.LWVFKDQG%XOOVKLW
7KRUVWHQ%RW]%RUQVWHLQ
3KLORVRSK\DQG/LWHUDWXUH9ROXPH1XPEHU2FWREHUSS
$UWLFOH
3XEOLVKHGE\-RKQV+RSNLQV8QLYHUVLW\3UHVV
'2,SKO
)RUDGGLWLRQDOLQIRUPDWLRQDERXWWKLVDUWLFOH
KWWSVPXVHMKXHGXDUWLFOH
Access provided by Gulf University for Science & Technology (3 May 2016 14:07 GMT)
Thorsten Botz-Bornstein
KiTscH and BULLsHiT
Abstract. Harry Frankfurt defines bullshit as the misrepresentation of
reality that remains different from lying because, contrary to the liar, the
“bullshitter” does not try to deceive. The question, in the realm of art,
is whether kitsch overlaps with bullshit as a sort of “aesthetic bullshit”
or if there are differences between bullshit as a predominantly ethical
phenomenon and kitsch, which works more with categories such as
pleasure and indulgence. i will show that, given bullshit’s intrinsic link
with the technique of embellishment, bullshit is as much at home in
the realm of aesthetics as in the realm of ethics.
H
arry Frankfurt’s twenty-two page long essay “On Bullshit”
was published in 1986 in an academic journal and appeared as
a stand-alone book in 2005. The small book was successful and has
sparked many discussions by both academics and public intellectuals.
in this article i want to examine if, in the realm of art, kitsch overlaps
with bullshit as a sort of “aesthetic bullshit” or if there are differences
between bullshit as a predominantly ethical phenomenon and kitsch,
which works much more with categories such as pleasure and indulgence.
Given bullshit’s intrinsic link with techniques such as embellishment
and the willful stylization of facts, as well as its ambition to create an
autonomous reality, bullshit seems to be as much at home in the realm
of aesthetics as in the realm of ethics.
Frankfurt insists on the aesthetic capacities of the proverbial “bullshit
artist” because bullshitting is “not a craft but art.”1 Frankfurt defines
bullshit as the deceptive misrepresentation of reality that remains different from lying because, contrary to the liar, the “bullshitter” does
not try to deceive (Frankfurt, pp. 6–7). What matters for Frankfurt
Philosophy and Literature, 2015, 39: 305–321. © 2016 The Johns Hopkins University Press.
306
Philosophy and Literature
is not the facts’ truth value but the bullshitter’s “state of mind.” The
bullshitter is bluffing but not lying; bullshit is not false, merely fake and
phony (p. 47). The bullshitter attempts to establish a new reality, which
is an alternative reality “not inferior to the real thing” (p. 47) and, very
importantly, people are typically not forced to believe in the misrepresented reality; the “real” reality is often not entirely dissimulated. i will
also work with Max Black’s concept of humbug—which is, according to
Frankfurt, closely related to bullshit and has a “whiff of self-satisfaction
and self-complacency.”2
Kitsch is an aesthetic product that depends on exaggerated sentimentality, banality, superficiality, and triteness, and has been defined
as “artistic deficiency,”3 as an overly formulaic aesthetic expression,4
or as an aesthetic phenomenon contradicting the “law of adequacy.”5
While there is apparently no classical definition of kitsch, a common
understanding of kitsch is (1) as a tasteless copy of an existing style,
or (2) as the systematic display of bad taste or artistic deficiency. in a
more contemporary, globalized context, kitsch seems to have acquired
a supplementary dimension of “cultural anesthesia,”6 serving as an aesthetically vulgar means to enter a consumer-oriented dream world. in
this article, both kitsch and bullshit will be established as ethico-aesthetic
qualities that skip certain rules. it will become clear that in globalized,
postindustrial societies, not only kitsch but also bullshit has become
more diverse and that new approaches toward both are needed.
I
Kitsch will not (and, in my opinion, cannot) be dealt with as an empirically established and measurable entity. Kitsch is a concept used in language by certain people who agree on certain characteristics through
which kitsch can be defined. This is why kitsch “exists,” and it exists
only in this sense: as an extensional and intensional term referring to
a distinct selection of objects having certain qualities. The claim that
such a common understanding exists within some social groups does
not need to be substantiated any further, because the fact that the word
kitsch can be used in language within certain groups does prove that such
a common understanding exists. The profile of these groups is mainly
determined by local cultures and education. “common understanding” is
not a misnomer because kitsch is not merely an art-theoretical term but
is used by some people also in everyday language. it is even possible to
be familiar with the phenomenon of kitsch without knowing the term,
for example by calling such phenomena “tacky.”
Thorsten Botz-Bornstein
307
a detailed analysis of those patterns is not the purpose of this article,
though certain methodological points need to be specified. if we identify as group (a) the people who adhere to a “common understanding”
of kitsch along the lines pointed out in the introduction, and who are
therefore critical of kitsch, we can identify as group (B) those who do
not believe in this definition of kitsch. However, we will have to divide
this latter group into three subgroups:
(B1) are consumers of kitsch who simply do not know what kitsch is,
because if they knew what it was, they would probably not consume it (i
say “probably” and do not make a judgment).
(B2) are people who understand perfectly well what kitsch is, but believe
that the entire concept of kitsch is irrelevant; they recognize it as a merely
subjective construction (produced by an elite) that does not correspond
to any “reality” and should therefore be abandoned.
(B3) are people who know what kitsch is but who like it nevertheless.
strictly speaking, they do not like kitsch as kitsch. They have an ironical
attitude toward it; they do not merely consume it but use it and play with
it (most typically in contexts that are alien to kitsch).
it is clear that the characteristic of (B1) is that they have less education than the other groups. They do not grasp the concept of kitsch
and (a) will probably reproach them for accepting kitsch as “the real
thing.” (B2) and (B3) most likely are as educated as (a), but differ in
their attitudes toward kitsch for reasons of taste as well as for ethical
or political reasons. (B3) share certain points with (B2) but are not as
relativistic as (B2).
i am spelling all this out in detail because i want to show that something similar applies to bullshit. Bullshit is also not an empirical fact but
a concept used within common language contexts by people who are
able to agree on certain characteristics of bullshit. Of particular interest
will be the (B3) position, because it is based on the assumption that
both kitsch and bullshit are not entirely immoral. More precisely, this
position holds that judgments of bullshit can be linked to the sort of
playful relativism that is proper to judgments in the realm of aesthetics.
Unfortunately, the methodological complications brought about by
the necessity to define various “kitsch attitudes” do not stop here. all
that has been said above about (a), (B1), (B2), and (B3) applies not
only to the perceiver of kitsch but also to the producer of kitsch. Usually,
308
Philosophy and Literature
in the aesthetics of kitsch, we are as interested in the kitsch consumer
as we are in the kitsch producer, while in bullshit we are usually more
interested in the act of bullshitting and less in how it is perceived.
in the aesthetic sense, this article introduces some new elements into
the theoretical discourse on bullshit. if the kitsch producer belongs to
(a), we might find her cynical because she is selling valueless items for a
lot of money. This case corresponds most clearly to that of bullshitting.
about a (B1) producer who is producing kitsch or bullshit without being
aware of it, we would probably not have much to say except that she is
naive. a kitsch producer belonging to group (B2), on the other hand,
can be accused of relativism. This relativism can become unbearable if
the expression of kitsch becomes “too much.”
it becomes clear that a (B2) position is difficult to maintain in the
realm of bullshit production and even of bullshit consumption, while it
is relatively common in the realm of kitsch. This point makes (B2) very
different from (B3). The (B3) producer might be an artist playing with
kitsch motives or a politician playing with rhetorical devices bordering
on bullshit. interestingly, the (B3) producer will probably not be submitted to the same ethical criteria as an (a) producer.
a further problem arises because the links leading from producer
to perceiver might not retain the initial intention. something might
be emitted by a (B3) producer as bullshit but be taken for granted by
a (B1) audience, which presents the possibility of the bullshit being
interpreted as a lie. But we don’t have to interpret it as a lie; we can
also simply say that it is the consumer’s fault “to believe such bullshit.”
in the realm of kitsch such cases are actually quite common: we would
not speak of fraud when a consumer buys a piece of kitsch because she
has been talked into believing that it is real art. Of course, everything
depends on the amount of rhetoric and “free choice” that the consumer
has had. if she had been shown some bogus documentation, then we
might speak of fraud.
i will approach kitsch and bullshit mostly from the point of view of
“common understanding” (which should not be confused with “common sense”). Occasionally i will refer to the perspective of (B2). Of
particular interest in this article are possible shifts from (a) to (B3)
that might more generally be admitted for kitsch, while the admittance
of such shifts for bullshit is rather new. a central question will be: is it
possible and legitimate to be fascinated by phenomena like kitsch and
bullshit, while knowing that both have negative connotations and can
even be dangerous?
Thorsten Botz-Bornstein
309
II
Bullshit is not a lie and kitsch is not forgery. Both kitsch and bullshit
do not hide the truth but, according to calinescu, kitsch “flies away from
reality” (calinescu, p. 244). The common understanding of the terms
holds that bullshit and kitsch exaggerate, that they are often simultaneously too superficial and too explicit. But they do not lie. This is true
even for propaganda, the form of kitsch/bullshit that comes closest
to fraud, which will be discussed in detail below. something can be
identified as kitsch or bullshit only on the condition that people have
the option not to believe it. Military recruitment advertisements can
be understood as bullshit; but at the moment they posit a false world
for the basis of real-life decisions they become fraud. Once again, the
above-mentioned methodological problem remains important: for whom
does it constitute fraud? Only for somebody who does not see through
the plot. The person who knows that it is fraud might classify the same
ad as bullshit or its visual and verbal rhetoric as kitsch.
While the liar covers the truth under a nontruth that he wants to be as
substantial and dense as possible, bullshit and kitsch make nonsubstantial claims in order to create new, less-substantial realities that probably
cannot perfectly conceal the more substantial true reality. The Mona
Lisa printed on the pillow case is kitsch, as is any tasteless copy of an
existing painting, but it is not a falsified Mona Lisa that a forger is trying
to sell for millions. it is a copy of a famous artwork that acknowledges
being a copy and demands to be accepted as such. another example
comes from dorfles’s introduction to his famous book Kitsch, in which
he writes that kitsch occurs when chopin’s tunes “have been dragged
down to the level of sentimental songs.” still, the existence of the real
chopin is not contested.
The above two examples concern only those cases where kitsch
imitates existing works of art and the fake/reality dichotomy is easy
to establish. However, kitsch most often produces tacky and overdone
aesthetic expressions without imitating anything concrete. is it possible
to speak here of falsification? dorfles holds that kitsch “is essentially the
falsification of sentiments and the substitution of spurious sentiments
for real ones.”7 But how can one “falsify” sentiments? did Hume not, in
his thesis on the standard of taste, explain that “the sentiment is always
true”?8 The sentiment sparked by kitsch is different from the sentiment
sparked by art, but it is no less true. dorfles distinguishes the “real
feeling” produced by art from the “sentimentality” produced by kitsch
310
Philosophy and Literature
and suggests that the latter is a falsification of the former. it seems to
me that sentimentality is here produced in the form of a less substantial,
but in no way false, feeling.
Kitsch does not consistently transgress the limits that distinguish the
authentic from the false, but it alters them; just as the bullshitter’s free
interpretation of reality follows not the rules of a perfect crime but
rather those of creative manipulation. in certain cases concerning (B3)
producers, the manipulation can also be playful. in no cases do kitsch
and bullshit falsify the truth. The worst one can say is that they distort
the truth through exaggeration, a willful lack of critical activity, or by
simply not being serious. apart from that, both bullshit and kitsch are
“conservative” in the sense that they represent closed-minded entities
and are rarely eager to absorb new insights (this concerns, of course,
only the kitsch and bullshit produced and consumed by [a] and [B1]
and is contrary to the way in which they are used by [B3]).
according to Philip crick, kitsch is compact and “final in its quality,”9
and the same is true for bullshit. Partly this means that bullshit and kitsch
do not falsify but simplify realities. They prefer standardized, fetishized,
and compressed claims and images to the more complex claims and
images current in reality and real art. correspondingly, when watching
a kitschy blockbuster or when hearing a politician utter obvious bullshit
we often mumble, “Well, reality is more complicated than that.” The
simplification patterns work along the lines that Greenberg analyzed
as the principal mechanics of kitsch when writing that kitsch limits its
presentation to the effect and does not care about the cause. The parallel with bullshit is particularly obvious here as Frankfurt points out
that the bullshitter does not care about truth (Frankfurt, pp. 17–19).
similar to Greenberg, Tomáš Kulka writes that “for kitsch the ‘what’
is more important than the ‘how.’”10 The kitsch “artist” might work a
lot on the “how,” but will subsequently present it as the one and only
“what” that no critical thinking should ever dare to analyze. in other
words, both kitsch and bullshit are offered as take-away conclusions.
While in real art we often attempt to participate in the underlying creative process and strive to inquire about the “why” (the premises) of
some aesthetic choices, in kitsch there is not supposed to be any such
“why”; we are simply urged to take the product for granted and enjoy.
in the most typical kitsch cases, the “secret” is mere exaggeration or
awkward juxtaposition, neither of which requires deeper investigation
but tends to overwhelm the consumer. a typical kitsch quality is indeed
that of being “hackneyed” and trite. in real art, on the other hand, we
Thorsten Botz-Bornstein
311
tend to ask ourselves, “How did the artist do that?” similarly, when reading a well-argued critical article clarifying claims that were not obvious
in the beginning, we might feel the need to examine “how” the writer
came to such conclusions. This rarely happens with bullshit, except
when we want to prove that it is inaccurate. consequently, Greenberg
establishes the difference between nonkitsch and kitsch like this: Picasso
(nonkitsch) paints the cause while Repin (kitsch) paints merely the effect
(Greenberg, p. 15).
III
i mentioned above that bullshit, though being in the first place of
ethical interest, has often been dealt with from an aesthetical point of
view because it is so closely linked to techniques of embellishment and
stylization. For kitsch the reverse is true. Though kitsch is officially an
aesthetic term, Robert solomon finds that “much of the literature attacking kitsch is political rather than aesthetic.”11 Of importance here is the
postwar revision of the distinction between mass culture and high art
through which kitsch has “suddenly assumed an importance that had
as much to do with politics as with aesthetics.”12
in the political context kitsch is mainly discussed in ethical and not in
aesthetic terms. another force that turns kitsch into a matter of ethics
is its apparent justification of overly hedonistic expressions. Whenever
kitsch is judged harshly, the justification is likely to happen on ethical
grounds, that is, kitsch will be diagnosed as a sort of bullshit. in politics,
kitsch and bullshit are often twins if we think of propaganda art or of
metaphors used in twentieth-century totalitarian discourses. The problem is that in these realms, both kitsch and bullshit assume the kind of
cynical power that is not part of their initial definitions. True, in most
cases, the bullshitter knows what is true and simply says the contrary;
but that alone is not enough to make her a cynic. Propaganda kitsch
and bullshit can be cynical, but then they are merely particular branches
of kitsch/bullshit.
What are the differences between kitsch and bullshit? First, we do not
encounter them under the same conditions. Much bullshit is fabricated
by people who do not belong to (B1); the producers do not believe in
what they say, and this is obvious to many consumers. The position of
the kitsch producer is more complicated. she might belong to (B1),
in which case condemnations can be expressed on the grounds of aesthetics but not of ethics. But even if she belongs to (a) and produces
312
Philosophy and Literature
awful kitsch just to make money, she can still say that she likes it, that
is, takes refuge in (B1). This creates the false impression that kitsch is
morally more acceptable than bullshit; however, with regard to their
essence both are the same. Both can be judged on ethical as well as
aesthetic grounds.
as a result, apologetic discourses on bullshit will most likely refer to
the “merely” aesthetic qualities of bullshit. in a way, they say that their
bullshit is merely kitsch. “Unlike the liar, who deliberately obscures
what he takes to be true, bullshitters may often be honest and sincere,”
writes Reisch.13 Bullshit can indeed easily be explained as a sort of kitsch
and—normally—kitsch does not cheat because there is no necessary
link between bad taste and dishonesty.
in a rarer case, kitsch is declared to be “merely” bullshit. clancy
Martin points to nietzsche’s concept of “art as a lie” and finds that what
nietzsche actually means is that artists are bullshitters.14 What nietzsche
might have meant in the first place is that all art contains a grain of
kitsch in order to please the public. What is worse, being a kitsch artist
or a bullshit artist? My guess is that most artists would go for the latter.
Hermann Broch, in one of the most classical texts on kitsch ever
written, insists on seeing kitsch in purely ethical terms because kitsch
is not art, not even bad art: “The producer of kitsch does not produce
‘bad’ art.... it is quite impossible to assess him according to aesthetic
criteria; rather he should be judged as an ethically base being, a malefactor who profoundly desires evil.”15 More explicitly, Broch traces the
essence of kitsch to “the confusion of the ethical category with the
aesthetic category” (Broch, p. 71). This last argument is strange in that
it evokes the impression that aesthetics, once it is abandoned by ethics and left on its own, can only produce kitsch. However, can only the
right ethics prevent aesthetics from producing kitsch? are there not
intrinsic aesthetic standards able to prevent art from becoming kitsch?
We cannot discuss here the fundamental problem of whether aesthetics
is subordinate to ethics or whether art has its own code of honor. But
i believe that Broch’s conclusion is hasty as he suggests that everything
that is merely beautiful but not also good automatically turns into kitsch.
This claim is not convincing with regard to art, though Broch seems to
have given a good account of what at least (a) and (B3) believe to be
the essence of bullshit.
Bullshit counts very much on the relativist judgments that are more
common in aesthetics than in ethics. Bullshit rarely proceeds “scientifically” by going from premise to conclusion, but attempts to delude by
Thorsten Botz-Bornstein
313
creating contexts or ambiguous definitions that work in its favor. Bullshit
might commit the most outrageous fallacies (red herring, suppressed
evidence, begging the question, appeal to ignorance) while hoping that
people will be blinded by aesthetic and rhetorical devices. its “focus is
panoramic rather than particular,” says Frankfurt (p. 52), which indicates a shift of focus from analytical to aesthetic elaborations. However,
aesthetics (like rhetoric) is not merely relativist either. There are certain
rules to follow and kitsch skips some of those necessary aesthetic stances,
for example those of adequacy, appropriateness, sophistication, and the
necessity of effort and seriousness in art. Most typically, kitsch does so
in order to obtain cheap effects of intense emotion. This is similar to
how bullshit works in politics, where claims or ideologies often move
too quickly toward desired political aims without being backed by critical thought.
can the above question—central to this article—of whether bullshit
is a matter of ethics or aesthetics now be answered? The comparison of
bullshit and kitsch elucidates the constellation of some crucial elements.
distorting reality is obviously a matter of ethics, and in that sense, bullshitting should be judged in terms of ethics. However, the bullshitter can get
away with her distortion because the style with which she commits the
distortion aestheticizes the ethical default. What matters in bullshit is the
stylistic arrangement and this turns bullshit into a subject for aesthetics.
The easiness, nonchalance, innocence, and—sometimes—naiveté with
which the bullshitter passes over reality can turn the bullshitter into an
artist acting within a playful and merely aesthetically established reality:
“claims are made, judgments cast, arguments presented, all with the
unbearable lightness of those free of any responsibility or commitment,”
writes de Waal.16
IV
We move forward in our discussion with whether a shift from (a) to
(B3) is possible not only in the realm of kitsch but also in the realm
of bullshit. Frankfurt asks why there is so much bullshit, and admits
that the answer is difficult to determine. On the other hand, “Why is
there so much kitsch?” has been answered by a whole string of commentators. Most answers work along the lines of Kulka’s; he points out
that kitsch thrives best in a “civilization that is based on excess consumption” (Kulka, p. 13). The problem is that, obviously, kitsch also
thrives in those totalitarian societies where capitalist-style consumption
314
Philosophy and Literature
is nonexistent—though admittedly, over there, it arises in other parts
of the politico-social structure. Though it is not the purpose of this
article to examine the link between kitsch and capitalism more closely,
one can assume that something similar applies to the distribution of
bullshit. The social significance of bullshit depends on whether we are
discussing democratic or totalitarian societies.
What has so far become obvious in this essay on the contemporary position and perception of kitsch is that both hardline, anti-kitsch positions
and more “postmodern,” relativist ways of interpreting kitsch do coexist.
The way in which kitsch and bullshit are connected to different social
groups determines the significance it has for different people. Hardliners
usually assume that kitsch is merely a one-dimensional instrument of
oppression and “dullification” of the people. The kitsch-liberal position,
on the other hand, is more prepared to judge kitsch by considering
the complexity of pluralistic class structures in contemporary societies
or by considering the relativizing power of globalization. some even
interpret kitsch as a liberating pluralistic power in the arts or as part of
a culture of resistance that can revert to complex rhetorical methods
determined by irony. The recent emergence of a “kitsch phenomenon”
such as tattoos would be an example of the latter.17 Kitsch-liberals can
belong to (B3) but will most typically come from (B2).
Kitsch-liberals such as selle and nelles go as far as presenting kitsch
as a new “anti-snob device.” They defend kitsch on the grounds that it
is simply real—at least more real and less pretentious than much of the
so-called high culture—because kitsch is not based on lying (while high
culture, with its “false” and imaginary norms, often is): kitsch “is not
founded merely on deceit; it is not an ‘as if’ culture, it is ‘lived’ culture,
and whoever calls it kitschy is making an absolute of a position based
on educational tradition and normative interest.”18 Their argument,
a classic (B2) case, might appear naive because design obviously does
involve deception, or at least a rhetorical/persuasive component. still,
it is interesting to note that for these authors, kitsch is able to fight the
bullshit of high culture; as a consequence, the entire “kitsch as kitsch”
concept should be declared obsolete: “The parvenus know themselves
what is suitable, and their measure of suitability has, as a new standard,
taken the place of temperate restraint. There is no kitsch, only design”
(s&n, p. 41).
another argument—related to the preceding one but coming closer
to (B3) because it is less relativist—puts forward the “humane” dimension of kitsch as a counterreaction to excessively rationalistic worldviews
Thorsten Botz-Bornstein
315
because kitsch helps us to “come to terms with an increasingly abstract
and non-intuitive understanding of reality.”19 Here kitsch fights the
bullshit of modern culture at its worst, including its boastful rationalization and its pretentious scientification of everything. The “humane
dimension” argument is particularly pertinent when kitsch adopts the
shape of cuteness. it is indeed possible that a “Hello Kitty” sticker on
the fridge or a kitsch lamp in the sitting room makes everyday life a
little more bearable for many modern people.
This argument is relatively old. calinescu finds in adorno’s insinuations the idea that kitsch is a “pleasurable escape from the drabness
of modern quotidian life” (calinescu, p. 228) and Gregotti, in his contribution to dorfles’s book, recognizes kitsch “as a kind of exorcism of
the world of industry and mass-consumption.”20 in summary, we can say
that even if we assume consumer culture to be at the root of most of the
world’s kitsch, two mechanisms need to be distinguished: (1) consumer
culture produces kitsch in the form of marketing, and (2) kitsch can
arise as a counterreaction to consumer culture.
The question of why there is so much bullshit needs to be answered
against this background. it is difficult to find as many statements defending bullshit as there are statements defending kitsch. as mentioned,
(B2) bullshit positions are practically nonexistent and (B3) positions
are relatively rare. One reason is that bullshit, like kitsch, has some roots
in totalitarian politics but, unlike kitsch, bullshit has been less able to
liberate itself from those roots. For kitsch, things were relatively easy:
kitsch cannot be intrinsically totalitarian because if otherwise, we could
not explain why it is so prevalent not only in totalitarian societies but
in liberal democracies (see Boyers, p. 199), or proliferates in liberal
societies even more than in communism and fascism.
in any bullshit speech, on the other hand, we are more likely than
in kitsch to hear the voice of a wannabe dictator. if, as Milan Kundera
affirms, kitsch is the aesthetic ideal of all politicians,21 we can add that
bullshit is their rhetoric ideal. apart from that, it should not be forgotten
that the antibullshit stance has even had traditional scientific backing,
something that kitsch cannot boast. according to Hardcastle, logical
positivism attempted to eliminate all bullshit from the world.22
Even propaganda (and not just kitsch) has been said to be more
prevalent in democracies than in totalitarian societies. noam chomsky
states in achbar and Wintonick’s documentary Manufacturing Consent
that dictatorships have no need for propaganda because they can just
kill anyone who disagrees. Only in democracies (where people can make
316
Philosophy and Literature
relatively free choices) is propaganda truly needed. On the other hand,
propaganda seems to be more labor saving as a method of producing
consent, which is probably the reason why it is current in both dictatorships and democracies. in other words, dictatorships need kitsch and
bullshit for propaganda reasons, while democracies need kitsch and
bullshit mainly for commercial (though also for political) reasons.
as far as rhetoric is concerned, it is telling that, some hundred and
fifty years ago, rhetoric lost its earlier status as the reasonable power of
argumentation and became very much identified, from the nineteenth
century onwards, with political propaganda, violence… and bullshit. in
historical terms, the reason for this was the emergence of larger and
less personal political structures in Europe, which turned out to be less
benevolent for the cultivation of “good” rhetoric. Hans Mayer writes that
“the art of speaking (rhetoric) necessitates narrow political and social
conditions and a public life that can count on individuals as transmitters of political will in the way in which they existed in the Greek polis
and the city states of the Renaissance or rural communities in swiss
cantons, and which had its climax in the rhetoric of the national convent
of the French Revolution.”23 Today rhetoric is often believed to burst
with life but lack reason; in other words, it is identified with bullshit.
david Tietge, in his essay “Rhetoric is not Bullshit,”24 criticizes this state
of affairs and attempts to separate rhetoric from bullshit. He is right
in doing so. However, one reason why the confusion of the two could
happen in the first place is that rhetoric simply lost control of bullshit.
Here there is a parallel with kitsch. according to dorfles, at the time
of Romanticism art could still control kitsch more or less successfully
because kitsch was “contained within a framework of facades in the neoclassical Biedermeier style (and american Romanticism in the colonial
style)” (dorfles, p. 50). at one point it lost control of kitsch, with the
result that today many hold Romanticism responsible for kitsch (p. 52).
Gianni Vattimo draws the conclusion that after Romanticism, any
“idealization of beautiful and ethical life” became impossible because
the “classically perfect identification between content and form, and
the completeness and definitive quality of the work, is anachronistic,
illusory and in the end positively kitsch (nowadays only merchandise
promoted in advertising is presented in this way).”25 Vattimo’s conclusion points to a strange paradox attached to postmodernism: on the one
hand, postmodern ways of interpreting kitsch are often identified with
more relativistic attitudes brought about by the blurring of the borders
between high and low art. On the other hand, there is an “increasing
Thorsten Botz-Bornstein
317
remoteness of ‘high’ art from the perspective of the masses who remain
prisoners of the kitsch which for its part seems, paradoxically and in
caricature, to be the realization of the ‘new mythology’ dreamed of by
the Romantics” (Vattimo, p. 72). This means that people in group (a)
have simply no right to enjoy the “complete and well-rounded, boasting
the harmonious conciliation and perfect interpenetration of content
and form” (Vattimo, p. 86) that used to be the standard in the classical
age. Whoever enjoys such art enjoys kitsch and belongs to group (B).
can rhetoric and reason regain control of bullshit instead of merely
diabolizing it? can one imagine reason reigning bullshit either along the
lines of deconstructing rules or along the lines of ironic but controlled
appropriation? This article has attempted to formulate such paths. in
liberal, globalized, “virtualized,” and postindustrial societies, not only
kitsch but also bullshit has become more diverse and more pervasive.
as a result, hardline antibullshit positions are more difficult to assume
than ever. Take, for example, the internet and “virtual reality,” which
is, in some sense, bullshit by definition. in the 1980s, Frankfurt’s and
Black’s articles could not address the problems of virtual reality. However,
Frankfurt clearly declares that “the bullshitter attempts to establish a
new reality,” which is an alternative reality “not inferior to the real thing”
(Frankfurt, p. 47). This is in agreement with the definition of virtuality
and, in general, Frankfurt seems to believe that our culture is moving
away from truth and toward antirealism.
Black is even more explicit when defining humbug as a sort of “virtual
lying” based on the definition of the virtual as “being functionally or
effectively but formally not of its kind” (Black, p. 134). Virtual technology works with immersion into virtual reality in the sense of a perception
of being physically present in a nonphysical world. “immersion” is a
metaphor for the loss of the critical mind and, in that sense, virtual
reality is bullshit. if anything, it makes clear that the more paradoxical, self-critical evaluation of bullshit suggested above, which flows out
of a consistent comparison of bullshit with kitsch, is inevitable. We are
obviously bound to live with the “bullshit” called virtual reality on a
day-to-day basis, just as we are living with kitsch. a critical distance can
only be established through deconstruction and ironic appropriation.
Total elimination is impossible.
Has a liberal (B3) position ever been outlined for bullshit? Maes and
schaubroek theorize bullshit in a way similar to how kitsch-liberals theorize kitsch: it can, for example, be “a means to lay contact with others
or keep the conversation going, it can be a source of warmth.”26 i’m
318
Philosophy and Literature
afraid that’s as far as it goes. There seems to be nothing like the acceptance of bullshit in the name of pluralism or even as a counterreaction
to totalitarian worldviews. There is no real (B2) position for bullshit.
However, can’t bullshit be used to fight bullshit just like kitsch has been
used to fight bullshit? My answer is: yes it can. Much bullshit might
already be committed out of exasperation with the rigid, administrative
universe filled with useless requirements that we are living in. Ranting
colleagues who have to hand in their updated cV to the administration
four times a year produce tons of bullshit aimed at ridiculing the system
and revealing its deficiencies.
as a matter of fact, bureaucracies produce a lot of “efficiency bullshit”
that can very well be opposed by producing … bullshit. Political correctness, though initially designed to prevent discrimination, can easily go
over the top and become a dictatorial sort of bullshit in its own right.
again, counterbullshit (such as using the feminine gender throughout
this article) is arguably an efficient approach. it is certainly not recommended to go to those extremes suggested by (B2) and declare, as nelle
and selles do with regard to kitsch, the entire bullshit concept to be
obsolete, meaning that bullshit is all right and that anything goes. But,
as a matter of fact, very few people would say this about kitsch either.
What i am advocating is a (B3) position for bullshit; i find the (B2)
position too radical.
V
as long as bullshit knows that it is bullshit (and everybody else knows
it as well), bullshit can be used to challenge orders. Kitsch is kitsch and
bullshit is bullshit. There is nothing intrinsically annoying about them
except when they become pretentious, in other words, when they become
pushy and move closer to lies. Just as kitsch has increasingly come to be
seen as an artistic device, bullshit could be seen as a rhetorical device,
playfully—but still controlled by reason—deconstructing existing rules.
Frankfurt names the general retreat from correctness to sincerity as
one of the more obscure sources of bullshit, and there i see a major
problem with Frankfurt’s analysis: “Rather than seeking primarily to
arrive at accurate representations of a common world, the individual
turns toward trying to provide honest representations of himself”
(Frankfurt, p. 65). What Frankfurt means and what he criticizes is that
once we have acquired the image of an honest person, we can bullshit
as much as we want. correctness and accuracy—which are, for Frankfurt,
Thorsten Botz-Bornstein
319
the only powers able to fight bullshit—will no longer be standard in a
world in which we are looking only for honesty.
i do not agree. Today it is very much possible to understand “honesty”
(just like bullshit) as a counterreaction to exaggerated requirements
of correctness or pseudo-correctness. it seems to me that Frankfurt,
when saying that “the individual turns toward trying to provide honest
representations of himself,” confuses honesty with “personality,” which
is very often a pretended honesty and thus bullshit. However, honesty is
precisely what we should use in order to fight bullshit.
Marilyn Motz, in her analysis of douglas Lurton’s 1950s bestseller The
Power of Positive Thinking,27 points out that in a world where everybody
thinks positively, “personality [will have] replaced character as the primary measure of one’s worth. a pleasant smile, a well-groomed appearance, self-control and conformity replaced honesty…”.28 Positive Thinking,
which asks us to adopt a radically “positive attitude” toward everything
even when reality looks completely otherwise, carries many qualities that
justify its classification as typical bullshit. The radically positive-thinking
person is a “bullshit personality” whose pleasant smile is, in the final
instance, dishonest. Though positive thinking is always “correct” (not
in the sense of political correctness though distantly related to it), it is
dishonest because it lacks self-criticism, is narcissistic, and leans toward
auto-hypnotic self-aggrandizement. and like the bullshitter, the positive thinker pretends not to be aware of this. is “honesty” here not the
best remedy? a (B3) position of bullshit includes honesty and it can be
reached by thinking about parallels between kitsch and bullshit.
Gulf University for science and Technology
1. Harry G. Frankfurt, On Bullshit (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005), first
published in Raritan Quarterly Review 6, no. 2 (1986): 81–100 (52). citations are from
the book and hereafter abbreviated Frankfurt.
2. Max Black, “The Prevalence of Humbug,” in The Prevalence of Humbug and Other Essays
(cornell: cornell University Press, 1983), pp. 115–46 (119); hereafter abbreviated Black.
3. Gillo dorfles, introduction, Kitsch: The World of Bad Taste, ed. G. dorfles (new York:
Bell, 1969), p. 10; hereafter abbreviated dorfles.
4. clement Greenberg, “avant-Garde and Kitsch,” in Art and Culture: Critical Essays
(Boston: Beacon Press 1961), pp. 9–15 (10).
320
Philosophy and Literature
5. Matei calinescu, Five Faces of Modernity (durham: duke University Press, 1987), p.
257; hereafter abbreviated calinescu.
6. catherine a. Lugg, Kitsch: From Education to Public Policy (London: Falmer Press,
1999), p. 4.
7. Gillo dorfles, “Pornokitsch and Morals,” in dorfles, Kitsch: The World of Bad Taste,
pp. 221–24 (221).
8. david Hume, “Of the standard of Taste,” in Of the Standard of Taste and Other Essays
(London: allyn and Bacon, 1918), pp. 6–7.
9.
Philip crick, “Kitsch,” The British Journal of Aesthetics 23, no. 1 (1983): 49–52 (50).
10. Tomáš Kulka, Kitsch and Art (University Park: Pennsylvania state University Press,
1996), p. 82; hereafter abbreviated Kulka.
11. Robert c. solomon, “On Kitsch and sentimentality,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism 49, no. 1 (1991): 1–14 (3).
12. Robert and Peg Boyers, “Kitsch: an introduction,” Salmagundi 85/86 (1990): 197–200
(197); hereafter abbreviated Boyers.
13. George Reisch, “The Pragmatics of Bullshit, intelligently designed,” in Bullshit and
Philosophy: Guaranteed to Get Perfect Results Every Time, ed. G. Hardcastle and G. Reisch
(chicago: Open court, 2006), pp. 33–48 (44).
14. clancy W. Martin, “Review of Harry Frankfurt, ‘On Bullshit’,” Ethics 116, no. 2
(2006): 416–21 (419).
15. Hermann Broch, “notes on the Problem of Kitsch,” in dorfles, Kitsch: The World of
Bad Taste, pp. 49–76 (76); hereafter abbreviated Broch.
16. cornelis de Waal, “The importance of Being Earnest: a Pragmatic approach to
Bullshitting,” in Hardcastle and Reisch, Bullshit and Philosophy, pp. 99–113 (109).
17. Thorsten Botz-Bornstein, “From the stigmatized Tattoo to the Graffitied Body:
Femininity in the Tattoo Renaissance,” Gender, Place and Culture: A Journal of Feminist
Geography 20, no. 2 (2012): 1–17.
18. Gert selle and Peter nelles, “There is no Kitsch, There is Only design!” Design
Issues 1, no. 1 (1984): 41–52 (41); hereafter abbreviated s&n.
19. Volker Kalisch, “Mozart und Kitsch: ‘Ein musikalischer spaß’?” International Review
of the Aesthetics and Sociology of Music 23, no. 1 (1992): 43–60 (50–51).
20. Vittorio Gregotti, “Urban Kitsch,” in dorfles, Kitsch: The World of Bad Taste, pp.
254–64 (256).
21. Milan Kundera, The Unbearable Lightness of Being (new York: Harper & collins,
1999), p. 243.
22. Gary L. Hardcastle, “The Unity of Bullshit,” in Hardcastle and Reisch, Bullshit and
Philosophy, pp. 137–50 (141–42).
23. Hans Mayer, “Rhetorik und Propaganda,” in Zur deutschen Literatur der Zeit (Hamburg:
Rowolt, 1967), p. 125 (my translation).
Thorsten Botz-Bornstein
321
24. david Tietge, “Rhetoric is not Bullshit,” in Hardcastle and Reisch, Bullshit and
Philosophy, pp. 229–40.
25. Gianni Vattimo, Beyond Interpretation: The Meaning of Hermeneutics for Philosophy
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), p. 89; hereafter abbreviated Vattimo.
26. Hans Maes and Katrien schaubroek, “different Kinds and aspects of Bullshit,” in
Hardcastle and Reisch, Bullshit and Philosophy, pp. 171–81 (178).
27. douglas Elsworth Lurton, The Power of Positive Thinking (new York: McGraw Hill,
1956).
28. Marilyn Ferris Motz, “‘i Want to Be a Barbie doll When i Grow Up’: The cultural
significance of the Barbie doll,” in Pop Cultural Reader, ed. c. Geist et al. (Bowling Green:
Bowling Green University Popular Press, 1983), pp. 122–36 (134).