University of Windsor
Scholarship at UWindsor
Philosophy Publications
Department of Philosophy
2011
Use Value, Life Value, and the Future of Socialism
Jeff Noonan
University of Windsor
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/philosophypub
Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons
Recommended Citation
Noonan, Jeff. (2011). Use Value, Life Value, and the Future of Socialism. Rethinking Marxism, 23 (1),
117-134.
https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/philosophypub/2
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at Scholarship at
UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Publications by an authorized administrator of
Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact scholarship@uwindsor.ca.
This article was downloaded by: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network]
On: 3 December 2010
Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 783016864]
Publisher Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 3741 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK
Rethinking Marxism
Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:
http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713395221
Use Value, Life Value, and the Future of Socialism
Jeff Noonan
Online publication date: 03 December 2010
To cite this Article Noonan, Jeff(2011) 'Use Value, Life Value, and the Future of Socialism', Rethinking Marxism, 23: 1, 117
— 134
To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/08935696.2011.536352
URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08935696.2011.536352
PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE
Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf
This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or
systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or
distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents
will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses
should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss,
actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly
or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
RETHINKING MARXISM
VOLUME 23
NUMBER 1
(JANUARY 2011)
Use Value, Life Value, and the Future of
Socialism
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
Jeff Noonan
The paper argues that the future of socialism depends upon the category of use value
being grounded in a wider and deeper conception of life value. Only as such can it
serve as the regulating principle of a future democratic socialist society. Life value is
anchored in an understanding of the human life’s space-time continuum understood
as a continuum of life requirements. The multiple life crises regularly generated by
capitalism are crises of its incapacity to adequately satisfy these life requirements.
The practical conclusion is that a democratic socialist economy must prioritize the
production not of use values as such, but only of those use values that also have life
value.
Key Words: Use Value, Life Value, Capacities, Life Requirements, Socialism
In a recent interview Walden Bello argues that ‘‘orthodox economics has long ceased
to be of any help in understanding the crisis . . . From the progressive perspective,
what we are seeing is the intensification of one of the central crises or contradictions
of global capitalism: the crisis of overproduction, also known as overaccumulation or
overcapacity. This is the tendency of capitalism to build up, in the context of
heightened capitalist competition, tremendous productive capacity that outruns the
population’s capacity to consume owing to income inequalities that limit popular
purchasing power’’ (Bello 2009, 1). On one level Bello is correct, but by speaking in
aggregate terms like ‘‘overaccumulation’’ and ‘‘underconsumption’’ without specifying what is overaccumulated and what is underconsumed, Bello’s own analysis
replicates a key limitation of orthodox economic thought.
Let us assume that a more egalitarian distribution of income is achieved. Will this
new purchasing power be spent on SUVs, Xboxes, pesticides, or alligator shoes? The
problem of disaggregating demand is not a problem in neoclassical economics
because it assumes, from a microeconomic perspective, that the satisfaction of
consumer demand is always rational regardless of its content (see Brown 2008, 61/9).
Likewise, disaggregation at the macroeconomic level is also irrelevant to a measure
of economic health like gross domestic product. So long as GDP is rising, it does not
matter whether the increase is due to the production of plutonium or pajamas nor
does it matter how that income is distributed. A rising GDP is always good in
neoclassical economics, and a falling GDP is always bad (Sen 1999, 290/2).
ISSN 0893-5696 print/1475-8059 online/11/010117-18
– 2011 Association for Economic and Social Analysis
DOI: 10.1080/08935696.2011.536352
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
118
NOONAN
A socialist critique and alternative to neoclassical economics*/especially one
concerned, as any must be today, with the relationship between the natural
environment and human economic systems*/requires a normative foundation capable
of disclosing what these aggregate terms conceal. What they conceal is the material
irrationality of capitalism, by which I mean that capitalist money value (which is what
the aggregate terms actually measure) is alienated from the fundamental bases of
natural life support and social life development upon which it ultimately depends.
Given this alienation, the system, its defenders, and its metrics of economic health
are blind to the ways in which the growth of money value damages and destroys what
I will call, following John McMurtry, natural and social life value. Capitalism is thus
blind to the way in which it systematically wastes and despoils the very systems upon
which its own existence depends.
I believe that the solution to the manifold life crises that capitalism generates is
socialist. However, the traditional socialist alternative of prioritizing use value over
monetary exchange value is an inadequate platform from which to grasp this material
irrationality. While Marx’s critique has the merit of exposing the life-destructive
effects of capitalist growth dynamics as a whole, the simple prioritization of use
value over exchange value in a future socialist economy is not able to consistently
distinguish materially rational from materially irrational choices at the microeconomic level. The solution lies in making explicit what is only implied in Marx’s
critique: an underlying conception of life value as the necessary regulating value of
production and distribution in a democratic and ecologically sound socialist lifeeconomy.
My argument will be developed in three moments. In the first, I will explain the
foundational concept of life value through a critique of Marx’s conception of value
and use value. In the second section I will employ the idea of life value to bring to
light the deep structure of life crises caused by the way in which capitalism colonizes
the three dimensions of the human life space and time continuum: its naturalbiological foundations, its sociocultural expressions, and its temporal conditions of
freedom. Given the complexity of these life crises, I cannot examine them in
adequate empirical detail here. The main concern is to illustrate the reality of life
requirements and the threats posed to their satisfaction by capitalism and its money
value system. In the final section I will conclude that an effective socialist political
response demands a solution to the contradiction between the future-oriented
promises of socialist theory and the present reality of life crisis caused by the
colonization of the life space-time continuum. This contradiction can be resolved by
anchoring socialist politics in a constructive and tranformationalist program that
begins from existing prefigurative economic and political practices that prove, even if
only to a limited extent, that the dependence of human life on labor and commodity
markets is neither necessary nor ultimate. As with the second part, the complexity
and context dependence of political practice limit the scope of what can be said in
defense of my claims. A comprehensive political program is neither possible in this
paper nor desirable given the need for situated reasoning and argument that all
politics demands.
VALUE AND LIFE VALUE
119
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
Money Value, Use Value, and Life Value
When we think of ‘‘economic rationality’’ in classical or neoclassical terms, we are
taught to think in terms of utility-maximizing choices and Pareto optimality (see
Brown 2008, 77/84; McMurtry 2009, 69/91). The problem, however, is that utility
functions and the relations established between the agents who pursue them in a free
market are abstractions that cannot tell us what the consequences are for the natural
field of life support and the social field of life development which in reality the
capitalist market presupposes. If a healthy economy is understood as one in which the
‘rational’ pursuit of self-maximizing gain generates Pareto-optimal equilibrium in
which no one can gain any further satisfaction without imposing higher costs (less
desire satisfaction) on at least one other agent, then global consequences can be
materially irrational. Yet, this material irrationality cannot be seen as necessary
because the classical and neoclassical measure of economic health abstracts the
economic process from both its natural and social bases. Thus, a market in old-growth
trees becomes Pareto-optimal when every firm that wants to produce lumber from
the old-growth forest cannot increase its share without encroaching on the share of
other firms; the aesthetic and life-supportive value of the resource being permanently consumed does not factor into the account. ‘‘Efficient’’ markets can thus
destroy the natural and social bases of economic activity as such without orthodox
economic science even having the tools to measure this destruction.
Going back to Nicolas Georgescu-Roegen, ecological economics has understood
quite well the irrationality involved in abstracting the economy from the natural field
of life support upon which it depends (see Georgescu-Roegen 1971; Daly 1977; Daly
and Farley 2004; Victor 2008; Brown 2008; Brown and Carver 2009). The problem with
ecological economics, however, is that it fails to specify the concrete social dynamic
that is responsible for this alienation in a capitalist society. If orthodox economics
may be faulted for failing to understand the necessary anchoring of the economy in
the natural field of life support, ecological economics may be faulted for failing
to theorize the anchoring of specifically capitalist growth dynamics in class relations
(in the traditional Marxist sense of class according to which classes are distinguished
by their relationship to the means of production), property forms, and the
competitive dynamics of capitalism (Marx 1986a, 885/6). Under capitalism, but
contrary to ecological economics, growth is not pursued for its own sake but rather
for the sake of money-value expansion under the competitive pressures generated by
market forces and in the context of fundamental class division. Unless this
specifically capitalist growth dynamic is challenged by challenging the class structure
and the rule of money value that cause ‘‘economic growth,’’ no solution to the life
crises that capitalism generates can reasonably be expected.
The problem of ecological economics is in large part due to its failure to seriously
consider the depth principles of Marx’s critique of capitalism, which was the first to
argue that the class relationships and competitive dynamics that structure specifically capitalist markets generate a long-term contradiction between the development
of the capitalist economy and the health of natural and social life-support systems.
No one has done more than John Bellamy Foster to uncover the hidden ecological
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
120
NOONAN
value of Marx’s understanding of the labor process as a metabolic interchange
between human beings and the natural world. If nature is a presupposition of all
human labor, no socially organized labor process can be materially rational that
destroys over the long term the most basic material presupposition of its own
existence (Foster 2000, 155/77). Perhaps even more important, as Foster and Clark
remind us, Marx always distinguished between economic value and ‘‘real wealth.’’
Real wealth, they argue, that ‘‘comes from nature and labour power is concerned
with the satisfaction of genuine human needs’’ (Foster and Clark 2009, 13). This
conception of real wealth is indeed life-grounded in the sense in which I employ the
term here and a needed corrective to both neoclassical economics and narrow
conceptions of labor as the source of all need-satisfying resources. Nevertheless
Foster, like Marx, never attempts to systematically articulate what ‘‘genuine human
needs’’ are nor does he consider the ranges of life value expressed and enjoyed
through the expression of human capacities not comprehended under the category of
productive labor. While I agree with Foster that the ‘‘productivist’’ critique of Marx
overlooks his and Engels’s ecological concerns with soil fertility, pollution, health
conditions in factories, and the social conditions of urban working-class life, what
remains unsaid in this valuable rereading is that Marx discloses the material
irrationality of capitalism from the objective side of its processes, but leaves
untouched the subjective side: that is, what it would be rational for people to
demand in a socialist economy. Marx has little to say about the rationality of
microeconomic choices because he does not question the material rationality of the
category of ‘‘use value.’’ In my terms, he fails to perceive that materially rational
demand, like materially rational production, must be limited to the consumption of
use values that have life value rather than use values generally.
This problem is to some extent recognized and addressed in the work of ecosocialist
David Schwartzman, who singles out the military-industrial complex for its profound
waste of resources in the production of the means of death. Implicit in this critique is
the recognition that any materially rational expenditure of resources and energy must
be life-serving rather than life-negating (Schwartzman 2009, 6/33). However,
Schwartzman does not develop this insight further into an analysis of the systematic
derangement of the idea of ‘‘rational choice’’ under capitalism, but focuses instead
on the scientific foundations of a democratic socialist economy based upon solar
rather than fossil-fuel energy. While quite illuminating in its own right, the success of
such an alternative cannot be predicated on scientific grounds alone, but must
involve the wider and deeper rethinking of what one means by rationality and
productivity in the context of a systematic explication of life value in its multiple
dimensions.
In order to understand the full meaning of life value, we must begin from certain
fundamental facts about life in general and human life in particular. Four key points
stand out. First, life forms a continuum in which each life form depends in specific
ways on the natural field of life support. Life forms have wider or narrower ranges of
life capacities, but all depend ultimately upon their ability to satisfy their life
requirements, which, at the most basic level, involves transforming energy from the
environment to fuel their metabolic processes and life activities. Hence one can say
that nature is the most basic form of what McMurtry calls the ‘‘life-ground of value’’
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
VALUE AND LIFE VALUE
121
(1998, 23). The life ground of value is the connection between living things and the
material conditions that sustain them, allow them to grow, and act in their
characteristic ways. Second, when we turn to specifically human life, it becomes
clear that human beings depend not only on their metabolism with nature but also
upon social interaction in order to consciously express and enjoy our basic organic
capacities to sense, feel, move, think, imagine, and create. Hence, for human life,
the life ground of value has a social as well as a natural form. Third, and restricting
ourselves now to human life, it follows that humans, both in order to persist and in
order to live meaningful and valuable lives, must live within natural fields of life
support and social fields of life development that satisfy our natural and social life
requirements. Where these natural and social life requirements are not met, human
beings are harmed, either in their metabolic functioning or in their ability to express
and enjoy their human capacities in meaningful and valuable ways. Life requirements, therefore, are natural inputs or social institutions and practices that human
beings must satisfy if they are not to be objectively harmed in their natural organism
and social being (McMurtry 1998, 267). Finally, and following from the third point, life
is better or worse for human beings according to the degree to which our lives are
able to freely express and enjoy life capabilities in more ‘‘inclusively coherent
ranges’’ (McMurtry 2010, 73). The qualifier ‘‘inclusively coherent ranges’’ is necessary
so as to avoid the problems of a measure of overall social health like Pareto
optimality, which is blind not only to damage to the natural life-support system but
also to exploitative and oppressive social relationships. The goal of maximally
coherent ranges of life-capacity expression and enjoyment is contingent upon the
degree to which the natural field of life support and the social field of life
development satisfy or do not satisfy fundamental life requirements.
Life value, it follows, is the most general form of value possible and human life
value is its highest known expression. For human beings, that which has life value is
any resource, institution, or practice that satisfies a life requirement or is an
expressed and enjoyed capacity enabled by the satisfaction of a life requirement
whose expression and enjoyment contributes positively to the life value of others
(McMurtry 2002, 155). It is the life value of resources, institutions, and practices that
explains why people ought to and are justified in caring and concerning themselves
with changing social relationships when those social relationships deprive them of one
or more life requirements.
Human life value is thus limited to the range of life requirements and
the constellations of life-capacity expression and enjoyment that make a positive
contribution to the natural field of life support and the social field of life
development. At the same time, though subject to objective limits, life value is
not an external standard imposed from on high upon subjective consciousness. Note
that anything that has life value as an expression of human capacities must also be
enjoyed by the consciousness that expresses it. Where consciousness is not alienated
from the life ground of value, it is capable on its own of discovering for itself those
forms of capacity expression that have and those that do not have life value and thus
choosing, without imposition from above, modes of individuation and action that are
both subjectively satisfying and objectively beneficial to the fields of life support and
life development of which one is a member.
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
122
NOONAN
The evidence for this claim not only comes from life-value philosophy, but is
corroborated in much humanistic psychological research, such as that undertaken by
Tim Kasser. Kasser notes the richer quality of experienced happiness in activities he
calls ‘‘intrinsically motivating’’ as opposed to those actions (like shopping for
superfluities) that are compelled by an external reward system. In such cases,
subjects who reflectively attend to their own feelings discover that the intrinsically
motivated activities produce richer and more lasting feelings of happiness while
behaviors compelled by an external reward system produce only fleeting feelings of
satisfying an urge which reappears no sooner has it been satisfied (Kasser 2002, 77).
The field of expressed and enjoyed life value is open and not predetermined by
philosophical argument. It excludes nothing of what human life really requires for its
existence and goodness but includes nothing that, when produced, consumed, or
appropriated, destroys life value or contributes nothing to it. Thus, producing
armaments is ultimately life-destructive since their primary use is to threaten,
wound, or kill other human beings. The routinized consumption of status commodities
with no link back to the development of our human capacities for feeling, thought,
imagination, or creation contributes nothing of real life value to human life, since by
this compelled behavior, nothing of life value for self or others is produced. In order
to understand life value more fully, it is necessary to examine in more detail how it is
anchored in the three dimensions of human life.
Each dimension of the human life space-time continuum is unique but exists only
in relation to the other two. The natural dimension of human life is grounded in
our biology and gives rise to a set of obvious natural life requirements. The
sociocultural dimension of human life is grounded in our biological nature (we can
survive only through social interaction), but is expressed through the emergent
properties of conscious and intentional action in institutionally and symbolically
mediated contexts. Consciousness gives rise to irreducible social life requirements
such as love and care, especially while young, education through which the
imaginative and cognitive capacities of conscious may be developed, a political
system in which we can participate in the production of the laws we will have to
obey, a cultural system that preserves and creates natural and artistic beauty, and
a democratically planned economic system that is steered by the goal of creating
social space for individuals to make real positive contributions through their work
to the well-being of others. The third dimension links the natural and social.
Because human beings are natural beings, we are mortal. Our lifetime is finite, and
the goodness and badness of our lives thus depends upon what we are able to
become over the limited course of a human life. Thus, in addition to natural and
social life requirements, there is also a temporal life requirement to experience
time as an open matrix of possibilities for free activity rather than a closed
structure of routine with which we must comply.1
While none of these particular life requirements is foreign to Marx’s work, Marx
nowhere makes explicit the underlying idea of life value that links them together in a
1. Space prevents a complete analysis and defense of these life requirements. For a more
detailed historical and philosophical examination and defense, see Noonan (2006).
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
VALUE AND LIFE VALUE
123
continuum. Nor have subsequent generations of Marxists done so.2 Part of the reason
he does not, I will suggest, is because his systematic critique of capitalism is
conducted in terms of a concept of value that is, like the classical conception of value
from which it derives, exclusively focused on the value of commodities. In the
Grundrisse, for example, Marx defines value in general as ‘‘not only the exchangeability of this commodity in general, but its specific exchangeability. It is at once the
indicator of the ratio in which the commodity exchanges for others and the indication
of the ratio in which it has already been exchanged for others (materialised labor
time) in the process of production. Value is a commodity’s quantitatively determined
exchangeability’’ (1986b, 78). In volume 1 of Capital, the definition is further refined.
‘‘Once we have abstracted from the determining qualities of commodities,’’ Marx
argues, ‘‘there is nothing left but what is common to them all . . . human labour in the
abstract . . . all that these things can tell us is that human labour power has been
expended in their production, that human labour is embodied in them. When looked
at as crystals of their social substance, common to them all, they are*/Values’’
(1986c, 46).
I contend that Marx conflates the general form of value with the general form of
the value of commodities. If we stick with his general definition of value, then
anything that is not inside the production and distribution process of capitalism
literally has no value. His conception of ‘‘real wealth’’ allows us to bring the life value
of nature into account, but remains too narrow, as I noted above, to comprehend the
full scope of life value. While one might rejoin that my argument rests on an
equivocation, that I am using value in a wide, normative sense and Marx is using it in a
narrow, economic sense for contextual reasons that I ignore, I think that such a
rejoinder misses the deeper philosophical and political point. The point is that the
fields of life value are much wider than the field of economic value and real wealth,
and both are embedded in and depend upon the wider fields of life value that Marx’s
critique of capitalism presupposes but does not explicate.3 The dynamics of capitalist
markets are such that they are driven to colonize all fields of life value: that is, to
subordinate them to the money-value system that rules the capitalist economy. The
problem here is not just that, as Marx would have it, the capitalist colonization of life
space and time interposes exchange value between human beings and the use values
of the commodities they now must purchase, but more profoundly, that the capitalist
exchange-value/use-value relation obscures the life value both presuppose. If
socialism restricts its arguments to the formula that socialism will free use values
from the rule of exchange value, without first asking whether the use values it will
liberate from the commodity form will have life value, then it risks repeating the
same underlying alienation of its economy from the life ground of value and thus
potentially repeating the same materially irrational goal of endless growth and the
2. In the broad Marxist tradition, Marcuse comes closest to an explicit idea of life value. See
especially Marcuse (1969, 7/22, 46).
3. Istvan Mészáros approaches this sort of argument in his most recent work insofar as he
grounds his argument against capitalist ‘‘antivalue’’ in a universal conception of human moral
value linked to our mortality and creativity, but again an explicit and explicitly defended
conception of life value is absent (see Mészáros 2008, 35/43).
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
124
NOONAN
same leveling utilitarianism of life purpose that its critique of capitalism ought to
overcome.4 Yet Marx does not issue this challenge, instead defining use value in
relation to any and all human purposes without any anchor in the satisfaction of real
life requirements. For Marx, a use value is ‘‘a thing that by its properties satisfies
human wants of some sort or another. The nature of such wants, whether, for
instance, they stem from the stomach or from fancy, makes no difference’’ (1986c,
43).
The key point may be restated and deepened as follows. While any use value
produced in a democratic socialist life economy must have life value, not everything
that has life value is exclusively a use value. The emotional labor that parents expend
in loving their children has use value to children in so far as they require it. Its life
value, however, is not exhausted in its instrumental usefulness to children. Without
love and care, children can fail to thrive and tend to develop psychosocial pathologies
which impede their ability to love and care for others in turn, but with it they grow
into caring adults who care about others in turn (Fraad 2008, 270/83; more generally,
see Noddings 1984, 59/64; Kasser 2002, 88/9). The full life value of emotional labor
includes the growth of self beyond egocentric concern for self-maximization toward
recognition of the equal life value of others. It embraces both subject and object of
this labor in a higher unity of shared life purpose. The care expressed and received in
emotional labor is itself life-affirming insofar as through it one grows and enriches
one’s own life by creating the conditions in which another’s life grows and is enriched.
That which is life-valuable always opens the interests of the self to the interests of
others in this way. To understand life value is thus to understand that there is no
ultimate conflict between self and other and self and world, but rather that one’s
own good is always bound up with the good of others and the world to which one
belongs. This recognition is valuable in itself and not simply as a means of liferequirement satisfaction.
The limitations of the idea of use value are even more evident if we think of the
human life requirement for free time. Free time, as I said, is not simply a given
quantity of time outside paid and unpaid employment which the agent in question can
use however he or she feels like using it. The life value of free time is not that it
enables us to do what we feel like without regard for others, but that it frees us to
imagine and project how we might individuate ourselves through those capacities we
choose to express and enjoy in ways that give back to the natural and social fields of
life support that have borne us to the point where we are capable of thinking and
acting as individual agents.
Thus, while the life value of anything is always damaged by its commodificiation, it
does not follow that this damage can be undone by conceiving of every life value as a
use value and grounding a democratic socialist life economy in the production of use
values. Let us consider this crucial point from the perspective of Marx’s aphorism that
a socialist society will be based on the principle, ‘‘from each according to his
abilities, to each according to his needs’’ (1978, 531). In the context of worldwide
4. Perhaps surprisingly, ecological economics, too, fails to anchor use value and human needs in
the life ground of value as well. For representative examples of the problem, see Victor 2008,
132, and Brown and Carver 2009, 56/7.
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
VALUE AND LIFE VALUE
125
ecological crisis, the task for socialists is to be able to specify exactly what we mean
by needs. Marx is of little help in this regard. As both Heller and Fraser have shown,
Marx uses the term, if not loosely, at least in many different senses that he never
organizes systematically (see Heller 1976; Fraser 1998). The lack of systematicity
becomes a problem when we focus on the category of ‘‘luxury needs.’’ For Marx, the
category of luxury needs is historically variable. With rising productivity, that which
was once a luxury becomes an object of mass consumption. However, once an object
becomes an object of mass consumption, it begins to recode people’s feeling of selfesteem (Fraser 1998, 134). To lack that which everyone else has is to feel diminished
in the eyes of one’s fellow citizens. If it is true that former luxury needs retain their
being as needs, and if a socialist society must distribute according to needs, then
there is potentially no limit to what people may demand of a socialist economy. Marx
does not challenge the psychology of consumer demand as a capitalist pathology, but
appears to regard it as normal. As he argues in relation to housing, ‘‘a house may be
large or small, as long as the surrounding houses are equally small it satisfies all social
demands for a dwelling. But let a palace arise beside the little house, and it shrinks
from a little house to a hut. The little house now shows that its owner has only very
slight or no demands to make . . . the owner of the small house will feel more and
more uncomfortable’’ (1973, 163). Yet this feeling is materially irrational. As Marx
himself notes, the little house satisfies the owner’s life requirement for a house. The
proper socialist conclusion, it seems to me, is not to accept the owner’s feelings, but
to work to change them by pointing out their materially irrational implications.
This sort of questioning of individual motivations seems to invite the rejoinder that
it depends upon an imperious use of philosophy that is unlikely to be efficacious given
people’s propensity to live happily with conflicted motivations. ‘‘Do I contradict
myself? Very well, I contradict myself. (I am large, I contain multitudes),’’ wrote Walt
Whitman (1998, 78). Simply pointing out the irrationality of demands for more than is
life-sufficient may sound like mere moralizing from the perspective of the person
criticized. The psychology of political change is no doubt complex and beyond the
scope of my competence and this paper. Nevertheless, self-transformation seems
closely bound up with recognition of the reality of initially unnoticed harms. To simply
hector people about their choices generally (and appropriately) produces a defensive
reaction that hardens the problematic behaviour. But to work with a person in order
to help them see the unnoticed harms that unreflective choices cause can prove an
aid to self-transformation. A doctor who simply lectures a patient about the ill effects
of smoking will not likely be as successful in promoting healthier choices as the one
who accepts the patient’s choice, but then demonstrates what the real but
unobserved effects on the patient’s lungs are. The point is that the social critique
of individual choices must avoid pontificating and instead concentrate on building a
dialogue through which the person him- or herself begins to be self-reflective and
self-critical.
One could further rejoin that my critique of Marx is anachronistic*/that Marx could
in no way have anticipated the social damage that the psychology of consumer society
normalized and rationalized by the assumptions of orthodox microeconomics helps to
cause and reproduce. There is some merit in this argument. However, it cannot be
used to obviate the force of the criticism in relation to contemporary socialists, and
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
126
NOONAN
especially those who call themselves ecosocialists. It is true that ecosocialists are
aware that an unrestricted conception of needs as anything for which anyone has a
use risks making socialist society potentially as ecocidal as capitalism. As Kovel,
arguing against McNally, maintains, ‘‘Are workers*/not just in the industrial West, but
also in China, India, Indonesia, etc., as required by the internationalist ethos of
socialism*/to have more cars . . . without further deterioration of ecosystems?
Questions like these scarcely arise in socialist discourse, which . . . has significant
trouble going beyond capitalism’s fatal addiction to growth’’ (Kovel 2007, 228).
Kovel’s solution, which I fully endorse, is to replace the capitalist addiction to growth
with an ideal of sufficiency linked to the value of deeper self-realization in all
dimensions of human life (228). Where I disagree with him is in his conception of
needs.
Here, like Marx, he concedes too much to capitalist consumer psychology when he
grants that the addictions that people develop under capitalism actually rank as
needs. ‘‘As capitalism penetrates life worlds, it alters them in ways that foster its
accumulation, chiefly by introducing a sense of dissatisfaction or lack . . . In this way,
children develop such a craving for caffeine-laced, sugar-loaded, or artificially
sweetened soft drinks that it may be said that they positively need them’’ (Kovel
2007, 53; cf. Kovel and Lowy 2001). If one defines needs, as I do here, as life
requirements, then it can never be the case that our addictions are actual, positive
needs. Needs as life requirements are not simply wants for use values that we lack.
They are our actual, positive connection to the natural and social fields of life
support; they are our essential guide to the fundamentally practical question of what
goods a democratic socialist life economy ought to produce and how. If we allow that
consumer addictions are needs, then we use need in a purely descriptive sense, which
then undermines the normative force of the difference between a need and consumer
demand (for a non-Marxist appreciation of this point, see Braybrooke 1987, 8). If we
allow that my addiction to smoking is a need and also that my thirst for water is a
need, then the moral logic of satisfying either is the same. If ‘‘need’’ implies
necessity of satisfaction, and necessity of satisfaction imposes a moral duty on others
to satisfy it, then it would follow that there is a moral equivalence between satisfying
my addiction to nicotine and satisfying my thirst for water. Yet clearly there cannot
be a moral equivalence since the outcomes are opposed to each other: life in one
case, speedier death and ill health for others in the vicinity of the secondhand smoke
in the other.
Thus, the slogan of a democratic socialist society cannot be ‘‘from each according
to his or her abilities, to each according to his or her needs,’’ but rather, ‘‘from each
according to his or her capabilities to make a life-valuable contribution to the natural
and social fields of life support, to each according to his or her life requirements in
the three dimensions of being alive as a human being.’’ Without these qualifications
there can be no guarantee that socialism will not prove as materially irrational
as capitalism in its use of the natural field of life support, or that it will not prove as
culturally, ethically, and spiritually empty as capitalism in the social field of life
support. A democratic socialist society must be a life-grounded society, and a lifegrounded society must operate with a life economy in which ‘‘production and
distribution [are] for life need, and that in turn for life capacity and experience in
VALUE AND LIFE VALUE
127
more comprehensive enjoyment and expression [for] this is the only ultimate value on
earth. Any sane [materially rational] economy is these to serve it in opening horizons
of life-worth’’ (McMurtry 2002, 124). It is only with the fundamental idea of life value
in mind that we can fully understand the causes of the fundamental forms of life crisis
that currently rage across the globe.
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
Life Requirements, Life Capacities, and Capitalist Life Crisis
As I argued in the first section, the fundamental concepts of classical and neoclassical
economics are incapable of understanding the life crises caused by the colonization of
life space and time by capitalist commodity and labor markets. This is the case
because, unlike Marx, who regards the productive life of the species as ‘‘lifeengendering life,’’ the orthodox economic understanding of productivity is life-blind
(Marx 1975, 276). Any process is productive (in the capitalist sense of the term) which
produces a product or service that can be sold at a profit. The costs to life are not
normally factored into the measure of productivity. Thus, when oil was at $147 a
barrel, production in the Alberta oil sands was booming, employment was being
created at breathtaking speed, and Canada as a result had the highest growth rates in
the G-8 group of nations. What was not factored into the equation was the damage
caused to the Athabasca River watershed and the health of the people of the First
Nations who live on its shores, or the fact that it requires nearly as much energy in the
form of burning natural gas to produce the steam that separates the heavy crude from
the sand as is produced in the form of usable oil (Hatch and Price 2008). The
‘‘economically’’ and environmentally rational courses of action contradict each
other.
These problems are obvious once they have been separated out from orthodox
economic concepts. What is less obvious, but even more important from the
standpoint of constructing an alternative, is that because capitalism is a total system
insofar as it is impelled constantly to expand, it necessarily colonizes human-life
space and time, and through this colonization it creates a contradictory form of total
dependence of each individual on its growth dynamics. My use of ‘‘colonization’’ here
must be distinguished from that of Habermas because, for Habermas, the life-world is
the world of symbolic communication only (Habermas 1987, 119/27). Actual
biological life and its natural life-support system has no place in his conception of
the life-world. Yet it is just because capitalism colonizes the natural life-support
system and turns it to the purpose of producing money value rather than life value
that it is able to colonize the sociocultural life-support system (Meiksins Wood 2002,
95/142). There develops a life crisis wherever the actual life requirements or life
capabilities of human beings are made dependent upon capitalist labor and
commodity markets for their satisfaction or expression and enjoyment. The natural,
sociocultural, and temporal crises of human life are thus expressed as the loss of life
value of natural life-requirement satisfiers, sociocultural institutions and interactions, and the human experience of time consequent upon their subordination to the
money-value system that rules human activity in a capitalist society.
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
128
NOONAN
I cannot examine in particular detail each manifestation of life crisis. Instead, I
want to concentrate on the contradictory nature of market dependence as the key to
understanding why life crises persist even when, as in the case of the crisis of the
natural field of life support, their reality is undeniable. To begin we need to focus on
the moment of real dependence. Where even the basic means of life are priced
commodities, people become dependent upon money and therefore labor markets in
order to survive. Moreover, where the rule of money is universal, the ‘‘true social
bond,’’ as Marx says*/not only people’s lives but also their sense of well-being or their
ability to pursue what each calls a good life*/depends upon accumulating surplus
money with which one can participate in commodity markets and can afford to enjoy
free time, travel, and so forth (Marx 1975, 306). As Foster argues, ‘‘caught up in this
unrelenting process of accumulation and creative destruction, the system runs
roughshod over each and every thing that stands in its path: all human and natural
requirements that interfere with the accumulation of capital are considered barriers
to be overcome’’ (Foster 2008, 5).
The contradiction lies in the fact that, at the same time as dependence on labor
and commodity markets is absolutely real, it is equally absolutely illusory. As natural
organisms, human beings do not depend upon access to money but access to clean air,
potable water, nutritious food, protection from violent traumas, and health care. As
sociocultural beings considered from the perspective of what our conscious organism
is capable of doing, we are not dependent upon access to commodity markets for our
well-being, but rather on each other as mediated through social institutions through
which we cultivate our cognitive and imaginative capacities and which create real
opportunities for life-valuable work and political participation. Finally, considered as
finite or mortal beings, the experience of time is, as the existential frame of our
lives, ultimately not a matter of how much free time we can purchase, but of how we
are able to dispose ourselves to own future: that is, whether time is experienced as an
open matrix of possibilities for action or a closed structure of routine that we will
escape only at death.
Even though people might admit in the abstract that there is a life crisis where the
natural field of life support is systematically degraded, or where social institutions
are used to reproduce existing structures of inequality, or where culture becomes
vacuous and disposable, or where time is a closed structure of routine, the systematic
solution to these life crises cannot be easily seen from within the capitalist system
itself. More precisely, because the moment of absolute dependence is real, it is
extremely difficult for anyone whose livelihood depends week to week on wages to
see through to the illusory moment. The consequence is that when crises are
recognized, they are not recognized as crises internal to the system but seem to be
immediate individual or family crises for which a solution must be found in the near
present. Thus, for a worker laid off from the oil sands industry, the crisis does not
appear to be the looming environmental disaster predicted by environmentalists, but
the worker’s own unemployment, to be solved by stimulating demand for oil,
increasing its price, and making investment in oil sands profitable once again. The
wider and deeper forms of life crisis, the leveling of all human life requirements
and life capacities to their money value, and the determination of the content of
good and bad lives by the monetary returns different life ways are expected to bring,
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
VALUE AND LIFE VALUE
129
sound platitudinous when the money runs out. The British prime minister Gordon
Brown aimed to be reassuring to workers when he told the U.S. Congress that ‘‘while
today people are anxious and feel insecure, over the next two decades billions of
people in other countries are going to move from being simply producers of goods to
being consumers of our goods, and in this way our world economy will double in size’’
(Olive and Walkom 2009, IN4). Even assuming such growth is theoretically possible, its
energy demands and the waste that it will necessarily produce would greatly
exacerbate rather than solve the natural life crisis that underlies all forms of
capitalist life crisis. Given the real moment of market dependence, however, people
quite understandably demand that governments take whatever steps are necessary to
restart the cycles of money value growth. The damage these cycles cause to the other
forms of life value cannot be seen when the immediate form of life crisis affecting the
majority of people is an economic crisis, not of the general human capacity to
produce sufficient life-requirement satisfiers but of the system-specific requirement
of capitalism to do so profitably.
Where life-requirement satisfaction and life-capacity expression and enjoyment
depend on market access, social life activity becomes structured as a series of zero
sum competitions over the rewards the existing social structure provides. That which
has real life value*/healthy children and adults, the free development of cognitive and
imaginative capabilities across educational levels, meaningful and life-valuable work,
beauty open to the experience of all, democratic political systems, free time
experienced as an open matrix of possibilities for life-valuable self-expression*/none
none of which ultimately requires more than the satisfaction of natural and social
life requirements through conscious, cooperative human interaction in the natural
field of life support and the social field of life development, appears to depend
completely upon the state of market forces. The blindness of capitalism to the
destruction of natural life value is replicated socially to the extent that people accept
capitalist appearances for ultimate and unchanging reality: namely, that the good life
means success in zero sum competitions for maximum monetary returns to self.
On the other hand, there are encouraging signs emerging over the past year that
economic crisis is catalyzing a renewal of mass oppositional politics. There were the
mass demonstrations against the government in Greece, the forcing out of office of
the government of Iceland in the wake of the country’s bankruptcy, factory
occupations in the United States and Canada, a series of general strikes in France,
and the overthrow through mass action of the government of Martinique. In the short
term in the OECD countries these emerging movements are not likely to converge
around a democratic socialist alternative.5 Nor would it be reasonable to expect them
to do so in the short term. Theorists who argue that the only solution to capitalist life
crises is a democratic-socialist life economy face a contradiction between the
futurity of their promises and the immediate reality of life crisis that workers and
others face. If this contradiction is to be solved, it must be possible to supplement the
negative critique of capitalism with positive examples of at least partially
5. The Web site Radical Perspectives on the Crisis provides daily updates from correspondents
around the globe on the many struggles that have and continue to break out: http://
www.google.sites.radicalperspectives.org (accessed 9 March and 11 April 2009).
130
NOONAN
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
decolonized life spaces and times. These real working alternatives, what Kovel calls
‘‘prefigurative practices,’’ are zones in which life requirements are met through selforganizing, democratic, non-market-based production (Kovel 2007, 207/41). In a
prefigurative practice, another world is not only possible; it is actual and thus aids in
the struggle against the illusory side of market dependence by partially negating its
real side. To conclude, I will focus on three such prefigurative practices: nonstate
self-organizing collectives, the democratic moment of existing liberal-democratic
political institutions, and Venezuela’s ongoing experiment with ‘‘twenty-first century
socialism.’’
Reclaiming the Life Space-Time Continuum
If one looks for them, prefigurative practices of the first type appear everywhere.
They range in size from the very small (a community garden in an inner-city
neighborhood producing food for local use) to communities in their own right (like the
Landless Workers Movement of Brazil, which currently involves more than 500,000
members building a cooperative democratic society on land for which the capitalist
agricultural economy has no use). These prefigurative movements are not limited to
agriculture. In the wake of the Argentinian fiscal crisis of 2001, workers not only
occupied their workplaces, but took them over and continued production under
workers’ control. We should also include among this type of prefigurative practice
workers’ cooperatives that, while they compete in the market, are not organized for
the sake of market success but to meet members’ life requirements.
What all have in common is that they have succeeded in decolonizing life space
that has been deemed ‘‘waste’’ by the capitalist economy. For capitalism, ‘‘waste’’ is
anything that it cannot exploit for a profit (not anything that has no life value). Hence
much of what capitalism wastes, especially the fallow productive capabilities of
workers and farmers who cannot find remunerative employment, is actually lifevaluable. The realization of life value, however, is impossible so long as unemployed
workers continue to search for work in labor markets. The genius of each of these
prefigurative movements is that the organizers have understood that nothing
prevented the occupation and life-valuable use of spaces (fields, factories, etc.)
that capitalism had abandoned. Through the simple decision to use what capitalism
had no use for, life value, both in the form of life-requirement satisfiers and the wider
and deeper expression and enjoyment of life capabilities in new democratic
institutions and modes of work, is created. Thus to the objection, all too common,
that it is impossible to build a noncapitalist economy, these prefigurative practices
offer a partial but objective rejoinder. The work of J. K. Gibson-Graham has done
much to explicate the life-reclaiming logic of non-market-based, self-organizing,
democratic, local economic practices. Gibson-Graham explains that ‘‘alternative
cooperative and intentional economic activities . . . provide a ‘click’ moment that has
released non-capitalist imaginaries from the iron-clad imperative of . . . capitalist
modernization’’ (Gibson-Graham 2006, 75/6). This ‘‘click’’ moment is exactly what is
required if socialists are to convince people that they are capable of building a new
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
VALUE AND LIFE VALUE
131
world. The alternative is not a paper-and-pencil sketch; it is an incipient reality
replicated almost anywhere one chooses to look.
At the same time, however, these experiments are not without well-known
limitations. The most important is that they leave the question of challenging for
political power unaddressed (Mészáros 2008, 257). By occupying an abandoned niche,
local experiments in democratic self-organization succeed to some extent by flying
under the radar. If they grow too large and begin to run up against life space that
capitalism still finds it profitable to exploit, they risk suffering defeat at the hands of
state power arrayed so as to defend the capitalist colonization of life space. It does
not follow from this argument that any preset limitation to how far these local
experiments can succeed can be established. It only sounds a caution that at some
point their success will be challenged not only by competitive forces from the
market, but by political forces from the state. If the first type of prefigurative
movement is to become the basis for an alternative democratic socialist society,
therefore, they must address the problem of how to contend with organized state
violence. Yet here, too, there are prefigurative institutions whose life-value potential
has been generally neglected by Marxists (including myself). Those institutions are
the existing democratic institutions of liberal-democratic capitalist society.
Marxists have generally been loath to attempt to exploit the transformative
possibilities of existing liberal-democratic institutions because they have, correctly,
understood that these institutions have coevolved with the capitalist economy so as
to ensure, through both hegemonic practices and outright violence when necessary,
its reproduction and growth (see Meiksins Wood 1995, 19/48, 181/237). What has
been ignored by this historically correct analysis, however, is that to the extent that
these institutions depend upon their democratic credentials for their legitimacy, they
create spaces that can be exploited by a determined political movement for radically
transformational ends. Concretely, no law of which I am aware would make a
democratic-socialist party illegal, no law prevents such a party from contesting
elections, and no law could prevent such a party, properly organized and determined,
from winning. Any party holding political power has tremendous latitude to begin to
change laws and even constitutions. Hence one can imagine a gradual, step-by-step
recolonization of life space and time by a legal democratic-socialist party working
with the social movements involved in the local practices of reclaiming the life spacetime continuum and together wielding the existing democratically legitimate powers
of the state to internally transform it.
If life value really is better served by a democratic-socialist economy, then it must
be possible to convince the majority of people through open, public deliberation and
argument to mobilize for that future through a legal democratic party capable of
winning state power. We have seen the disasters that have followed upon vanguard
attempts to overcome capitalism at one blow; Marxists, who claim to understand
history, ought to be the first to learn from it. The first lesson that we should have
learned is that it is not possible for a small collective of minds to master the immense
complexity of social institutions that have evolved over hundreds of years. Rather
than heroic, immediate transformation, we should instead struggle to build new
democratic-socialist parties, to win the democratic struggle for state power on the
basis of an open program of progressive institutional change that will accelerate the
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
132
NOONAN
social logic of progressive decolonization of life space and time by using the law to
take back for life-value production the resources and institutions currently exploited
for money-value production.
This point leads to the third prefigurative practice, which can be interpreted as a
synthesis of the first two. It is the societywide set of experiments in democratic social
and economic organization currently under way in Venezuela and Bolivia. Given the
need for brevity, I will focus on the former. Venezuela teaches three important
lessons. First, it is exceedingly difficult to delegitimate duly elected governments
backed by real mass movements. The Venezuelan right has been forced to rely on
failed coup attempts because it has not been able to defeat the Chávez movement
at the polls. Second, Venezuela provides concrete evidence that the historical
enmeshment of liberal-democratic forms with capitalist society establishes no
concrete limits on what popularly backed state power can be used to accomplish.
That the Venezuelan state has been, for most of its history, used to oppress the
majority of people at the behest of imperialism has not prevented Chávez from
transforming state institutions from within. This internal transformation has been
accomplished by changing the constitution through constitutional means, backed
each step of the way by clear supportive majorities. Finally, and this is perhaps the
most important lesson, Chávez, despite his rhetorical bluster, has actually been
cautious and deliberate in his efforts to decolonize life space and time. In other
words, he has recognized the problem that social complexity and globalization pose
to the problem of fundamental socioeconomic transformation and has met this
challenge by adopting an evolutionary model of social change. By ‘‘evolutionary
model’’ I mean that his governments have given one set of reforms time to stabilize
before deepening and extending them. In this way the insuperable problems of
centralized planning are avoided while, at the same time, real practices and
institutions of democratic self-organization and life requirement/based production
and distribution are developing. I concur with Greg Wilpert’s assessment that ‘‘the
creation of a social economy clearly represents one of the Chavez govenment’s most
dramatic efforts to move away from capitalism towards self-management . . . It is not
a frontal assault against capitalism, as socialist parties used to advocate, but a much
subtler assault, where self-managed enterprises co-exist with traditional capitalist
enterprises . . . The much slower substitution of the capitalist economy by the social
economy reduces the level of resistance from domestic and international capital . . .
thus making the success of such a transition greater’’ (Wilpert 2007, 191). The key to
this transformationalist and constructive approach to building socialism lies in its
ability to generate and sustain a progressive social momentum that solves problems
on a case-by-case basis. The existence of real social momentum plus a properly
modest approach to problem solving has so far enabled the Venezuelan experiment to
proceed democratically, without coercion save in cases of open assaults upon
democracy by the right wing, and, most important, successfully as measured by
real improvements in the ability of Venezuelans to meet their life requirements
across the human life space-time continuum and to develop their life capabilities in
concert with others in a virtuous social circle of widening and deepening democratic
self-development.
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
VALUE AND LIFE VALUE
133
There can be no denying the reality of multiple life crises today. If it is true that
these life crises are systematically caused by the normal dynamics of capitalism, then
it follows that solutions require fundamental social change. Social change, however,
does not occur as a consequence of logical inference, but only through political
struggles. The history of Stalinism provides abundant empirical evidence about how
not to attempt political change. The emerging history of transformationalist and
constructive attempts at decolonizing life space and time offers a much more
promising route. In North America and Europe, the consolidation and deepening of
existing small-scale experiments in life space and time reclamation demand the
creation of a new political movement capable of both winning arguments and winning
power and, beyond that plateau, of using power to initiate a series of step-by-step
changes that build support because they work. As Marx argued, humans must prove
the truth in practice. Such complex truths as the superiority of a democratic socialist
society can only be proven over large and indefinite periods of time. The open-ended
character of socialist transformation should not be seen as a cause of despair, but
rather as cause for excitement, for the time and space of change is any point at which
we decide to start working together for it.
References
Bello, W. 2009. The global collapse: A non-orthodox view. Z-Net. www.zmag.org/
znet/viewArticle/20638 (accessed 3 March 2009).
Braybrooke, D. 1987. Meeting human needs. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
Press.
Brown, P. G. 2008. The commonwealth of life. Montreal: Black Rose Books.
Brown, P. G., and G. Carver. Right relationship. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler.
Daly, H. 1977. Steady-state economics. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
Daly, H., and J. C. Farley. 2004. Ecological economics: Principles and applications.
Washington, D.C.: Island Press.
Foster, J. B. 2000. Marx’s ecology. New York: Monthly Review Press.
*/*
*/ /. 2008. Capitalism’s environmental crisis: Is technology the answer? Monthly
Review 52 (7): 1/17.
*/*
*/ /, and B. Clark. 2009. The paradox of wealth: Capitalism or ecodestruction.
Monthly Review. www.monthlyreview.org/091101foster-clark.php (accessed 11
December 2009).
Fraad, H. 2008. Toiling in the labour of love. Journal of Psychohistory 35 (3): 270/84.
Fraser, I. 1998. Hegel and Marx: The concept of need. Edinburgh: University of
Edinburgh Press.
Georgescu-Roegen, N. 1971. The entropy law and the economic process. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Gibson-Graham, J. K. 2006. Imagining and enacting a postcapitalist feminist politics.
Women’s Studies Quarterly 34 (1/2): 72/8.
Hatch, C., and M. Price. 2008. Canada’s tar sands: The most destructive project on
earth. Toronto: Environmental Defence. February. www.environmentaldefence.ca
(accessed 18 April 2009).
Habermas, J. 1987. The theory of communicative action, Vol. 2, Lifeworld and
system. Boston: Beacon.
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 14:43 3 December 2010
134
NOONAN
Heller, A. 1976. The theory of need in Karl Marx. New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Kasser, T. 2002. The high price of materialism. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Kovel, J. 2002. The enemy of nature. London: Zed Books.
Kovel, J., and M. Lowy. 2001. An ecosocialist manifesto, 2001.
www.ecosocialistnetwork.org (accessed 2 May 2009).
Marcuse, H. 1969. An essay on liberation. Boston: Beacon.
Marx, K. 1973. Wage labour and capital. In Marx and Engels: Selected works, vol. 1.
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
*/*
*/ /. 1975. Economic and philosophical manuscripts of 1844. In Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels Collected works, vol. 3. New York: International Publishers.
*/*
*/ /. 1978. Critique of the Gotha program. In The Marx-Engels reader, ed. R. C.
Tucker. New York: W. W. Norton.
*/ /. 1986a. Capital. Vol. 3. Moscow: Progress.
*/*
*/*
*/ /. 1986b. Economic manuscripts of 1857/58 (Grundrisse). In Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels Collected works, vol. 28, 49/540. New York: International
Publishers.
*/*
*/ /. 1986c. Capital. Vol. 1. Moscow: Progress.
McMurtry, J. 1998. Unequal freedoms. Toronto: Garamond.
*/*
*/ /. 2002. Value wars. London: Pluto.
*/ /. 2009. Rationality and scientific method: Paradigm shift in an age of collapse.
*/*
Interchange 40 (1): 69/91.
*/*
*/ /. 2010. Philosophy theme: What is good, what is bad? The value of all values
across times, places, and theories. In Encyclopaedia of life-support systems.
Oxford: EOLSS Publishers and UNESCO.
Meiksins Wood, E. 1995. Democracy against capitalism. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
*/*
*/ /. 2002. The origins of capitalism: A longer view. London: Verso.
Mészáros, I. 2008. The challenge and burden of historical time. New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Noddings, N. 1984. Caring. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Noonan, J. 2006. Democratic society and human needs. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s
University Press.
Olive, D., and T. Walkom. 2009. Will things get worse? Toronto Star, 7 March, IN4.
Schwartzman, D. 2009. Ecosocialism or ecocatastrophe? Capitalism Nature Socialism
20 (1): 6/33.
Victor, P. A. 2008. Managing without growth. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
Whitman, W. 1998. Song of myself. In Leaves of grass. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Wilpert, G. 2007. Changing Venezuela by taking power. London: Verso.