meeting. Then with Al Gore’s more modern version, through the idea of information superhighway sold in the 1996 presidential campaign (Oblak Črnič, 2012). Both attract considerable media attention, adding even more confusion to the debate (Bradley, 1994; Brown, 1993; Etzioni, 1992). The other important contribution to selling the idea of electronic democracy came from a few essays of reasonable argumentative (and sales) success in identifying certain trends in the use and social application of technologies present in society and extrapolating from them, pointing to future directions and even estimating the consequences of where the world was heading. Therefore, before papers and books on electronic democracy, the discourse on the possibilities of democracy based on electronic communications was underpinned, more or less emphatically, by essays that formulated a kind of general theory of society (or of the future of our societies), in which it was admitted that the future technological stage would finally allow the advent of much better democracies than those we have at present. Authors such as J. Naisbitt (1982) and Alvin Toffler (1980) are, in this sense, very important for stressing the idea of electronic democracy in their predictions about the society of the future − an attitude that will be replicated by other general theorists of society, such as Manuel Castells, albeit differently. Toffler, for example, made it very clear that the old problems of communication shall no longer get in the way of a consistent and expanded direct democracy6. The 1990s added Howard Rheingold’s virtual community (1993) and John P. Barlow’s cyberspace (1996) to the rhetorical verve of the moment. These essays fueled the collective imagination and achieved reasonable success in certain intellectual sectors with their estimates of what should work in terms of democracy and technology in the society of the future. This seemed to be the state of affairs between the late 1980s and the mid1990s: rhetorical polarization between enthusiasts and skeptics of electronic democracy, and a growing number of experiments in the use of technologies for political participation, for opinion polls and interaction between citizens and elected officials. This is where the scientific treatment of the subject starts. The scientific discussion on the likelihood of the existence of an electronic democracy and what it should look like did not take long to emerge. Many important researchers have contributed in the last thirty years to help us understand the significance of the rapid development of information and communication technologies for public life and the way they affect life in society, political institutions and, in particular, the not so simple democratic system. The answers made up a broad spectrum. Some positions were moderately skeptical, others bet openly on the future of democracy based on technology, and others still were decisively skeptical or opposing. The moderate skeptics wanted to check whether there was any fire beneath all the smoke. Everyone is talking about teledemocracy and electronic democracy, and enthusiastically so, but is it just rhetoric and political diversion or is there really something serious that merits the attention of political science, political communication and sociology? F. Christopher Arterton is an example of a skeptical author, at least with regards to the democratic determinism of technology. Moderate your expectations about the requalification of democracy due to the impact of communication technologies, he says. He concludes that the current stage of communications has indeed enabled an important increase in direct interaction between public office holders and the mass of citizens, which is a good thing, but unfortunately, in such interaction, one still notices “significant inequalities between leaders and the public in terms of control over the initiation, timing and content of political messages”7. In addition, after reviewing several teledemocracy projects, he concludes that technologies, considered in themselves, do not demonstrate the capacity to really engage citizens. The success of a project would therefore be much more related to the organizational choices of whoever designed it, that is, to choices based on their values and their assumptions about participation (what they hope to obtain, by which means, to what extent) than to the technological possibilities. Democracy, therefore, shall not be “inevitably [...] induced by the revolution in communications technology”8. Thus our author concludes, visibly disappointed, that direct democracy has not yet loomed in the horizon: “As I see it, the trend in our politics appears to be not toward the eventual replacement of representative institutions with procedures for direct policy determination by citizens”. And he sadly finishes: “At best, change may lead to an invigoration of representative processes facilitated by communications media”9. In the same period John Downing considers, from a different point of view, that Arterton’s excessive caution was hardly supported by the most recent developments of technologies. Above all, the latter ignores computer communications beyond their use for teleconferencing. What Downing does then is review experiments that consist of projects focusing on computer communications, especially the PeaceNet and Public Data Access projects. The former, founded in 1986 in California, aimed to support peace movements; the latter, also from the 1980s, was born in the Reagan era to make government information accessible to the public. Downing’s conclusions are positive in indicating potential pro-democracy applications of communication projects via computers, which he synthesizes in four dimensions. • Such projects allow “the directed gathering and analysis of data on key issues that affect communities and subgroups of the population that might be otherwise overlooked or ignored”. • By making irrelevant the need for everyone to be together at the same time, these projects allow the mobilization of people who are generally separated in time and space, thus bringing together enough people and publicity “to pressure powerful political interests”. • Besides nerve centers, such projects can serve “as forums for developing the requisite language and agendas for political action.” • Because they connect people beyond national boundaries, such projects “can begin to address the common problems of humanity, such as human rights, toxic waste, and peace, by strengthening the resources and reserves of democratic culture” (Downing, 1989). But the opponents and detractors of teledemocracy were also numerous, hailing from at least two sides. The first critical front comes from those who believe that teledemocracy overestimates technology while underestimating the political system or neglecting the dominance exerted by the economic system over technology. What bothers them is the pretension of modifying the political system by “simply” adding electronic tools or “naiveties” such as: a. poor understanding of the resistance of political institutions to selfreformation; b. a (wrong) assumption of the neutrality of technology, which would supposedly allow itself, without further ado, to be shaped by democratic intentions, submitting its particular logic to the social purposes imposed on it. The second front of criticism comes from those who, while sharing the discontent with the state of democracy and desiring changes in the arrangement of contemporary democracy, view with distrust the model of democracy that might emerge from teledemocracy. Teledemocracy is quickly accused, as we shall see later, of proposing a sort of alternative direct democracy whereby public and free deliberation among the citizens themselves, in the Athenian model, would be replaced by an “at a distance” plebiscitary majoritarianism, based on electronic technologies. Scott London (1995) summed up the common criticisms prevailing until the mid-1990s and found seventeen items, which can be broken down into practical problems of technology, problems of political implementation, and problems related to the democratic and political assumptions behind the experiments. The following are examples of practical problems related to technology. • most experiments had low rates of participation; • the costs of organizing such technological experiments are still prohibitively high; • conversation via electronic means is generally context free and therefore lacks things that can give it meaning and purpose; • public opinion is produced without the actual (physical) presence of the interlocutors, and becomes easily fickle. The following relate to problems of political implementation, according to London: • consulting citizens through feedback can be inefficient and timeconsuming for representatives; • one cannot assume that voters feel compelled to become engaged in the specifics of policymaking; • some public issues are poorly suited to very broad discussions because they are either too technical, too specific or too regionalized; • issues of inequality of access, due to social exclusion or poor technological literacy, are not resolved. Democracy-based problems include the following issues: • devices such as those used to register opinion leave no room for reasoned, lateral dialogue and debate; • the compilation of opinions resulting from televoting cannot be considered equal to a public voice; • individuals are atomized in this process; • excessive speed is inimical to consistent democratic deliberation; • citizens are not free to frame issues on their own terms in electronic polls or televoting; • in cases in which there is no clear majority on an issue, simple majoritarian solutions (by a minimum margin) are not adequate; • participation in electronic consultations does not involve the ability of citizens to act on their own initiative, and therefore they do not feel responsible for the policies designed; • as there is no adequate supply of information necessary for the decision, the manifestation of the will becomes susceptible to traditional means of communication and advertising; • the same is true with respect to susceptibility in setting the social and political agenda. The dimensions of digital democracy For the authors of this period it is clear that demonstrating the relevance of technology for democracy requires raising points that are truly decisive for the democratic life to which the influence of technology makes or would make much difference. Such points should be summarized in four dimensions: registering or consulting public opinion, information, decision making and deliberation. Obviously, since the teledemocracy phase, there has been much public talk about political participation, which is absent from this list. As a matter of fact, it is a premise that materializes in all these dimensions – political participation of citizens had always been considered a decisive factor for the democratic effect of technology. Moreover, these four dimensions can be distributed into two spheres: the sphere of citizens or civil sphere (society) and the sphere of political decision (the state, the political system). Regarding information, the issue is raised of how citizens may obtain information on public policies, government and the political system to make the political decisions that concern them in the democratic regime, such as electoral decision, understanding of politics and defense of their interests. But there is also the flow of information and data stemming from the state for citizens’ use. In the case of registering the public will, through either voting or government consultation, there is once again a flow between society and government with vectors going up and down. Political decision making is the prerogative of elected representatives, but if there is any significant enhancement to be achieved in this regard, it consists of some form of citizen participation in decision making. Finally, public deliberation is the prerogative of citizens, but, again, what may be relevant and innovative in this sense is precisely to somehow transform the horizontal flows of conversation between citizens into vertical flows intended to influence the system and the government. Registering public opinion Electronic voting was one of the first political applications of technology for democratic purposes. Advocates of a direct electronic democracy argue that technological solutions could be used to get citizens to vote more frequently, quickly, cheaply and continuously on a greater ranges of issues (Hilbert, 2009). Perhaps even more than once a day (Berkeley, 1962). And, above all, from the comfort of their homes (Hollander, 1985). There would no longer be, according to the more enthusiastic, any technological limitation to direct democracy with regard to continuous consultation of the popular will. In fact, much of the dispute on electronic democracy theory occurring up to the mid-1990s is related to estimating the role played by electronic systems in the expression of the popular will. The advocates of teledemocracy had no doubt that in liberal democracies in which the government and the political system were increasingly distant and disconnected from the population, and increasingly closed up in their inherent functioning, no means of making the will of people reach their representatives should be neglected. Even more so if such registering of citizens’ opinions could be quick, inexpensive, up-to-date, capable of following in real time the pace of legislative discussion on public policies and the pace of government reaction to social issues imposed by the circumstances of the moment. With the new possibilities afforded by electronic communications – tele-polls, tele-referendums and televoting via telephone, computer networks, interactive cable television –, public authorities could no longer complain about the spatial and temporal difficulties of following the voice of the people, or the low reliability and high cost of forms of heeding popular sovereignty in referendums, plebiscites and consultations. Why should the public voice be disregarded now that it was within earshot of the representatives? The result is, naturally, enthusiasm. The reaction was not slow in coming and brought in its wake the first wave of skepticism against the idea of electronic democracy. It basically consisted in saying that opinion registering systems do not affect any fundamentally relevant function of democracy at all. Such a thing, if actually put to work, will only superficially change the impervious liberal-democratic state, since the sphere of political decision making will continue to be controlled by elected representatives and the government, and zealously protected from any “meddling” by the masses. That if it was capable of change, the state would change into something even worse, a sort of electronic plebiscitarianism or majoritarianism that would produce interest aggregation at best. Benjamin Barber, who devoted much time to criticizing the idea of teledemocracy in the 1980s, made this point his main trench. His criticism is explained by the fact that in this same period he proposed a democratic theory model called strong democracy (Barber, 1984), a democracy based on participation and autonomous deliberation of citizens, which contrasts with thin democracy, according to him the model in use in current liberal democracy, with low participation and production of political decision monopolized by strong social actors. For Barber, the problem with the demagogues of electronic democracy based on opinion polls and the fanatics of the democratic automatism of technology “is not their understanding of technology but their grasp of democracy”10. The decision to technologically implement a representative democracy, a plebiscitary democracy or a deliberative democracy, for example, has radically different implications and requirements with respect to technologies. And with respect to what technologies may or may not be able to offer, or offer more or less efficiently, I would add. Of course, some authors consider that the best application of technologies consists precisely of promoting a “plebiscitary majoritarianism,” a system based on the identification of majoritarian opinions (without ever considering that it is an aggregation of the private interests of private persons). In this case, Barber expresses a very common concern in the 1990s: “New technology can be a dangerously facile instrument of such unchecked majoritarianism.”11 Which will lead to the claim that “the kind of democracy being proposed is a debased, impoverished version of the true ideal. Democracy becomes a mere device for registering preferences”12. Another philosopher, Michael Walzer, writing at the same time, found himself compelled to fit into his famous book on democratic theory, Spheres of Justice, a criticism of what he then considered to be the dominant representation of the impact of modern technology on democracy: isolated individuals, watching television in the living room, talking only with their spouses, voting in referendums on crucial national issues by pressing a button on some sort of device. “But is this the exercise of power? I am inclined to say, instead, that it is only another example of the erosion of value – a false and ultimately degrading way of sharing in the making of decisions”13. An example of this same criticism is recorded in a review by Jean Elshtain of QUBE, the instant polling service via interactive television already mentioned. According to the author, the mistake made by the then defenders of teledemocracy was having a misjudged view of democracy, mistaking it for a simple system of plebiscites. But there is no democratic political community, she states, without incorporating “a deliberative process, involving discussion with other citizens, developing a shared sense of moral responsibility for one’s society and the enhancement of individual possibilities through action in, and for, the res publica”14. The plebiscite is not a sufficient guarantee of democracy, since an autocratic regime may well exist disguised as majoritarian opinion: “That opinion can be registered by easily manipulated, ritualistic plebiscites”15. Teledemocracy was not actually limited to systems of registering opinions, as some of its proponents and many of its detractors insisted, but the assumption that there lay a project of direct electronic democracy (plebiscitary, based on interest aggregation and neglectful of public deliberation) provoked considerable reaction. Apparently, direct democracy via electronic plebiscites needed to be exorcised. So much so that, re-assessing in the late 1990s the rhetorical and theoretical polarization of the age of teledemocracy, Professor Stephen Coleman relates that, for some time, the common discursive strategy of those who defended the democratizing role of information and communication technologies, but at the same time wished to evade the objections to the idea of teledemocracy, “is to assert resolutely their rejection of anything approaching direct democracy”16. Direct democracy without deliberation and based on mere aggregation of inclinations was transformed into the caricature of teledemocracy (and consequently of electronic democracy) and the theoretical scarecrow that could easily and conveniently be destroyed. Information, data “Information” is one of these terms of scant conceptual precision and great popular success in democratic theory. That is precisely why it is a common item in lists of highlights either of the qualities of democracy, understood as the regime in which information is generated and flows more freely, or of the needs for implementing healthy democracies. It therefore could not be absent from the short list of technology’s essential contributions to democracy. Information firstly appears in the form of “politically relevant content, including news, opinions, and factual data – in vast quantities”17. In this case, the common observation is that ICTs in general and the internet in particular have been lavish “in facilitating quicker and more complete access than that of conventional media to political and government information locally, nationally, and internationally.”18 Given that democracy is essential for citizens to make well-informed political decisions, and that digital information and communication media and environments contribute significantly to providing citizens with the information that they need, it becomes quite easy to justify the relevance of technology to democracy. Secondly, one must consider the actual information about citizens, their opinions, dispositions, beliefs, desires, fears and activities, flowing to the political system and government. The good side of this flow of information can be considered as “the directed gathering and analysis of data on key issues that affect communities and subgroups of the population that might be otherwise overlooked or ignored”19. In this sense, information is basically yet another way of registering public opinion, necessary for public policies and other political decisions for which one wishes to consider the political desires of the majority of citizens. On the other hand, the negative side of this view of information as “citizen data” is the danger that applications designed to collect and process this type of content represent for the privacy of individuals. Thirdly, information appears in the form of government data. As early as the 1990s the conviction existed that documents and other data from governments and state bodies could be made available online to citizens, since the barriers to their access could be considerably mitigated with the use of information and communication technologies. The predicted effects of public access to public data have included, since then, technology-mediated government transparency. Debate, discussion, horizontal communication It is curious how early in the debate on electronic democracy we see the idea that electronic communications might benefit democracy by affording the possibility of public discussion of social and political problems. This aspect of democracy is not so obvious, since it does not rival with the need to take into account the opinion of citizens or the importance of political and governmental information for enlightened citizenship. Even in democratic theory, the notion that public deliberation is essential for a well-founded democracy makes a late appearance. How then, in the theory of electronic democracy, did the imposition of the theme occur so “early”? In my hypothesis, there are two good reasons for this. The first concerns the production of arguments to oppose the notorious plebiscitary majoritarianism as a way of establishing a dense, participatory democracy, closer to the model of direct democracy. The plebiscitarianism of teledemocracy projects was duly contested in theoretical terms with the claim that there was another means, more efficient and more in tune with a demanding concept of democracy, of formation of public will and opinion: open, horizontal discussion, free among citizens. After all, as Athenian classic democracy has taught us, majority voting and rule are methods to conclude discussions at the end of which decisions need to be made, but only if a consensus has not been reached and solely when arguments have been exhausted. Only a crude majoritarianism would skip deliberation and go straight to the vote, dispensing with everything that is the basis of democracy: the search for clear consensus, mutual enlightenment among citizens on equal terms, the normative value of the principle of the best argument, the gains in cooperation and co-responsibility reaped from decisions generated in free discussions, the strengthening of horizontal ties among citizens, the formation of active citizenship. Another possible reason why claims about the importance of debate and an active public sphere have permeated the qualification of digital democracy lies in the temporal coincidence between the initial phase of the discussion on electronic democracy and the boom of deliberative democracy in democratic theory, both in the 1990s. Decision making Political regimes are distinguished from each other by the methods and assumptions adopted to make decisions that affect life in common. Autocratic regimes are characterized by limiting decision making to a few people or only one, while in the democratic regime the decision is made by all, directly or through representatives chosen for this purpose. Political decision, therefore, plays an important role in the definition of democracy, so seeking a place for it in electronic democracy is only natural. The issue of increasing citizen participation in decision making through communication technologies involves different aspects. First of all, we have a set of decisions for which citizen participation is required, even in forms of democracy that are scarcely amenable to the public will – that is, that are bent on reserving to the elected and the state bureaucracy virtually all prerogatives related to decision making. These may be circumstances in which the parliamentary system transfers to citizens the decision on public policies, ratifying or not decisions made by representatives, or choosing between predetermined options, as in referendums and plebiscites, or circumstances in which the regular legislative process determines that stakeholders be heard before the parliamentary decision, as in public consultations. In both cases, the mediation of technology can represent not only a reduction in the costs of these processes of measuring the popular will, but also the opportunity for efficient and accessible participation, better adapted to the convenience of the citizenry. In addition, we have decision making whereby the political system opens up to citizen cooperation. Cases in point are regulation of standards or public policies, collaborative production of bills, policy design, etc. Mandated by constitutions or specific laws or induced by public policies or representatives open to citizen collaboration, opportunities for participation in these intermediate forms of citizen intervention have greatly increased. And communication technologies are an essential condition for the implementation of levels of participation previously deemed unthinkable. Which includes, in this case, an effort to involve citizens more closely in public affairs. Lastly we have the core of political decision, in legislative decisions typical of regular parliamentary work or in government decisions, regarding the implementation of public policies and public management decisions. This is a dimension usually reserved for the elect, and only projects to restore direct democracy include the possibility of transferring this level of political decision directly to citizens, without representation or delegation. Alternatively, two possibilities are usually demanded related to this scope of decision making by electronic democracy: • Monitoring: citizens have the right to know how and by whom decisions are made, as well as the nature and scope of such decisions. Technological mediation is available precisely to shed light on decision makers, on the activities of state officials, on the discretion exercised by civil servants and political authorities, even in the use of their prerogatives. • Demand for transparency in the legislative process, which extends to knowing whether any illegitimate factor (such as corruption) has affected the decision of any of the actors involved in the decision. But also required is transparency of government activity as a whole – and of the conditions under which it is exercised – of public management, of the exercise of the discretionary power of each servant. Public transparency, therefore, does not relate only to public affairs, but also to the actors involved in decision making and the circumstances in which decisions are made. *** As seen from the analysis of the four dimensions of electronic democracy recognized in the teledemocracy phase, not everything is disputed. Criticism mainly centered on the issue of registering the opinions and positions of citizens, which for many detractors seemed to represent the core of the proposal. The other dimensions, also defended by the advocates of teledemocracy, such as information, deliberation and civil participation in political decision, raised no controversy. This is important to understand that behind the rhetoric of opposition to teledemocracy lay a rejection not of electronic democracy, but of an electronic democracy consisting of an aggregation of opinions through opinion-gathering mechanisms. QUBE seems to have monopolized political fantasies to such an extent that it ended up summarizing what many considered to be the quintessence of teledemocracy and electronic democracy in general. Other experiments and ideas (such as town meetings and electronic town halls), which held deliberation and citizen participation in decision making in high regard, because they did not haunt imaginations, were not called on to help mitigate the criticism of teledemocracy. Thus, although it may seem, based on the bibliography, that the period of teledemocracy closes with the victory of those who rejected electronic democracy, something quite different happened. The door was closed to the use of communication technologies for political and democratic purposes (in polls and plebiscites), while the importance of the other dimensions involved was confirmed, such as information production, deliberation and participation in political decision. In the future, as we shall see, the plebiscitary functions will be replaced by public consultation mechanisms, discussion forums and other forms of lateral and vertical interaction involving citizens and authorities. Therefore, the period of experimentation with teledemocracy and of speculation on ways of using new technologies in the democratic process can in no way be viewed as a failure. Many of the intuitions born from experiments based on a technology that did not thrive, the interactive cable television, have been retrieved since the mid-1980s to be applied again, using the technology of networked computers. Likewise, the debates about the advantages and disadvantages of the application of technologies in the political process were resumed when the technology glimpsed was already the internet. The place of digital democracy, in public debate and academic discussion, was created and safeguarded by the discussion about teledemocracy. 1 As we shall see, there have been and still are contending designations of digital democracy. As far as possible, I shall use “digital democracy” and “e-democracy” to refer to the phenomenon being addressed here, when more specific contextual designations, as in the case of the teledemocracy period, are unnecessary. However, when translating or reproducing the argument of another author, I will adopt the expression he uses. Be that as it may, readers should consider as synonymous the expressions teledemocracy, electronic democracy, virtual democracy, cyberdemocracy, eDemocracy, e-democracy and digital democracy. I shall normally use the two latter only because they are the most employed today. 2 T. Vedel, “The Idea of Electronic Democracy: Origins, Visions and Questions”, Parliamentary Affairs, v. 59, n. 2, pp. 226-35, 10 Feb. 2006, p. 226. 3 For more on the role of town meetings in US political history, cf. <https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Town_meeting>. 4 In this specific case, rhetoric and experiments have been present since the late 1960s and the 1970s (de Sola Pool, 1973; Etzioni, 1972; Flood, 1978; Laudon, 1977; Smith, 1978), the theoretical discussion is from the 1980s (Abramson; Arterton; Orren, 1988; Arterton, 1987, 1988; Bjerknes; Ehn; Kyng, 1987; Sola Pool, 1983; Downing, 1989; Elshtain, 1982; Hollander, 1985), extends to the late 1990s (Barber, 1997; Becker, 1993, 1998; Brants; Huizenga; van Meerten, 1996; Buchstein, 1997; Davies; Jegu, 1995; Dutton, 1992; Etzioni, 1992; Fountain, 2003a; Grosswiler, 1998; London, 1995; Ogden, 1994; Street, 1997; Tsagarousianou, 1998; van Dijk, 1996; Varley, 1991; Watson et al., 1999; Ytterstad; Watson, 1996) and, already in decline, to the early 2000s (Becker; Slaton, 2000; Kangas; Store, 2003; Whyte; Macintosh, 2001). 5 A. Etzioni, “Minerva: An Electronic Town Hall”, Policy Sciences, v. 3, n. 4, pp. 457-74, Dec. 1972, p. 457. 6 Cf. A. Toffler, The Third Wave, Toronto: Bantan Books, 1980, p. 429. 7 F. C. Arterton, “Political Participation and ‘Teledemocracy’”, PS: Political Science and Politics, v. 21, n. 3, pp. 620-7, Jan. 1988, p. 620. 8 Idem, Teledemocracy: Can Technology Protect Democracy?, Newbury Park: Sage, 1987, p. 623. 9 Ibidem, p. 621. 10 B. R. Barber, “The New Telecommunications Technology: Endless Frontier or the End of Democracy?”, Constellations, v. 4, n. 2, pp. 208-28, Oct. 1997, p. 224. 11 Ibidem. 12 J. Street, “Remote Control? Politics, Technology and ‘Electronic Democracy’”, European Journal of Communication, v. 12, n. 1, pp. 27-42, 1 Mar. 1997, p. 32. 13 M. Walzer, Spheres of Justice, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1985, p. 307. 14 J. B. Elshtain, “Democracy and the QUBE Tube”, The Nation, pp. 108-9, 1982, p. 108. 15 Ibidem. 16 S. Coleman, “Can the New Media Invigorate Democracy?”, The Political Quarterly, v. 70, n. 1, pp. 16-22, Jan. 1999, p. 18. 17 T. Vedel, op. cit., p. 231. 18 R. Hurwitz, “Who Needs Politics? Who Needs People? The Ironies of Democracy in Cyberspace”, Contemporary Sociology, v. 28, n. 6, pp. 655-61, 1999, p. 657. 19 J. D. H. Downing, “Computers for Political Change: PeaceNet and Public Data Access”, Journal of Communication, v. 39, n. 3, pp. 154-62, Sept. 1989, p. 162. The Internet is a vast, amorphous metaphor in search of tangibility. A highway, an agora, a mall, a library, a portal, a Web, a brain, an ethereal universe of bits and bytes. We surf, we scroll, we browse, we search, we navigate, we post, we chat, we lurk, we log on and we go offline. Stephen Coleman People often refer to e-democracy as something you can be “for” or “against”. Since no one living in democratic countries is against democracy (with the exception of marginal groups), then it must be the “e” people find objectionable. Åke Grönlund T HE POPULARIZATION OF THE INTERNET, the massive adoption of home computing with connection to, as it was once called, the “world computer network”, did not happen all at once, obviously, but it did happen in a decade. In the early 1990s, it was already clear that microcomputers with internet connection were the major trend in the adoption of communication and information technologies, even in technologically peripheral countries such as Brazil. The technological innovation that made home computers possible was established in the 1980s, but it was certainly not as a home data processor (or a sophisticated and expensive typewriter) that microcomputers would become popular in the next decade. If the popularization of home computers did indeed bring computing machines into the household, the most important fact was that it opened the door to the massification of another innovation, already consolidated for military and scientific purposes: the internet. In the early 1990s, the convergence of home computing with the internet seemed somewhat comparable to the technological leap that had first put the radio, then broadcast TV, then cable and satellite TV in people’s homes. But the speed of the technological innovation and the ensuing massive adoption are even more surprising than in the emergence of previous technologies. Between 1990 and 1995 two innovations in particular were determining factors for the popularization of home computers with internet access. Both had to do with the invention of graphic interface for the use of new technologies, which made computers (the case of Windows and the invention of the graphic standard) and also the internet (the case of the web and the “surfing” internet [Brugger, 2013; 2016]) intuitive, interesting and fun for people to use. The boom in the adoption of web-connected computers kicks off in mid-decade and by its end has already reached massive patterns. At the dawn of the 21st century, the home computer/internet pattern is already one of the most important and characteristic social phenomena. Digital democracy takes off As of 1996 something very singular starts happening. First of all, the notion of what to pay attention to in technological terms changed: the focus shifts from television to computer and from cable to internet technology. There was no competition, either in commercial success or speed of adoption. We are now, self-consciously, in the “internet age” (Brants, 1996). In experimental projects, in rhetoric and in research, the term “distance democracy” is definitely replaced by the more general expression “electronic democracy” – or by its contenders, such as the aforementioned “cyberdemocracy” and “virtual democracy.” If we use academic attention as a reliable indicator of the social, scientific and political importance attached to a subject, then there is no doubt that the age of digital democracy is inaugurated in 1996. The first exhibit presented in support of this hypothesis is that between 1996 and 1999, the same number of titles on democracy and technology is published as from 1972 to 1995. The comparison of publications per decade (Chart 1) clearly evidences the temporal delimitation of the subject and marks the second half of the 1990s as its effective starting point. CHART 1 Breakdown of publications on digital democracy per decade – 1976-2015 In addition, if we look at the historical distribution of academic attention, we will see that only since 1996 production on our subject became numerically relevant, constant and increasing, as can be seen in the time series that includes all publications up to 2016 (Chart 2 ). CHART 2 Distribution of publications on digital democracy per year – 1996-2016 The 1996-2005 decade is homogeneous neither in technological innovation nor in social use of technology, and all that is reflected in the theme of electronic democracy. The second half of the 1990s is known as the “commercial turning point” of the internet, when the internet standard reserved for academics is replaced by the popular internet, but also of its popularization boom. Internet service providers thrive, the cost of machines and access drops consistently, public curiosity about what can be done, as people said, in the “virtual world” explodes, as does the desire to be “plugged in”. The race for the internet-linked computer is the order of the day until the turn of the millennium. By the end of the century, new users are already extremely interested in online interaction, which abounds in the shape of electronic forums and web chats, but also in digital tools for instant communication. In the first half of the 2000s this trend is consolidated and will result in web-based relationships, content-sharing and social media (Allen, 2013; Zimmer; Hoffmann, 2016), very popular in this period. Orkut appeared in 2004, YouTube in 2005, Twitter and Facebook’s open version in 2006, but social networking sites had been available since 1997 (like SixDegrees.com) (Boyd; Ellison, 2007). From the thematic point of view, the discussion on conceptual principles, the theory of electronic democracy, is at the core of academic attention to the impact of technologies on democracy for most of the period. In the ten-year period between 1995 and 2004, the golden age of digital democracy theory, more than two-thirds of all publications adopt or include a theoretical approach. That means, first of all, that most studies, even those aimed at analyzing experiments and the rhetorical struggle for preferred models of implementing technology in democracy, must, in one way or another, speculatively face issues related to the justifications of the likely impacts of technological changes on democracy. After all, even rhetoric and experiments in electronic democracy have to support their claims before skeptical audiences, some of them opponents of the idea or of the consequences they can anticipate. Virtually everyone who writes in the field must be theoretical to some degree in this period, even when their training and viewpoint lack a consistent conceptual basis. In previous years, up to the mid-1990s, the theoretical approach about the “whys” and “what fors” of teledemocracy ensured the chances of survival of the theme of electronic democracy. After 2006, however, digital democracy was broken down into subthemes which thrived throughout the whole period, practically forming specific areas with their own specifically developed theories, experiments and rhetoric and, as we shall see, their own history. The main subthemes of digital democracy – participation, the public sphere and exclusion, and, a little later, transparency – emerge over the period in question, but up to 2004 the conceptual treatment of digital democracy prevails over all other subthemes. After 2004 there is somehow an inverted trend as the other themes of digital democracy, as a whole, start prevailing over the general theory of e-democracy to eventually surpass it individually between 2006 and 2008. CHART 3 Academic attention to digital democracy subthemes per year – 1996-2005 The explanation is that this is a moment in which everyone is asking themselves, explicitly or implicitly, questions that require answers in terms of political theory and democratic theory. The initial question from the teledemocracy phase regarded, for example, whether the new communication technologies would have a significant impact on politics, on government and, above all, on democracy. This debate continued between 1996 and 2005 through the discussion about the possibilities and characteristics of technologies for and against democracy or the permeability of liberal democracies to the new possibilities afforded by technology, for example. And it progressed as people sought to understand which type of democracy might emerge from the impact of new technologies on the political system and government, as well as understand the interactions between both and society. Great debates followed on the democratic functions that might be improved (or made worse) by new technologies, on whether a direct electronic democracy is possible or desirable, on the democratic patterns arising, for better or for worse, from the application of technologies. Finally, the question is raised as to whether the effect of new technologies on the political system, government and society would produce the model of democracy we want or need. Of the five major subthemes of digital democracy, only two were actually present in the second half of the 1990s: the theory of e-democracy and public deliberation by digital means. Although e-participation had been present already in the previous phase, in implementation projects and rhetoric, this did not translate into significant production in the bibliography. Actually, e-participation is, alongside digital divide, a typical theme of the 21st century, as inferred from Chart 3. But why is e-deliberation so precocious compared to the other themes? Firstly it should be said that it is actually a combination of two themes, close in their intellectual origin but approached in a relatively independent way by the authors: public sphere and public deliberation. The subtheme of public sphere, or of the “new online public sphere”, followed up on the applications of the Habermasian concept of public sphere, in the field of political communication, to the universe of mass communication. The idea of a new public sphere, no longer subject to the limits of mass communication heavily criticized by Habermas in the 1960s, was based on a representation of the internet as a free space for horizontal conversation among citizens about affairs of common interest, and contributed considerably to introduce issues of democratic theory in the assessment of the digital revolution. Since its inception the internet had always been adaptable to tools and environments where people could talk to each other, but now they could dispense with the mediation – and the embarrassments – of journalism and politics, as well as the limits imposed by the need for all interlocutors to be present at the same time in the same place, not to mention the advantages afforded by anonymity, the universalization of contacts unrestrained by space, the supposed absence of political control in the web. The internet, therefore, seemed to be purposefully designed to implement the ideal of the public sphere or, at the very least, to renew hopes in the revival of the public sphere experience (Calhoun, 1998; Carpignano, 1999; Poster, 1997; Schneider, 1996). Approaches to the internet based on the idea of public sphere soon thrived, especially by authors in the fields of political theory, democratic theory or communication, in a momentum that peaked at the end of the period under analysis (Brants, 2005; Dahlberg, 2001a, 2001b; Downey; Fenton, 2003; Gimmler, 2001; Muhlberger, 2005; Papacharissi, 2002; Stromer-Galley, 2003). Skeptics naturally made an appearance (Dean, 2003), but the prevailing mood made the Habermasians of the public sphere feel completely at home in digital democracy. Public sphere was not the only Habermasian theme to feel at ease in digital democracy in this period. The theory of deliberation was another theme frequently highlighted between 1996 and 2005. There is a coincidence in time that might explain this curious fact, as this same period witnessed the boom of deliberative democracy in philosophy and political theory. Philosophers and political scientists, such as James Bohman (1996), Amy Gutmann (Gutmann; Thompson, 1996), Seyla Benhabib (1996) and John Dryzek (2000), published at the time some of the most important books on deliberative democracy, not to mention the release in the US of the translation of the book Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaates1, by Jürgen Habermas, which is the major point of reference of this trend of democratic theory. Studies in the area thrived in the following years, accompanied by attempts to verify, in practice, how the so-called public deliberation might work. The popularization of the internet seemed then to be a unique opportunity to test applications of deliberative democracy (Buchstein, 1997; Coleman; Gøtze, 2001; Dahlberg, 2001c; Froomkin, 2003; Gastil, 2000; Graham; Witschge, 2003; Janssen; Kies, 2005; Maia, 2002; Trechsel et al., 2004; Witschge, 2002). Even a few theoreticians of this model of democracy were seen in the field discussing applications of public deliberation to the digital world (Bohman, 2004; Chambers, 2005; Iyengar; Luskin; Fishkin, 2003; Schlosberg; Dryzek, 2002). In fact, the approach to the theme of online public discussion strongly influenced by democratic theory stems from three sources, all of them rooted in Habermas, though not exclusively: a. the discussion on the bourgeois public sphere, in Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere (Habermas, 1962); b. the theory of the ethics of argumentation, in Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Habermas, 1983); c. the theory of deliberative democracy formulated in Between Facts and Norms (Habermas, 1992). The second of these themes extended into the third, but it is at the origins of the approaches that to this day try to test the deliberative quality of online argumentative interactions. Be that as it may, what matters is that this trend allowed the theme of online discussion to become, for the theme of digital democracy post-1996, what teledemocracy had represented for this same theme between 1972 and 1995. In the early 21st century, in turn, two new subthemes come to the forefront. First, the theme identified by the term digital divide, which considers as a main democratic issue the political inequalities caused by the digital exclusion of members of a society or the inequality in access to technology between different countries and regions. At that moment, the digital inclusion of some and the digital exclusion of others seems merely to reproduce, and enhance, the important issue of contemporary democracy related to social inequality, caused by the social inclusion of some and the exclusion of others. Without political equality there is no democracy, it is that simple. And if digital exclusion increases the poverty of parts of the political community and the vulnerability of certain countries and regions suffering from other vulnerabilities, is digital democracy still democratic? At the very least, then, digital divide needed to be addressed as an issue as pressing as social exclusion. The theme was already present in the 1990s in political and media rhetoric, but it enters academic production consistently in the 2000s (Dewan; Riggins, 2005; Dimaggio; Hargittai, 2001; Hargittai, 2002; Jung; Qiu; Kim, 2001; Kennedy; Wellman; Klement, 2003; Norris, 2001; OECD, 2001; Servon, 2002; van Dijk, 2005; van Dijk; Hacker, 2003). In fact, the subtheme plays a curious role in the discussion on e-democracy, since it serves as a kind of constant resistance going against the grain of the actual area, constantly defying the idea that digital democracy might actually exist. The subtheme of inequality or exclusion is, using the biblical allegory, the real “thorn in the flesh” of the idea of digital democracy, not to deny it, but to act as its moral conscious, a persistent reminder that it is there and must be considered. The theme of e-participation, on the other hand, is a case on its own. Experiments involving citizen participation have always accompanied pari passu the idea of democracy via technology. In part because the concept at its origin, political participation, is so naturally broad that, conveniently explored, it can encompass practically all the functions technology is able to put at the service of democracy: from interaction between governors and the governed to the registration of opinions, from televoting to online discussion among citizens, from mobilization to political expression. Moreover, since the inception of the idea there has always been a clear link between the yearning that technologies might improve democracies and a widely shared diagnosis that a consistent democratic deficit exists in contemporary liberal-democratic states, a deficit deeply related to reduced political participation of citizens. The trend in democratic theory actually named participatory democracy (Barber, 1984; Pateman, 1970) has long contributed to prescribe greater civil participation as a remedy for democracies that have deflated the concept of popular sovereignty, that rely on low levels of interest and cooperation and even lower shares of social capital (Putnam, 2000) – but plenty of apathy and cynicism to match – among its citizens. Citizen political participation emerges therefore as a path for the “redemocratization of democracies”. Public discourse about communication technologies coming to the rescue of democracy is thus typical of settings that share the idea of the existence of a democratic gap that can only be filled with greater participation (Gomes, 2005a, 2005b). And participatory democracy is one of the points of contact between democratic theory and digital democracy. Therefore, although we have works on e-participation already in the 1970s (Doty; Zussman, 1975; Laudon, 1977), 1980s (Arterton, 1988; Mitropoulos, 1985) and 1990s (Streck, 1998; White, 1997), it is in the 2000s that the theme really takes off, and so consistently that in 2016, digital participation accounts for 50% of everything published in the area of e-democracy. One of the reasons for the success of the subtheme is already manifest in the period and consists of the plurality of experiments, projects and phenomena sheltered under the umbrella of e-participation. In those years, e-participation is generally discussed, but especially for: • digital petitions (Macintosh; Malina; Farrell, 2002); • participatory budgets, partially or wholly online (Rios et al., 2005; Roeder et al., 2005); • electronic public consultations (Ainsworth, 2005; Pearce, 2001; Whyte; Macintosh, 2001); • tools for interaction between citizens and government (Coleman; Hall; Howell, 2002; Jensen, 2003; Lotov, 2003); • resources for civil cooperation in decision-making processes related to regulation (Beierle, 2003; Brandon; Carlitz, 2002; Fountain, 2003b); • political decision making in general terms (Kersten, 2003; Macintosh, 2004); • and, above all, the fashionable theme at the time, electronic voting (Biasiotti; Nannucci, 2004; Chevret, 2003; Gibson, 2001; Houston et al., 2005; Lauer, 2004; Oostveen; Van Den Besselaar, 2004; Smith; Macintosh, 2003). Many and varied things, therefore, go under the name of “e-participation,” by then renowned and widespread. The impact of technology on democracy: the controversy on the effects From the viewpoint of the theoretical treatment of digital democracy, these are years that tackle the problem of assessing the impact of technologies to produce democracy. A vital matter, since on its answer depends the possibility of continuing to consistently talk about digital democracy. Along this path, we first encounter the view according to which considerable dispute and confusion surround the attempt to estimate the intensity of the impact of technology on democracy, to the point that many (still) feel quite comfortable understanding electronic democracy “as something you can be ‘for’ or ‘against’”2. One can perceive a lot or very little in electronic democracy, and one can perceive good things and bad things in the use of technologies, as in the universe of digital communications there are very different things to perceive and different assumptions to be made. The result? For some, this merely indicates that the meaning of new technologies for democracy “is unclear and controversial”3, that the direct link between new technologies and democracy “is far more controversial, palpably dangerous if not entirely false”4, that those who wish to grasp the probable effects of information and communication technologies on democratic processes “are met with a confusing tangle of propositions, many of which are contradictory and all of which are interrelated in unexplicated ways”5. What this means exactly can be ascertained by examining the lists of contrasting conclusions about the effects of technology on democracy. These range from the modest estimates of those who view technology as a complement of democracy to ambitious arguments of those who consider that “electronic media will conquer many of the problems of scale that made direct democracy an impracticable ideal”6, to mention just one example. And, lastly, there are even those that claim that the very concept of electronic democracy results from an improbable collage: “The idea of electronic democracy is still in its infancy. It looks like an explosive cocktail, blending a dose of Athenian agora, another of Rousseau, shaken with bits of Jefferson and Mill, plus a zest of Californian ideology”7. In other words, on the effects of technology on democracy much has been said and then some. Above all it is the list of disparities of themes and evaluations that explains the internal tension of the concept: Fears of social polarization due to inequitable access to ICTs or of increasing government intrusion into our private lives are juxtaposed against the promise of rejuvenated political participation engendered by new communication channels. Visions of citizens being empowered by ubiquitous access to government information are tempered by warnings of information overload8. Or, in another roll: Researchers have linked the rise of the Internet to greater citizen empowerment and to the reinforcement of existing divisions of power; to increased social fragmentation and to the rise of new forms of community; to reinvigorated democratic discourse and to Internet road rage that poisons civic engagement; to a new golden age of participatory democracy and to threats of ever greater surveillance and control of individuals; to an interactive age of democracy that overcomes voter apathy and to a commercialization of political life that marginalizes democratic concerns9. In short, with the bibliography at hand, we are forced to conclude that practically everything good and democratic, and everything bad, antisocial and antidemocratic can be done via digital communications and digital communication environments. But there are even those who consider that it is not a matter of choosing between noticing this or highlighting that, but of different aspects of the same phenomenon, and that, strictly speaking, electronic democracy has, at least, three faces, each of which “reflects a different aspect of the ICT-driven political phenomena and each implies a separate vision of the democratic process”10. • The first face would include everything that technology does to remedy the crisis of democracy: improving – in terms of costs, mobilization, coordination, internal communication, building of international networks – the dynamics of political organizations and the provision of online public services, and enabling political participation, social mobilization and civic engagement. • The second face, in turn, would entail what, according to its critics, electronic democracy would do to stimulate the democratic crisis: the insistence on plebiscitarianism that weakens citizenship and the increase of social stratification and power structures due to digital divide. • The third face of the application of technology to democracy is the recognition of its own irrelevance, caused by the fact that what is seen online is the commodification of the internet and cosmetic changes in the spectacularization of politics, not fundamental changes. In the words of Porebski: “After the decade of the information revolution we experience exactly the same problems of democracy as in the precomputer times. New bottle can not change the taste of the old wine”. And he concludes, pessimistically, on the impossibility of reducing the controversy surrounding the meaning of digital democracy: “It is not very probable that in the near future the indisputable vision of the electronic democracy impact on politics will emerge”11. A somewhat different approach is taken by some authors that argue that a decision about what technologies can offer to democracy depends on decisions about democracy itself. For some, for example, uncertainty about the democratic reach of technology must be put down to the absence of a prior decision on the idea of democracy present in the aspirations of the different projects and theories of electronic democracy. According to Benjamin Barber, for example, it is equally plausible to think that technology is both an impediment to democracy and an improvement in the quality of the political community, depending, of course, on the answer to the question of what democracy represents for us. “In other words”, he says, “it turns out there is no simple or general answer to the question ‘is the technology democratizing?’ until we have made clear what sort of democracy it is we have in mind”12. Given this context, a few solutions are put forward. And here again there are differences. Authors range from those who seem to suggest that the glowing side and fearful faces of the impact of technology on democracy are neither circumstantial nor temporary to those who demand “models of democracy” like Benjamin Barber and Jan van Dijk, for whom the decision on which model to adopt would allow the field to become less ambiguous. There are those who believe that electronic democracy is still in its infancy and that time must be allowed to see if it can materialize into practical systems the transformation of the utopian “strong democracy”13, and those who think that perhaps confusing expressions like “electronic democracy” should be abandoned and replaced with more precise designations such as “electronic mobilisation,” “electronic participation” or “electronic voting,” which, unconstrained by the connotations and confusions of the former, “can make the debate on political consequences of new technologies use more rational and substantial”14. The estimate – and the diagnosis – of the intensity of effects does not progress historically. In fact, there have been advocates of weak, complementary or incremental effects from the 1980s to the present. Of course one must keep in mind that the estimate of low impact may be less correlated with an underestimation of the effects exerted by technology on democracy and more with the contrast between the influence perceived and the influence expected. Thus, authors who describe considerable impacts of experiments may still be frustrated in their high expectations, since to them the effect seems to be much smaller than expected. It is best therefore not to ascribe normativity to estimates of effect beyond the arguments presented. Two different starting points, for example, can lead us to a definition based on disappointment. Arterton, for instance, an enthusiast of teledemocracy projects, perhaps due to high expectations or maybe because he dealt with a considerable amount of academic criticism of electronic democracy, settles for an “at best” argument: “At best, change may lead to an invigoration of representative processes facilitated by communications media”15. H. Buchstein, in turn, a critic of even moderate positions on the pro-democracy effects of the internet, concludes with the same rhetoric: “A better case [scenario] would have the Internet supplementing existing political institutions”16. Arguments in favor of the supplementation and incremental improvement (or invigoration) of democracy through technology are the preferred model of the viewpoint of weak effects. The effects are weak for a few reasons. One relates to the fact that resistance to profound changes is natural to political institutions at the stage in which they are. John Nugent is of that opinion. He goes with the general rule that a new technology or communications media (and he has nothing less than the internet in mind) is more likely to reflect or complement the political order than modify it. For all its importance, the Internet has not remade the American political landscape. Like other communications media, it has supplemented the world in which it was created, and its political implications must be considered within the context of that world. […] A major reason technology has not lived up to such bold predictions is that political participation and governmental process are structured by institutions and processes established by state and federal constitutions, which are quite resistant to change17. E-democracy, as he defines it, “refers to processes carried out online – communicating with fellow citizens and elected representatives about politics, for example”, but also to new ways for citizens to keep informed and participate politically. But, he concludes, a new way of obtaining information or communicating with elected officials does not change the way the legislative process happens, for example, completely closed to citizen participation. In the literature of the period, the relevance of the impact of technology on democracy correlates with what may be included in the concept. Does digital democracy consist of ways of communicating with elected representatives and obtaining political information? Then its effect on the system is minimal. Is it an effective way of polling public opinion capable of influencing decision makers? The level of effectiveness increases. But, in general, those who see little effect are not willing to concede much in terms of the pro-democracy functions of technology. If digital democracy is used “to refer to the use of information and communication technologies (ICTs) to connect politicians and citizens by means of information, voting, polling, or discussion”18, its estimated impact is greater, because the spectrum of its reach is broader. But if the reference is distributed in the democratic retail between the strengthening of political participation, the increasing role of plebiscites and online debates in decision making or simply any use of computers and computer networks to carry out basic democratic processes, what matters is the weight we give to each of those elements. Lastly, if its reference is “rationalization of governmental organization, improving policy processes, reinstating the primacy of parliament and the city council, opening up public information systems previously accessible only to public officials and the press, and improving the role of the citizen as voter”, in this case, there is considerable impact. However, it is still used “mostly instrumentally, as a technological extra which helps to improve and perfect the existing representative democracy”19. Contrariwise, however, most authors of that period and the following decade insisted on very high expectations about the influence of technologies on democracy. Expressions like “a radically new form of democratic practice modified by new information technologies” and “democracy substantively changed by new technology”20, or convictions that “this new communications technology will not just affect democracy, it will transform it”21, that “modern ICT is absolutely essential for helping democracies transform themselves toward a strong democracy or a more participatory stage of democratic evolution”22 clearly reflect this mentality, albeit with some rhetorical exaggeration. The approaches to the theory of electronic democracy that adopt a viewpoint of strong effects of technology on democracy focus on the distinction between secondary or conventional functions of technology influence on political institutions, and substantial and consistent functions. So it all depends on how one evaluates what deeply affects or might affect a democratic system, and what would have a secondary effect on it, which is open to potential disagreements. But, in general, it seems less relevant to e-democracy theorists when technologies are used to do “politics as usual” than when they produce intense forms of public transparency otherwise hard to achieve, for example. They believe that a mere digitization of public services to reduce costs and facilitate the work of state bureaucracy is less relevant than a new era of online public service delivery, driven by the interests of citizenship. The phase of models of democracy In the subfield of the theory of digital democracy, the predominant discussion in those years centered on the quarrel about models of democracy. In many ways, the conceptual discussion of electronic democracy considerably correlated with developments in democratic theory. The question of “models of democracy” is one of those strong points of interaction, mainly based on two books whose influence was especially noted in the 1990s and 2000s. I refer to Strong Democracy, by Benjamin Barber (1984), and Models of Democracy, by David Held (1987), two books of democratic theory that developed very successful typologies of democracy in order to enable people to interpret and compare democratic patterns in time and space. Barber himself addressed the theme of electronic democracy, although his horizon of reference is basically restricted to the pattern of experiments and the rhetorical wave associated with teledemocracy projects. Due to his view that a true democracy must be strong, dense, not weak and thin, he always seemed rather uncomfortable with the idea that telecommunication technologies might represent a new stage in global democracy. Well, first of all, it must be explained that, actually, he does believe there is a democratic potential in communication technology innovations that deserves to be explored, and also that they offer possibilities for civic republicans, and even for those who defend a demanding concept of democracy, “to strengthen civic education and enhance direct deliberative communication among citizens.”23 What bothers him is “technoenthusiasts” arguing that the new communication technologies will allow us to overcome all the communication and democracy deficits of our political system, such pretension being merely supported by electronic plebiscitary systems and improvement in obtaining information. Not true, he says. A political culture based on an inconsistent model of democracy is not the most conducive to democratic determinisms, much less pro-democratic. So that “even where it can be shown that the technology inherently holds out the promise of civic and democratic potential, it is not likely to reflect the thin, representative, alienating version of democracy that currently dominates political thinking?”, he skeptically asks24. It is not that technology develops deterministically to produce weak, thin democracies, instead of generating a consistent, participatory, strong democracy. What Barber states is that, given a culture of weak democracy, unless there is a manifest resolve to guide technologies to the production of “a more participatory and robust civic system”, the outcome may be the production of “the same incivility and cynicism that characterized politics in the older technologies, e.g. radio and television”25. For example, we may look at interactivity, the ability to connect people and to enable reciprocity between them, which all recognize as inherent in new technologies. The potential of interactive technologies to produce public deliberation and interaction among citizens and between citizens and rulers is evident, but interactive technologies alone will not solve the fact that the political system is increasingly impervious to popular will and closed to citizen participation. The most important issue, however, concerns what kind of democracy might emerge from the use of new telecommunications technologies. This is clear for Barber: anyone wishing to talk about electronic democracy must first say what type or definition of democracy they have in mind. It is a question that demands from respondents a stand on real democracy and their ideal model of democracy, to then judge what can or cannot be offered by electronic communication technologies. Taking a similar view in a 1995 paper, Scott London draws a contrast between models of teledemocracy and deliberative democracy. According to the author, there are “two models of public talk”. It seems exaggerated to oppose a set of experiments and a few claims, more rhetorical than theoretical, involving the impact of technologies on democracy with a current of democratic theory of high conceptual elaboration, but since deliberative democracy was also a consistent inspiration for experimentation (and rhetoric) in digital democracy, the comparison does bear some fruit. For him, the two models are justified according to different premises. Teledemocracy is based on approaches that, in political theory, are known as rational choice, negative liberalism or the logic of collective action; understands the political world as a free market in which interests compete and conflict; and, I add, values more the existence of channels to express opinion than the way it is produced. Deliberative democracy, in turn, considers that political will cannot simply emerge from the friction of pre-established interests, but from “reasoned discussion about issues involving the common good” (London, 1995). The following table summarizes the contrast proposed by London. The author’s side is, naturally, already chosen. TABLE 2 Teledemocracy vs. deliberative democracy Teledemocracy Deliberative democracy Public opinion and citizen feedback are essential to good governance. Aggregated opinions do not constitute public judgment. Dynamic public discourse fosters a healthy marketplace of ideas. Political truths emerge from public deliberation, not from the competition of ideas. Effective political talk is vertical – between The most effective political talk is lateral – between citizens. citizens and policymakers. With new technologies, citizens can govern themselves. Self-government requires collective decision making – thus mechanisms of dialogue and collaboration. The speed of new technologies can enhance democracy. Speed is inimical to public deliberation. Free speech is the cornerstone of democracy. Democracy is founded on the principle of dialogue, not monologue. Public participation must be increased. Quality, not quantity, is the measure of democratic participation. Citizens need equal access to information. Information, usually seen as the precondition for debate, is better understood as its by-product. Source: Scott London, “Teledemocracy vs. Deliberative Democracy: A Comparative Look at Two Models of Public Talk”, Journal of Interpersonal Computing and Technology, v. 3, n. 2, pp. 33-55, 1995. The Netherlander Jan van Dijk takes an entirely different approach. He argues that there may also be a link between the concept of democracy and judgment on the contribution of ICTs to the political system in general and to democracy in particular. However, unlike Barber and London, he does not start out from a binary contrast between democratic standards, or say that one can only evaluate the pro-democracy effects of electronic media in the light of a concept of democracy. Van Dijk draws on other assumptions, including the conviction that information and communication technologies positively impact democracy in a number of ways. The real reason to call in question the conceptions of democracy is to avoid the “all-or-nothing” approach which had lasted for two decades in the rhetoric on the subject, in the direct opposition format of either direct democracy or representative democracy. In his opinion, if something had become clear in this long debate it was, first of all, the conviction that “the conceptions of democracy are much more complicated than a simple dualism between direct and representative democracy”26. In addition, van Dijk admits that, by the mid-1990s, the phase had passed in which the decision on the interactions between democracy and new technologies depends entirely on rhetoric and theory: ICTs had reached a considerably advanced level of maturity and were assimilated into the daily practices of the political system; they are no longer merely seen as possibilities for the future. Therefore, it is possible to work with one eye on the conceptions of democracy and another on the applications of ICTs in the political system, making plausible connections between different conceptions of democracy and the applications and technological solutions that can be implemented in real democracies. Consequently, in more than one reformulation (2000, 2012, 1996), he tries to draw parallels between the models of democracy and the applications and functions of electronic democracy best suited to them. In his successive reelaborations, van Dijk settles on five to six views of electronic democracy, subdivided into government-centered perspectives (models of legalistic and competitive democracy) and citizen-centered perspectives (models of plebiscitary, pluralist, participatory and libertarian democracy). First, there is the model of legalist democracy, which is the classic model of liberal democracy: procedural (democracy has to do with the rules of the game and not the result of decisions), based on representative government, separation of powers, system of checks and balances, fundamental rights and guarantees to protect the freedom of individuals from authoritarian power, majority rule, universal suffrage. Direct democracy and populism are rejected and feared. The fundamental democratic deficit in the implementation of the model has to do with the shortage of information necessary to guide and help citizens make decisions. “So, following the legalist model ICT is designed and used as a means to remove information shortages and reinforce the present political system by more effective and efficient ways of information processing and organisation. ICT is also applied to increase the transparency of the political system.”27 The communication media or tool of preference of the model is the one that serves two functions: a) provide more and better information; b) provide interaction, so representative governments are more open and responsive to people. Competitive democracy is a version of the same liberal-democratic pattern, but with a very strong emphasis on the idea that democracy is ultimately a means of selecting leaders. The election of representatives is placed at the center of democratic concerns, and “politics has to be seen as an everlasting competition between parties and their leaders for the support of the voting public”28. In this model, ICT serves democracy when it lends itself to the goal of facilitating and qualifying elections and campaigns and helps in the generalized and segmented distribution and organization of all information necessary for a qualified electoral decision. In addition, the use of technologies to provide government efficiency is not without impact on democracy. Plebiscitary democracy, unlike the other models composing the typology proposed by Held, is generated specifically by van Dijk to deal with the view of democracy assumed in teledemocracy applications. In this construct, channels of direct communication between political leaders and citizens lead to the amplification of citizen voice in public policies. Direct democracy is therefore appreciated as a form of decision making and heeding, whenever possible, the individual position of each citizen, through plebiscites. In this model, the most important technological function for democracy is, therefore, the systems of registering votes and opinions. The first applications of teledemocracy were configured to meet the demands stemming from this model which, among other things, resulted in the rebirth of plebiscitary perspectives in the United States29. Pluralist democracy, as the name implies, is opposed to models of democracy based on centralization of political decision and monopolization of power, which result either from the belief that democracy is fundamentally a method in which many select the few who lead them or the conviction that the distribution of representation is strictly hierarchical and pyramidal. On the contrary, democratically healthy public life is more horizontal than vertical, with citizens involved in associations and civil society organizations, forced to cooperate and negotiate solutions to their own problems. And political systems consist of various interest and pressure groups and political parties that make up multiple minority power centers. From such a perspective, ICTs can serve two functions. “First, the multiplication of channels and stand-alone media supports the potential pluriformity of political information and discussion”, in such a way that practically all perspectives and all organizations are ensured the possibility of expressing their own position. “Second, the advance of interactive communication networks, in contrast to the allocution of broadcasting, perfectly fits to a network conception of politics.”30 Participatory democracy emphasizes the contribution of citizens to the political community through active political intervention in all phases of the democratic process, from the formulation of social problems to the elaboration and implementation of public policies. Participative democracy simply requires making room for the intervention and cooperation of citizens in all spheres in which political power is exercised on behalf of the people. The model, on the other hand, repeats the individualist bias present in other conceptions of democracy, as well as, consequently, methods of gauging the will of the people through individual interest aggregation. The figure of the informed citizen is a key part of this perspective. As far as technological functions go, those “able to inform and activate the citizenry” are preferred − under two conditions: a) projects and implementations should include everyone and not just the information elite; b) the project should favor instruments of discussion31. The libertarian view of democracy was the last model introduced by van Dijk (2000; 2012), but refers to a view widely spread among early advocates of democracy in cyberspace. Anti-statists par excellence and radical advocates of freedom and self-determination of individuals, including their inviolable privacy, libertarians accept anything that does not violate (or promote) their values, including freedom to experiment with electronic technologies. Indeed, among those who first embraced electronic technologies and the internet are the advocates of the independence and autonomy of cyberspace and the new electronic boundaries (Barlow, 1995; 1996). Whatever affirms the freedom of individuals, of the communities and of societies over states, governments, political systems, and corporations is endorsed by libertarianism. After affirming that there is electronic democracy for virtually all tastes, Jan van Dijk definitely concludes in favor of eclecticism: “The discussion between the advocates of the models of democracy can not be solved. Only compromises can be made”, he says. The author suggests that compromises involving all models of electronic democracy should include the universal introduction of three important goals: “(1) a more responsive government, (2) a better information supply in both directions – the government and the public administration on the one side and the citizenry at the other – and (3) a more transparent political system”32. Another interesting typology is the one proposed by Roger Hurwitz (1999), of the Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT), based on three models – or patterns – which he believes are commonly found in the history of democracy: partisan, deliberative and monitorial. In partisan democracy, “parties organize political activities primarily to get their candidates elected and then to have their plans adopted, if they have any”, while in deliberative democracy the proponents “organize around issues and call on people as concerned citizens to express their views to decision makers”. Lastly, in the monitorial model, “politics comes to life when there is great dissatisfaction with a current state of affairs and finds expression in ad hoc protest movements often directed at elected officials”33. The deliberative democracy model has a particular interest in chat rooms (we are in 1999), forums and other devices for conversation, means to exploit the availability of information and eventual online access to authorities. The online presence of parties, candidates and campaigns, in turn, serves the model of partisan democracy. The monitorial model is reflected in the use of lobbying, petition drives, demonstrations and mobilizations, which are the ways citizens react to crises or to the perception of pressing social problems. Because it forms communities of interest that transcend time, space, and the need of formal presentation of participants, the internet is a powerful tool for this type of democratic action, according to Hurwitz34. The typology proposed by Lincoln Dahlberg, professor in New Zealand at the time, is based on a very different perspective. Reader of Jürgen Habermas, Dahlberg reflects one of the earliest influences in the sub-area of digital democracy, situated around Habermas’s oeuvre, particularly The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere and Between Facts and Norms, and the Habermasians of deliberative democracy. In common with the previous categorizations, there is the premise that the perspectives described in the typology should address discourses and practices (online political projects and experiments with democracy on the internet), as well as theoretical models. That leads Dahlberg to identify the three dominant camps in the domain of electronic democracy. First, “a communitarian camp, which stresses the possibility of the Internet enhancing communal spirit and values”; then, “a liberal individualist camp, which sees the Internet as assisting the expression of individual interests”. Last, the deliberative camp that shows up the internet in a positive light “as the means for an expansion of the public sphere of rational-critical citizen discourse – discourse autonomous from state and corporate power through which public opinion may be formed that can hold official decision makers accountable”35. One can identify the author’s purpose with his typology in three categories. The first two camps represent two of the pioneering viewpoints in internet rhetoric: the communitarianism of the precursors of virtual communities and of the use of the internet for a democracy based on social capital and community integration (Rheingold, 1993), and the teledemocracy perspective, with its strong emphasis on the provision of information and on direct interactions between citizens and decision makers, assuming the existence of a prepared and determined political citizen, who lacks only adequate information and channels of expression to make appropriate decisions. This way, Dahlberg made room to accommodate the deliberative perspective of Habermasian origin, which refuses the communitarian idea that the internet serves basically for the “pre-discursive expression of shared values or private interests”36 and also refutes the liberalindividualism to which the internet serves primarily to channel individual interests, established outside horizontal discussions among citizens. In contrast, the “deliberative democrats argue that a ‘strong’ model of democracy requires a public sphere of rational-critical discourse”. Or that a “respectful and reflexive deliberation is demanded”, so that individuals may become publicly-oriented citizens and, ultimately, a public opinion is developed that is able to “feed into formal decision-making processes”37. The Swedish political scientist Joachim Åström (2001), in turn, started out from Barber’s binary taxonomy and added a third category, formulating three models of e-democracy: quick, strong and thin democracy. TABLE 3 Central dimensions of democracy according to Åström Quick democracy Strong democracy Thin democracy Aim Power to the people Consensus Efficiency/choice Ground for legitimacy Principle of majority Public debate Accountability Citizensʼ role Decision maker Opinion former Customer Interactive Open Discussion Information Mandate of the elected Bound ICT use focusing Decisions Source: Joachim Åström, “Should Democracy Online Be Quick, Strong, or Thin?”, Communications of the ACM, v. 44, n. 1, 1 Jan. 2001. For Åström, quick democracy represents a possible stance in the debate on electronic democracy. Like other models, it looks favorably on a considerable increase of citizens’ direct participation in political decision making and requires active citizenship. The representative model is seen as a practical necessity or a necessary evil, to be avoided whenever possible, including through possibilities offered by ICTs. “Radical proponents of this model see ICT as the decisive means by which direct democracy Athenian style can be implemented in today’s society,” according to Åström. He goes on to add: “Through computer networks, individuals’ views and opinions can be solicited, registered, stored, and communicated, so direct democracy can be implemented not only at a local level but nationally and even internationally.” So representative democracy would then be “substituted by independent cybercitizens who act in a responsible manner at the electronic agora, without any politician acting as an intermediary and guardian”38. Less radical proponents, in turn, do not want the complete abolition of the representative system, but to “combine it – revitalize it – with direct elements”. There are those who think of a government based on a political party and chosen in elections, but which would make a kind of direct democracy work, “put important bills and other political decisions to popular votes, just as it does with legislative votes under representative democracy”39. And there are even those who merely imagine the consulting use of opinion polls through technology. Unlike other models, with which the conviction of the importance of civil participation is shared, quick democracy wants to “increase the speed of decision-making processes”. How? By all methods that allow the swift assessment of the will of the majority, through voting or other means of opinion polling mediated by technology. Might citizens be up to it? Apparently, there is no doubt: “In this view, all citizens are assumed to have at least the same amount of wisdom as the elite”40. As seen, quick democracy is the form found by Åström to somehow retrieve the criticized plebiscitary majoritarianism of teledemocracy. Strong democracy, already known, is described as participatory, but, above all, deliberative. It supposedly emerged as a countermodel to the pattern of weak and thin democracy predominant in liberal-democratic states, which basically require civil participation, only at electoral moments, and shield and isolate policy decision makers from the sphere of citizenship. Strong democracy requires more legitimacy in political decision making than that afforded by the election of representatives, but it likewise doubts that the predetermined and unintended will of individuals is able to bestow the necessary legitimacy on the system. The only appropriate source of democratic legitimacy would be the process of forming will and political opinion through deliberation. Like quick democracy, the strong version presumes active citizenship, which acts on issues of common interest, but unlike the former, strong democracy wants to “slow down” decision making “by involving people in discussion and deliberation processes”41. Electronic forums seem appropriate for this. This model harbors sympathy for elements of direct democracy, but with caution, since there is here a certain degree of skepticism regarding “raw public opinion”, integral but not yet treated and refined. In Åström’s view, therefore, strong democracy would disapprove of much of quick democracy. Besides, he considers the rhythm the latter proposes for decision making hasty and believes that it is an illusion to think that there is qualified opinion on complex social problems readily available to be automatically and easily collected by electronic means. “Voting and polling should be deliberative, and citizens informed by information, discussion, and debate.”42 Thin democracy, the third model, is hardly interested in increasing civil participation, since it deems the ordinary citizen “disinterested in politics and unqualified for participation”. Basically, democracy has to do with choosing leaders in open elections, based on their programs. The basis of legitimacy of those who govern is resolved with accountability. The role of technologies in this model is to be the means by which organizations spread information and obtain support, instruments to facilitate the work of representatives and, ultimately, channels for the provision of public services43. But what, after all, was intended with the controversy of the models of democracy and, consequently, of e-democracy? In the first place, to solve the impasse that the controversy around teledemocracy had brought to the area. The people who planned and executed the first projects were activists of the socalled New Left (Tsagarousianou, 1999, p. 189), and they were eventually flanked on the right and on the left. On the right by the defenders of the strict model of representative democracy, which traditionally harbors, especially at that time, considerable mistrust of the worth of the contribution of ordinary people to political decisions. Given that citizens are not very rational and show little interest in public affairs, and therefore could hardly achieve what Robert Dahl calls a “proper understanding” of political issues, giving greater weight to citizens in the process of political decision making is not exactly something that, in this perspective, could be understood as requalification of democracy. It seems just the opposite, dangerous technological populism. The left flank is occupied by the viewpoint of a strong democracy, amenable to any perspective of direct or participatory democracy, distrustful of representative government and the anemic democracy it offers. The anticapitalist dimension of the far left perspective triggers a warning against televoting, but the larger suspicions (presented earlier) attack the modality of gauging citizens’ will through the devices of technology, with no qualified interaction, without sufficient participation, with no in-depth clarification. The formulations of the models of democracy have two purposes. The purpose of Barber and London is to continue harassing teledemocracy through a binary contrast between an adequate position, ours, and the wrong position, theirs. But the most common purpose, present in the other authors, was to break the siege on electronic democracy, represented by the attack on teledemocracy, proposing an eclectic alternative. The conclusion reached by pluralist authors is that technologies are capable of delivering more democracy, whatever the model of preference of whoever formulates e-democracy projects. One may even dislike the model favored by others, and it is quite clear that each author has his or her own preferences, but it can be said that technology can do something for every preferred emphasis, pattern or type of democracy. And that democracy, however it is conceived, is the better for it. Facing the last resistances As we have seen, in the decade between 1996 and 2005, there is a remarkable concentration of efforts to assess the impact of technology on democracy and to formulate models of e-democracy. But equally noteworthy is the way in which some of the harshest criticisms of the idea of digital democracy, formulated in the previous decade, are tackled during the period of consolidation of the area. Let us consider some of them and the counter-arguments presented. Criticisms 1 to 3, originated in the previous period and already familiar to us, will be treated briefly. The fourth, more complex, will be addressed at greater length. 1. The more general idea that the use of communication technologies alone can solve problems of democracy is false. For example, the fact that we have the technological capacity to share political decisions more broadly does not mean they become the responsibility of citizens rather than the competence of elected representatives. It is not merely a matter of technology, but of institutional design (McLean, 1989): “Technology does nothing to solve the conceptual problems that democracy generates”44. This criticism seems to face a rhetorical scarecrow, created out of thin air just to be easily quashed, advocating a technological automatism according to which the mere existence of channels and possibilities would lead governments and the bureaucracy to instantly transfer all possible data to citizens, and the citizens, in turn, to pore over such information to consume and develop it. Well, in truth, reliable, updated and abundant data made available to citizens are, as we know today, essential for democracy, for improving peoples’ lives and even for the advancement of society. But nothing is automatic in democracy, not even the existence of the best technological means available. Historically, interest aggregation was initially the most evident goal of electronic democracy projects. It was not only the most compatible with the stage attained by telecommunications in 1970-1990, but also the one that required the least changes in political systems considerably shut off to citizens. We cannot tell whether that was exactly what the developers and advocates of the use of technologies to foster democracy wanted, but we can say that, under the circumstances, it was the opportunity to obtain more democracy via technologies. Technologies could be easily used to increase the supply of information of their interest or collect their opinion or the popular feeling on public issues, and such possibilities were often exploited. What is regrettable is that advocates of a model quickly became detractors of alternative patterns and quickly the goals that considered the interests and opinions of individuals were treated as forms of commercial exchange and citizens as private and privatized consumers. In some cases, the baby was thrown out with the bathwater – electronic democracy was not democracy. 2. The type of democracy that emerged from electronic democracy was “a debased, impoverished version of the true ideal. Democracy becomes a mere device for registering preferences”45. The problem with this criticism is confusing the function that a particular technology can provide with a general judgment about democracy, resulting solely from the fulfillment of that function. Having a communication channel available that allows votes to be registered does not mean having a kind of democracy based on the remote gauging of preferences. One thing bears no relationship to the other. It simply means that we now have a democracy that has at its disposal a resource to register the preferences of citizens even at a distance, which, although it might not substantially change the democratic quality of society, is at least one more thing to be incorporated into the repertoire of resources of that society. 3. It is not only a matter of fostering a debased form of democracy through technology, but also that the technologies of electronic democracy ultimately foster antidemocratic asymmetries. It is the famous argument that, due to inequality in access and use, technologies represent yet another advantage, added to the repertoire of those already predominant in society. The powerful thus become even more powerful, to the detriment of the socially excluded, who, in addition to other forms of exclusion, will also suffer from the technological divide. This argument does not represent a consistent objection to the idea of electronic democracy either, unless it is demonstrated that the democratic resources of technology were the cause of social inequality in a given society. Problems of inequality and social exclusion are faced by addressing their true causes, not preventing a society from developing just because the socially included will have even more benefits to the detriment of the excluded. Otherwise, not only will social exclusion not be reduced, but society will miss out on opportunities to develop. In addition we have seen that, twenty years after Street’s review, digital exclusion has become considerably smaller than social exclusion. Therefore, atrophying the development of digital democracy does not seem to have contributed, as predicted, to enhance social inequalities. Quite the contrary. 4. If digital democracy is unable to produce more and better civil participation and public deliberation, then it cannot help to improve democracy. In the decade between 1996 and 2005, we are still dealing, albeit not with the same intensity, with the symptomatic issue of the reach of e-democracy. An interesting argument regarding the subject was presented by the AngloAmerican political scientist Pippa Norris in an important book of 2001 called Digital Divide. It is quite true that Norris’s argument is an explicit criticism of the left-wing conception of e-democracy and that it is clearly positioned on the other side, in a Schumpeterian model. But it is ultimately a consistent argument against those who consider participation and deliberation necessary requirements for the existence of digital democracy, a position she considers excessively narrow. For Norris, those who adopt a concept of direct, strong or plebiscitary democracy must anticipate a direct role for citizens in the decisionmaking process, defined as the eminent form of participation, but if political participation and public deliberation are merely an important element of any concept of democracy, they cannot be transformed into its single element. The alternative model offered by Norris thus highlights other elements that must be considered, such as • “pluralistic competition among parties and individuals for all positions of government power”; • “civil and political liberties to speak, publish, assemble, and organize, as necessary conditions to ensure effective competition and participation”; and • “Participation among equal citizens in the selection of parties and representatives through free, fair, and periodic elections”46. It is noted that participation here is limited to “participation in elections”. The other two dimensions are explicitly typical aspects of liberal democracy: civil and political liberties and electoral democracy. Participation and deliberation, in the sense conferred on them by left-wing perspectives, “such as direct citizen decision-making and deliberation in the policy process, or electronic voting”47, are not on the horizon, which, on the other hand, would not make digital democracy any less necessary or urgent, given that “in most societies throughout the world it is the core institutions of representative government and civic society that urgently need to be nurtured and strengthened”48. Norris’s judgment on the disputes and controversies over the role of digital technologies for democracy, carried out in the debate on the role of technologies for direct or strong democracy, is that it is a substantially flawed debate for being centered on requirements of participation in political decision, including in deliberative participation. For her, this whole discussion can be considered nothing more than “a distracting irrelevance, a buzzing mosquito, deflecting attention from the potential function of Internet in strengthening the institutions of representative governance and civic societies worldwide”49. The key issue, to be repositioned towards the center, about the possibility of a digital democracy therefore consists of how the two main actors of democracy, governments and citizens, will use “the opportunities provided by the new channels of information and communication to promote and strengthen the core representative institutions connecting citizens and the state”50. In this regard, opportunities for public participation and civic engagement generated via new technology are important, as is the ability of the Internet to provide information promoting the transparency, openness, and accountability of governing agencies at national and international levels, and to strengthen channels of interactive communication between citizens and intermediary institutions51. Public participation and civic engagement via digital means, but also etransparency, open government, e-accountability and interactive channels of communication with the intermediary institutions of the state are all different functions through which technologies have an impact on democracy. And the current state of the internet allows some of them to be better executed than others. So that even if typical functions of strong or direct democracy, such as civic engagement and militant participation, do not seem to be well resolved in digital democracy, there are typical functions of representative democracy much better managed in digital media, such as support for minority parties in their campaigns, the constitution of transnational networks of third-sector organizations, the offer to journalists and stakeholders of greater and better access to official documents and legislative proposals. Thus, according to Norris, promoting participation in political decision making, besides being just one more function capable of being performed through the internet, may not be the most efficiently executed by digital technologies among other functions which also benefit representative democracy. It is unnecessary to dispute with Norris the value assigned to participation and deliberation for the democratic quality of a society, nor the degree of intensity demanded of each of them for the level of legitimacy of the liberaldemocratic state. Schumpeterians tend to consider that societies with a very high-level of political participation of citizens are not only very difficult to govern, but inevitably fail to deliver important democratic values such as equality, freedom, pluralism, rights. And if at any moment the various fascisms, with their mass civil participation, were the counterexample of what one wanted to avoid, nowadays the right-wing populisms spreading through Western democracies are sufficient reason to recommend prudence in adhering to the hypothesis that participation is good in itself (Gomes, 2011). On the other hand, Norris is certainly right in rejecting the “all-or-nothing” argument of digital democracy based on extremely demanding requirements of democracy, such as participation and deliberation in institutional policy decision making, which we do not dare demanding from society at large to recognize it as truly democratic, yet do so constantly and mistakenly regarding e-democracy. Finally, the clear and binary contrast between participation and representation hardly makes such sense as some might claim. As Norberto Bobbio affirmed, “between pure representative democracy and pure direct democracy there is not the qualitative leap that advocates of direct democracy believe, as if between one and the other existed a watershed and the landscape changed completely as soon as we passed from one margin to the other”52. It is much more of a continuum in which participation and deliberation are, in general, more means than ends in themselves. In this case, it should be noted that not all participation necessarily involves participation in political decision making, but that there are considerable gains in participation which entails, for example, the expansion of the process of democratization of society. In this respect there is something very interesting for democracy in the air when democratization “consists not so much, as is often erroneously said, in the transition from representative democracy to direct democracy, but rather in the transition from political democracy in the strict sense to social democracy”53. That means that not everything that is at stake in democracy relates to the democratization of the state, or the occupation of the sphere in which political decisions are made by active citizens, but to the increase of participants in decision making within society itself, in trade unions, councils, organizations, institutions. 1 Published in the US as Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996). 2 Å. Grönlund, “Democracy in an IT-framed Society: Introduction”, Communications of the ACM, v. 44, n. 1, pp. 22-6, 1 Jan. 2001, p. 25. 3 H. Buchstein, “Bytes that Bite: The Internet and Deliberative Democracy”, Constellations, v. 4, n. 2, pp. 248-63, Oct. 1997, p. 248 4 B. R. Barber, op. cit., p. 208. 5 C. Weare, “The Internet and Democracy: The Causal Links Between Technology and Politics”, International Journal of Public Administration, v. 25, n. 5, pp. 659-91, 20 Apr. 2002, p. 660. 6 H. Buchstein, op. cit., p. 248. 7 T. Vedel, op. cit., p. 234. 8 C. Weare, op. cit., p. 660. 9 Ibidem, p. 662. 10 L. Porebski, “Three Faces of Electronic Democracy”, Proceedings of the 10th European Conference on Information Systems (ECIS), Gdansk, Poland, 2002, p. 1220, available at: <http://aisel.aisnet.org/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1082&context=ecis2002>, accessed on: 11 Dec. 2017. 11 Ibidem, p. 1225. 12 B. R. Barber, op. cit., p. 223. 13 T. Vedel, op. cit., p. 234. 14 L. Porebski, op. cit., p. 1225. 15 F. C. Arterton, “Political Participation and ‘Teledemocracy’”, op. cit., p. 621. 16 H. Buchstein, op. cit., p. 260. 17 J. D. Nugent, “If E-Democracy Is the Answer, What’s the Question?”, National Civic Review, v. 90, n. 3, pp. 221-34, Jan. 2001, p. 224. 18 Å. Grönlund, op. cit., p. 23. 19 K. Brants; M. Huizenga; R. van Meerten, “The New Canals of Amsterdam: An Exercise in Local Electronic Democracy”, Media, Culture & Society, v. 18, n. 2, pp. 233-47, 1 Apr. 1996, p. 238. 20 L. A. Friedland, “Electronic Democracy and the New Citizenship”, Media, Culture & Society, v. 18, n. 2, pp. 185-212, 1 Apr. 1996, p. 185. 21 T. Westen, “E-Democracy: Ready or Not, Here It Comes”, National Civic Review, v. 89, n. 3, pp. 217-28, 2000, p. 217. 22 T. Becker, “Rating the Impact of New Technologies on Democracy”, Communications of the ACM, v. 44, n. 1, pp. 39-43, 1 Jan. 2001, p. 39. 23 B. R. Barber, op. cit., p. 208. 24 Ibidem, p. 213. 25 Ibidem. 26 J. G. M. van Dijk, “Models of Democracy – Behind the Design and Use of New Media in Politics”, Javnost – The Public, v. 3, n. 1, pp. 43-56, 7 Jan. 1996, p. 44. 27 Ibidem, p. 48. 28 Ibidem. 29 Ibidem, p. 49. 30 Ibidem, p. 50. 31 Ibidem, p. 54. 32 Ibidem, p. 55. 33 R. Hurwitz, op. cit., p. 657. 34 Ibidem, p. 660. 35 L. Dahlberg, “The Internet and Democratic Discourse: Exploring The Prospects of Online Deliberative Forums Extending the Public Sphere”, Information, Communication & Society, v. 4, n. 4, pp. 615-33, 2001, p. 616. 36 Ibidem, p. 620. 37 Ibidem. 38 J. Åström, “Should Democracy Online Be Quick, Strong, or Thin?”, Communications of the ACM, v. 44, n. 1, 1 Jan. 2001, p. 50. 39 Ibidem. 40 Ibidem. 41 Ibidem. 42 Ibidem. 43 Other typologies of models of democracy were explored in those years, but did not reach more sophisticated levels of taxonomy. One worth mentioning is the typology of Arthur Edwards (1995) that identifies three conceptions of electronic democracy: populist, liberal and republican. And that of Jens Hoff (Hoff; Horrocks; Tops, 2000), with four models of e-democracy: consumerist, plebiscitary, pluralist and participatory. 44 J. Street, op. cit., p. 32. The three criticisms are not John Street’s, but were reviewed by him in the cited article. 45 Ibidem, p. 32. 46 P. Norris, Digital Divide: Civic Engagement, Information Poverty, and the Internet Worldwide, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001, p. 102. 47 Ibidem, p. 103. 48 Ibidem, p. 104. 49 Ibidem. 50 Ibidem. 51 Ibidem. 52 N. Bobbio, Il futuro della democrazia, Turim: Einaudi, 1984, p. 15. 53 Ibidem, p. 66. Democracy is not easy to define. […] In this context, it’s not surprising that there are numerous definitions of digital democracy. For some it refers to the use of digital tools to provide information and promote transparency, for others it describes the ways in which information and communications technologies (ICTs) can broaden and deepen participation, while others talk of promoting empowerment by enabling citizens to make decisions directly through online tools. We simply define the term as “the practice of democracy using digital tools and technologies”. Julie Simon et al. A new internet T HE TEN-YEAR PERIOD BETWEEN 2006 AND 2015 consolidates the trend of the new internet, characterized, first of all, by the significant growth of the then relationship websites (later popularized as “social networking websites”) and websites for sharing photos, videos, etc. (the so-called “social media”). The new dominant idea in the market at this moment is Web 2.0, interactive and cooperative, to which converge classic communitarian ideas of the technological collective imagination. However, it is the very idea of website and the classic web that is challenged by two innovations consolidated in this period: the internet of applications and the mobile internet. The last decade witnessed a new “race for machines” following the buying spree of home computers in the 1990s, which is the quest for portable devices with processing capacity and internet connection. Connection starts breaking free from home and office computers and becomes mobile wherever we go thanks to portable devices and cell phones. In short, the term “personal computer” now really starts making sense. In addition, the application as a pattern of internet use accompanies the boom of mobile device consumption, established in the 2010s on a global level. Some iconic innovations of the period, such as MacBook Pro (2006), which popularized the truly portable notebook, iPhone (2007) and the Android operating system (2008), merely signaled the mainstream trend of consumption and social adoption of technologies of communication. In addition, the last decade has such singular characteristics compared to the previous ten years that one can practically speak of a new internet. The internet based on mobile devices, permanent connection and digital media applications barely resembled the one based on web browsing and desktops, with intermittent connection, in which a “virtual world” was breaking loose from the “real world” and one needed to leave one to enter the other. The last decade was the years of the ubiquity of digital technologies, in which e-, the prefix that designated the new world of electronic communications, was replaced by the adjective smart, as in smart TV, smartphone, smart gov, smart cities, smart democracy, the prefix m-, from mobile, as in m-government and m-democracy, and the adjectives 2.0 and 3.0. And these are the years of the discovery of big data – the huge repositories of collected, processed and usable digital data that promise to reveal everything about everything – and establish the normative horizon of open government data at the service not only of society but also of humanity. From the point of view of the social use of digital communications, the last decade is marked by hyperconnection (Gomes, 2016b) and its developments. Hyperconnection is a state in which individuals always have at hand a device that is hardly ever switched off or disconnected from the network. More than that, in this state, people are increasingly surrounded by multiple devices, often with redundant functions, through which they satisfy functions and needs such as making social contact, updating themselves about facts, things and people that interest them, obtaining information, talking with other people, transferring to digital social networks content of all kinds and formats, keeping and making appointments, orienting themselves in space and in life, overcoming boredom, working, interacting, among other things. Other important social phenomena are associated with hyperconnection. The main one is social internet or internet based on social media, digital social networks and the intense consumption or production of digital content. “Content” is the term referring generally to any type of written, graphic or audiovisual material (and all of them at the same time) available in digital communications. The most relevant outcome of social internet is the development of digital, online social environments, based on tools and applications for social networking. We are not talking about each one of the websites, applications and services for social networking making up a social environment, so that there is a social environment for Facebook, another for Twitter, Instagram, YouTube and so on. Rather, each person has their own social network within each of the digital networking services, made up of their various friends, followers, followees, fans... or whatever name is given to the people in contact with them. Digital environments serve as points of reference, intellectual, affectionate, political, ideological, of identity, etc., according to the divide each person deems important and uses as a criterion to select the connections they will maintain online. In addition, in the state of hyperconnection people are in touch with their own digital environment without having to leave or “disconnect” from the traditional social environments in which we are inserted – family, friends, colleagues, members of religious groups or political parties, etc. There is nothing that imposes exclusionary choices like doing a family activity or being with friends or being connected in your own digital environment. Lastly, the digital environment is mobile and truly personal, in the sense that, once the connecting devices are working, access to the digital environment moves with us, at all times of the day and in all circumstances possible: one can read, view, publish, share and interact with the digital environment during class, in the quiet of one’s bedroom, in the bathroom, at meetings, at the beach, on holidays, at the airport, according to one’s convenience and interest. First of all, it should be noted that in the explanation of the internal movements of digital democracy, a few social events are of great importance. Just as the cyber-libertarians of the 1990s were deeply impressed by the use of the internet by the Zapatistas in 1993 and the demonstrations against the World Trade Organization (WTO) meeting in Seattle in 1999, the first successful use of online political campaigns (Howard Dean in 2004 and Barack Obama in 2008) greatly influenced the theme of digital elections and campaigns, and the protests in Iran in 2009 and the so-called Arab Spring, which begins the following year, had a deep impact on the themes of online political participation and the role of the internet in demonstrations, political action, social mobilization, organization of civil society and even revolutions. In the world of cell phones that never turn off or disconnect, at an age in which we all live at the same time, and complementarily, online and offline, in a universe in which our basic needs of information and direction are solved by tapping, clicking and typing on device screens, it seems quite plausible that the means of digital communications, the actual communications and the online environments they create have a considerable impact on democracy, politics and government. After all, nothing is more evident for someone living in the 21st century than the increasing digitization of life. There is nothing metaphysical in such awareness. Everyone realizes, for example, that in contemporary society, the services sector involving interaction is gradually switching or supplementing its traditional interfaces (the counter, the booth, the clerk, the sales assistant, the form) with digital interfaces. The purchase, the bank transaction, the contract, the contact, everything is done more and more online. This also includes the provision of government services, increasingly digitized worldwide. Moreover, our actual social, family and private interactions have become increasingly mediated by digital communication technologies, devices, machines, media and environments. From the most routine forms of conversation, from the exchange of affection and public, private and intimate information to the consumption and production of information, the exchange of opinions, worldviews and perspectives, the satisfaction of guidance needs, the attention to daily life and the life of those who are dear to us or those who are merely the object of our curiosity. Thus, much of what we do every day, such as consume, find directions, keep ourselves informed, close business transactions or interact increasingly depends on the mediation of digital technologies. It is no surprise, then, that other less basic but equally important activities and interests are similarly influenced by the digital media and environments surrounding us. If we use digital social networks to keep up with politics, if we turn to information available online for political guidance, if today our networks of contacts and political relationships are generally based on websites and interaction applications, why should it come as a surprise that the political demonstrations we take part in are also digitally mobilized, that many of the political initiatives we take are supported by digital media, that the social and political campaigns we engage in have an online base? Along the same lines, if we accept quite peacefully that the digitization of interactions and relationships has a considerable impact on virtually everything we do, we are equally ready to admit that this impact extends to other spheres of life, including life in common, within the political community. After all, we live in communities and states, under the law and regimes of common life, within the reach of constraints and potential political conditions that establish the limits of what are rights and what are duties for each one of us. In other words, our whole life unfolds within the limits of the social contract and the political community, and, naturally, according to how this political community is governed. Once the progressive digitization of private life and social interactions is admitted, it seems a natural consequence to admit that there is a growing technological mediation of public life, that is, of that sphere of life in society that has to do with public affairs and issues, with the functioning of political community and with its institutional form, the state. Public life necessarily entails a normative dimension, which means that it is not related to things as they really are, but to the way things should be. Much of the energy expended in politics, for example, has to do with views, with perspectives of how decisions that affect everyone’s life should be made, with which public policies are preferable and how they should be implemented to achieve this or that end. As there is also a normative dimension in general, based on valueoriented views and perspectives, supporting and motivating protests, demonstrations, revolutions. Lastly, in the sphere of the state’s functioning system, this normative dimension is even more imperative, since democracy is a response to preferences about the choice of leaders, the organization, assignment and limitation of political power, the decision making that affects the lives of all, the production of laws, the configuration of the judiciary and the application of justice, the types of rights and guarantees and to whom they are guaranteed. The acknowledgment that politics and democracy also involve value-based preferences and views does not, however, undermine the public perception that the digitization of all spheres of life seems a natural path. The fact that public life is constantly imbued with a dispute over values does not alter our common perception that digital mediation provides us with channels, tools and resources that decisively affect politics, governments and democracy. On the contrary, it seems quite natural to our contemporaries that digital environments should provide scenarios that are especially suitable for the dispute over values and interpretations of social problems, for the answer to such problems in the form of public policies to give shape and flow to demands from the world of everyday life, for the friction of worldviews, agendas and preferences. Just as digital channels serve adequately to pressure and monitor rulers and public officials, to challenge decisions made by established bodies, to challenge the political and intellectual hegemonies of any of the state powers. Lastly, and to make a long story short, there is a growing consensus that digital means, environments, projects and devices can serve to transfer power to citizens, to the small fry of democracy, in the face of the social formats (institutions, corporations, organizations) that compete with them for: a) the capacity to make an impact on public policies, legislation and regulation; b) the influence over elections and all manners of choosing leaders and their agendas; and c) the possibility of constraining or controlling those who govern in this or that direction. So virtually everything that seems to be part of what is understood as materialization or implementation of the democratic regime seems today to be somehow intertwined with means, environments and uses of digital technologies. It does not matter whether such technologies are understood as mere instruments or channels, or, more demandingly, as means and mediators, or in their ultimately demanding form, as a condition of possibility to have more and better democracy. The idea that democracy, in particular, and public life, in general, are in some way intertwined with the universe of digital communications derives, according to the argument I have been developing, from the social perception of the digitization of everyday life. Since intimate life and social life are so digitized, that is, based on interactions mediated by digital technologies, it seems to follow logically that public life is subject to the same regime. Digital technologies surround us so naturally that they are almost confused with the landscape and are no longer thematized or questioned. Digital technologies increasingly resemble those skills acquired in remote times, such as writing or speaking, that we no longer think about; rather, we think by means of them, through them. It is therefore becoming increasingly unusual and extravagant to imagine that we can do anything without the environment of our digital technologies. Which leads us directly to the following questions: If everything in our life is increasingly digital, why should only democracy be analog? If the ubiquitous technology allows us to do much of what interests us online, why should only democracy be left offline? Themes and trends in recent years Following the trend observed at the end of the previous decade, the level of direct attention given to the theory of e-democracy remained well below it deserved until 2004. Apparently, the function which the theory of e-democracy served, the discussion on the possibility, models, problems and perspectives of democracy in digital means and environments was no longer as necessary or as urgent as it was until the mid-2000s. Until then, as we have seen, the theoretical framework and conceptual justification of the expectations of the use of technology to produce more and better democracies seemed decisive to establish a place for e-democracy in society, politics and science. As far as political environments and society in general go, the theory of e-democracy served to provide legitimacy and thus mobilize funds and support for experiments with teledemocracy or electronic democracy projects, so that people and organizations would feel encouraged to design and implement democratization initiatives through technology. In societies such as ours, what would be more capable of granting legitimacy to a new phenomenon, and one surrounded by suspicion and skepticism, than democracy itself as an idea and normative horizon? Regarding science, digital democracy followed the same course as any new discipline or new scientific field, especially in the humanities: it had to open its way with several reasoned and well-founded justifications until the path was cleared of the most skeptical challenges and most severe criticisms. In the case in point, how better could legitimacy be sought than placing e-democracy in the lap of democratic theory? The conceptual discussion of the possibilities and limits of e-democracy, therefore, had a purpose, but it was not an end in itself; its relegation to a lower, but consistent and constant, level seems therefore to be a symptom that the field is moving towards scientific consolidation and that, apparently, the idea that democracy may greatly benefit from technology is no longer challenged or misunderstood as it has been in the recent past. But where did e-democracy go, considering that it disappeared from the titles of articles and chapters and the center stage? It was simply assimilated, more or less explicitly, into the framework of the products. Whether articles, reports or projects of digital democracy, part of them is usually devoted to the argumentative defense of e-democracy or to justifying the initiative, experiment or phenomenon, based on some of the requirements and values of democracy, such as equality, justice, participation, popular sovereignty, transparency, pluralism, deliberation. In the second decade of the 21st century, digital democracy is one of those ideas whose time has apparently come, and basically all that is left of the task of justifying projects, initiatives or phenomena is to precisely claim the fact that they are e-democratic projects, initiatives or phenomena. Moreover, and unlike previous periods, in the last ten years of digital democracy the discussion is no longer focused on the general possibilities of electronic democracy, but has unfolded into different questions about the various subthemes, each one with its own adventures and histories of consolidation, including in a highly interdisciplinary manner. Instead of simply asking questions about whether the internet can indeed have an impact on democracy, politics and the state, each line now asks how we can have more and better participation, deliberation, transparency, pluralism, rights, etc. by means of digital technologies. Or how we can tackle and overcome the limits of the various levels of digital divide. On the other hand, a kind of new model of digital democracy emerged during this period with the consolidation of a literature that starts out from or assumes premises of something that, in the absence of a better name, we might call grassroots democracy, a trend in political theory that values the community, minority groups, interests at the core of society, participation, political action in protests, mobilization, demonstrations, and, sometimes, confrontation. A leftwing trend in general, represented by researchers from the spheres of civil society and social movements, who had long kept at a reasonable distance from edemocracy, considered elitist, capitalist, consumerist and incapable of solving even the problems of digital divide, much less of social exclusion and injustice. The scarecrow of oppressive or elitist technology drove them away from the field of digital democracy and kept them skeptical or antagonistic. In the 2010s, however, a grassroots trend emerged in the internet and political studies that considerably raised interest in the democratizing worth of digital technologies. Judging from the academic attention to the subthemes, there was an extraordinary growth in attention to digital protests, online activism, emovements, digital collective action and online engagement since the Arab Spring and the boom of digital protests worldwide (see Chart 4). Digital environments and websites and applications of digital social networks are naturally at the base of all this. The main subthemes addressed by the advocates of grassroots democracy in their studies are grouped under “internet and society” and represent the great innovation in the cross between politics and democracy in the field of digital democracy in recent years. In general, the approach to these various topics includes a considerable degree of normative content often related to democratic issues: struggles for justice and rights, popular sovereignty, reaction to oppression, struggle for freedom and against inequities, defense of minorities and vulnerable groups, protests against violations of rights and injustices. Thus, the last six years in particular have seen the rise of a new democratic momentum in which technology is put at the service of the oppressed, the wronged, those who fight and demonstrate for justice, rights, recognition, equality, and freedom. CHART 4 Publications on the subthemes of internet & society – 2006-2015 However, beyond the prevalence of e-democracy in online political matters, as seen in the attention given to traditional left-wing political themes, it is necessary to understand precisely the behavior of traditional themes of digital democracy in the last eleven years (see Chart 5). For example, the theme of participation has grown exponentially and prevails over all others, also confirming the trend of the late preceding decade. At the peak of the analyzed production, in 2012, it accounted for 55% of production in the area of edemocracy, remaining at a very high level since then, despite a brief downward oscillation. If we were to assess the importance of the use of technologies for citizen participation from the number of projects, volume of funds invested, reports or studies of multilateral organizations that review and encourage edemocracy, we would probably achieve the same results. There are many reasons for the success of e-participation in the field of digital democracy, starting with the breakdown of the theme shown above, involving a large range of important activities for democracy and, it should not be forgotten, for the government: public consultations, petitions, participation in decision making, electronic and/or online voting, mobilization of citizens by public authorities, regulation, etc. Many and varied aspects can be and are the subject of e-participation projects or issues of concern for governments, society, social and business organizations and multilateral organizations, all convinced that, at the current stage of the use and spread of technologies, they can be addressed or resolved by means of digital instruments. A second reason for the prominence of e-participation in the set of concerns related to digital democracy has to do with the increased scientific diversification of researchers in the field of e-democracy. Communication researchers, political scientists and democracy theorists predominated in the area of e-participation in the first decade, but from the 2000s onward, public administration and especially computer science increased their share significantly in the area. In the last decade, for example, researchers in computing accounted for almost half of publications on the subject. This is probably the most relevant factor explaining the growth of e-participation compared to the other themes of digital democracy. There is, moreover, a new and apparently very consistent theme in the field of e-participation, which is crowdsourcing, collective collaboration, generally in the interface with digital government or electronic parliament, which has been growing exponentially since 2010. We can include here things like collective eparticipation • in public policies (Charalabidis et al., 2012; Macintosh, 2004; Rethemeyer, 2006); • in government decision making (Garcia; Vivacqua; Tavares, 2011; Linders, 2012); • in fostering transparency (Bertot; Jaeger; Grimes, 2010; Carlo Bertot; Jaeger; Grimes, 2012; Zinnbauer, 2015); • in legislative procedure (Christensen; Karjalainen; Nurminen, 2015; Heikka, 2015), etc. As is typical of this period, crowdsourcing, or citizen-sourcing (Nam, 2012), pays close attention to new digital participation resources, based on social media, web 2.0 and mobile devices (Brovelli; Minghini; Zamboni, 2016; Charalabidis et al., 2014; Wang et al., 2017). In fact, due to the rapid and intense growth of attention, a considerable increase of the theme can be predicted in the coming years. CHART 5 Academic attention to subthemes of digital democracy by year – 2006-2016 E-deliberation is a subject whose behavior was considerably erratic over the period, peaking in 2009 and facing some decline since then. Although it continued being an important subarea of digital democracy, especially in the study of projects applied to the discussion of citizens among themselves and with public authorities, the area drifted away, especially at the end of the decade, from its traditional reference point of deliberative democracy. Perhaps this reflects the actual internal movement of deliberative democracy, which lost part of its élan in democratic theory, branching out into much more applied and pragmatic directions. Apparently, the authors of these new developments in the field show less interest in what happens in the mobile internet and in social media and 2.0 applications than the authors of the first wave of deliberative democracy. Interestingly, specifically regarding the subfield of “online politics”, there is a striking growth of interest in discussions carried out in digital environments. The study of online discussion, subdivided into three main themes – discussion and political talk, divergence and polarization, selective exposition and heterogeneity – is a singularity of current research, with growing and intense production since at least 2008. It is not, however, a metamorphosis of the area of public deliberation specific to digital democracy, since in general the bibliography does not reflect a normative approach of the democratic type. What researchers are most curious about is the fact that people increasingly talk to each other about politics, often to fiercely diverge and polemicize, thereby generating a tendency for polarization and the formation of echo chambers or digital bubbles, closed environments of high affinity among its members. The theoretical framework is not grounded on the Habermasian tradition, nor even on democratic theory, but on theoretical and methodological models of communication and psychology, such as the spiral of silence theory and the hypothesis of selective exposure. Finally, we have the case of e-transparency, a typical theme of this last period. At first sight, public transparency is not afforded the same importance in the area of digital democracy as it has received in democratic theory, political science and public administration. For government areas, for society, for multilateral organizations and even for the scientific field, transparency, especially public transparency, was a key theme at the turn of the century and remains so. Transparency, on the one hand, and its counterparts that fill liberal democracies with dread, corruption, physiology and opaqueness in government, are now a matter of general concern. Why then is the subject of e-transparency still modestly addressed worldwide, and if it has any importance in Brazil, is this basically a response to a law that forces public administration itself to engage in fiscal e-transparency? Why does not e-transparency have the same power as edeliberation or, above all, of e-participation? I have not found a satisfactory answer to that question. But what I can say to mitigate the sense that e-transparency does not receive the treatment it deserves is that issues of digital public transparency have in fact prospered considerably in the form of the themes of open government and open government data. That it is, therefore, in the interface of the areas of digital democracy and digital government that transparency finally gets the importance it deserves, as seen in Chart 6. CHART 6 Academic attention to e-transparency and open government This gives us the opportunity to close this reconstruction of the course of digital democracy with the hypothesis of the interface between e-democracy and digital government. As Chadwick explained, there is even a social division of labor between the two areas: “Public administration scholars, public policy analysts, and public management specialists focus on e-government, whereas political communication specialists, social movement scholars, and democratic theorists sharpen their analytical tools on e-democracy”1. However, deep down the connection between the two areas, albeit not direct, is certainly feasible. The theme of e-government is more recent than the theme of e-democracy. It appears around 1996 (Milward, Snyder, 1996), but only actually constitutes a discipline at the start of the current century. The phase of teledemocracy, for example, did not have a corresponding “telegovernment” phase, although, naturally, the government in particular and the state in general were always among the dimensions considered when debating the use of technology to solve democratic deficits in liberal democracy. But the dominant approach was always based on the normative horizon of democracy, its requirements, values and principles. And it always maintained a strong interface with digital democracy, from which, supposedly, it derives much of its social legitimacy. Of course, not everything of value in the idea of a government based on digital technologies refers to democratic requirements, such as transparency, participation or deliberation, or the values of democracy. To a large extent, it is enough that it refers to social requirements and values stemming from other normative horizons, such as ideas of effectiveness, efficiency, rationality, and economy. Or to the principle that the role of digital government, of an electronic parliament, of a smart city, etc., is simply to improve people’s lives. “Improving people’s lives” may be something other than increasing political equality or public transparency, enhancing participation or leading elected representatives to share power with citizens, which are important democratic triggers, since it may mean something like improving the quality of life of citizens, reducing the burden of bureaucracy or the deficiency of public services to which they are entitled. On the other hand, one must also consider that values such as increasing the efficiency of digital government or principles such as “governments need to improve citizens’ lives through technology” may gain a considerable boost from the normative horizon of democracy. Thus, it is obvious that governments that deliver good public services via digital means are good, but if e-public service delivery is designed focused on the citizen, the sovereign of the state, and not state bureaucracy, it will be even better. That is also true of, for example, smart cities. And if the digital state, besides being efficient, modern, rational and economic, is also transparent and participatory, there will be no loss of any of the intrinsic values of the new public administration and there will additionally be a considerable increase in its democratic quality. Introducing an e-democratic “virus” in the e-government system seems, therefore, an important contemporary imperative for better societies. And “better”, today, means also more democratic. More edemocratic. New trends in digital democracy Having come so far, where do we go? There are two ways to approach this question, albeit briefly. The first is to find out where we are heading, which themes and fields of applications are currently attracting the attention of researchers, managers and society. The second is to suggest the themes we should address, if digital democracy is to offer consistent answers to the demands of democracy. In the first case, the main factor is identifying dominant trends, while in the second case, it is more important to identify possible gaps in the field. Where are we heading? We summarize a few important trends that deserve the attention of people who are already involved or who will become involved with digital democracy in the coming years. • With the consolidation of the idea of digital democracy, the golden age of the theory of e-democracy has passed and the approach tends to be more and more practical, applied and segmented. Unless some kind of new challenge to the legitimacy of digital democracy appears on the horizon, these trends are more likely to prevail. Practical problems related to technological models, specific characteristics of digital solutions used or studies of experiments (projects, initiatives implemented) and experiences (spontaneous ways of using digital technologies that influence or are applicable to democracy) tend to focus attention over the next years. In addition, the tendency of themes to become autonomous shall probably persist, with at least some of them transformed into specific fields, as is currently happening with e-participation, e-deliberation and the subarea of internet and society. The trend towards fragmentation, however, if not corrected, could lead to the loss of the overall perspective of digital democracy. This would lead, as is already happening in the case of e-participation, to indices of digital participation in which autocratic countries score very high, as if the democratic quality of the type of participation involved were superfluous for e-democracy (Lidén, 2012, 2015). Or to confusions, such as viewing digital democracy as one of the subtopics of digital government, completely reversing not only the history of the larger area, but common sense in political theory. The risk, therefore, is of the newly-autonomous themes becoming detached from the idea of digital democracy, which does indeed involve technology, but for which democracy is indispensable. There would be no gain in this. • In this sense, the attempt of applications and fields with increasing autonomy to reconnect with digital democracy may become an important counter-trend in the area of e-democracy. This need has already been particularly felt in the area of digital government, in which a considerable concentration of attention in providing electronic services or in digital solutions for smart cities and smart government tends to lead to a disconnection with e-democracy and its requirements, denounced by many authors (Anderson; Bishop, 2005; Chadwick, 2003; Hoff; Scheele, 2014; Kardan; Sadeghiani, 2011). This strengthens the trend to force the introduction of democratic criteria in e-government initiatives and projects to redirect, for example, digital solutions and applications of public service delivery to e-democracy (Chen, 2010; King; Cotterill, 2007; Lee; Lee, 2014; van Velsen et al., 2009). It seems natural to imagine that this trend will be reinforced as fragmentation increases. • Another clear trend, already outlined above, refers to the new technological pattern sm+m, that is, social media + mobile. This has been the dominant trend in the 2010s, and nothing seems to indicate that it will abate in the coming years. The idea that social media is the new pattern of social use of the internet is already strong in some subareas, such as digital government (Bonsón et al., 2012; Feroz Khan et al., 2014; Mossberger; Wu; Crawford, 2013; Porumbescu, 2016; Small, 2012), internet and society (Breuer; Landman; Farquhar, 2015; Kaun, 2016; Valenzuela, 2013), crowdsourcing in public policies (Charalabidis et al., 2012; 2014; Spiliotopoulou et al., 2014), open government (Gunawong, 2015; Stamati; Papadopoulos; Anagnostopoulos, 2015; Wirtz; Daiser; Mermann, 2017) and eparticipation (Alarabiat; Soares, 2016; Dini; Saebo, 2016; Vogt; Förster; Kabst, 2014). Social media may occasionally be replaced by the label 2.0 (Henman, 2013, Nam, 2012, Pankowska, 2016; Sun; Ku; Shih, 2015), with similar meaning. In the same way, the use of m- to denote mobile digital technologies for communication is becoming the current version of the classic e-, for electronic, which has prevailed for forty years. M- is already clearly evident as a trend in the various subareas of digital government (Gouscos; Drossos; Marias, 2005; Lee; Tan; Trimi, 2006; Ogunleye; van Belle, 2014; Sheng; Trimi, 2008; Trimi; Sheng, 2008) and in the theme of e-participation (Thiel et al., 2015; Thiel; Lehner, 2015). In the next decade, the major area of digital politics, state and democracy will increasingly be sm+m. • Finally, there seems to be unanimity in the conviction that big data is the theme of the hour. We are all, from democracy theorists to computer scientists, from political communication scholars to mathematicians, from health professionals and researchers to political scientists, from bioinformatics scholars to economists and physicists, imagining the fantastic applications to solve specific problems of each area or multidisciplinary issues which will result from access to massive amounts of digital data, information about people, their circumstances and conditions, about society, about governments, about the economy, about things and, above all, about the relationships among them. It is not simply a matter of the volume of data, but of the added computational intelligence employed in gathering and using them. As Danah Boyd and Kate Crawford pointed out in a recent article: “Big Data is less about data that is big than it is about a capacity to search, aggregate, and cross-reference large data sets”2. From a technological point of view, this implies that more and more we have to deal with issues related to “maximizing computation power and algorithmic accuracy to gather, analyze, link, and compare large data sets”3, but from the point of view of politics and democracy, there are doubts as to whether all this will help us create better societies, better government and improve people’s lives, or if the opposite is most likely to happen. This is a hot issue that research is just starting to address. • Big data, however, is just the beginning of a thematic thread. Next in line is open data. It’s not just a matter of having large databases, but of the political and democratic phenomena of open data and the opening of data. Open data can be defined, according to Marijn Janssen and colleagues, as “non-privacy-restricted and non-confidential data which is produced with public money and is made available without any restrictions on its usage or distribution”4. The premise behind the idea of open data is that public bodies are generally the largest generators or gatherers of data in most spheres of social life and must be compelled to make this data available to society for whatever purposes individuals and groups deem appropriate. • Which inevitably leads us to the third theme of the tetrad, open government (or public) data. The opening of government data has a few important implications, first and foremost regarding the actual government. By opening their huge databases to public access, public bodies and government agencies, in a sense, agree to give up the control that gave them discretionary power, non-accountable to the public, only to the internal hierarchy of the public sector itself. This means sharing power and, ultimately, exposing themselves. • And so we come to the fourth theme, deeply interconnected with the third, the issue of so-called open government. The expression has become extremely popular in recent years, especially after President Barack Obama published the famous Memorandum on Transparency and Open Government on his first day in office and, in September 2011, signed the Open Government Partnership, a multilateral initiative, still in force, aimed at encouraging and engaging governments in promoting transparency, combating corruption and using technologies to strengthen democratic governance. As defined by Albert Meijer and colleagues, the opening of government “is the extent to which citizens can monitor and influence government processes through access to government information and access to decision-making arenas”5. This implies at least two important dimensions of digital democracy: e-transparency and e-participation, in addition to a third dimension, already stated above: open governments should be collaborative (McDermott, 2010). In any case, the fact is that academic attention, political attention and normative efforts regarding the opening of government by digital means grew rapidly in those years (as Chart 6 shows). Having reached the end of this account, after seeing how we got here, how the idea of digital democracy developed and was consolidated and the new trends in this area, we still have time to ask ourselves how e-democracy is helping us to deal with the problems of democracy. We have seen the progress of the themes of participation, public deliberation in digital media and environments and, finally, grassroots e-democracy, so that the deficit correlated with low political participation among the population and civic apathy has deserved due consideration. The liberal problem of invisible governments and the opaque state, and the problem of new and old democracies related to patrimonialism, physiology and patronage and, ultimately, corruption can only be faced with more transparency, more accountability of political agents, more monitoring by citizens. We are at the core of the most recent agenda related to e-transparency, to forms of participation of a monitorial e-democracy, and finally to open data and open government. It is too early to say to what extent governments will move down that road, but the direction seems very promising. There is, however, a gap that has not been adequately filled concerning the contribution of e-democracy to existing democracies, which relates to the limits of the rule of law and to problems in extending rights, guarantees and freedoms equally to all citizens. It cannot be said that the theme of violation of rights, of injustices and structural oppression and of equal and effective access to justice is not being addressed. But it must be admitted that the enhancement and consolidation of a society of rights, specifically political rights and freedoms, and the role of digital resources in monitoring and reporting violations of rights are not yet a main task of digital democracy, documented in academic attention. This is a line of research and action that still needs to be built. To conclude So, are we all reconciled with the idea of digital democracy? Certainly not. Several are the sources from which still emerge challenges to the idea that something truly worthwhile can stem from the application of digital solutions to produce political, governmental, legislative and social solutions. In fact, it is often a question, as we have seen in the history of literature on the subject, of requiring digital democracy to be more democratic than real democracies. This makes no sense, since e-democracy is not a type of democracy, but the use of technologies to strengthen, correct or improve existing democracies. Or even to implement or improve democratic dimensions of authoritarian states. If society or its rulers decide to improve their democracy or to make certain institutions and processes more democratic, the current state of technology and the uses citizens make of it are indispensable resources to achieve those goals. Technology can both deliver participation and deliberation and deliver public transparency, pluralism, open governments, interaction between citizens and authorities, reinforcement of access to rights and justice, defense of rights and guarantees, denunciation of violations and abuse, mobilization, engagement. Digital democracy is merely the set of resources, tools, projects, experiments, experiences and initiatives that exploit technologies to produce more democracy and better democracies. It is that simple. In a political system with low interest in participation, for example, the digital democracy of that society will hardly be participatory, because the technological resources will be used preferentially for other applications. That has nothing to do with technology, but with the preferences of society, its rulers and its institutions. In this case, it would not be reasonable to criticize digital democracy for not delivering as much participation as anyone would wish. It would be wiser to criticize the low interest in participation by governments and institutions. Moreover, those who demand unified digital solutions to the democratic deficit of certain states and societies, however broad they may be, seem to have difficulty in understanding that complex and pluralistic democracies can hardly be built on the basis of a single element. It is curious, in this sense, how criticisms of digital democracy are always more simplistic than the lists of the complex problems of contemporary democracy in democratic theory. Sentences such as “we need a more lively and participatory democracy, controlled by citizens” do not address complicated obstacles that stand in the way of democracy, such as the need for growing technocracy (decisions based on specializations and technical expertise), for increased bureaucracy, the “ungovernability” of mass democracies, among others. Complex democracies have so many needs that to think that everything can be solved with more technological resources for participation or deliberation sounds rather naive. On the other hand, undermining the worth of the plethora of digital solutions for improving democracy just because the digital democracy kit employed by a given society does not assign the same value as I do to function x or y as an adequate remedy for most of the democratic deficits of that society does not seem reasonable or justified. Ours are societies that, besides being complex, are considerably pluralistic, so that there is no “model” of democracy in which we all might fit or a democratic emphasis that could satisfy all our needs. Finally, the obstacles to the exercise of democracy are so numerous and diverse that any help from technology, in any dimension, should be considered welcome. The simplest set of digital democracy resources would already mean an increase in the quality of existing democracy, even more so in the case of a consistent e-democracy that has a significant, pro-democracy impact on public life, the political system and the state. 1 A. Chadwick, “Bringing E-Democracy Back in: Why It Matters for Future Research on E-Governance”, Social Science Computer Review, v. 21, n. 4, pp. 443-55, 1 Nov. 2003, p. 444. 2 D. Boyd; K. Crawford, “Critical Questions for Big Data”, Information, Communication & Society, v. 15, n. 5, pp. 662-79, June 2012, p. 663. 3 Ibidem. 4 M. Janssen; Y. Charalabidis; A. Zuiderwijk, “Benefits, Adoption Barriers and Myths of Open Data and Open Government”, Information Systems Management, v. 29, n. 4, pp. 258-68, Sept. 2012, p. 258. 5 A. J. Meijer; D. Curtin; M. Hillebrandt, “Open Government: Connecting Vision and Voice”, International Review of Administrative Sciences, v. 78, n. 1, pp. 10-29, 22 Mar. 2012, p. 13. ABRAMSON, J. B.; ARTERTON, F. C.; ORREN, G. R. Electronic Commonwealth: The Impact of New Media Technologies on Democratic Politics. New York: Basic Books, 1988. AINSWORTH, S. “Online Consultation: E-Democracy and E-Resistance in the Case of the Development Gateway”. Management Communication Quarterly, v. 19, n. 1, pp. 120-45, 1 Aug 2005. ALARABIAT, A.; SOARES, D. S. “Electronic Participation through Social Media”. In: Proceedings of the 9th International Conference on Theory and Practice of Electronic Governance (ICEGOV ’15-16). New York: ACM Press, 2016. Available at: <http://dl.acm.org/citation.cfm? doid=2910019.2910109>. Accessed on: 6 July 2017. ALLEN, M. “What Was Web 2.0? Versions as the Dominant Mode of Internet History”. New Media & Society, v. 15, n. 2, pp. 260-75, 1 Mar. 2013. ANDERSON, L.; BISHOP, P. “E-Government to E-Democracy”. Journal of E-Government, v. 2, n. 1, pp. 5-26, 28 Dec. 2005. ARTERTON, F. C. Teledemocracy: Can Technology Protect Democracy?. Newbury Park: Sage, 1987. ________. “Political Participation and ‘Teledemocracy’”. PS: Political Science and Politics, v. 21, n. 3, pp. 620-7, Jan. 1988. ÅSTRÖM, J. “Should Democracy Online Be Quick, Strong, or Thin?”. Communications of the ACM, v. 44, n. 1, pp. 49-51, 1 Jan. 2001. BARBER, B. R. Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984. ________. “The New Telecommunications Technology: Endless Frontier or the End of Democracy?”. Constellations, v. 4, n. 2, pp. 208-28, Oct. 1997. BARLOW, J. P. “Property and Speech: Who Owns What You Say in Cyberspace?”. Communications of the ACM, v. 38, n. 12, pp. 19-22, 1 Dec. 1995. ________. “A Declaration of the Independence of Cyberspace”. Davos, 8 Feb. 1996. Available at: <https://projects.eff.org/~barlow/Declaration-Final.html>. Accessed on: 11 Dec. 2017. BECKER, T. “Teledemocracy: Gathering Momentum in State and Local Governance”. Spectrum: Journal of State Government, v. 66, n. 2, p. 14, 1993. ________. “Transforming Representative Democracy: Four Real-Life Experiments in Teledemocracy”. In: WOOLPERT, S; SLATON, C. D.; SCHWERIN, E. W. (eds.). Transformational Politics: Theory, Study, and Practice. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998. pp. 185-200. ________. “Rating the Impact of New Technologies on Democracy”. Communications of the ACM, v. 44, n. 1, pp. 39-43, 1 Jan. 2001. BECKER, T. L.; SLATON, C. D. The Future of Teledemocracy. London: Greenwood Publishing Group, 2000. BEIERLE, T. C. “Discussing the Rules: Electronic Rulemaking and Democratic Deliberation”. Resources for the Future (Discussion paper 03-22), 2003. BENHABIB, S. Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996. BERKELEY, E. C. The Computer Revolution. Garden City: Doubleday, 1962. BERMAN, J.; WEITZNER, D. J. “Technology and Democracy”. Social Research, v. 64, n. 3, pp. 131319, 1997. BERTOT, J. C.; JAEGER, P. T.; GRIMES, J. M. “Crowd-Sourcing Transparency: ICTs, Social Media, and government Transparency Initiatives”. Proceedings of the 11th Annual International Conference on Digital Government Research, Puebla, Mexico, 2010, pp. 51-8. BIASIOTTI, M. A.; NANNUCCI, R. “Implementing eDemocracy: eVoting and eParticipation”. In: CUNNINGHAM, M. (ed). eAdoption and the Knowledge Economy: Issues, Applications, Case Studies, Pts. 1 and 2, v. 1, 2004. pp. 745-50. BJERKNES, G.; EHN, P.; KYNG, M. Computers and Democracy: A Scandinavian Challenge. Avebury: Gower, 1987. BOBBIO, N. Il futuro della democrazia. Turin: Einaudi, 1984. BOHMAN, J. Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity and Democracy. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996. BOHMAN, J. “Expanding Dialogue: The Internet, Public Sphere, and Transnational Democracy”. The Sociological Review, v. 52, pp. 47-64, 14 June 2004. BONSÓN, E. et al. “Local e-Government 2.0: Social Media and corporate Transparency in Municipalities”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 29, n. 2, pp. 123-32, Apr. 2012. BOYD, D.; CRAWFORD, K. “Critical Questions for Big Data”. Information, Communication & Society, v. 15, n. 5, pp. 662-79, June 2012. BOYD, D. M.; ELLISON, N. B. “Social Network Sites: Definition, History, and Scholarship”. Journal of Computer-Mediated Communication, v. 13, n. 1, pp. 210-30, Oct. 2007. BRADLEY, D. “The Clinton Electronic Communications Project: An Experiment in Electronic Democracy”. Internet Research, v. 4, n. 1, pp. 64-70, 1994. BRANDON, B. H.; CARLITZ, R. D. “Online Rulemaking and Other Tools for Strengthening Our Civil Infrastructure”. Administrative Law Review, v. 54, n. 4, pp. 1421-78, 2002. BRANTS, K. “Policing Democracy: Communication Freedom in the Age of Internet”. Javnost – The Public, v. 3, n. 1, pp. 57-70, 7 Jan. 1996. ________. “The Internet and the Public Sphere”. Political Communication, v. 22, n. 2, pp. 143-6, Apr. 2005. BRANTS, K.; HUIZENGA, M.; VAN MEERTEN, R. “The New Canals of Amsterdam: An Exercise in Local Electronic Democracy”. Media, Culture & Society, v. 18, n. 2, pp. 233-47, 1 Apr. 1996. BREUER, A.; LANDMAN, T.; FARQUHAR, D. “Social Media and Protest Mobilization: Evidence from the Tunisian Revolution”. Democratization, v. 22, n. 4, pp. 764-92, 2015. BROVELLI, M. A.; MINGHINI, M.; ZAMBONI, G. “Public Participation in GIS via Mobile Applications”. ISPRS Journal of Photogrammetry and Remote Sensing, v. 114, pp. 306-15, 2016. BROWN, R. H. et al. The National Information Infrastructure: Agenda for Action. Washington D.C: US Department of Commerce, 1993. BRUGGER, N. “Web Historiography and Internet Studies: Challenges and Perspectives”. New Media & Society, v. 15, n. 5, pp. 752-64, 1 Aug. 2013. ________. “Introduction: The Webs First 25 Years”. New Media & Society, v. 18, n. 7, pp. 1059-65, 1 Aug. 2016. BUCHSTEIN, H. “Bytes that Bite: The Internet and Deliberative Democracy”. Constellations, v. 4, n. 2, pp. 248-63, Oct. 1997. CALHOUN, C. “Community without Propinquity Revisited: Communications Technology and the Transformation of the Urban Public Sphere”. Sociological Inquiry, v. 68, n. 3, pp. 373-97, July 1998. CARLO BERTOT, J.; JAEGER, P. T.; GRIMES, J. M. “Promoting Transparency and Accountability through ICTs, Social Media, and Collaborative e-Government”. Transforming Government: People, Process and Policy, v. 6, n. 1, pp. 78-91, 16 Mar. 2012. CARPIGNANO, P. “The Shape of the Sphere: The Public Sphere and the Materiality of Communication”. Constellations, v. 6, n. 2, pp. 177-89, June 1999. CHADWICK, A. “Bringing E-Democracy Back in: Why It Matters for Future Research on EGovernance”. Social Science Computer Review, v. 21, n. 4, pp. 443-55, 1 Nov. 2003. CHAMBERS, S. A. “Democracy and (the) Public(s): Spatializing Politics in the Internet Age”. Political Theory, v. 33, n. 1, pp. 125-36, 1 Feb. 2005. CHARALABIDIS, Y. et al. “Public Policy Formulation through Non Moderated Crowdsourcing in Social Media”. In: TAMBOURIS, E.; MACINTOSH, E. A.; SAEBO, O. (eds.). ePart 2012. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, v. 7444. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, 2012. pp. 156-69. ________. “Passive Crowdsourcing in Government Using Social Media”. Transforming Government: People, Process and Policy, v. 8, n. 2, pp. 283-308, 13 May 2014. CHEN, Y.-C. “Citizen-Centric E-Government Services: Understanding Integrated Citizen Service Information Systems”. Social Science Computer Review, v. 28, n. 4, pp. 427-42, 1 Nov. 2010. CHEVRET, C. “Le vote électronique par Internet: du déplacement du rituel électoral à la perte de la symbolique républicaine”. Esprit Critique: Revue Internationale de Sociologie et des Sciences Sociales, v. 5, n. 4, 2003. CHRISTENSEN, H. S.; KARJALAINEN, M.; NURMINEN, L. “Does Crowdsourcing Legislation Increase Political Legitimacy? The Case of Avoin Ministeriö in Finland”. Policy & Internet, v. 7, n. 1, pp. 25-45, Mar. 2015. COLEMAN, S. “Can the New Media Invigorate Democracy?” The Political Quarterly, v. 70, n. 1, pp. 16-22, Jan. 1999. ________. “The Future of the Internet and Democracy Beyond Metaphors, Towards Policy”. In: OECD. Promises and Problems of E-Democracy. Paris: OECD Publications Service, 2003, pp. 143-62. COLEMAN, S.; GØTZE, J. Bowling Together: Online Public Engagement in Policy Deliberation. London: Hansard Society, 2001. COLEMAN, S.; HALL, N.; HOWELL, M. Hearing Voices: The Experience of Online Public Consultations and Discussions in UK Governance. London: Hansard Society, 2002. COLEMAN, S.; SPILLER, J. “Exploring New Media Effects on Representative Democracy”. The Journal of Legislative Studies, v. 9, n. 3, pp. 1-16, Oct. 2003. DAHLBERG, L. “The Habermasian Public Sphere Encounters Cyber-Reality”. Javnost – The Public, v. 8, n. 3, pp. 83-96, 7 Jan. 2001a. ________. “Extending the Public Sphere through Cyberspace: The Case of Minnesota E-Democracy”. First Monday, v. 6, n. 3, 5 Mar. 2001b. ________. “Democracy via Cyberspace: Mapping the Rhetorics and Practices of Three Prominent Camps”. New Media & Society, v. 3, n. 2, pp. 157-77, 1 June 2001c. ________. “The Internet and Democratic Discourse: Exploring The Prospects of Online Deliberative Forums Extending the Public Sphere”. Information, Communication & Society, v. 4, n. 4, pp. 615-33, 2001d. DAVIES, G. W. P.; JEGU, P. “OVIDE and Teledemocracy”. Journal of Information Science, v. 21, n. 5, p. 383, 1995. DEAN, J. “Why the Net Is Not a Public Sphere”. Constellations, v. 10, n. 1, pp. 95-112, Mar. 2003. DE SOLA POOL, I. Talking Back: Citizen Feedback and Cable Technology. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1973. ________. Technologies of Freedom: On Free Speech in an Electronic Age. Cambridge: Belknap Press, 1983. DEWAN, S.; RIGGINS, F. J. “The Digital Divide: Current and Future Research Directions”. Journal of the Association for Information Systems, v. 6, n. 12, pp. 298-337, 2005. DIMAGGIO, P.; HARGITTAI, E. “From the ‘Digital Divide’ to ‘Digital Inequality’: Studying Internet use as Penetration Increases”. Working Paper Series n. 15. Princenton: Princeton University Center for Arts and Cultural Policy Studies, Princeton University, pp. 1-23, 2001. DINI, A. A.; SAEBO, O. “The Current State of Social Media Research for eParticipation in Developing Countries: A Literature Review”. Proceedings of the 49th Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences (HICSS), Koloa, Hawaii, 5-8 Jan. 2016. Available at: <http://ieeexplore.ieee.org/document/7427522/>. Accessed on: 11 Dec. 2017. DOTY, P.; ZUSSMAN, R. “Electronic ‘Town Meetings’: Two Experiments in Participatory Technology”. IEEE Transactions on Communications, v. 23, n. 10, pp. 1126-33, Oct. 1975. DOWNEY, J.; FENTON, N. “New Media, Counter Publicity and the Public Sphere”. New Media & Society, v. 5, n. 2, pp. 185-202, 1 June 2003. DOWNING, J. D. H. “Computers for Political Change: PeaceNet and Public Data Access”. Journal of Communication, v. 39, n. 3, pp. 154-62, Sept. 1989. DRYZEK, J. S. “Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. DUTTON, W. H. “Political Science Research on Teledemocracy”. Social Science Computer Review, v. 10, n. 4, pp. 505-22, 1 Dec. 1992. EDWARDS, A. R. “Informatization and Views of Democracy”. In: VAN DE DONK, W. B. H. J.; SNELLEN, I.; TOPS, P. W. (eds.). Orwell in Athen: A Perspective on Informatization and Democracy. Amsterdam: IOS Press, 1995, pp. 33-49. ELSHTAIN, J. B. “Democracy and the QUBE Tube”. The Nation, pp. 108-9, 1982. ETZIONI, A. “Minerva: An Electronic Town Hall”. Policy Sciences, v. 3, n. 4, pp. 457-74, Dec. 1972. ________. “Teledemocracy: Ross Perot Left the Residue of a Good Idea Behind Him: The Electronic Town Meeting”, The Atlantic, pp. 36-9, 1992. FEROZ KHAN, G. et al. “From E-Government to Social Government: Twitter Use by Korea’s Central Government”. Online Information Review, v. 38, n. 1, pp. 95-113, 8 Jan. 2014. FLOOD, M. M. “Let’s Redesign Democracy”. Behavioral Science, v. 23, n. 5, pp. 429-40, 1978. FOUNTAIN, J. “Electronic Government and Electronic Civics”. SSRN Electronic Journal, v. 18, pp. 185-212, 2003a. ________. “Prospects for Improving the Regulatory Process Using E-Rulemaking”. Communications of the ACM, v. 46, n. 1, pp. 63-4, 2003b. FRIEDLAND, L. A. “Electronic Democracy and the New Citizenship”. Media, Culture & Society, v. 18, n. 2, pp. 185-212, 1 Apr. 1996. FROOMKIN, A. M. “Habermas@discourse.net: Toward a Critical Theory of Cyberspace”. Harvard Law Review, v. 116, n. 3, pp. 750-871, 2003. GARCIA, A. C. B.; VIVACQUA, A. S.; TAVARES, T. C. “Enabling Crowd Participation in Governmental Decision-making”. Journal of Universal Computer Science, v. 17, n. 14, pp. 1931-50, 2011. GASTIL, J. “Is Face-to-Face Citizen Deliberation a Luxury or a Necessity?”. Political Communication, v. 17, n. 4, pp. 357-61, Oct. 2000. GIBSON, R. K. “Elections Online: Assessing Internet Voting in Light of the Arizona Democratic Primary”. Political Science Quarterly, v. 116, n. 4, p. 561, 2001. GIMMLER, A. “Deliberative Democracy, the Public Sphere and the Internet”. Philosophy & Social Criticism, v. 27, n. 4, pp. 21-39, 1 July 2001. GOMES, W. “A democracia digital e o problema da participação civil na decisão política”. Fronteiras – Estudos Midiáticos, v. 7, n. 3, pp. 214-22, 2005a. ________. “Internet e participação política em sociedades democráticas”. Revista Famecos, v. 27, n. 3, pp. 58-78, 2005b. ________. “Participação política online: questões e hipóteses”. In: MAIA, R. C. M.; GOMES, W.; MARQUES, F. P. J. A. (eds.). Internet e participação política no Brasil. Porto Alegre: Sulina, 2011. pp. 19-46. ________. “20 anos de política, estado e democracia digitais: uma ‘cartografia’ do campo”. In: SILVA, S. P. DA; BRAGATTO, R. C.; SAMPAIO, R. C. (eds.). Democracia digital, comunicação política e redes: teoria e prática. Rio de Janeiro: Letra & Imagem, 2016a. ________. “‘Nós somos a rede social!’: o protesto político entre as ruas e as redes”. In: MENDONÇA, R. F.; PEREIRA, M. A.; FILGUEIRAS, F. (eds.). Democracia digital: publicidade, instituições e confronto político. Belo Horizonte: Editora da UFMG, 2016b. pp. 371-94. GOUSCOS, D.; DROSSOS, D.; MARIAS, G. F. M-GOV. “A Proposed Architecture for Mobile Government Transactions”. Proceedings of the 1st European Mobile Government Conference (Euro mGov), Brighton, pp. 221-33, 10-11 July 2005. GRAHAM, T.; WITSCHGE, T. “In Search of Online Deliberation: Towards a New Method for Examining the Quality of Online Discussions”. Communications, v. 28, n. 2, pp. 173-204, 16 Jan. 2003. GRÖNLUND, Å. “Democracy in an IT-framed Society: Introduction”. Communications of the ACM, v. 44, n. 1, pp. 22-26, 1 Jan. 2001. GROSSWILER, P. “Historical Hopes, Media Fears, and the Electronic Town Meeting Concept: Where Technology Meets Democracy or Demagogy?”. Journal of Communication Inquiry, v. 22, n. 2, pp. 133-51, 1 Apr. 1998. GUNAWONG, P. “Open Government and Social Media: A Focus on Transparency”. Social Science Computer Review, v. 33, n. 5, pp. 587-98, 1 Oct. 2015. GUTMANN, A.; THOMPSON, D. Democracy and disagreement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996. HABERMAS, J. Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1962. ________. Moralbewusstsein und kommunikatives Handeln. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1983. ________. Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaates. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1992. ________. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996. HACKER, K. L.; TODINO, M. A. “Virtual Democracy at the Clinton White House: An Experiment in Electronic Democratisation”. Javnost – The Public, v. 3, n. 1, pp. 71-86, 7 Jan. 1996. HALE, M.; MUSSO, J.; WEARE, C. “Developing Digital Democracy: Evidence from Californian Municipal Web Pages”. In: HAGUE, B. N.; LOADER, B. D. (eds.). Digital Democracy: Discourse and Decision Making in the Information Age. London: Routledge, 1999. pp. 96-115. HARGITTAI, E. “Second-level Digital Divide: Differences in People’s Online Skills”. First Monday, v. 7, n. 4, 2002. HEIKKA, T. “The Rise of the Mediating Citizen: Time, Space, and Citizenship in the Crowdsourcing of Finnish Legislation”. Policy & Internet, v. 7, n. 3, pp. 268-291, Sept. 2015. HELD, D. Models of Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1987. HELLSTRÖM, J. “Mobile Participation? Crowdsourcing During the 2011 Uganda General Elections”. CM International Conference Proceeding Series, v. 46, n. 0, pp. 249-258, 2012. HENMAN, P. “Governmentalities of Gov 2.0”. Information, Communication & Society, v. 16, n. 9, pp. 1397-418, Nov. 2013. HERN, M.; CHAULK, S. T. U. “Roadgrading Community Culture: Why the Internet Is so Dangerous to Real Democracy”. Democracy & Nature, v. 6, n. 1, pp. 111-20, 2000. HILBERT, M. “The Maturing Concept of E-Democracy: From E-Voting and Online Consultations to Democratic Value Out of Jumbled Online Chatter”. Journal of Information Technology & Politics, v. 6, n. 2, pp. 87-110, 12 May 2009. HOFF, J.; HORROCKS, I.; TOPS, P. W. Democratic Governance and New Technology: Technology Mediated Innovations in Political Practice in Western Europe. London: Routledge, 2000. HOFF, J.; SCHEELE, C. E. “Theoretical Approaches to Digital Services and Digital Democracy: The Merits of the Contextual New Medium Theory Model”. Policy & Internet, v. 6, n. 3, pp. 241-67, Sept. 2014. HOLLANDER, R. Video Democracy: The Vote-from-home Revolution. Mt. Airy: Lomond, 1985. HOUSTON, A. L. et al. “Will Remote Electronic Voting Systems Increase Participation?”. Electronic Government, an International Journal, v. 2, n. 4, p. 353, 2005. HURWITZ, R. “Who Needs Politics? Who Needs People? The Ironies of Democracy in Cyberspace”. Contemporary Sociology, v. 28, n. 6, pp. 655-61, 1999. IYENGAR, S.; LUSKIN, R. C.; FISHKIN, J. S. “Facilitating Informed Public Opinion: Evidence from Face-to-Face and Online Deliberative Polls”. Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, Philadelphia, 2003. JANSSEN, D.; KIES, R. “Online Forums and Deliberative Democracy”. Acta Politica, v. 40, n. S3, pp. 317-35, 15 Sept. 2005. JANSSEN, M.; CHARALABIDIS, Y.; ZUIDERWIJK, A. “Benefits, Adoption Barriers and Myths of Open Data and Open Government”. Information Systems Management, v. 29, n. 4, pp. 258-68, Sept. 2012. JAYASENA, G. N.; KARUNARATNA, D. D. “Towards an Enabling Framework for eDemocracy through the Integration of Citizen Participation along the Spatial Dimension Using Free and Open Source Technologies”. Proceedings of the 24th South East Asia Regional Computer Conference, Bangkok, Thailand, v. 14, 2007. JENSEN, J. L. “Virtual Democratic Dialogue? Bringing Together Citizens and Politicians”. Information Polity, v. 8, pp. 29-47, 2003. JUNG, J.-Y.; QIU, J. L.; KIM, Y.-C. “Internet Connectedness and Inequality: Beyond the ‘Divide’”. Communication Research, v. 28, n. 4, pp. 507-35, 1 Aug. 2001. KANGAS, J.; STORE, R. “Internet and Teledemocracy in Participatory Planning of Natural Resources Management”. Landscape and Urban Planning, v. 62, n. 2, pp. 89-101, 10 Jan. 2003. KARDAN, A. A.; SADEGHIANI, A. “Is e-Government a Way to e-Democracy?”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 28, n. 4, pp. 466-73, Oct. 2011. KAUN, A. “Our Time to Act Has Come: Desynchronization, Social Media Time and Protest Movements”. Media, Culture & Society, 21 Apr. 2016. KENNEDY, T.; WELLMAN, B.; KLEMENT, K. “Gendering the Digital Divide”. IT & Society, v. 1, n. 5, pp. 149-72, 2003. KERSTEN, G. E. “E-Democracy and Participatory Decision Processes: Lessons From e-Negotiation Experiments”. Journal of Multi-Criteria Decision Analysis, v. 12, n. 2–3, pp. 127-43, Mar. 2003. KING, S.; COTTERILL, S. “Transformational Government? The Role of Information Technology in Delivering Citizen-Centric Local Public Services”. Local Government Studies, v. 33, n. 3, pp. 33354, June 2007. LAUDON, K. C. Communications Technology and Democratic Participation. New York: Praeger, 1977. LAUER, T. W. “The Risk of e-Voting”. Electronic Journal of E-government, v. 2, n. 3, pp. 177-86, 2004. LEE, J.; LEE, H. “Developing and Validating a Citizen-Centric Typology for Smart City Services”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 31, n. S1, pp. S93-S105, 2014. LEE, S. M.; TAN, X.; TRIMI, S. “M-Government, from Rhetoric to Reality: Learning from Leading Countries”. Electronic Government, v. 3, n. 2, pp. 113-26, 2006. LIDÉN, G. “Is e-Democracy More than Democratic?: An Examination of the Implementation of Socially Sustainable Values in e-Democratic Processes”. Electronic Journal of e-Government, v. 10, n. 1, pp. 84-94, 2012. ________. “Technology and Democracy: Validity in Measurements of e-Democracy”. Democratization, v. 22, n. 4, pp. 698-713, 2015. LINDERS, D. “From e-Government to we-Government: Defining a Typology for Citizen Coproduction in the Age of Social Media”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 29, n. 4, pp. 446-54, Oct. 2012. LONDON, S. “Teledemocracy vs. Deliberative Democracy: A Comparative Look at Two Models of Public Talk”. Journal of Interpersonal Computing and Technology, v. 3, n. 2, pp. 33-55, 1995. LOTOV, A. V. “Internet Tools for Supporting of Lay Stakeholders in the Framework of the Democratic Paradigm of environmental Decision Making”. Journal of Multi-Criteria Decision Analysis, v. 12, n. 2-3, pp. 145-62, Mar. 2003. MACINTOSH, A. “Characterizing e-Participation in Policy-making”. Proceedings of the 37th Annual Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences, Big Island, Hawaii, 5-8 Jan. 2004. Available at: <http://ieeexplore.ieee.org/document/1265300/>. Accessed on: 11 Dec. 2017. MACINTOSH, A.; MALINA, A.; FARRELL, S. “Digital Democracy through Electronic Petitioning”. Advances in Digital Government, v. 26, n. 10, pp. 137-48, 2002. MAIA, R. C. M. “Redes cívicas e internet: do ambiente informativo denso às condições da deliberação pública”. In: EISENBERG, J.; CEPIK, M. (eds.). Internet e política: teoria e prática da democracia eletrônica. Belo Horizonte: Editora da UFMG, 2002. pp. 46-72. MCDERMOTT, P. “Building Open Government”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 27, n. 4, pp. 40113, Oct. 2010. MCLEAN, I. Democracy and the New Technology. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1989. MEIJER, A. J.; CURTIN, D.; HILLEBRANDT, M. “Open Government: Connecting Vision and Voice”. International Review of Administrative Sciences, v. 78, n. 1, pp. 10-29, 22 Mar. 2012. MILWARD, H. B.; SNYDER, L. O. “Electronic Government: Linking Citizens to Public Organizations through Technology”. Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory (J-PART), v. 6, n. 2, pp. 261-75, 1996. MITROPOULOS, M. “Implications of Cable TV for Participatory Democracy”. Cities, v. 2, n. 2, pp. 178-9, May 1985. MOSSBERGER, K.; WU, Y.; CRAWFORD, J. “Connecting citizens and Local Governments? Social Media and Interactivity in Major U.S. Cities”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 30, n. 4, pp. 3518, Oct. 2013. MUHLBERGER, P. “Human Agency and the Revitalization of the Public Sphere”. Political Communication, v. 22, n. 2, pp. 163-78, Apr. 2005. NAISBITT, J. Megatrends. New York: Warner Books, 1982. NAM, T. “Suggesting Frameworks of Citizen-sourcing via Government 2.0”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 29, n. 1, pp. 12-20, 2012. NORRIS, P. Digital Divide: Civic Engagement, Information Poverty, and the Internet Worldwide. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001. NUGENT, J. D. “If e-Democracy Is the Answer, What’s the Question?”. National Civic Review, v. 90, n. 3, pp. 221-34, Jan. 2001. OBLAK ČRNIČ, T. “Idea(l)s on e-Democracy and Direct Online Citizenship”. Southeastern Europe, v. 36, n. 3, pp. 398-420, 1 Jan. 2012. OECD. “Understanding the Digital Divide”. Industrial Law Journal, v. 6, n. 1, pp. 52-4, 2001. OGDEN, M. R. “Politics in a Parallel Universe: Is There a Future for Cyberdemocracy”. Futures, v. 26, n. 7, pp. 713-29, Sept. 1994. OGUNLEYE, O. S.; VAN BELLE, J. P. “Exploring the Success, Failure and Factors Influencing mGovernment Implementation in Developing Countries”. Proceedings of the IST-Africa Conference and Exhibition, 2014. OOSTVEEN, A.-M.; VAN DEN BESSELAAR, P. “Internet Voting Technologies and Civic Participation: The Users’ Perspective”. Javnost – The Public, v. 11, n. 1, pp. 61-78, 7 Jan. 2004. PANKOWSKA, M. “Government 2.0: Innovation for E-Democracy”. In: INFORMATION RESOURCES MANAGEMENT ASSOCIATION, Politics and Social Activism: Concepts, Methodologies, Tools, and Applications. 3 v. Hershey: IGI Global, 2016. pp. 1509-27. PAPACHARISSI, Z. “The Virtual Sphere: The Internet as a Public Sphere”. New Media & Society, v. 4, n. 1, pp. 9-27, 1 Feb. 2002. PATEMAN, C. Participation and Democratic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970. PEARCE, S. “E-Democracy: Consultations in the UK Parliament”. Paper presented at the Congress on Innovations for an e-Society Challenges for Technology Assessment, Berlin, 17-19 Oct. 2001. POREBSKI, L. “Three Faces of Electronic Democracy”. Proceedings of the 10th European Conference on Information Systems (ECIS), Gdansk, Poland, 2002. Available at: <http://aisel.aisnet.org/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1082&context=ecis2002>. Accessed on: 11 Dec. 2017. PORUMBESCU, G. A. “Linking Public Sector Social Media and e-Government Website Use to Trust in Government”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 33, n. 2, pp. 291-304, Apr. 2016. POSTER, M. “CyberDemocracy: Internet and the Public Sphere”. In: D. Porter (ed.), Internet Culture. New York: Routledge, 1997. pp. 201-18. PUTNAM, R. D. Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community. New York: Simon & Schuster, 2000. RETHEMEYER, R. K. “Policymaking in the Age of Internet: Is the Internet Tending to Make Policy Networks More or Less Inclusive?”. Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory, v. 17, n. 2, pp. 259-84, 7 June 2006. RHEINGOLD, H. The Virtual Community: Homesteading on the Electronic Frontier. New York: AddisonWesley, 1993. RIOS, J. et al. “Participatory Budget Formation through the Web”. In: BÖHLEN, M. et al. (eds.). EGovernment: Towards Electronic Democracy. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, 2005. pp. 268-76. ROEDER, S. et al. “‘Public Budget Dialogue’ – An Innovative Approach to E-Participation”. In: BÖHLEN, M. et al. (eds.). E-Government: Towards Electronic Democracy. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, 2005. pp. 48-56. SCHLOSBERG, D.; DRYZEK, J. S. “Digital Democracy: Authentic or Virtual?”. Organization & Environment, v. 15, n. 3, pp. 332-5, 2002. SCHNEIDER, S. M. “Creating a Democratic Public Sphere through Political Discussion: A Case Study of Abortion Conversation on the Internet”. Social Science Computer Review, v. 14, n. 4, pp. 373-93, 1 Dec. 1996. SERVON, L. “Four Myths about the Digital Divide”. Planning Theory & Practice, v. 3, n. 2, pp. 222-7, 2002. SHENG, H.; TRIMI, S. “M-Government: Technologies, Applications and Challenges”. Electronic Government: An International Journal, v. 5, n. 1, pp. 1-18, 2008. SIMON, J. et al. Digital Democracy: The Tools Transforming Political Engagement. London: Nesta Foudation, 2017. SMALL, T. A. “E-Government in the Age of Social Media: An Analysis of the Canadian Government’s Use of Twitter”. Policy & Internet, v. 4, n. 3-4, pp. 91-111, Dec. 2012. SMITH, A. The Politics of Information. London: Mcmillan, 1978. SMITH, E.; MACINTOSH, A. “E-Voting: Powerful Symbol of E-Democracy”. In: TRAUNMÜLLER, R. (ed.). Electronic Government. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, 2003. pp. 240-5. SPILIOTOPOULOU, L. et al. “A Framework for Advanced Social Media Exploitation in Government for Crowdsourcing”. Transforming Government: People, Process and Policy, v. 8, n. 4, pp. 545-68, 14 Oct. 2014. SPINELLI, M. “Democratic Rhetoric and Emergent Media: The Marketing of Participatory Community on Radio and the Internet”. International Journal of Cultural Studies, v. 3, n. 2, pp. 26878, 1 Aug. 2000. STAMATI, T.; PAPADOPOULOS, T.; ANAGNOSTOPOULOS, D. “Social Media for Openness and Accountability in the Public Sector: Cases in the Greek Context”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 32, n. 1, pp. 12-29, Jan. 2015. STRECK, J. “Pulling the Plug on Electronic Town Meetings: Participatory Democracy and the Reality of the Usenet”. In: TOULOUSE, C.; LUKE, T. W. (eds.). The Politics of Cyberspace. London: Routledge, 1998. pp. 18-47. STREET, J. “Remote Control? Politics, Technology and ‘Electronic Democracy’”. European Journal of Communication, v. 12, n. 1, pp. 27-42, 1 Mar. 1997. STROMER-GALLEY, J. “Voting and the Public Sphere: Conversations on Internet Voting”. Political Science and Politics, v. 36, n. 4, pp. 727-31, 2003. SUN, P.-L.; KU, C.-Y.; SHIH, D.-H. “An Implementation Framework for E-Government 2.0”. Telematics and Informatics, v. 32, n. 3, pp. 504-20, Aug. 2015. THIEL, S.-K. K. et al. “Insights from a m-Participation Prototype in the Wild”. Proceedings of the IEEE International Conference on Pervasive Computing and Communication Workshops (PerCom Workshops), St. Louis, 23-27 Mar. 2015. Available at: <http://ieeexplore.ieee.org/document/7134013/>. Accessed on: 11 Dec. 2017. THIEL, S.-K.; LEHNER, U. “Exploring the Effects of Game Elements in M-Participation”. Proceedings of the 2015 British HCI Conference, Lincoln, UK, 13-17 July 2015. Available at: <http://dl.acm.org/citation.cfm?doid=2783446.2783587>. Accessed on: 11 Dec. 2017. TOFFLER, A. The Third Wave. Toronto: Bantam Books, 1980. TRECHSEL, A. H. et al. “Evaluation of the Use of New Technologies in Order to Facilitate Democracy in Europe”. STOA Working Paper 116 EN, European Parliament, 2004. TRIMI, S.; SHENG, H. “Emerging Trends in M-Government”. Communications of the ACM, v. 51, n. 5, pp. 53-8, 1 May 2008. TSAGAROUSIANOU, R. “Back to the Future of Democracy? New Technologies, Civic Networks and Direct Democracy in Greece”. In: TSAGAROUSIANOU, R.; TAMBINI, D.; BRYAN, C. (eds.). Cyberdemocracy: Technology, Cities and Civic Networks. London: Routledge, 1998. pp. 41-59. ________. “Electronic Democracy: Rhetoric and Reality”. Communications, v. 24, n. 2, pp. 189-208, 1999. VALENZUELA, S. “Unpacking the Use of Social Media for Protest Behavior: The Roles of Information, Opinion Expression, and Activism”. American Behavioral Scientist, v. 57, n. 7, pp. 92042, 1 July 2013. VAN DIJK, J. G. M. “Models of Democracy – Behind the Design and Use of New Media in Politics”. Javnost – The Public, v. 3, n. 1, pp. 43-56, 7 Jan. 1996. ________. “Models of Democracy and Concepts of Communication”. In: HACKER, K. L.; VAN DIJK, J. G. M. (eds.). Digital Democracy: Issues of Theory and Practice. London: Sage, 2000. ________. The Deepening Divide: Inequality in the Information Society. Thousand Oaks: Sage, 2005. ________. “Digital Democracy: Vision and Reality”. Innovation and the Public Sector, v. 19, pp. 49-62, 2012. VAN DIJK, J. A. G. M.; HACKER, K. “The Digital Divide as a Complex and Dynamic Phenomenon”. The Information Society, v. 19, n. 4, pp. 315-26, 2003. VAN VELSEN, L. et al. “Requirements Engineering for e-Government Services: A Citizen-Centric Approach and Case Study”. Government Information Quarterly, v. 26, n. 3, pp. 477-86, 2009. VARLEY, P. “Electronic Democracy”. Technology Review, v. 94, n. 8, pp. 43-51, 1991. VEDEL, T. “The Idea of Electronic Democracy: Origins, Visions and Questions”. Parliamentary Affairs, v. 59, n. 2, pp. 226-35, 10 Feb. 2006. VOGT, S.; FÖRSTER, B.; KABST, R. “Social Media and E-Participation: Challenges of Social Media for Managing Public Projects”. International Journal of Public Administration in the Digital Age, v. 1, pp. 85-105, 2014. WALZER, M. Spheres of Justice. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1985. WANG, Y. et al. “Mobile Crowdsourcing: Framework, Challenges, and Solutions”. Concurrency and Computation: Practice and Experience, v. 29, n. 3, 2017. WATSON, R. T. et al. “Teledemocracy in Local Government”. Communications of the ACM, v. 42, n. 12, pp. 58-63, Dec. 1999. WEARE, C. “The Internet and Democracy: The Causal Links Between Technology and Politics”. International Journal of Public Administration, v. 25, n. 5, pp. 659-91, 20 Apr. 2002. WESTEN, T. “E-Democracy: Ready or Not, Here It Comes”. National Civic Review, v. 89, n. 3, pp. 217-28, 2000. WHITE, C. S. “Citizen Participation and the Internet: Prospects for Civic Deliberation in the Information Age”. The Social Studies, v. 88, n. 1, pp. 23-28, Jan. 1997. WHYTE, A.; MACINTOSH, A. “Transparency and Teledemocracy: Issues from an ‘EConsultation’”. Journal of Information Science, v. 27, n. 4, pp. 187-98, 2001. WIRTZ, B. W.; DAISER, P.; MERMANN, M. “Social Media as a Leverage Strategy for Open Government: An Exploratory Study”. International Journal of Public Administration, pp. 1-14, 9 Mar. 2017. WITSCHGE, T. “Online Deliberation: Possibilities of the Internet for Deliberative Democracy”. In: P. M. Shane (ed.), Democracy Online: The Prospects for Political Renewal through the Internet, New York: Routledge, 2002. YTTERSTAD, P.; WATSON, R. T. “Teledemocracy: Using Information Technology to Enhance Political Work”. MISQ, v. 20, n. 3, p. 347, Sept. 1996. ZIMMER, M.; HOFFMANN, A. L. “Preface: A Decade of Web 2.0 – Reflections, Critical Perspectives, and Beyond”. First Monday, v. 21, n. 6, 10 June 2016. ZINNBAUER, D. “Crowdsourced Corruption Reporting: What Petrified Forests, Street Music, Bath Towels, and the Taxman Can Tell Us About the Prospects for Its Future”. Policy & Internet, v. 7, n. 1, pp. 1-24, Mar. 2015. ABOUT THE AUTHOR With a PhD in philosophy, Wilson Gomes is a researcher in the areas of political communication and democracy, government and politics in digital environments and full professor of communication theory at the School of Communication of the Federal University of Bahia (Ufba). He is the author of papers and books in the area of communication and politics, including Transformações da política na era da comunicação de massa (Transformations in Politics in the Age of Mass Communication – Paulus, 2004), Jornalismo, fatos e interesses (Journalism, Facts and Interests – Insular, 2009) and A política na timeline (Politics in the Timeline – Eufba, 2014). He coordinates the Center for Advanced Studies in Digital Democracy (CEADD) of Ufba and the National Institute of Science and Technology in Digital Democracy (INCT.DD). SOCIAL SERVICE OF COMMERCE Regional Management in São Paulo State President of the Regional Board Abram Szajman Regional Director Danilo Santos de Miranda Editorial Board Ivan Giannini Joel Naimayer Padula Luiz Deoclécio Massaro Galina Sérgio José Battistelli Edições Sesc São Paulo Manager Marcos Lepiscopo Deputy Manager Isabel M. M. Alexandre Editorial Coordination Jefferson Alves de Lima Editorial Production Rafael Fernandes Cação Communications Coordination Bruna Zarnoviec Daniel [cc] Wilson Gomes, 2018 [cc] Edições Sesc São Paulo, 2018 You are free to copy and redistribute this book’s text, as long as you give appropriate credit and do not use the material for commercial purposes. (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0) https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ Copy Editing Silvana Vieira Translation Anthony Cleaver Translation Revision Viviane Zeppelini Proofreading Richard Sanches Design and ePub File Production Werner Schulz Cover Werner Schulz Author Photo Heitor Oliveira G585d Gomes, Wilson Democracy in the digital world: history, issues and themes / Wilson Gomes. – São Paulo: Edições Sesc São Paulo, 2018. – 6.200 Kb; e-PUB. – (Digital Democracy). Bibliography ISBN 978-85-9493-104-7 (e-book) 1. Digital technologies. 2. Digital interactions. 3. Digital democracy. 4. History. I. Title. II. Gomes, Wilson da Silva. DDC 004.019 Edições Sesc São Paulo Rua Cantagalo, 74 – 13º/14º andar 03319-000 – São Paulo SP Brazil Tel. 55 11 2227-6500 edicoes@edicoes.sescsp.org.br sescsp.org.br/edicoes