Yugoslav Journal of Operations Research
33 (2023), Number 4, 531-548
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2298/YJOR221115006L
EXPECTED UTILITY FOR PROBABILISTIC PROSPECTS
AND THE COMMON RATIO PROPERTY
Somdeb LAHIRI
Former-Professor PDEU & Adjunct Professor Lok Jagruti (LJ) University
somdeb.lahiri@gmail.com
Received: November 2022 / Accepted: February 2023
Abstract: We prove the existence of an expected utility function for preferences over probabilistic prospects satisfying Strict Monotonicity, Indifference, the Common Ratio
Property, Substitution and Reducibility of Extreme Prospects. The example in [1] that is
inconsistent with the existence of a von Neumann-Morgenstern for preferences over probabilistic prospects, violates the Common Ratio Property. Subsequently, we prove the existence of expected utility functions with piecewise linear Bernoulli utility functions for
preferences that are piece-wise linear. For this case a weaker version of the Indifference
Assumption that is used in the earlier existence theorems is sufficient. We also state analogous results for probabilistic lotteries. We do not require any compound prospects or mixture spaces to prove any of our results. In the third last section of this paper, we “argue”
that the observations related to Allais paradox, do not constitute a violation of expected
utility maximization by individuals, but is a likely manifestation of individuals assigning
(experiment or menu-dependent?) subjective probabilities to events which disagree with
their objective probabilities.
Keywords: Probabilistic prospects, preferences, expected utility, common ratio property,
piece-wise linear, Allais’ paradox, subjective probability, uncertainty aversion
MSC: 91A30, 91B06, 91B08.
1. INTRODUCTION
Consider an individual with initial monetary wealth 𝑤 > 0 and the maximum amount
of money that can be gained by the individual is 𝑀 > 0. Hence the maximum the individual
can lose is w and at any point after participating in an uncertain prospect, the individual’s
wealth is an amount in the closed interval [0, 𝑀 + 𝑤]. Thus, the individual can gain any
amount 𝑥[−𝑤, 𝑀]. Clearly, 0 belongs to the open interval (−𝑤, 𝑀).
Uncertain prospects are of two kinds. In one kind, the gains are state dependent allowing for the assessment of (subjective) probabilities of the states. There is another kind of
uncertain prospect, where the probabilities of the gains are exogenously specified. In reality, an uncertain prospect of the second kind is also a state dependent uncertain prospect
532 S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
for which the assessment of probabilities has already been completed. A formal and rigorous discussion of the underlying calculus of subjective probability can be found in [2].
Allowing for a slight variation of the framework considered in [1], we define a binary
probabilistic prospect, as a pair (𝑥, 𝑝)([−𝑤, 0)(0, 𝑀])(0,1] which denotes that the individual gains a non-zero amount of money x with probability p and with probability 1 – p
the individual gains zero, (i.e., neither gains nor loses any money) after participating in an
uncertain prospect. Negative gains denote losses.
Rubinstein in [1] uses a simplified version of the example used to demonstrate Allais
Paradox to show that it violates the Independence Assumption- the latter being a sufficient
condition for the existence of a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function for preferences
over probabilistic prospects- and, is inconsistent with the existence of any such utility function. In section 7 we argue that the paradoxical behavior can be explained in terms of an
expected utility function for preferences over “state-dependent” prospects if we use subjective probabilities. In any case, the definition of the Independence Assumption that is
referred to in [1], explicitly uses the concept of compound lotteries, that is not defined
anywhere in the paper.
In this paper, we consider finite arrays of binary probabilistic prospects which we refer
to as “probabilistic prospects”. Instead of using Independence we use an assumption, that
we call “Common Ratio Property”. We show that the example in [1] that we referred to
earlier violates the common ratio property. The Common Ratio Property originates in
Allais [3] under the name “Common Ratio Effect” and is also used by Kahneman and
Tversky [4] in the context of the example that is shared by Rubinstein in [1]. It is referred
to and briefly explained in [5]. A thorough discussion of the Common Ratio Effect and its
implications in choice, pricing as well as on happiness is available in [6]. As mentioned in
[5] and [6], almost all non-expected utility theories, including that of Kahneman and
Tversky [4], that explain the so-called Allais Paradox (which we dispute in Section 7) satisfy the Common Ratio Property. Our understanding of this property (which is repeated
after its formal statement is, the following: Given an array of returns from uncertain prospects, what matters in choosing between them are not the absolute value of risks measured
probabilistically, but their relative values. Such an assumption is possible and verifiable,
because we define probabilistic prospects to allow for status quo with positive probability.
Our first major result in this note proves that along with the Common Ratio Property,
four other assumptions that we refer to as Strong Monotonicity, Indifference, Substitution
and Reducibility of Extreme Prospects are together sufficient for the existence of an expected utility function for preferences over probabilistic prospects. All assumptions, except
for Substitution, are defined in terms of binary probabilistic prospects. In fact, it is easy to
see that the “common ratio property”- which is defined in terms of binary probabilistic
prospects - is also a necessary condition for the existence of an expected utility function
for preferences over probabilistic prospects.
In a subsequent section we prove the existence of “expected utility functions with
piecewise linear Bernoulli utility functions” for “preferences that are piece-wise linear”.
For this case a weaker version of the Indifference Assumption that is used in the earlier
existence theorems is sufficient. Section 13.4 in Eeckhoudt et al. [7] is concerned with such
Bernoulli utility functions having two pieces. However, the second and very realistic example (considerably more realistic than the St. Petersburg Paradox) about a hypothetical
individual by the name of Sempronius in section 1.1 of [7], shows that although two pieces
S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
533
are sufficient for explaining “loss aversion” more than two pieces are required for explaining preference for a more diversified portfolio of assets over a less diversified one. Before
moving on to a discussion of the Allais Paradox, we examine the special and very popular
case of probabilistic prospects that allow for gains but no losses. We refer to such probabilistic prospects as probabilistic lotteries. It is easily seen that fewer and a considerably
weaker set of assumptions are sufficient for the representation of preferences over probabilistic lotteries by expected utility. We do not require any compound prospects or mixture
spaces to prove any of our results presented here.
Section 7 is one of several justifications for our attempt here to provide an easily
accessible axiomatic characterization of expected utility maximization in choosing from a
finite set of probabilistic prospects, the latter being the backbone of financial decision making, game theory and decision analysis. A small sample of the wide applicability of expected utility maximization can be found in [8]. Further, scientific theories are meant to be
robust and context specific-not infallible. There could be genuine reasons-such as lack of
information- which prevents exact knowledge of monetary gains and losses arising out of
choices. This could be a valid reason for bounded rationality, but not one that justifies an
elaborate research agenda on non-expected utility theories of monetary gains and losses.
Decision making in the absence of exact information about monetary gains and losses, is
the subject matter of a different research endeavor altogether.
It is worth noting that every intertemporal discounted utility maximization problem
may be viewed as an expected utility maximization problem, with the discount factor representing the probability of being rewarded in the immediately next period. The most general investigation of intertemporal decision making- including the possibility of “hyperbolic discounting”, with a non-empty finite set of available alternatives and in a two-period
model, can be found in [9]. In the paper by Cruz-Rambaud and Sánchez Pérez [10] it has
been pointed out that the worth of a (binary) probabilistic prospect may depend on when
the gains and losses are incurred, i.e. if (𝑥, 𝑝, 𝑡) denotes a binary prospect in which x is the
gain (or loss) that will be realized with probability p, ‘t’ periods later, then then the preference between (𝑥, 𝑝, 𝑡) and (𝑦, 𝑞, 𝑠) may be different from the one between (𝑦, 𝑞, 𝑡) and
(𝑥, 𝑝, 𝑠). In this work we assume that all potential risky gains and losses will be available
at the same time in future. Our analysis here does not have any explicit intertemporal dimension. That however does not mean, that the utility functions based on which expected
utility comparisons over probabilistic lotteries take place, are not amenable to exponential
or hyperbolic discounting. More, generally the utility function itself could be explicitly
indexed by time, i.e., the utility function for gains (or losses) that will be available ‘t’ periods later. Intertemporal applications about uncertain future consumptions using nonexpected utility can be found in [11].
In several respects, our approach and results are significantly different from the huge
literature on the existence of expected utility functions that has been produced till date and
is comprehensively surveyed in [12]. In the first place our approach is completely combinatorial, made possible by a simplifying assumption which we refer to as Indifference,
rather than assuming “Continuity” which is a topological concept and implies Indifference
along with the other assumptions after some routine manipulations. If we agree to refer to
the body of mathematics using real or rational numbers that does not depend on anything
beyond the ordered field property of the real or rational number system as “basic algebra”,
then the methodology used here is precisely that-and no more. In particular, nothing that
we use requires appealing to the least upper bound property (completeness axiom) of the
534 S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
real number system. This allows our results to be accessible to a much larger audience than
is currently the case. In any case, a proof of representability of preferences over alternatives
that are uncertain monetary outcomes, by an expected utility function beginning with Continuity, would have to proceed by proving Indifference. Since the objective of this paper is
to prove the possibility of the desired representation by an expected utility function using
a concept that allows us to ignore mixtures of probabilistic prospects, and not that of
providing technical refinements, we choose to simplify the underlying mathematics without compromising on rigor.
Secondly, the conventional framework in which representability by an expected utility
function is discussed – such as in Appendix A of Chapter 1 in [5] – is based on lotteries or
risky outcomes in the amount of individual wealth. However, as pointed out succinctly in
section 13.4 of [7], individuals treat gains and losses differently, manifested in loss aversion. Thus, instead of considering uncertainty of wealth, we consider uncertainty of gains
(a loss being a “negative gain”). Regardless of whether or not the possibility of representability of preferences over alternatives representing uncertain gains by expected utility of
gains follows from the existing results about representability of preferences over alternatives representing uncertain wealth by expected utility of wealth, we are not aware of any
explicit theorem about the former. Further, even if there is any such result that we are
unaware of, there certainly aren’t any that uses our assumptions, particularly the common
ratio property.
Thirdly, the existing theorems concerning representation of preferences over alternatives representing uncertain monetary outcomes by expected utility either use an assumption called Independence, which would require the preferences to be defined on the much
larger set of finite mixtures of probabilistic prospects (including degenerate ones), as in
[5], or invoke an assumption that permits mixtures of alternatives representing uncertain
monetary outcomes, to be identical-and not merely indifferent-to the alternative representing uncertain monetary outcomes, with the latter probabilities being obtained by applying
the probability multiplication rule, as in Chapter 8 of [13]. This is known in the literature
as “reduction of compound lotteries” (ROCL) axiom. However as noted in thought experiments reported in Ellsberg [14], laboratory experiments reported in [15] and [16], which
are all cited in [17], there is a strong correlation between ambiguity aversion and “violation
of ROCL”, with the intuitive and observed validity of the former implying credibility of
the latter. The question that may be asked at this juncture is the following: Since probabilistic prospects imply the non-existence of ambiguity, ROCL should not be problematic in
our context and hence what is the problem with invoking ROCL? Our answer to this question, would be along the following lines. The desirability of a property should be intrinsic,
and not by default. Consider a “kleptomaniac” whose habit is to steal items sold in supermarkets. Suppose this person relocates to a town or city where there are no supermarkets
and goods are sold in grocery stores and similar stores. Clearly, in such a town, the kleptomaniac does not get to reveal his dubious propensities. However, that does not in any
way indicate that he has been cured of his moral or psychological disorder. He continues
to remain a kleptomaniac regardless of whether he gets the opportunity to give way to his
temptations or not. Otherwise, it would be like saying that “a thief ceases to be a thief (or
becomes innocent), once arrested by the police and put into prison”, which is obviously a
very unlikely statement. Hence, not having assumed ROCL explicitly and not including
mixtures of probabilistic prospects in our domain for preferences, the only way ROCL
S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
535
could be implicit or for that matter conceivable in our framework is if it was implied by
the assumptions, we invoke, which is certainly not the case.
Fourthly, the assumptions and results that we provide in this paper are intended and
meant to be applicable only in the context of alternatives representing uncertain monetary
gains (and losses). We do not consider the most abstract setting where outcomes could be
objects other than money, even if such an extension is possible. With outcomes being other
than monetary gains, the field is wide open for theories and decision support systems other
than ones using expected utility. That there is ample scope for decision making under uncertainty which deviates from expected utility maximization is documented in [18] and
several references therein. We neither intend nor expect the results in this paper to fall in
the category of “one size fits all” theories, even if theorizing of this sort is conceptually
possible in the social sciences.
The section preceding the concluding section of this paper is a modest tribute to
Howard Raiffa, whose seminal work “Decision Analysis: Introductory Lectures on
Choices under Uncertainty”, is the place where decision analysis started “happening”. No
amount of axiomatic analysis can be a substitute for the fact that expected utility maximization is applicable and profusely applied for decision making when a choice has to be
made between alternatives each of which represent uncertain gains. Raiffa [19] is an authoritative account of such applications that are meaningful, possible and additionally goes
on to show how it can be done. Without Raiffa’s intellectual legacy, our work and similar
others, would be an exercise in futility. Fortunately, with the huge literature on decision
analysis based on and inspired by Raiffa [19], that is not the case.
2. THE MATHEMATICAL MODEL
A probabilistic prospect is a finite array 𝐿 = < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > for some positive
integer ‘𝑛’, where for each 𝑗{1, … , 𝑛}, (𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝𝑗 ) is a “binary probabilistic prospect” and
∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 belongs to the left-open, right-closed interval (0,1]. The interpretation of a probabilistic prospect is that at most one of the ‘𝑛’ binary probabilistic prospects that it comprises
of can yield a non-zero gain (loss if the gain is negative) and the probability of getting
neither a gain nor a loss, i.e., zero gain, is 1 − ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 . In other words, the events associated
with non-zero gains/losses and zero gains, are mutually exclusive and exhaustive.
Let ℒ denote the set of all probabilistic prospects and let ℒ 1 denote the strict subset of
all “binary probabilistic prospects”.
The following property of probability prospects is implied by the definition of a finitely
additive probability measure.
Additivity: If for < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > ∈ ℒ it is the case that for some 𝑗, 𝑘{1, … , 𝑛} with
𝑗 < 𝑘, 𝑥𝑗 = 𝑥𝑘 = , then < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑛−1 , 𝑞𝑛−1 ) > where (𝑥ℎ , 𝑝ℎ )
= (𝑦ℎ , 𝑞ℎ ) for all h{1,…, n}\{j} with ℎ < 𝑘, (𝑦𝑗 , 𝑞𝑗 ) = (, 𝑝𝑗 + 𝑝𝑘 ) and (𝑦ℎ , 𝑞ℎ ) =
(𝑥ℎ+1 , 𝑝ℎ+1 ) for all ℎ{1, … , 𝑛}, ℎ ≥ 𝑘 .
Additivity is not an assumption, but a property that is satisfied by the set of probabilistic
prospects ℒ.
In what follows we require the possibility of zero gains with probability one denoted
< (𝑀, 0) >.
For ease of exposition and when there will be no cause for confusion, we will denote
< (𝑥, 𝑝) > ℒ 1 {< (𝑀, 0) >} by (𝑥, 𝑝).
536 S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
We assume that there is a binary relation ≽ on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)} such that for all L1,
L2ℒ {(𝑀, 0)}: L1 ≽ L2 is interpreted as L1 is worth at least as much (satisfaction) as L2.
The symmetric part of ≽ denoted is interpreted as “is worth exactly as much as” and its
asymmetric part denoted ≻ is interpreted as “is worth more than”.
Assumption concerning ≽ on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)}: ≽ on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)} (i.e., the binary relation
“worth paying at least as much as” on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)}) is a preference relation i.e., ≽ is
reflexive, complete (or connected or total) and transitive binary relation on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)}.
The symmetric part of ≽ denoted is interpreted as “is worth exactly as much as” and
its asymmetric part denoted ≻ is interpreted as “is worth more than”.
An expected utility function for ≽ is a function 𝑊: ℒ → ℝ such that there exists a function
𝑢: [−𝑤, 𝑀] ℝ for which the following are satisfied:
(i) 𝑢(0) = 0.
(ii) For all 𝐿 = < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > ℒ, 𝑊(𝐿) = ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ).
(iii) For all 𝐿1 , 𝐿2 ℒ: 𝐿1 ≽ 𝐿2 if and only if W(𝐿1 ) ≥ W(𝐿2 ).
The function u is called a Bernoulli utility function for ≽.
3. ASSUMPTIONS ABOUT PREFERENCES ON 𝓛 {(𝑴, 𝟎)} AND A
PRELIMINARY LEMMA
In what follows we invoke the following assumptions for the preference relation ≽ on
ℒ {(𝑀, 0)}.
Assumption 1 (Strong Monotonicity): For all (𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞) ℒ 1 with 𝑥 𝑦 and 𝑝 𝑞:
(i) [𝑥 > 𝑦, 𝑝 𝑞] implies [(𝑥, 𝑝) ≻ (𝑦, 𝑞)]; (𝑖𝑖) [𝑥 = 𝑦 > 0, 𝑝 > 𝑞] implies [(𝑥, 𝑝) ≻ (𝑦, 𝑞)];
(iii) [ 𝑥 = 𝑦 < 0, 𝑝 > 𝑞] implies [(𝑦, 𝑞) ≻ (𝑥, 𝑝)].
Assumption 1 summarizes the basic and intuitively plausible idea that “gains are preferred to losses”.
Assumption 2 (Indifference): For all 𝑥[−𝑤, 0) (0, 𝑀]: (a) if 𝑥 > 0 then there exists
𝑟(0,1] such that (𝑥, 1)(𝑀, 𝑟); (b) if 𝑥 < 0 then there exists 𝑟(0,1] such that
(𝑥, 1)(−𝑤, 𝑟).
Assumption 2 is of a psychological nature. It says that the security associated with a
modest sure gain is overall equivalent to the ecstasy experienced with a sudden and unexpectedly high windfall profits. The nagging insecurity associated with a modest sure loss
is overall equivalent to unexpected bankruptcy.
After all, some do make a living by taking risks while some prefer a stable income and
both have reasons to feel happy and sad.
Assumption 3 (Common Ratio Property): For all (𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞)ℒ 1 and 𝑡(0,1]: [(𝑥, 𝑝) ≽
(𝑦, 𝑞)] implies [(𝑥, 𝑡𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑡𝑞)].
Assumption 3 says that given an array of returns from uncertain prospects, what matters
in choosing between them are not the absolute value of risks measured probabilistically,
but their relative values. Such an assumption is possible and makes sense, because we define probabilistic prospects to allow for status quo with positive probability.
Note 1: It is easy to see that Assumption 2, i.e., Indifference, is a consequence of Assumption 1 (Strong Monotonicity) and this very weak version of continuity.
S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
537
Weak Continuity: For all (𝑥, 𝑝)ℒ 1: (a) (𝑀, 1) ≻ (𝑥, 𝑝) with 𝑥 > 0 implies that there exists
[0,1] such that (𝑀, ) ∼ (𝑥, 𝑝); and (b) (𝑥, 𝑝) ≻ (−𝑤, 1) with 𝑥 < 0 implies that there exists
[0,1] such that (−𝑤, ) ∼ (𝑥, 𝑝).
Note 2: The “common ratio property” in [5] says that preferences are independent of
changes in the magnitude of the probabilities so long as monetary gains and the “ratio”
of probabilities remain unchanged.
Note 3: As a consequence of Assumption 1, it follows that given any 𝐿ℒ if
{𝑥[−𝑤, 𝑀]| 𝐿 (𝑥, 1)} , then it must be a singleton whose unique member 𝑐𝐿 is called
the certainty equivalent of L.
Lemma 1: If ≽ satisfies Assumptions 1, 2 and 3, then there exists a strictly increasing
function 𝑣: [−𝑤, 𝑀] ℝ satisfying 𝑣(−𝑤) = −1 and 𝑣(𝑀) = 1, such that for all
(𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞) ℒ 1 : [(𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞)] if and only if [𝑝𝑣(𝑥) ≥ 𝑞𝑣(𝑦)].
Proof: By Assumptions 1(ii) and 2 for all 𝑥([−𝑤, 0)(0, 𝑀]), there exists a unique real
number 𝑣(𝑥) such that: (a) if 𝑥 > 0, then 𝑣(𝑥) > 0, (𝑥, 1) (𝑀, 𝑣(𝑥)) and 𝑣(𝑀) = 1; (b) if
𝑥 < 0, then 𝑣(𝑥) < 0, (𝑥, 1) (−𝑤, −𝑣(𝑥)), 𝑣(−𝑤) = −1. Let 𝑣(0) = 0.
For all 𝑝, 𝑞(0,1] with 𝑝 > 𝑞, we have by Assumption 1(ii), (𝑀, 𝑝) ≻ (𝑀, 𝑞) and by
Assumption 1(iii), (−𝑤, 𝑞) ≻ (−𝑤, 𝑝) for all 𝑝(0,1].
For all 𝑝, 𝑞(0,1], we have by Assumption 1(i), (𝑀, 𝑝) ≻ (−𝑤, 𝑞).
Clearly 𝑣 is strictly increasing, since:
(a) If 𝑥 > 𝑦 > 0, then (𝑥, 1) (𝑀, 𝑣(𝑥)) and (𝑦, 1) (𝑀, 𝑣(𝑦)) with 𝑣(𝑥), 𝑣(𝑦) > 0 and
by Assumption 1(i) (𝑥, 1) ≻ (𝑦, 1), so that (𝑀, 𝑣(𝑥)) ≻ (𝑀, 𝑣(𝑦)) from which and by
Assumption 1(ii), 𝑣(𝑥) > 𝑣(𝑦).
(b) If 0 > 𝑥 > 𝑦 > 0, then (𝑥, 1) (−𝑤, −𝑣(𝑥)) and (𝑦, 1) (−𝑤, −𝑣(𝑦)) with
𝑣(𝑥), 𝑣(𝑦) < 0 and by Assumption 1(i) (𝑥, 1) ≻ (𝑦, 1), so that (−𝑤, −𝑣(𝑥)) ≻ (−𝑤, −𝑣(𝑦))
from which and by Assumption 1(iii), −𝑣(𝑥) < −𝑣(𝑦), i.e. 𝑣(𝑥) > 𝑣(𝑦).
(c) If 𝑥 > 0 > 𝑦, then by the definition of 𝑣, 𝑣(𝑥) > 0 > 𝑣(𝑦).
Consider the function 𝑣: [−𝑤, 𝑀] ℝ defined above.
Thus 𝑣(𝑥) > 0 for all 𝑥(0, 𝑀], 𝑣(𝑥) < 0 for all 𝑥[−𝑤, 0) and 𝑣(0) = 0.
By Assumption 3, for all 𝑝(0,1] and 𝑥(0, 𝑀]: (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑀, 𝑝𝑣(𝑥)) as well as
(𝑀, 𝑝𝑣(𝑥)) ≽ (𝑥, 𝑝); and for all 𝑝(0,1] and 𝑥[−𝑤, 0): (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (−𝑤, −𝑝𝑣(𝑥)) as well as
(−𝑤, −𝑝𝑣(𝑥)) ≽ (𝑥, 𝑝).
Thus, for all 𝑝(0,1] and 𝑥(0, 𝑀]: (𝑥, 𝑝) ∼ (𝑀, 𝑝𝑣(𝑥)); and for all 𝑝(0,1] and
𝑥[−𝑤, 0): (𝑥, 𝑝) ∼ (−𝑤, −𝑝𝑣(𝑥)).
Hence, for all (𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞)ℒ 1 :
(a) If 𝑥, 𝑦(0, 𝑀], (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if (𝑀, 𝑝𝑣(𝑥)) ≽ (𝑀, 𝑞𝑣(𝑦)).
(b) If 𝑥(0, 𝑀] and 𝑦(0, −𝑤] then by Assumption 1(i) (𝑥, 𝑝) ≻ (𝑦, 𝑞) and 𝑝𝑣(𝑥) > 0 >
𝑞𝑣(𝑦).
(c) If 𝑥, 𝑦(0, −𝑤], (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if (−𝑤, −𝑝𝑣(𝑥)) ≽ (−𝑤, −𝑞𝑣(𝑦)).
Thus, for all (𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞)ℒ 1 :
(a1) By Assumption 1(iii), if 𝑥, 𝑦(0, 𝑀], (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if 𝑝𝑣(𝑥) ≥ 𝑞𝑣(𝑦).
(b1) By Assumption 1 (i), if 𝑥(0, 𝑀] and 𝑦(0, −𝑤], (𝑥, 𝑝) ≻ (𝑦, 𝑞) and 𝑝𝑣(𝑥) > 0 >
𝑞𝑣(𝑦).
(c1) By Assumption 1 (iv) If 𝑥, 𝑦(0, −𝑤], (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if −𝑝𝑣(𝑥) −
𝑞𝑣(𝑦).
538 S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
Clearly, (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if 𝑝𝑣(𝑥) ≥ 𝑞𝑣(𝑦). Q.E.D.
Note 4: The version of the paradox in [1] violates the requirement (that follows from
1
4
Assumption 3) which says that: if (𝑥, 1) ≻ (𝑦, 5), then multiplying the probabilities by , we
1
4
1
should get (𝑥, 4) ≽ (𝑦, 5).
Further, note that for the main existence result in this section, Assumption 3 holds on
ℒ as well, i.e., for all < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) >, < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) >ℒ: if
< (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > ≽ < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) > and t(0,1], then < (𝑥1 , 𝑡𝑝1 ), … ,
(𝑥𝑛 , 𝑡𝑝𝑛 ) > ≽< (𝑦1 , 𝑡𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑡𝑞𝑚 ) >. However, we will not be requiring Assumption 3
in its full generality; its use restricted to ℒ 1 , as has already been done in Lemma 1, is
enough for our purpose.
We will require the following additional assumptions for the main result in this section.
Assumption 4 (Substitution): If < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) >, < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑛 , 𝑞𝑛 ) > ℒ,
< (z, r) > ℒ 1 , < (𝑧, 𝑟) > < (𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝𝑗 ) > for some j{1,…,n} and 𝑟 𝑝𝑗 , then < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … ,
(𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑛 , 𝑞𝑛 ) > where (𝑥𝑘 , 𝑝𝑘 )=(𝑦𝑘 , 𝑞𝑘 ) for all 𝑘{1, … , 𝑛}\{𝑗} and
(𝑦𝑗 , 𝑞𝑗 ) = (z,r).
Since preferences are defined over prospects – binary or otherwise – in order to avoid
misunderstanding, in the statement of Substitution we have purposely written: “… <
(𝑧, 𝑟) > ℒ 1 , < (𝑧, 𝑟) > < (𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝𝑗 ) > ⋯”, even though we have agreed to identify and
denote binary prospects such < (𝑧, 𝑟) > by (𝑧, 𝑟). Substitution does not require a
probabilistic prospect to be a component of another probabilistic prospect. It just requires
extracting (𝑧, 𝑟) from < (𝑧, 𝑟) > and replacing (𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝𝑗 ) by (𝑧, 𝑟).
Note that instead of 𝑟 𝑝𝑗 we could have used the less restrictive criteria ∑𝑛𝑘=1 𝑝𝑘 − 𝑝𝑗
+ 𝑟(0,1] in Assumption 4 and continue our analysis without hindrance.
Let us agree to refer to probabilistic prospects of the form < (𝑀, 𝑝), (−𝑤, 𝑞) > as
extreme prospects.
Assumption 5 (Reducibility of Extreme Prospects): (i) For all 𝑝(0,1]: (𝑀, 𝑝) ≻ (𝑀, 0)
and (𝑀, 0) ≻ (−𝑤, 𝑝). (ii) There exists , > 0, satisfying the following condition: For all
𝑝, 𝑞(0,1]:
(a) < (𝑀, 𝑝), (−𝑤, 𝑞) > (𝑀, 𝑝 −
(b) < (𝑀, 𝑝), (−𝑤, 𝑞) > (−𝑤, 𝑞
𝑞) if 𝑝 − 𝑞 ≥ 0;
− 𝑝) if 𝑝 − 𝑞 <
0.
4. THE MAIN RESULT
We now present the main result of this paper.
Proposition 1: If ≽ on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)} satisfies Assumptions 1 to 5, then there exists an
expected utility function for ≽.
Proof: By Lemma 1 we know that there exists a function 𝑣: [−𝑤, 𝑀] [−1,1] satisfying the
following properties:
(1) 𝑣(𝑀) = 1, 𝑣(0) = 0, 𝑣(−𝑤) = −1, 𝑣(𝑥) > 0 for all 𝑥[𝑀, 0) and 𝑣(𝑥) < 0 for all
𝑥[−𝑤, 0).
(2) For all (𝑥, 𝑝) ℒ 1 : (i) 𝑥 > 0 implies (𝑥, 𝑝) (𝑀, 𝑝𝑣(𝑥)); (ii) 𝑥 < 0 implies
(𝑥, 𝑝) (−𝑤, −𝑝𝑣(𝑥)).
(3) For all (𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞) ℒ 1 : (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if 𝑝𝑣(𝑥) ≥ 𝑞𝑣(𝑦).
S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
539
Let , > 0 be the given real numbers in Assumption 5. Let 𝑢: [−𝑤, 𝑀] ℝ be defined
as 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑣(𝑥) for all 𝑥[0, 𝑀] and 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑣(𝑥) for all 𝑥[−𝑤, 0).
Thus:
(1*) 𝑢(𝑀) = , 𝑢(0) = 0, 𝑢(−𝑤) = −, 𝑢(𝑥) > 0 for all 𝑥[𝑀, 0) and 𝑢(𝑥) < 0 for all
𝑥[−𝑤, 0).
(2*) For all (𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞)ℒ 1 : (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if 𝑝𝑢(𝑥) ≥ 𝑞𝑢(𝑦).
Let < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > ℒ.
Note that it is not possible for both ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) as well as ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) to be
equal to zero.
It is easy to see that ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) = ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 )- ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ).
By repeated application of Assumption 4 and (2) above we get that
< (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > < (𝑦1 , 𝑝1 𝑣(𝑥1 )), … , (𝑦𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 𝑣(𝑥𝑛 )) > where for all 𝑦𝑗 = 𝑀 if 𝑥𝑗 > 0
and 𝑦𝑗 = −𝑤 if 𝑥𝑗 < 0.
Thus:
If ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) = 0, then < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > (M, ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 )) = (M,
∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 )).
If ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) = 0, then < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > (−𝑤, − ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 )) = (−𝑤,
− ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 )).
If ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) 0 and ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) 0, then
< (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > < (𝑀, ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 )), (−𝑤, − ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 )) >.
By Assumptions 5 (ii), if ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) 0 and ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) 0, then:
(i) < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > <(M, ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) − ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 )> if
∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} pj v(xj )- ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) ≥ 0 ;
(ii) < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > < (−𝑤, ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) − ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 )) > if
∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) − ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) < 0.
The above can be written as follows.
If ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) 0 and ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) 0, then:
(i) < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > < (𝑀, ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) − ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) > if
∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) ≥ 0;
(ii) < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > < (−𝑤, ∑{𝑗|𝑥 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) − ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ))> if
𝑗
∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) < 0
Recall that for < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > ℒ, ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) = ∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 ≥0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) −
∑{𝑗|𝑥𝑗 < 0} 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ).
Thus, given < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) >, < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) > ℒ:
(a) It follows from Lemma 1, that: if ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) 0 and ∑𝑚
𝑗=1 𝑞𝑗 𝑣(𝑦𝑗 ) 0 then:
< (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) >≽< (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) > if and only if ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) ≥
∑𝑚
𝑗=1 𝑞𝑗 𝑢(𝑦𝑗 ).
(b) It follows from Lemma 1 and Assumption 5 (i), that if ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) 0 and
𝑚
∑𝑗=1 𝑞𝑗 𝑣(𝑦𝑗 ) = 0
then:
(i)
< (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > ≻< (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) >
if
∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) > 0 = ∑𝑚
(𝑦
),
(𝑦
)
𝑞
𝑢(𝑦
)
;
and
(ii)
<
,
𝑞
…
,
,
𝑞
>
≻<
(𝑥
,
𝑝
),
…
,
(𝑥
,
𝑝
)
>
𝑗
1 1
𝑚 𝑚
1 1
𝑛 𝑛
𝑗=1 𝑗
if ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) < 0 = ∑𝑚
𝑗=1 𝑞𝑗 𝑢(𝑦𝑗 ).
540 S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
(c) It follows from reflexivity and transitivity of ≽ (i), that if ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑣(𝑥𝑗 ) = 0 =
then: < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > (𝑀, 0) (𝑀, 0) < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) > and
hence < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) >.
For 𝐿ℒ, let 𝑊(𝐿) = ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) if 𝐿 = < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) >.
Thus for < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) >, < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) > ℒ,
∑𝑚
𝑗=1 𝑞𝑗 𝑣(𝑦𝑗 ),
< (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) >≽ < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) >
if and only if W(< (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) >) ≥ W(< (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) >) = 0. Q.E.D.
5. PIECEWISE LINEAR PREFERENCES
Of particular interest in decision theory (see section 13.4 of [7]) are preference relations
on ℒ {(M,0)} satisfying the following “piece-wise linearity” property.
A preference relation ≽ on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)} is said to be piece-wise linear if for some
positive integer ‘𝑛’ with 𝑛 ≥ 2, there exists a non-empty finite set of real numbers {xj| 𝑗 =
0, 1, … , 𝑛} including ‘0’ and satisfying −𝑤 = 𝑥0 < 𝑥1 < ⋯ < 𝑥𝑛 = 𝑀, such that for all
𝑝(0,1) and 𝑗{0, … , 𝑛 − 1}: (a) If 𝑥𝑗 0 𝑥𝑗+1 then (𝑝𝑥𝑗 + (1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 , 1) < (𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝),
(𝑥𝑗+1 , 1 − 𝑝) >; (b) If 𝑥𝑗 = 0 𝑥𝑗+1 then (𝑝𝑥𝑗 + (1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 , 1) (𝑥𝑗+1 , 1 − 𝑝); and (c) If
𝑥𝑗 0 = 𝑥𝑗+1 then (𝑝𝑥𝑗 + (1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 , 1) (𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝).
In this case ≽ is said to be a piece-wise linear preference relation on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)}
generated by {xj| 𝑗 = 0, 1, … , 𝑛}.
In what follows, we denote the set {𝑥𝑗 | 𝑗 = 0, 1, … , 𝑛} by 𝑋.
A piece-wise linear preference relation ≽ on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)} generated by 𝑋 is said to
satisfy:
Assumption 2' (Indifference): For all 𝑥𝑋: (a) if 𝑥 > 0 then there exists 𝑟(0,1] such that
(𝑥, 1) (𝑀, 𝑟); (b) if 𝑥 < 0 then there exists 𝑟(0,1] such that (𝑥, 1) (−𝑤, 𝑟).
Assumption 2' is considerably weaker than Assumption 2.
The proof of the following lemma is almost exactly the same as the proof of Lemma 1.
Lemma 2: If ≽ is a piece-wise linear preference relation on ℒ {(M,0)} generated by 𝑋
that satisfies Assumptions 1, 2' and 3, then there exists a set of ‘n’ distinct real numbers
{𝑢(𝑥𝑗 )| 𝑗 = 0, 1, … , 𝑛} satisfying 𝑢(𝑥𝑗+1 ) > 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) for 𝑗{0, … , 𝑛 − 1} with 𝑢(−𝑤) =
−1, 𝑢(0) = 0 and 𝑢(𝑀) = 1, such that for all (𝑥, 𝑝)(([−𝑤, 0)(0, 𝑀])𝑋) (0,1]: (a)
(𝑥, 𝑝) (𝑀, 𝑝𝑢(𝑥)) if 𝑥 > 0; (b) (𝑥, 𝑝) (−𝑤, −𝑝𝑢(𝑥)) if 𝑥 < 0; and (c) for all
(𝑦, 𝑞) (([−𝑤, 0)(0, 𝑀])𝑋) (0,1], (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ ((𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if 𝑝𝑢(𝑥) ≥ 𝑞𝑢(𝑦).
An immediate corollary of Lemma 2 and Substitution (Assumption 4) is the following,
whose proof includes very easy arguments analogous to the ones used in Proposition 1.
Corollary of Lemma 2: If ≽ is a piece-wise linear preference relation on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)}
generated by 𝑋 that satisfies Assumptions 1, 2', 3, 4 and 5 then there exists a strictly
increasing function 𝑢: [−𝑤, 𝑀] ℝ with 𝑢(−𝑤) = −1, 𝑢(0) = 0 and 𝑢(𝑀) = 1, such that for
all 𝑗{0, … , 𝑛 − 1}, 𝑝[0,1], 𝑥 = 𝑝𝑥𝑗 + (1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 , 𝑥 0: 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑝𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) + (1 − 𝑝)𝑢(𝑥𝑗+1 ) and
(a) If 0 < 𝑥𝑗 < 𝑥𝑗+1 and 𝑝(0,1), then (𝑥, 1) (𝑀, 𝑝𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) + (1 − 𝑝)𝑢(𝑥𝑗+1 )) = (𝑀, 𝑢(𝑥));
(b) If 0 > 𝑥𝑗 > 𝑥𝑗+1 and 𝑝(0,1), then (𝑥, 1) (−𝑤,−𝑝𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) − (1 − 𝑝)𝑢(𝑥𝑗+1 )) =
(−𝑤, −𝑢(𝑥));
(c) If 0 > 𝑥𝑗+1 and 𝑝𝑥𝑗 = 0 then (𝑥, 1) = ((1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 , 1) (𝑥𝑗+1 , 1 − 𝑝) (−𝑤, −(1 −
𝑝)𝑢(𝑥𝑗+1 )) = (−𝑤, − 𝑢(𝑥));
S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
541
(d) If 0 > 𝑥𝑗 , and (1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 = 0 then (𝑥, 1) = (𝑝𝑥𝑗 , 1) (𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝) (−𝑤, −𝑝𝑢(𝑥𝑗 )) =
(−𝑤, −𝑢(𝑥));
(e) If xj+1 > 0 and 𝑝𝑥𝑗 = 0, then (𝑥, 1) = ((1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 , 1) (𝑥𝑗+1 , 1 − 𝑝) (𝑀, (1 −
𝑝)𝑢(𝑥𝑗+1 )) = (𝑀, 𝑢(𝑥)); and
(f) If 𝑥𝑗 > 0 and (1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 = 0, then (𝑥, 1) (𝑝𝑥𝑗 , 1) (𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝)(𝑀, 𝑝𝑢(𝑥𝑗 )) = (𝑀, 𝑢(𝑥)).
However, with the same assumptions, we can prove the following stronger result.
Lemma 3: If ≽ is a piece-wise linear preference relation on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)} generated by 𝑋
that satisfies Assumptions 1, 2', 3, 4 and 5 then there exists a strictly increasing function
𝑢: [−𝑤, 𝑀]ℝ with 𝑢(−𝑤) = −1, 𝑢(0) = 0 and 𝑢(𝑀) = 1 satisfying the following
properties:
(i) For all 𝑗 {0, … , 𝑛 − 1}, 𝑝 [0,1], 𝑥 = 𝑝𝑥𝑗 + (1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 , 𝑥 0: 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑝𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) +
(1 − 𝑝)𝑢(𝑥𝑗+1 ).
(ii) For all 𝑝(0,1] and 𝑥(0, 𝑀]: (𝑥, 𝑝) ∼ (𝑀, 𝑝𝑢(𝑥)); and for all 𝑝(0,1] and
𝑥[−𝑤, 0): (𝑥, 𝑝) ∼ (−𝑤, −𝑝𝑢(𝑥)).
(iii) For all (𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞) ℒ 1 : (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if 𝑝𝑢(𝑥) ≥ 𝑞𝑢(𝑦).
Equipped with Lemma 3, we are in a position to prove the following proposition.
Proposition 2: If ≽ is a piece-wise linear preference relation on ℒ {(𝑀, 0)} generated by
𝑋 that satisfies Assumptions 1, 2', 3, 4 and 5 then there exists an expected utility function
for the preference relation, and the Bernoulli utility function u for any such expected utility
function is piece-wise linear, i.e., for all 𝑗{0, … , 𝑛} and 𝑝[0,1], if 𝑥 = 𝑝𝑥𝑗 + (1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 ,
then 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑝𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) + (1 − 𝑝)𝑢(𝑥𝑗+1 ).
6. THE SPECIAL CASE OF PROBABILISTIC LOTTERIES
In this section we study the possibility of representing preference relations over an
important special case of probabilistic prospects that do not allow for the possibility of
losses. We call such prospects, probabilistic lotteries.
A binary probabilistic lottery is a pair (𝑥, 𝑝)(0, 𝑀]) (0,1] which denotes that the
individual gains a positive amount of money 𝑥 with probability 𝑝 and with probability
1 − 𝑝 the individual gains zero, (i.e., neither gains nor loses any money) after participating
in an uncertain prospect.
A probabilistic lottery is a finite array 𝐿 = < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > for some positive
integer ‘𝑛’, where for each 𝑗{1, … , 𝑛}, (𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝𝑗 ) is a “binary probabilistic lottery” and ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗
belongs to the left-open, right-closed interval (0,1].
Let ℒ + denote the set of all probabilistic lotteries and identifying probabilistic lotteries
of the form < (𝑥, 𝑝) > with its only binary probabilistic lottery in the array, let ℒ 1+ denote
the strict subset of all “binary probabilistic prospects”.
We assume that there is a binary relation ≽ on ℒ + whose symmetric part of is denoted
by and whose asymmetric part is denoted by ≻.
An expected utility function for ≽ is a function 𝑉: ℒ + ℝ such there exists a function
𝑢: [0, 𝑀] ℝ for which the following are satisfied:
(i) 𝑢(0) = 0.
(ii) For all 𝐿 = < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > ℒ + , 𝑉(𝐿) = ∑𝑛𝑗=1 𝑝𝑗 𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ).
(iii) For all 𝐿1 , 𝐿2 ℒ + : 𝐿1 ≽ 𝐿2 if and only if (𝑊(𝐿1 ) ≥ W(𝐿2 ).
As before the function u is called a Bernoulli utility function for ≽.
542 S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
Assumption 6 (Restricted Strong Monotonicity): For all (𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞) ℒ 1+ : 𝑥 ≥ 𝑦, 𝑝 ≥ 𝑞
with at least one strict inequality implies (𝑥, 𝑝) ≻ (𝑦, 𝑞).
Assumption 7 (Restricted Indifference): For all 𝑥(0, 𝑀], there exists 𝑟(0,1] such that
(𝑥, 1) (𝑀, 𝑟).
Assumption 8 (Common Ratio Property): For all (𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞) ℒ 1+ and 𝑡(0,1]: (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽
(𝑦, 𝑞) implies (𝑥, 𝑡𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑡𝑞).
The following lemma and its proof are similar to that of lemma 1 and its proof.
Lemma 4: If ≽ satisfies Assumptions 6, 7 and 8, then there exists a strictly increasing
function 𝑣: [0, 𝑀] [0, 1] satisfying 𝑣(0) = 0 and 𝑣(𝑀) = 1 such that for all
(𝑥, 𝑝), (𝑦, 𝑞)ℒ 1+ : (𝑥, 𝑝) ≽ (𝑦, 𝑞) if and only if 𝑝𝑣(𝑥) ≥ 𝑞𝑣(𝑦).
We now invoke the following additional assumption.
Assumption 9 (Restricted Substitution): If < (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) >, < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … ,
(𝑦𝑛 , 𝑞𝑛 ) > ℒ + , < (𝑧, 𝑟) > ℒ 1+ , < (𝑧, 𝑟) > <(𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝𝑗 )> for some 𝑗{1, … , 𝑛} and 𝑟 pj, then
< (𝑥1 , 𝑝1 ), … , (𝑥𝑛 , 𝑝𝑛 ) > < (𝑦1 , 𝑞1 ), … , (𝑦𝑚 , 𝑞𝑚 ) > where (xk, pk) = (yk, qk) for all
𝑘{1, … , 𝑛}\{𝑗} and (𝑦𝑗 , 𝑞𝑗 ) = (𝑧, 𝑟).
The following proposition is similar to proposition 1 and its proof is much easier than
the proof of proposition 1
Proposition 3: If ≽ on ℒ + satisfies Assumptions 6 to 9, then there exists an expected utility
function for ≽.
The analogous version of Assumption 5, i.e., Reducibility of Extreme Prospects, is not
required to prove the existence of an expected utility function for the preference relation ≽
on ℒ + .
As in the previous section, say that a preference relation ≽ on ℒ + is piece-wise linear
if or some positive integer ‘𝑛’ with 𝑛 ≥ 2, there exists a non-empty finite set of real numbers {xj | 𝑗 = 0, 1, … , 𝑛} including ‘0’ and satisfying 0 = x0 < x1 <… < xn = 𝑀, such that for
all 𝑝(0,1):
(a) if 𝑗{1, … , 𝑛 − 1} then (pxj + (1 – p)xj+1,1) <(𝑥𝑗 , 𝑝), (𝑥𝑗+1 , 1 − 𝑝)>;
(b) (𝑝𝑥0 + (1 − 𝑝) 𝑥1 , 1) (𝑥1 , 1 − 𝑝).
In this case ≽ is said to be a piece-wise linear preference relation on ℒ + generated
by {𝑥𝑗 | 𝑗 = 0, 1, … , 𝑛}.
A piece-wise linear preference relation ≽ on ℒ + generated by {𝑥𝑗 | 𝑗 = 0, 1, … , 𝑛} is said
to satisfy:
Assumption 7' (Restricted Indifference): For all 𝑗{1, … , 𝑛}, there exists 𝑟𝑗 (0,1] such
that (𝑥𝑗 , 1) (𝑀, 𝑟𝑗 ).
As before Assumption 7' is considerably weaker than Assumption 7.
Following a path similar to the one traversed in the previous section, we can state and
prove the following proposition.
Proposition 4: If ≽ is a piece-wise linear preference relation on ℒ + generated by {𝑥𝑗 | 𝑗 =
0, 1, … , 𝑛} that satisfies Assumptions 6, 7', 8 and 9 then there exists an expected utility
function for the preference relation, and the Bernoulli utility function u for any such
expected utility function is piece-wise linear, i.e., for all 𝑗{0, … , 𝑛} and 𝑝[0,1], if 𝑥 =
𝑝𝑥𝑗 + (1 − 𝑝)𝑥𝑗+1 , then 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑝𝑢(𝑥𝑗 ) + (1 − 𝑝)𝑢(𝑥𝑗+1 ).
S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
543
7. ALLAIS’ PARADOX REPRESENTS DISAGREEMENT OVER
PROBABILITIES
In this section we discuss an issue that became a compelling thought for me while
reading [1]. Our understanding and interpretation of the issue reinforces the reasons for
continuing with conventional framework, (i.e., that of expected utility maximization) in
which problem of choices from among a finite set of probabilistic lotteries – particularly
the famous Allais paradox in [3] – is formulated.
The simplified version of the Allais paradox that Rubinstein considers and which goes
as follows:
Experiment 1:
Choose between 𝐿1 = ($4000, 0.8) and 𝐿2 = ($3000, 1).
Experiment 2:
Choose between 𝐿3 = ($4000, 0.2) and 𝐿4 = ($3000, 0.25).
If (Rubinstein’s version of) Allais Paradox is to be believed then in the first Experiment
most individuals chose 𝐿2 and in the second Experiment most individuals chose 𝐿3 .
On the basis of this observation, we are told that if the individuals were expected utility
maximizers with the Bernoulli utility function for monetary prizes being 𝑢 and satisfying
𝑢(0) = 0, then 𝑢(3000) > 0.8𝑢(4000) for Experiment 1 should imply 0.25 𝑢(3000) >
0.2𝑢(4000) implying that contrary to observation L4 should be chosen and not L3.
Hence, we are expected to conclude that individuals may not be behaving as though
they are expected utility maximizers.
It has been known for a long time-at least since Friedman and Savage [20] – that
decision theory is concerned with as if behavior of individuals which may not necessarily
reflect conscious behavior. The way Rubinstein in [1] defines (probabilistic) lotteries and
the way the Experiments above are framed, imposes on the individuals some exogenously
given probabilities, with which they are expected to do the expected utility calculationsconsciously or unconsciously – and make choices. Hence, it is not unrealistic to conclude
from the above observations that if individuals are faced with binary probabilistic lotteries,
then the individuals may not be maximizing expected utility using the exogenously given
probabilities, and no more than that. There is no guarantee, that choosers don’t impute
(antagonistic?) motives to those offering choices and use other probabilities for EU
maximization. It does not mean that individuals may use probabilities different from the
ones that are exogenously given for the purpose of expected utility maximization; nor and
more importantly does it mean that individuals “do not” maximize expected utility if a
money prize is associated with an uncertain event and the individual is allowed to
conjecture his/her own-possibly experiment or “menu” dependent-subjective probability
of the event, i.e., the assigned subjective probabilities may depend on the set of
probabilistic prospects that the individual has to choose from. In fact, most probabilistic
lotteries in the real-world are such state dependent lotteries and not probabilistic lotteries.
What would be the implication of Allais’ paradox if instead of choosing from
probabilistic lotteries individuals were required to choose from state dependent lotteries?
Let 𝑋 be the set of all possible outcomes of an experiment any non-empty subset of
which is called an event and denoted by E.
A “simple state dependent lottery” (SSDL) is a pair (𝑥, 𝐸) where x is a non-negative
real number denoting the money prize an individual receives if the event 𝐸 occurs and
nothing if 𝐸 does not occur.
544 S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
Consider an urn containing 55 black balls, 25 red balls and 20 white balls all of which
are evenly distributed in the urn in such a way that if the experiment of “picking a ball
randomly from the urn, noting its color and then returning the ball to the urn” was repeated
a large number of times then relative frequency with which each ball-regardless of its colorwould be chosen, is approximately 1%.
The above information is shared with all individuals who participate in the following
two experiments.
Experiment 3:
Choose between 𝐿1 = ($4000, 𝐸) and 𝐿2 = ($3000, 𝑋), where 𝐸 is the event that the color
of a ball randomly chosen from the urn is either black or red but not white.
Experiment 4:
Choose between 𝐿3 = ($4000, 𝐸1 ) and 𝐿4 = ($3000, 𝐸2 ), where 𝐸1 is the event that the
color of a ball randomly chosen from the urn is white and 𝐸2 is the event that the color of
a ball randomly chosen from the urn is red.
In what follows we will – in keeping with existing tradition introduced in Section 2 of
this paper – refer to the concept of approximate relative frequency of the occurrence of an
event in a very large number of trials of the experiment in which the event could occur
simply as objective probability.
What anyone who participates in the two experiments of “picking a ball randomly from
the urn, noting its color and then returning the ball to the urn” knows are the following:
(1) the objective probability of E is 80%.
(2) the objective probability of E1 is 20%.
(3) the objective probability of E2 is 25%.
(4) each participant in the experiment knows that he/she will get exactly one attempt at
each experiment and definitely not a large number of attempts in any.
Given this information which is shared with all the participants, we need to weigh it
against the other piece of information which is almost universally known but rarely
invoked by any decision theory: many individuals consider themselves unfortunate
(unlucky), compared to a small number of individuals who consider themselves fortunate
(lucky).
From the point of view of the chooser, 𝐸 = Lucky and 𝐸 𝑐 = Unlucky.
Consider Experiment 3:
Choose between 𝐿1 = ($4000, 𝐸) and 𝐿2 = ($3000, 𝑋), where objective probability of 𝐸
is 80%.
Given that in Experiment 3, if 𝐿1 is chosen, then the occurrence of event 𝐸 with an
objective probability of 80%, yields a prize of $4000/–, whereas if 𝐿2 is chosen, then one
gets $3000/– for sure, is it very strange to expect that for a large number of such individuals
the “subjective probability of 𝐸”, in the sense of Ramsey [21] and de Finetti [22], is slightly
less than 3/4 given that the “objective probability of 𝐸” is 4/5? In other words, is it very
strange to expect that for a large number of such individuals the “subjective odds against
𝐸” are slightly greater than 1/3 given that the “odds against 𝐸 based on projected relative
frequencies” is 1/4?
The implication of the above is that for an individual who measures satisfaction in
money units and is also “pessimistic”, the latter being a very likely observation, if
1
1−𝑃3 (𝐸)
𝑃4 (𝐸2 )−𝑃4 (𝐸1 )
< <
= subjective odds against 𝐸 (where for 𝑖 = 1, 2: 𝑃𝑖 (𝑒𝑣𝑒𝑛𝑡) is the
𝑃4 (𝐸1 )
3
𝑃3 (𝐸)
subjective probability the individual assigns to the event in Experiment i), then
S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
545
maximization of “expected monetary value”- which is expected utility maximization for
risk neutral individuals-is consistent with the observations related to Allais’ paradox.
Note that any 𝑃4 (𝐸1 ), 𝑃4 (𝐸2 )(0,1) which is a constant multiple of the relative
frequencies projected for E1 and E2 satisfy the property that the percentage difference
between 𝑃4 (𝐸2 )and 𝑃4 (𝐸1 )is less than the percentage difference between the money prizes
associated with 𝐸2 and 𝐸1 respectively. In such a situation, the only additional assumption
we require most individuals to satisfy in order for their behavior to be consistent with
“maximization of expected monetary value” is that given a choice between receiving
$3000 for sure and a lottery that gives a money prize of $4000 with some amount of
uncertainty, the individuals would assign a subjective probability to the uncertain event 𝐸
that is less than 3/4, which is (not significantly) less than the projected relative frequency,
i.e. 4/5.
What we intend to say above is that the expected utility maximization problem that is
“implicitly” solved by the decision maker depends on subjective probabilities which reflect
the decision maker’s “attitude”-as we mentioned earlier-towards risk, or more generally
the SSDL’s under consideration, leading to the possibility of their dependence on the
SSDL’s that the decision maker has to choose from. Further this attitude for a large number
of individuals, if not most, is such, that when faced with a choice between two SSDL’s,
with one rewarding a sure money prize and the other a slightly higher money prize that is
conditional on the occurrence of an uncertain event, many-if not most- individuals assign
subjective odds against the uncertain event greater than those based on objective
probabilities. Such an attitude may be called uncertainty aversion. It is aptly expressed by
the proverb: “A bird in the hand is worth two in the bush”.
Clearly, uncertainty aversion- the way we define it- requires the possibility of assigning
menu-dependent subjective probabilities by the decision maker (chooser).
Note that given a choice between SSDL’s all of which yield prizes conditional on
uncertain events, it is quite possible for the assigned subjective probabilities to be equal to
the corresponding projected relative frequencies for expected monetary value
maximization to be consistent with claims similar to the ones made for the Allais paradox.
The observations related to the Allais paradox does not constitute a violation of expected
utility maximization; it only says that subjective probabilities used by expected utility
maximizers may disagree with objective probabilities, due to uncertainty aversion.
8. AN EXAMPLE OF EXPECTED UTILITY THEORY IN ACTION
In this section we provide the basic problem discussed in section 2 of Chapter 1 of [19],
which is the “almost universally” accepted template for motivating decision analysis under
uncertainty based on expected utility maximization, when the decision maker is required
to choose an alternative from a set of alternatives each representing uncertain monetary
gains and losses.
As in section 1.2 of [19], “please imagine a collection of 1000 urns, each of which has
one of the labels”, 1 or 2 pasted on its front. Each urn contains only red balls and black
balls, the particular composition of which depends on the label. The composition of each
type is specified in section 1.2 of [19]. The “gentleman” who owns the urns selects one of
them at “random”, i.e., by a procedure such that if it was repeated a large number of times
the relative frequency with which an urn of each type would be chosen is approximately
50%. Needless to say, the problem could be made more interesting by letting the relative
546 S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
frequencies depend on the type of the urn. Alternatively, the decision maker, who is
different from the “experimenter” (who we referred to as the “gentleman”) based on
information available to him assigns a probability of 1/2 to an urn of each type being
chosen. Once the urn is chosen, it is placed on a table and its label-known by the
experimenter- is quickly removed, so that the decision maker does not know the type of
the urn that is placed on the table.
The decision maker knows that there are two possible “states of nature”: 𝐸1 = the chosen
urn is of type 1 and 𝐸2 = the chosen urn is of type 2 .
Subsequently the decision maker is given a choice between (a) participating in a
procedure which requires him to choose one of two “state-dependent dependent prospects”
the first yielding a gain of $40 if the state of nature is 𝐸1 and losing $20 if the state of
nature is 𝐸2 , the second yielding a gain of $100 if the state of nature is 𝐸1 and losing $50
if the state of nature is 𝐸2 ; (b) not participating in the procedure described in (a).
The decision maker’s first problem is to assess the probability of 𝐸𝑖 denoted P(𝐸𝑖 ) for
𝑖 = 1,2, based on the information available to him about the total number of urns and the
“long run” relative frequencies of an urn of each type being chosen. Once that is done, the
choice problem faced by the decision maker reduces to the following.
Choose between:
(a) Given probabilistic prospects
< (40, 𝑃(𝐸1 )), (−20, 𝑃(𝐸1 )) > and < 50, 𝑃(𝐸1 )), (100, 𝑃(𝐸2 )) >
choose one, where the number represent gains in dollars.
(b) Don’t choose (a).
Assuming that the decision maker is an expected utility maximizer with a Bernoulli
utility function u, the decision maker will choose (a) if and only if 𝑚𝑎𝑥{𝑢(40)𝑃(𝐸1 ) +
𝑢(−20)𝑃(𝐸2 ), 𝑢(−50)𝑃(𝐸1 ) + 𝑢(100)𝑃(𝐸2 )} ≥ 𝑢(0) = 0; otherwise he will choose (b).
If 𝑚𝑎𝑥{𝑢(40)𝑃(𝐸1 ) + 𝑢(−20)𝑃(𝐸2 ), 𝑢(−50)𝑃(𝐸1 ) + 𝑢(100)𝑃(𝐸2 )} ≥ 0, he will choose
< (40, 𝑃(𝐸1 )), (−20, 𝑃(𝐸2 )) > if and only if 𝑢(40)𝑃(𝐸1 ) + 𝑢(−20)𝑃(𝐸2 ) ≥ 𝑢(−50)𝑃(𝐸1 ) +
𝑢(100)𝑃(𝐸2 ); otherwise he will choose < (−50, 𝑃(𝐸1 )), (100, 𝑃(𝐸2 )) >.
9. CONCLUSION
Finally, we wish to add clarifications for some very common conceptual misunderstanding that often leads to much confusion.
(a) It is unfortunate that the concept of “loss aversion” has been mis-understood by
many as conflicting with “expected utility maximization”, when in reality its real
purpose is to assert that utility functions display risk-aversion and not risk neutrality at initial wealth, the latter being the characteristic of expected monetary value
maximisers. However, this may create some difficulty for results in mathematical
finance, for instance the arbitrage theorem, but by itself does not conflict with expected utility maximization.
(b) The piecewise linear utility functions with just two linear segments used to explain
loss aversion may be far too simplistic and fails to explain the “diversification”
paradox of Bernoulli.
(c) On page 298, Friedman and Savage in [20], explicitly states the “as if” argument
to explain individual behaviour, implying that the validity of theories in the physical sciences cannot be questioned on the basis of what one believes about the cognitive ability of what physical sciences are concerned with.
S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
547
Even if one were to disagree with Friedman and Savage or question the need for such
theories in operations research or the decision sciences, the least that one would have to
concede is the normative appeal of expected utility theory and hence its use for professionally and technically qualified consultants, provided they are well informed about the gains
and losses associated with each alternative. It is with them in mind that this paper has been
written and the mathematical prerequisite for understanding it being nothing more than
basic algebra and certainly not a graduate course in real analysis. If expected utility theory
fails to describe human behaviour due to its computational complexity or framing effects,
it can certainly be used for the purposes of decision aiding or as a decision support system,
as it is already done in industry these days. In fact, with the increasing use of professional
decision aids in markets and industry any argument against expected utility maximization
based on the “cognitive limitations” of decision makers is becoming less credible day by
day. The potential constraint on the applicability of expected utility maximization, particularly in business and management, has very little to do with its plausibility, desirability
or computational complexity. Such constraints are usually due to lack of exact information
about the state-dependent payoffs associated with each probabilistic prospect, but that is
the subject matter of a related, but different line of research.
Acknowledgment. In very grateful memory of Late Professor Somesh Chandra Bagchi
who taught me probability theory and the same in memory of the best class-room instructor
I ever had, who taught me expected utility theory as a topic in graduate microeconomics
(the former at Indian Statistical Institute-Calcutta and the latter at the University of
Minnesota), to both of whom I dedicate the paper.
I would like to thank Utteeyo Dasgupta, Gavin Kader and Robert (Bob) Nau for discussions, clarificatory comments and observations on this paper. I also wish to thank
Sudipto Dasgupta for having gifted me way back in 1977 my first copy of Howard Raiffa’s
introductory text which is cited in this paper. He may have forgotten it, but I have not.
Section 7 of this paper was presented (virtually) at the 97th annual conference of the
Western Economic Association International (WEAI)- June 29-July 3, 2022- at Portland,
Oregon. I wish to thank Corey Williams and Omid Ardakani immensely for very informed
and pertinent comments and questions on my presentation. Finally, it is my pleasant duty
to thank two anonymous referees of this journal for their comments towards improvement
of this paper and my deep gratitude to one in particular, for a no-nonsense, precise and
thorough evaluation of it, with several constructive suggestions, which must have consumed a considerable amount of his/her time and energy.
Funding. This research received no external funding.
REFERENCES
[1] A. Rubinstein, "Similarity and Decision-making under Risk (Is There a Utility Theory
Resolution to the Allais Paradox?).," Journal of Economic Theory., vol. 46, pp. 145-153, 1988.
[2] S. Lahiri, "Subjective Probability Theory for Decision Making.," 2022. [Online]. Available:.
https://www.academia.edu/79051776/Subjective_Probability_Theory_for_Decision_Making
_Notes_prepared_by_Somdeb_Lahiri
[3] M. Allais, "Le comportement de l'homme rationnel devant le risque: critique des postulats et
axiomes de l'école Américaine," Econometrica, vol. 21 , no. 4, p. 503–546, 1953.
548 S. Lahiri / Expected Utility for Probabilistic Prospects and the Common Ratio Property
[4] D. Kahneman and A. Tversky, "Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk, "
Econometrica, vol. 47, no. 2, pp. 263-291, 1979.
[5] T. Biswas, "Decision-Making Under Uncertainty.," Macmillan Press Ltd., London, 1997.
[6] M. Schneider and M. Shor, "The Common Ratio Effect in Choice, Pricing and Happiness
Tasks.," University of Connecticut, Department of Economics, Discussion Paper Number
2016, vol. 29, 2016.
[7] L. Eeckhoudt, C. Gollier and H. Schlesinger, "Economic and Financial Decisions Under Risk.,"
Princeton University Press, NJ, 2005.
[8] G. Bonanno, "Decision Making", 2017. [Online]. Available:
https://faculty.econ.ucdavis.edu/faculty/bonanno/PDF/DM_book.pdf.
[9] S. Lahiri, "Sophisticated Strategic Choice," New Mathematics and Natural Computation, vol.
14, no. 2, pp. 277-294, 2018.
[10] S. Cruz-Rambaud and A. Sánchez Pérez, "The Magnitude and “Peanuts” Effects: Searching
Implications," Front. Appl. Math. Stat. , p. 4:36, 2018.
[11] A. Chakraborty, Y. Halevy and K. Saito, "The relation between behavior under risk and over
time," American Economic Review: Insights, 2(1), pp. 1-16, 2020.
[12] G. Parmigiani and R. Inoue, "Decision Theory: Principles and Approaches", John Wiley and
Sons, Ltd. Chichester, West Sussex, 2009.
[13] I. Gilboa, "Theory of Decision under Uncertainty," Cambridge University Press, New York,
2009.
[14] D. Ellsberg, "Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms," The Quarterly Journal of Economics,
vol. 75, no. 4, pp. 643-669, 1961.
[15] Y. Halevy, "Ellsberg Revisited: An Experimental Study," Econometrica, vol. 75, no. 2, pp.
503-536, 2007.
[16] G. Harrison, J. Martinez-Correa, Swarthout and J. T, "Reduction of compound lotteries with
objective probabilities: Theory and evidence.," Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization,
vol. 119, pp. 32-55, 2015.
[17] C. Hong, G. Kader and W. Wenqian, "Source Recursive Expected Utility on Rich Mixture
Sets," Unpublished Working Paper, 2022.
[18] S. Lahiri, "Extended choice Correspondences & an axiomatic characterization of the
probabilistic Borda rule," Mathematical Methods in Economics and Finance, vol. 15/16, no. 1,
pp. 15-34, 2022.
[19] H. Raiffa, "Decision Analysis: Introductory Lectures on Choices under Uncertainty, " AddisonWesley Publishing Company Inc., Phillipines, 1968.
[20] M. Friedman and L. Savage, "The Utility Analysis of Choices Involving Risk," Journal of
Political Economy, vol. LVI, no. 4, pp. 279-304, 1948.
[21] F. Ramsey, "Truth and Probability," The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical
Essays, R.B. Braithwaite (ed.). London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, & Co., 1931. (Also
reprinted in Studies in Subjective Probability, H. E. Kyburg, Jr. and H. E. Smokler (eds.), 2nd
edition, New York: R. E. Krieger Publishing Company, 23–52, 1980).
[22] B. de Finetti, "La prévision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives," Annales de l'Institut
Henri Poincaré, no. 7, pp. 1-68, 1937. (Also available in: Theory of Probability: A Critical
Introductory Treatment. Translated by Antonio Machi and Adrian Smith. Chichester, UK. John
Wiley and Sons Ltd., 2017).