Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Joe Agassi, Intellectual Irritant

2017, Encouraging Openness: Essays for Joseph Agassi. Eds Bara-Am and Gattei

This tribute begins with a recollection of my friendship with Joe and Judith which led to rewarding contacts with many of their friends and colleagues. Joe encouraged me to cast caution to the winds and unpack the implications of Popper’s ideas on objective knowledge and non-dogmatism without being distracted by the arguments about whether objective knowledge exists. The story moves on to some little appreciated aspects and implications of Popper’s thoughts; the synergy between Popper and the Austrian school of economics; the role of the moral framework of society; his early engagement with the problem of paradigms (his criticism of conventionalism); his warning about the danger of Big Science; his influence on Gordon Tullock. There is a reminder of the treasure trove of material on the website of Joe’s friend and collaborator Ian Jarvie. In view of their close partnership this is a tribute to Joe as well as to Ian. There is some criticism which Joe will see as the most enjoyable part of the paper. And last but not least, no tribute to Joe would be complete without a mention of his life partner and collaborator Judith.

Chapter 00 Published by Springer in the Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 325 2017. Joe Agassi, intellectual irritant Jan 6 2017 Final 8,200 words Abstract This tribute begins with a recollection of my friendship with Joe and Judith which led to rewarding contacts with Charlie Sawyer, Cherie Hoyt, Jancis Long and Mark and Ieva Notturno. Intellectually, Joe encouraged me to cast caution to the winds and unpack the implications of Popper’s ideas on objective knowledge and non-justificationism without being distracted by the arguments about whether objective knowledge exists. He contributed directly to economics in partnership with Klappholz and indirectly through his pupil Larry Boland who in turn mentored Stanley Wong. The story moves on to some little appreciated aspects and implications of Popper’s thoughts; the synergy between Popper and the Austrian school of economics; the role of the moral framework of society; his early engagement with the problem of paradigms (his criticism of conventionalism); his warning about the danger of Big Science; his influence on Gordon Tullock. There is a reminder of the treasure trove of material on the website of Joe’s friend and collaborator Ian Jarvie. In view of their close partnership this is a tribute to Joe as well as to Ian. There is some criticism which Joe will see as the most enjoyable part of the paper. And last but not least, no tribute to Joe would be complete without a mention of his life partner and collaborator Judith. 00.1 The personal side My first memory of Joe dates from the Popper Centenary Conference in 2002. The mobile enrolment centre appeared from nowhere on a trailer at the last minute before the designated time to enrol. Then Joe and Judith held court on the lawn in front of the university for their students and others. It was a magic occasion, with nothing to do and some time to spend in the mild late July sunshine. I seem to recall that there were chairs for Joe and Judith and a few others while most of us lounged on the grass to enjoy the relaxed conversation of the old friends and colleagues. Larry Boland was there, Ian Jarvie, John Wettersten, Bill Berkson and others who I don't recall. Joe and Judith became special friends in 2010 when they invited me to stay with them in Tel Aviv after I completed a “mixed faith” tour of Israel. That was the first of several visits to the house in Levi Eshkol Street, not far from the beach. This was a very enjoyable place to stay with stimulation and relaxation in turn. In addition to Joe’s conversation there was a continual flow of visitors. And the books. So many books that it seemed as though the bookshelves would hold up the ceiling if the walls collapsed. Joe said most of his books were out of sight in the basement and he had not reached the point of an elderly associate who stored books in his refrigerator. For relaxation there was a stroll to the beach or the supermarket, and B grade movies on TV in the evening. For their parts, Joe and Judith derived some amusement from my Australian accent. Perhaps the most significant visit occurred in 2011, en route to Paris to catch up with one of my sons, on the way around the world to Boston to meet another son. The visit was timed to coincide with the departure of some other guests who were keeping the bed warm for me. Arriving in the evening I met a friendly stranger in the lounge. This was Charlie Sawyer. Cherie was upstairs finishing the packing while Judith was making up the bed for the new arrival. Charlie and I soon discovered that we both grew up on dairy farms and this bond of shared experience infused a congenial conversation which continued until Charlie and Cherie set out to catch a 5am plane to Boston. In the course of the evening I mentioned that I would be passing through Boston and as Charlie went out the door he turned back and said over his shoulder “If you come to Boston, be in touch”. And so it came to pass that I stayed at Boxford among the woods, the ponds and the squirrels for an enchanting week or so, the first of many. But there is more! At the first visit, on the brink of departure from Boston for George Mason University, near Washington DC, Cherie suggested that I might like to get in touch with Jancis Long, a younger associate of Joe from his time in London. This was a long shot and I wondered what might come from an email from an unknown Australian who happened to be passing by. In the event, Jancis drove for an hour out of Washington and took me to lunch to talk about our mutual interest in Karl Popper and his associates. Years before, prompted by Joe (another important intervention by our intellectual irritant), she pursued a study of Imre Lakatos when he was a Stalinist aparatchick in Hungary (Long 1988). That is only half the story. Over lunch Jancis suggested that I might like to get in touch with Mark Notturno, another Popper scholar in Washington. She gave me a phone number and an email address. To my mind Notturno was a somewhat enigmatic figure. I knew his books and I knew that my friend Colin Simkin met him in passing at Popper’s home. I phoned the number with some trepidation, then after we talked for an hour or so one or the other of us suggested that we had better get together for coffee. The next day we met for coffee and conversation, punctuated by serious tennis-watching, pool and occasional recourse to medicinal Bourbon until it was too late to take the train back to George Mason and I stayed overnight. Next day Thanksgiving dinner turned into another late night and another overnight stay and the house in Bloomingdale DC became another home away from home. 00.2 The Intellectual Irritant: Unpacking Ideas “Somebody may be original in being systematic, even if he is not successful in his effort to be systematic” (Agassi 1968). The paper is about novelty in general, with Popper's ideas as a major example along with avant garde art and some examples of scientific discovery. The takeaway idea is the notion of originality emerging from the simple discipline of being systematic about an idea or insight and taking it as far as it will go. Prompted by that thought I embarked upon the task of drawing out the consequences of Popper's theories of objective knowledge and "non-justificationism" across a range of problems and issues. The work on objective knowledge did not progress to publication and it lived on my website until it moved into the collection Reason and Imagination (Champion 2015). The following is a slightly edited form of the introduction and summary. 20.2.1 Objective Knowledge This article is written to encourage literary intellectuals who may feel threatened by Lord Snow's scientists who "have the future in their bones" and who know all about the second law of thermodynamics. People need to be reminded that we do not live by bread and technology alone; we live by the values, traditions and myths which are embedded in our literature and are studied in the humanities. Our intellectual heritage is a mix of good and bad ideas and if they are not subjected to ongoing criticism there is a risk that the bad may drive out the good. Popper’s task in The Open Society and its Enemies was to examine the work of some revered figures, notably Plato, to identify bad ideas which can be eliminated without necessarily damaging the status and reputation of the authors. Popper's theory of objective knowledge breathes fresh life into the study of values, myths and traditions. This theory goes to the root of the problems of the social sciences and the humanities. His ideas about world 3 of objective knowledge have aroused little enthusiasm up to date, reflecting perhaps the time that new ideas need to germinate and bear fruit. I will show how this theory illuminates and unifies problems in the scope and methods of philosophy, in some aspects of moral and political philosophy, in the theory of literature and criticism, in the social sciences and in psychology. Section I contains some background on Popper's ideas, explaining why they have not penetrated to the educated public. Section II sketches the theory of objective knowledge and some of its history. Section III treats Russell's method of logical analysis and argues that the valuable part of this method consists of teasing out the objective content of scientific theories, not the process of clarifying concepts as is usually believed. Section IV argues that Wittgenstein's "forms of life" may be regarded as the objective contents of traditions These traditions exert plastic control over our activities and they can be subjected to rational (critical) scrutiny as soon as we become conscious of them. Section V argues that morals have a similar kind of existence and this enables them to exert a plastic control over our actions. They cannot usefully be described as true or false, but the acceptance or rejection of specific values can be controlled by critical discussion and can be a matter of critical preference between alternatives. Section VI examines the nature of creative literature and shows how T.S. Eliot's ideas about the social function of poetry can be illuminated by Popper's theory. Section VII suggests that this theory can contribute to a model of explanation in the social sciences; this is explained with reference to Durkheim's problem of social order and Weber's problem of social change. Section VIII pursues the idea that psychology needs to be revolutionised by looking at the brain as an organ that enables us to interact with objective knowledge in the form of theories, traditions and values. 20.2.3 Non-justificationism The concept of non-justificationism is peculiar to Popper and Popperians and it has made next to no impact in the academic community at large. Exceptions are Weimer (1979), Smith (1982), Butos (1987), Lester (2000) and Barry Smith’s exposition of fallibillistic apriorism (Smith 1996). Bartley in particular took on the idea and made it his own (1964 and 1984). Again I followed Joe’s hint to pursue the implications of the idea in several directions. One is the theory of literature with a rejoinder to the deconstructionists (Champion 1989). They threatened to outflank their critics by their robust rhetorical techniques which ensure that they would be a force that rival schools of criticism would have to reckon with for some time to come. Prompted by Notturno (1984) I suggested that the rival schools do not need to be intimidated by the pretence of philosophical sophistication on the part of Derrida et al. but instead they should embrace the approach of critical rationalism and become united in self-criticism. Another paper took up Hayek’s turn to non-justificationism in his last book The Fatal Conceit (Champion 2013a). A paper presented to the Australian Skeptics recruited non-justificationism for the cause of draining the swamp of prejudice and superstition by “cracking the dogmatic framework of western thought” (Champion 2015 Chapter 11). Yet another suggested a resolution to the “foundation of knowledge” problem which perplexed Carl Menger, the founder of Austrian economics (Champion 2013b Appendix VI). Menger intended to follow his foundational work with more volumes but instead he wrote a polemic on methodological issues and did not continue the main line of his theoretical work. He wanted to account for the foundations of scientific knowledge in economics and he did not succeed, possibly because he lacked a theory of fallible or conjectural knowledge. Without the benefit of such a theory he resorted to devices like “the rule of cognition” to make his case in the face of difficulties with empirical evidence as the foundation. With the benefit of a theory of conjectural knowledge he could have pressed on with his research program, appealing to the explanatory power of his theories rather than justification by any special method. 00.3 Economics. The philosophy and methods of economics became a growth area in the 1980s but some years later a survey concluded that nothing of much value had emerged, although when Popper is read as a critical rationalist, his ideas are robust and relevant (Hands 2001). The lost years which were dedicated to positivism, paradigm theory and the methodology of scientific research programs might have been saved if people had learned from Klappholz and Agassi (1959). They explained that Popper’s approach was all about robust criticism, with the implicit message was that there was no need for people to specialize in the philosophy and methodology of economics. People doing economics should be problem-centred, critical and imaginative, and that did not call for books, chairs and conferences on philosophy and methodology. From that perspective the new specialty of philosophy and methodology of economics could even be seen as a diversion rather than a contribution to the field. Larry Boland is one of the more helpful contributors to that literature. He took an economics degree and found his way into a course of lectures from Joe which changed the direction of his philosophical thinking and his approach to his substantial work in economics (the irritant at work again). He mentored Stanley Wong who made a very significant contribution with his doctoral dissertation, a critique of Paul Samuelson’s demand theory (Wong, 1978, revised 2006). The book has a helpful Foreword by Mirowski which is available on line (Mirowski 2006). Wong’s chapter on “understanding and criticism” is one of the clearest accounts of Popperian situational analysis in the literature. He explained the situational constraints of a theoretical problem situation and he then looked at the theory of demand (supply and demand) as it evolved in recent times, especially in Paul Samuelson’s project from the 1930s to 1950. Samuelson wanted to revolutionize the methods of economics by putting the theory of consumer preferences on a proper scientific basis, eliminating all non-empirical references in the theory. He received the Nobel Prize in economics for his efforts but Wong argued cogently that he did not succeed. The economics profession in general and Samuelson in particular went on as though nothing had happened but if Wong’s thesis is robust his critique of Samuelson is a capital achievement, based on Popper’s ideas, transmitted through the influence of Agassi and Boland. 00.4 The Synergy of Popper and the Austrian economists This is another example of following an idea to see where it leads. The idea in this case is that the most under-rated school of philosophy can empower the most under-rated school of economics and challenge the mainstream of economics to take the Austrians seriously. Popper’s ideas suggest that the Austrians are not vulnerable to the standard objection of the mainstream (the Austrians are not scientific) and they demonstrate that the supposedly scientific mainstream has got hold of the wrong end of the stick on the philosophy and methods of science. An introduction to the Austrian school is necessary to explain why the synergy is significant, if true. The founding fathers in the 19th century were native-born Austrians but nowadays most of the “Austrians” are Americans. They represent about 2% of the economics profession and most economists know next to nothing about the Austrian program. The leading features of the school include methodological individualism, the origin of social institutions such as money as the unintended consequences of human action, the salience of dynamic competition and entrepreneurial innovation in the marketplace, the subjective theory of value, recognition of the time factor in social and economic processes, and the uncertainty of human knowledge. The most distinctive feature and the one that has created the most problems in gaining wider acceptance is the epistemological concept of strong apriorism which purports to establish the axioms of the discipline, independent of empirical studies. This aroused the ire of Samuelson who wrote, referring to several authors including von Mises, Frank Knight, Lionel Robbins. “Well, in connection with the exaggerated claims that used to be made in economics for the power of deduction and a priori reasoning…I tremble for the reputation of my subject. Fortunately, we have left that behind us.” (Samuelson 1964) The founding father of the school was Carl Menger (1840-1921), followed by Friedrich von Wieser (1851-1926) and Eugen von Bohm-Bawerk (1851-1914). Major contributors include Knut Wicksell (1851-1926), Ludwig von Mises (1880-1973, Friedrich A. Hayek (1898-1994) and Murray Rothbard (1926-1995). Recent leaders include Ludwig Lachmann (1906-1990), Israel Kirzner (1930 - ) and a new generation including names such as Ebeling, Salerno, Rizzo, Caldwell, Boettke, Klein, Lewin, Koppl, Herbener, with doctoral programs at GMU, Texas Tech, Baylor, West Virginia, Rey Juan Carlos Madrid, and Francisco Marroquin. Early in the 20th century the Austrian ideas appeared to be firmly planted in the mainstream of the economics profession but the rise of Keynes and the logical positivists in the 1930s transformed the situation. After the war the Austrians became practically invisible until the movement staged a revival in the 1970s (Vaughn 1990). As to their scientific status, both positivism and falsificationism seemed to rule out the strong form of apriorism advocated by von Mises and after him Rothbard and the contemporary Hans Herman Hoppe. Popper’s ideas support the Austrian school of economics in three ways. First, his account of the role of methodological conventions and the theory of metaphysical research programs shows that Austrian a priorism cannot be dismissed as "unscientific" as many critics suppose.  Some of the so-called a priori principles of Austrian economics can be regarded as working assumptions, either methodological or metaphysical postulates, of the kind that occur in all sciences. These need to stand up to criticism but they do not have to be directly testable or falsifiable. They are tested at one stage removed by their capacity to sustain testable theories, progressive research programs and effective advice on policy issues (Champion 2002, 2011). Second, Popper’s method of situational analysis or the “logic of the situation” is remarkably similar to the approach advocated by von Mises in Human Action (1949) and by Talcott Parsons The Structure of Social Action (1937). All three were at work in the 1930s developing a framework for the study of economics and the other social sciences which could have: maintained sociology and economics as an integrated discipline; sponsored partnerships between economists and all students of social institutions - law, politics, literature, religion and cultural studies at large; ensured that "high theory" and empirical studies informed, enriched and corrected each other; contributed to good public policy, especially by monitoring the results of increased regulation and the erosion of "civic/bourgeois virtues". There was a window of opportunity for these three leading figures in their respective fields to form a united front across the disciplines of sociology, economics and philosophy to promote the ideas that they shared and to debate the issues where they disagreed. This did not happen, there was no united front and the defective ideas which all three identified in the 1930s became embedded in the rapidly growing community of academics and researchers after the war. Thirdly, Popper propagated some metaphysical theories which provide a congenial framework for the Austrian approach. In a nutshell, Popper and the Austrians are metaphysical fellow travellers. Barry Smith found that Carl Menger used a set of Austrian/Aristotelian ideas as the framework for his ideas and the ten propositions which he used to define the framework have some overlap with Popper’s metaphysical research program (Smith 1990 1996). 00.5 Popper versus paradigms in the 1930s. Popperian exegesis mostly dwells on his arguments with logicians so it took Jarvie’s Republic of Science to spell out what he called Popper’s “social turn” although it was signalled in The Logic of Scientific Discovery (section 5), in Chap 23 of The Open Society and section 32 of The Poverty of Historicism. The final section of chapter 1 Conjectural Knowledge in Objective Knowledge is especially helpful because it describes how Popper discovered a new range of problems after he realised that the quest for justification by way of verification was unsustainable. All theories are hypothetical (conjectural) because any or all may be overthrown although that process can take a long time if the adherents of the ruling program are unwilling to give it up. Popper used the term conventionalism to describe the attempt to retain an established theory against interloping novelties (Newton vs Einstein). This indicates that he was addressing the problems of paradigms long before Kuhn entered the fray. He became alert to the way that theories can be "immunized" against criticism by means of ad hoc hypotheses, by shifting definitions, ignoring inconvenient observations and even by challenging the competence of rival investigators. Kuhn added the string of incommensurability to the conventionalist’s bow and on politically sensitive issues there is recourse to the charge of ideological/political bias. In Popper’s view these conventionalist strategies raised the issue of the social nature of science and the norms, traditions and conventions of the scientific community “Thus I was led to the idea of methodological rules and…of an approach which avoided the policy of immunizing our theories against refutation.” (Popper 1972, 30). The next step in the evolution of his ideas came as he applied the critical approach to the test statements of the empirical basis and he recognised the conjectural and theory-laden nature of observation statements. That in turn led to the recognition that all languages are theory-impregnated and that called for a fundamental change in our perception of empiricism which hitherto had located the solid foundations of knowledge in sensory inputs. It also made me look upon the critical attitude as characteristic of the rational attitude; and it led me to see the significance of the argumentative (or critical) function of language...And it further led me to realize that only a formulated theory (rather than a believed theory) can be objective and to the idea that it is this formulation or objectivity that makes criticism possible; and so to my theory of a 'third world'. (ibid 31) Those very important paragraphs provide the pattern of Popper's progress from demarcation and induction to the rules of the game, to theories of language and the ideas of objective knowledge and the evolutionary link between language and critical. As Jarvie demonstrated in The Republic of Science, all those themes were present in Popper's first published work and it took a lifetime to draw out some of their implications. 00.6 What is to be done? Popper’s Leninist turn. Popper’s rules for the “republic of science” can be couched in the language of political demands or proposals which he suggested to replace the language of essentialism and historicism in political philosophy. The essentialist explicates the concept of democracy or the state, and the historicist looks at the history of democracy or the state, while Popper and Hayek pose questions about what is to be done – what sort of government do we want, and how do we want to change leaders, what do we consider to be the role of the state and the limits of state activity? Given this approach the task is to discover, formulate , and critically probe the implications and modify those principles which function as the 'rules of the game' in social life (Champion 2013c Chapter 5). The 'rules of the game' range from the possibly innate rules of grammar, through the tacit knowledge of local traditions and folkways to the rules of games and other codified forms of procedure. They include the laws of the land embodied in common law, statutes and constitutions. This would be essentially an ecological study with the emphasis on unintended 'downstream' effects of changes in the prevailing order. This approach would supplement the methods of conceptual analysis and crude 'positivist' empirical description of social and political systems. It would have the theoretical advantage of linking disciplines and the practical merit of being continually in touch with problems and their possible solutions. 00.7 Ian C Jarvie, Peter Munz and Colin Simkin Ian Jarvie was such a close friend and colleague of Joe that it is fitting to say a little more about his contribution as a tribute to Joe. We can be grateful for The Republic of Science and there is much more to mention including his service as editor of Philosophy of the Social Sciences and the unpublished material on his website which spans a remarkable range from studies of film to sociological research and a wide range of philosophical topics. There is a paper on Popper’s rationality and situational logic with a long list of problems which Popper addressed in The Open Society (Jarvie 1999) and a tribute to Bill Bartley (Jarvie 1989-90b). In the Bartley paper he referred to Agassi’s criticism that The Logic of Scientific Discovery did not take enough account of the role of metaphysics in the history of science, something which Popper addressed with the theory of metaphysical research programmes, perhaps in response to Joe in his capacity as the intellectual irritant! Peter Munz and Colin Simkin are included here for a different reason. They became friends of Popper during his exile in New Zealand and they are probably forgotten, so there may never be a better opportunity to remind people about these two stalwart champions of Popper. Peter Munz (1921-2006) was a truly remarkable quiet achiever. Educated in Germany, Switzerland and Florence he arrived in New Zealand as a refugee in 1940. He had the unique distinction of being a student of Popper in Christchurch and of Wittgenstein in Cambridge. Most of his life career was spent in New Zealand, lecturing in history at Victoria University, Wellington. An obituary charts his remarkable achievements in two lines of research during his teaching career and two other lines after he retired (Morris 2016). He published important books on religion and mythology, notably Relationship and Solitude: An Enquiry into the Relationship Between Myth, Metaphysics and Ethics (1965) and his other field was medieval history. In retirement he turned to philosophy and evolutionary psychology. On the Growth of Knowledge: Popper or Wittgenstein (1985) was a spirted defence of Popper against Wittgenstein and others including Kuhn and Rorty who were being recruited to the cause of relativism and postmodernism. Following Popper’s lead, biological and evolutionary themes dominated in Philosophical Darwinism: On the Origin of Knowledge by Means of Natural Selection (1993) and Critique of Impure Reason: An Essay on Neurons, Somatic Markers and Consciousness in 1999. Colin Simkin (1915-1998) was an economist. He started a lifelong friendship with Popper while The Open Society and Its Enemies was in in preparation and he wrote a charming memoire of that achievement (Simkin 1993 Appendix One). Later, at Oxford, he formed a similarly close friendship with the leading economist John Hicks and his wife which became the subject of another memoire (Simkin 2001). Being a man of strong principles and a lover of classical music he formed an profound antipathy for manly sports and games, especially cricket and rugby which were the dominant religions in New Zealand, although he could be persuaded to watch tennis and swimming on TV with his wife. He kept in close contact with Popper by correspondence (lacking the internet) and he frequently visited Popper in Britain. His friendship meant a lot to Popper and as a mark of respect he was allowed to smoke while they walked in the garden. We became friends and we met almost weekly for the last decade of his life. This revived his interest in writing and he produced a fine introduction to Popper’s ideas (Simkin 1993). 00.8 The Challenge of Big Science The world of science changed out of recognition in Popper’s lifetime and it is clear from his unpublished lectures at the London School of Economics that he was very concerned about the emergence of Big Science, driven by government money. President Eisenhower articulated similar concerns in his outgoing Presidential address (Eisenhower 1961). “The prospect of domination of the nation's scholars by Federal employment, project allocation, and the power of money is ever present.” Popper speculated about some influences which could kill science, including the incentives offered to scientists by the newly available money for research. He foresaw a problem of too much money chasing too few ideas, the publication explosion (good buried under bad), angling for money at the expense of good science. In Section 32 of The Poverty of Historicism he advanced an institutional theory to account for scientific and industrial progress and he speculated about factors which might impede progress, such as government control of the laboratories and journals. He did not pursue his speculations but he inspired the outstanding political economist Gordon Tullock to write The Organization of Inquiry (1965). I am not aware of any reference to Tullock in Popper’s published work but some Austrian economists with an interest in Tullock found some 70 pages of correspondence between Popper and Tullock in the 1950s and ‘60s (David Levy personal communication). Tullock’s book sketched a scenario for the evolution of a field of research in a downward spiral to a point where it approached the state of pseudoscience resembling Lysenkoism in Russian genetics and plant breeding. When he wrote in the 1960s he thought that the social sciences were on that path but he considered that the natural sciences were sound. Affiliation: School of Social and Community Medicine, University of Bristol, Bristol, United Kingdom ⨯ 00.9 Popper on the Moral Framework and Religious Faiths Popper was sceptical about moral philosophy, which he suggested could be mostly summed up in the Golden Rule. He acknowledged the importance of moral institutions and traditions, especially what he called the “moral framework” of society. In a paper delivered to the Mont Pelerin Society in 1954 he wrote: Among the traditions that we must count as the most important is what we may call the 'moral framework' (corresponding to the institutional 'legal framework') of a society. This incorporates the society's traditional sense of justice or fairness, or the degree of moral sensitivity that it has reached... Nothing is more dangerous than the destruction of this traditional framework. (Its destruction was consciously aimed at by Nazism) (Popper 1963 Chapter 17). Another much-neglected part of the moral framework is the prevailing attitude towards work, business and the cluster of ideas which Deirdre McCloskey (2010) has labelled “the bourgeois virtues” such as honesty, the work ethic, business acumen, prudence and temperance. European culture in classical and Christian times spurned work and the bourgeoisie. Yet from 1600 to 1800, startlingly, it developed a lively appreciation of the ‘bourgeois virtues’, from which came the stirrings of enterprise that made the modern world…But after 1848 the artists and intellectuals turned sharply against capitalism. From this, alas, came the events of 1914 and 1917 and all our woe. (McCloskey 2006) Religions have been the main sources and foundations of moral frameworks and Popper held interesting and nuanced views about God and religion although he was loth to talk about them in public. Late in life he consented to two interviews with rabbi Edward Zerin on condition that there should be no publication while he was alive. A small part of the transcript appeared in the Skeptic (US) in March 1998 and it is reprinted in a collection of papers (Popper, 2008, Chapter 5). Another thought-provoking public contribution can be found in a lecture that he delivered in 1940 in New Zealand in a series of university extension lectures on ‘Religion: Some Modern Problems and Developments’. One of his lectures is reprinted in After the Open Society (Popper 2008). He argued that the dispute between religion and science in the 19th century was a thing of the past because it was based on each side trespassing on the territory of the other. Science evolved out of the religious mythology that men first invented to explain the world and because most religions are “true belief” systems there is a strong and unhelpful residue of “true belief” in science itself. 00.10 A critical note on global warming Joe’s latest book, Beg to Differ, written with A. Meidan, touched on the debate between those who are alarmed about global warming and those who are not. Most students of global warming [read “most of the people with government grants to study global warming”] agree about most of the relevant facts. The world is getting significantly warmer since the beginning of the twentieth century to date [by perhaps one degree C]. This is a trend that will probably not desist overnight. [it reversed between 1940 and 1970 and it practically stopped in 1998] One of the main reasons for this trend is the burning of fossil fuel…If this trend goes on the damage for human society will be unbearable. (Agassi and Meidan p57) On the other side The globe undergoes warming and cooling repeatedly and for thus-far unknown reasons and with thus-far unpredictability…all the models have been refuted…Therefore there is no rational basis for the prediction that global warming will continue and cause a global catastrophe. (ibid p57-58) They ask: “Which of these two theories makes the world stranger?” 00.10.1 The strangeness of alarmism Possibly the strangest thing is that there is any alarm at all. Since 1850 the temperature has increased by about one degree C and the increase in CO2 in more recent decades has significantly greened the planet. For the best part of two decades since the El Nino in 1998 there has been very little warming (the pause) until the recent El Nino, followed by a rapid decline towards the post-1998 plateau level. As to the role of carbon dioxide and “carbon pollution”, the El Nino has nothing to do with CO2, the temperature declined between 1940 and 1970 while CO2 increased, and almost all of the models built to project the temperature based on increasing CO2 have been falsified (Spencer 2004). Turning to the most famous paper in the literature, the 97.1% consensus (Cook at al. 2013), the ace which President Obama played to push for global action on emissions, it is surprising read the paper and find no reference to the amount of warming or the need to worry about it. The points of consensus reported in the paper are (1) there has been warming (but who disagrees?) and (2) humans have contributed. Taking account of the heat-island effect, who disagrees with that? As to the amount of human impact, a significant but unreported finding in the project was that only 2% of the sample thought that humans contributed more than 50% of warming. That result was on the university website but not in the publication (Shollenberger 2016 location 66-104) . So the investigation appears to demonstrate a consensus that humans caused less than half of the (beneficial) warming of the last 150 years. What follows from that in the world of political initiatives? Later in the book Agassi and Meidan turned to the cost/benefit aspect of various scenarios. They were alert to the costs of mitigation strategies in terms of hospitals, schools and other desirable things that will have to be foregone to subsidise renewable energy. Here we find some genuinely alarming developments because the costs of mitigation and warming-alarmism are being experienced here and now, in contrast with hypothetical harms in the future based on failed models. On the cost side, some tens of thousands of people die from starvation each year caused by the increased price of food due to the diversion of corn and other crops from the human food chain into auto fuel. Jobs in power-intensive industries are under threat worldwide and surging power costs threaten the lives of the poor and the old who are liable to freeze to death in winter. It is important to realise that the mega-trillions spent to develop alternatives to fossil fuels are wasted until the renewables are adequate to the task and a new generation of storage batteries is available to cover days when the wind does not blow (or blows too hard) and the sun does not shine (not to mention the nights). Until that time fossil-fuel fired electricity is required to back up the renewables – that means supporting dual power sources and probably doubling the cost of power. The cost of subsidies to support crony capitalists in this area is very large as well (Butos and McQuade 2015). So the really strange thing is the alarm and the urgency to spend massive sums of money to create a host of real problems. This has many of the characteristics of “solutioneering”, a concept named by Roger James in his excellent introduction to Popper’s ideas (James 1980). “First. Jump to a solution before clearly formulating what the problem is (or indeed if there is one at all) or how success or failure are to be judged. Achievement of the solution then becomes the goal…I call this mistake solutioneering.” (ibid 3). Second, play up the desperate urgency of the situation – there is no time to waste, it is almost too late already - ignore the problems of implementing the solution, under-estimate the cost of the solution and over-estimate the cost of the alleged problem (see Lord Stern’s estimate of the cost of warming). If we are dealing with solutioneering in this case, what supports the paradigm of climate science which generates alarm? Part of the answer is: a number of things that Karl Popper addressed and criticized the best part of a century ago (see 00.5). Two sets of influences can be listed, first historical/systematic/background factors and second, immediate or foreground strategies to defend the ruling paradigm, especially by the allocation of government funds. 00.10.2. The historical background factors. One background factor is the ongoing concern in the positivist/empiricist philosophy of science with “confirmation theory” and the calculation of inductive probabilities of theories. A century after the rise of modern positivism there is still no way to confirm general explanatory theories or to allocate probabilities to them but countless generations of students have been inducted into the arcane lore of confirmation and induction, driven by the unstated assumption that we want to know how sure we are about what we think we know rather than criticising and testing our ideas to find growing points for advances in the field. Students are likely to emerge from these courses without any real insight into the world of science “outside the window” or the role of criticism in it. Add to confirmation bias in the philosophy of science some things which I have treated in a series of sketches under the heading “Joining the dots” (Champion 2016a). These dots are: The post World War 2 decline of education at all levels and the need for attention to what Jacques Barzun Called “the house of intellect”. The radicalization of the environmental movement which grew out of the “Ban the Bomb” movement of the 1950s and the international campaign against nuclear energy which followed. The postwar development of big science funded by governments. The rise of relatively uncritical “normal science” flagged by T. S. Kuhn and the impetus which he unwittingly gave to it. The long-term implications of the radicalization of university students in the 1960sand ‘70s. The role of environmental entrepreneurs in the United Nations, the proliferation of climate relate organizations and the governance of the IPCC. Gordon Tullock’s account of the way certain motivational factors on the part of scientists and the institutional structure of science can combine to run down the quality of scientific publications to the terminal stage where the point of view becomes a criterion for acceptance for publication (Champion 2016b). 00.10.3 Defending the ruling paradigm. Popper identified a number of “conventionalist strategies” to protect a ruling theory from competitors (see 00.5) and all of those practices have been deployed to marginalize critics of the alarmist paradigm. In view of the great cost of modern research which is almost entirely directed by governments, the most powerful strategies for paradigm defence are the “positive heuristic” (funding favoured programs) and the “negative heuristic” (not funding rival programs). To indicate the money involved, Butos and McQuade (2015) found that climate-related research and development in the US Federal Budget increased dramatically from 1995 to approach $17 Billion in the 2013 budget. A partial accounting showed the trend from $3.6 Billion in 2001 to $9.1 Billion in 2013. Against this, climate alarmists were agitated to find that “big oil” villains supported the anti-alarmist Heartland Institute. This including almost $800,000 from ExxonMobil between 1998 and 2005 (Wikepedia 2016). Since then Big Oil has found that it is more profitable to get on the green bandwagon and more Big Oil money is flowing to alarmism than skepticism (Morano 2013). If alarmists were concerned about scientists being bought with a few million dollars, how many scientists can be bought with $17 Billion, driven by a government agenda? Recall Popper’s warning that scientific progress could be stopped by government control of the laboratories! For an inside view of the US government agenda under the Obama administration, see Carlin (2015). Carlin is a lifelong environmentalist, hiker, whitewater rafter and international traveller who joined the Sierra Club in the 1960s. He is highly qualified in science (UCLA) and economics (RMIT) and he spent 27 years doing environmental studies and cost-benefit analysis in the US Environmental Protection Agency (EPA). Under the Bush presidency he observed practically no political interference with the work of the agency but his experience in the Obama years corroborated Popper’s concerns about government control of the laboratories. Turning to the positive and negative heuristics, a large part of climate science is devoted to model building. This involves thousands of scientists working on supercomputers in collecting data, development and data processing. The cost ensures that there are only government-funded models. They can be called “hot” models because up to date they have predicted temperatures far in excess of reality (see section 10.2). They provide input to the environmental impact field of climate science, demonstrating the GIGO principle (Garbage In, Garbage Out). Worldwide teams of biologists and others use the unrealistic projections to explore the implications for endangered species, the food and water supply and the proliferation of human diseases and their vectors. Of course the scenarios are alarming and very newsworthy for slow news days in the media. However in view of the assumptions which underpin these exercises they can only regarded as science fiction. As to the negative heuristic, there is scant funding for the considerable number of non-human influences on the climate, among them: Alternative models, less driven by CO2. The relative impact of different greenhouse gases, especially water vapour and the possible role of CO2 as an inhibitor of warming rather than a positive agent. Ocean circulation effects, both the relatively well known El Nino effect and the less explored deep ocean effects. Long-term natural oscillations like the Little Ice Age Solar activity which has both direct and indirect effects. Negative feedback loops including convection and cloud cover. It is interesting to note that despite the limited funding in the areas listed above, it was still possible to find almost 100 peer reviewed papers published in each of the last three years (2014, 2015, 2016) affirming the influential role of the sun in climate change (Richard 2016). 00.10.4 Revisiting the precautionary principle Up to date the precautionary principle has been urged by radical environmentalists to support the “solutioneering” approach to spare no expense and waste no time in mitigating CO2 emissions. However in view of the shaky basis of alarming projections and the real and immediate cost of mitigation programs, it appears that the precautionary approach calls for a halt to dramatic interventions until we have a better fix on the trajectory of warming and the causal factors in climate change. 00.11 Judith Buber Agassi and Charlotte Buhler Joe Agassi has been a tireless intellectual irritant for the best part of a century. I have no doubt that a lot of the credit for his productivity and his good humour can be assigned to his equally indomitable companion for most of that long time. No doubt there will be other tributes to Judith in this volume, coming from people who have known Joe and Judith for many decades. As a feminist, a wife and a scholar she is in the mould of Charlotte Buhler, the wife of Popper’s most important teacher. She was a truly remarkable woman, as can be said of Judith and I hope they will both be remembered, along with their partners, Karl Buhler and Joe Agassi, the indefatigable intellectual irritant. Agassi J 1968 The novelty of Popper's philosophy of science. International Phil. Quarterly 8, 1968. Agassi J, Meidan A 2016 Beg to differ. The logic of disputes and argumentation. Springer. Bartley W W 1964 Rationality versus the theory of rationality. In Bunge M (ed) The Critical Approach to Science and to Philosophy. The Free Press, New York:p3-31. Bartley W W 1983 The Retreat to Commitment, 2nd edition. Open Court, La Salle Illinois. Butos William N 1987 Rhetoric and rationality: A review essay of McCloskey’s The Rhetoric of Economics. Eastern Economic Journal 13(3):295-304. Butos William N and McQuade Thomas J (2015) Causes and consequences of the climate science boom. The Independent Review 20 (2):165-196. http://www.independent.org/publications/tir/article.asp?a=1080 Carlin A 2015 Environmentalism Gone Mad: Environmentalism Gone Mad: How a Sierra Club Activist and Senior EPA Analyst Discovered a Radical Green Energy Fantasy. Stairway Press, Mount Vernon WA. Champion R 1989 Towards constructive deconstruction. Critical Review, Winter :77-89. Revised 2005 http://www.the-rathouse.com/bartdeconstruct.html Champion R 2002 The Austrian school of economics as a Popperian research program. Website http://www.the-rathouse.com/RC_PopperPaper.html Champion R 2011 In defence of fallible apriorism and the Aristotelian program for economics. Nuova Civilta Delle Machine 1-2:69-88. Draft http://www.the-rathouse.com/WritingsonMises/FallibleApriorism.html Champion R 2013a Hayek, Bartley and Popper: Justificationism and the abuse of reason. In Leeson R (ed) Hayek: A Collaborative Biography. Part I Influences from Mises to Bartley. Palgrave Macmillan, New York:p213-225. Champion R 2013b Guide to The Open Society and its Enemies. Amazon. https://www.amazon.com/Guide-Society-Enemies-Popular-Popper-ebook/dp/B00C6RHIGO/ref=sr_1_2?ie=UTF8&qid=1483093545&sr=8-2&keywords=rafe+champion. Champion R 2013c Commentary on Hayek. Amazon https://www.amazon.com/Commentary-Hayek-Critical-Rationalist-Papers-ebook/dp/B00E0L8AR0/ref=sr_1_6?ie=UTF8&qid=1482889945&sr=8-6&keywords=rafe+champion Champion 2015 Reason and Imagination. Amazon. https://www.amazon.com/Reason-Imagination-thoughts-William-Bartley/dp/1507512112/ref=sr_1_4?ie=UTF8&qid=1483093591&sr=8-4&keywords=rafe+champion Champion R 2016a What Happened to Climate Science? Joining the Dots. http://catallaxyfiles.com/2016/10/11/what-happened-to-climate-science-the-dots/ Champion R 2016b Gordon Tullock on Induced Curiosity and the Decline of Scientific Integrity. http://catallaxyfiles.com/2016/10/18/climate-science-7-gordon-tullock-on-induced-curiosity-and-the-decline-of-scientific-integrity/ Cook J, Nuccitelli D, Green Sarah A, Richardson Mark, Winkler Barbel, Painting Rob, Way Robert, Jacobs Peter, Skuce Andrew 2013 Quantifying the consensus on anthropogenic warming in the scientific literature. Environmental Research Letters 8 024024 http://iopscience.iop.org/article/10.1088/1748-9326/8/2/024024/meta Eisenhower D D 1961 Address to the nation http://www.eisenhower.archives.gov/research/online_documents/farewell_address/Reading_Copy.pdf Hands D W 2001 Reflection without rules: Economic methodology and contemporary science theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. James Roger 1980 Return to Reason: Popper’s Thought in Social Life. Open Books, Wells Somerset. Jarvie Ian C Website http://www.yorku.ca/jarvie/ Jarvie Ian C 1989-90b Philosophy and Its Problems. http://www.yorku.ca/jarvie/online_publications/WWBIII.pdf Jarvie Ian C 1999 Rationality and Situational Logic in Popper’s Scientific Work. http://www.yorku.ca/jarvie/online_publications/VIENNAWD.pdf Jarvie Ian C 2000 The republic of science: The emergence of Popper's social view of science 1935-1945, Ripodi, Klappholz K, Agassi J 1959 Methodological prescriptions in economics. Economica 26:60-74. Lester Jan C 2000 Escape From Leviathan. Macmillan, London. Long J 1998 Lakatos in Hungary. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 28 (2):244-311. McCloskey D N 2006 The discreet virtues of the bourgeoisie: How Europe after 1600 half escaped the ancient condemnation of economic life. History Today 56(9). http://www.historytoday.com/deirdre-mccloskey/discreet-virtues-bourgeoisie McCloskey D N 2010 Bourgeois Dignity: Why Economics Can’t Explain the Modern World. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Michaels Patrick J, Knappenberger Paul C (2016) Lukewarming: The New Climate Science That Changes Everything. Cato Institute, Washington DC. Mirowski P 2002 Introduction to new edition Stanley Wong. The Foundations of Paul Samuelson’s Revealed Preference Theory. http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.401.3046&rep=rep1&type=pdf Morano Marc 2013 The BIG LIE: Sceptics Funded by Big Oil -no, the Alarmists are. http://www.climatedepot.com/2013/07/24/the-big-lie-sceptics-funded-by-big-oil-no-the-alarmists-are/ 30 Dec 2016 Morris P 2016 Obituary — Peter Munz. http://nzbooks.org.nz/2006/obituaries/obituary-peter-munz/ Notturno M A 1984 The Popper/Kuhn debate: Truth and the two faces of relativism. Psychological Medicine 14:273-89. Popper K R 1957 The Poverty of Historicism. Routledge, London. Popper K R 1963. Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London. Popper K R 1972 Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. The Clarendon Press, Oxford. Popper, K. R. 2008. After the Open Society. Shearmur J, Turner P N (eds). Routledge, London. Richards Kenneth 2016 The sun-climate connection. http://notrickszone.com/2016/11/21/the-sun-climate-connection-over-100-scientific-papers-from-2016-link-solar-forcing-to-climate-change/#sthash.RsP42PRx.dpbs Samuelson P A 1964 Theory and realism: A reply. The American Economic Review 54 (5):736-739. Shollenberger Brandon 2016 The Climate Wars: How the Consensus is Enforced. Amazon https://www.amazon.com.au/Climate-Wars-How-Consensus-Enforced-ebook/dp/B01CEZLAM0 Simkin C 1993 Popper’s Views on Natural and Social Science. Brill, New York. Simkin C 1993 The birth of The Open Society: A personal reminiscence. http://www.the-rathouse.com/2008/Simkin-on-Popper.html Simkin C 2001 John and Ursula Hicks – A personal recollection. In K Puttaswamaiah (ed.) John Hicks: His Contributions to Economic Theory and Practice. Transaction Publishers, London.pp5-14. http://www.the-rathouse.com/Colin_Simkin_on_John_Hicks.pdf Smith Barry 1990 Aristotle, Menger, Mises: An essay in the metaphysics of economics”. In Caldwell Bruce (ed) Carl Menger and his Legacy in Economics. Annual supplement to volume 22 History of Political Economy. Duke University Press, London:p.263-288. Smith, Barry 1996 In defense of extreme (fallibilistic) apriorism”. Journal of Libertarian Studies 12:179-192. Smith Huston 1982 Beyond the Post-Modern Mind. Crossroad, New York. Spencer R 2014 http://www.drroyspencer.com/wp-content/uploads/CMIP5-90-models-global-Tsfc-vs-obs-thru-2013.png Vaughn Karen 1994 Austrian Economics in America: The Migration of a Tradition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Weimer W B 1979 Notes on the Methodology of Scientific Research. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale NJ. Wikipedia 2016 The Heartland Institute. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Heartland_Institute 30 December 2016. Wong S 1978, 2nd ed 2006 Foundations of Paul Samuelson's Revealed Preference Theory: A Study by the Method of Rational Reconstruction. Routledge, London. 19