Article
The Political Logic of Victim Impact Statements
Rosebury, Brian
Available at http://clok.uclan.ac.uk/3398/
Rosebury, Brian ORCID: 0000-0002-6154-2685 (2011) The Political Logic of Victim
Impact Statements. Criminal Justice Ethics, 30 (1). pp. 39-67. ISSN 0731-129X
It is advisable to refer to the publisher’s version if you intend to cite from the work.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2011.559061
For more information about UCLan’s research in this area go to
http://www.uclan.ac.uk/researchgroups/ and search for <name of research Group>.
For information about Research generally at UCLan please go to
http://www.uclan.ac.uk/research/
All outputs in CLoK are protected by Intellectual Property Rights law, including
Copyright law. Copyright, IPR and Moral Rights for the works on this site are retained
by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Terms and conditions for use
of this material are defined in the http://clok.uclan.ac.uk/policies/
CLoK
Central Lancashire online Knowledge
www.clok.uclan.ac.uk
Author Posting. (c) John Jay College of Criminal Justice, City University of New York, 2011.
This is the author's version of the work. It is posted here by permission of John Jay College of Criminal Justice
CUNY for personal use, not for redistribution.
The definitive version was published in Criminal Justice Ethics, Volume 30 Issue 1, April 2011.
doi:10.1080/0731129X.2011.559061 (http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2011.559061)
The Political Logic of Victim Impact Statements
BRIAN ROSEBURY
The guilty get a good run in our judicial system while victims can be a dirty word. It's the
world turned upside down. . . .
Prominent defence lawyer Rob Stary, a member of the Law Institute's Criminal Law Section,
believes victim impact statements provide the opportunity to find out how the victim feels. . . .
“They are cathartic in their nature, they're helpful for the victim to articulate their position—
and that's important—and allow the judge when they're determining penalty to understand the
immediate long-term consequences,'' he explained. “Most judges, despite a view that they are
removed from the community, in fact are highly sensitive to the impact upon victims. That's
reflected in sentencing comments all over the place.''
Stary and I agree to disagree on this point.1
I Introduction: a political context
In this paper I discuss three aspects of the continuing debate over the use of Victim Impact
Statements (VIS) in criminal proceedings. I aim to show, in each case, the dependence of key
arguments in favor of VIS on presuppositions that can be characterized as political, in the
sense that they enter the debate not so much through argumentation internal to the ethics of
1
criminal justice, as through the influence of a wider popular and media consensus about the
entitlements of a citizen and the failings of the criminal justice system. I will focus primarily
upon those arguments for VIS that frame them within a discourse of “justice” rather than
“welfare,” but I will acknowledge and distinguish the latter when necessary. I hope that one
contribution of the paper will be to assist clarification of the distinction, and to promote
reconsideration of the weight each type of justification can carry.
An intimate relationship between the discourses of criminal justice and of the wider
political realm is inevitable and indeed desirable. Both are informed by the attempts of people
of goodwill to think rationally about deep and contested moral values, while keeping in clear
view the general and specific facts of human life. We should set aside, plausible though it
may sometimes seem, the notion of a wholly irrational popular sentiment beating down upon,
and potentially corroding, the sober deliberations of the legislators and the courts. Instead I
want to show, by evaluating certain arguments for VIS, that they are open to objections that
can be successfully refuted if, and only if, influential, and rather specific, political
presuppositions are brought to their aid. I do not aim to disprove or discredit these
presuppositions, only to demonstrate their role in the case for VIS, though I believe we may
think differently about the moral and political context of VIS if the analysis is accepted.
What are these presuppositions, and how have they arisen? In contemporary western
culture, most people believe that our social and political apparatus, including law, has value
to the extent that it serves or facilitates individual well-being. The individual life is the locus
of value; social goods are ultimately reducible to an aggregate of individual goods. This is not
a universal or necessary view, and various conservative, religious, and communitarian
traditions offer alternatives, mainly by affirming the existence of intrinsic or irreducibly
social goods,2 or by assailing the concept of individual autonomy. But it is the dominant
belief, natural to a liberal democracy. And within it, often only loosely corresponding to
2
political party allegiances, there are two distinct views of the role of the state and other public
agencies in contributing to individual goods. Both assume that individual human beings are,
by and large, rational decision makers: but they take different views of the kind of society to
that our rational decision making should lead us, and that in turn can best support our future
choices. The crucial difference, simply stated, is that one view envisages (and prefers) a
society of individually acting individuals, the other a society of individually and collectively
acting individuals.3
On the first view, broadly identifiable with market liberalism, the members of the
society are viewed as an aggregate of rationally self-interested and inherently competitive
individuals, each seeking his or her due, and pursuing his or her preferences. Economic
activity is regulated by law, in order that the competition among individuals is fair and
peaceful, but admits as little intervention by the state or other collective agencies as is
consistent with the safe and effective operation of the market. Thanks to the invisible hand of
the market, all—more or less—benefit from the competitiveness of each. The moral
imperative governing our activity in the economic sphere is to compete lawfully as an
individual, honoring contracts and expecting fair reward. To combine with others, except in
the context of contractual relationships among persons, such as those between buyer and
seller or employer and employee, is morally questionable on two counts: we surrender dignity
and autonomy, and we fall under suspicion of seeking to distort the market, through cartels or
the intrusion of political power.
Market liberalism has its origins in classical economics, but took on its distinctive
present-day political character in the later twentieth century, in reaction against the apparent
spread and prestige of centrally-directed economic systems, most menacingly exemplified by
the Soviet Union. Political economists such as Hayek and Friedman criticized state
intervention in the market, not merely for compromising its efficiency as a mechanism for
3
expressing individual choice, but as necessitating definite repressions of liberty. A system of
state intervention, in the name of welfare, redistribution or “positive liberty,” would empower
a governing elite, liable to “declare almost any interest a general interest and . . . make large
numbers serve purposes in which they are not in the least interested” [italics added].4 To this
analysis, the libertarianism of Nozick added the claim that distributions resulting from lawful
free market activity were ipso facto just, and that government intervention in pursuit of a
planned distribution could not but violate individual rights. 5 At a popular level, these beliefs
have helped to form a consensus, or at least a widespread sentiment, that the state and its taxfunded agencies (“big government”) stand in natural opposition to our individual interests
and wishes. In this discourse, the idea that the agencies of the public realm might be serving
to advance our collective interests, not least by limiting and policing the economic power of
the very rich, is ignored or debunked. Indeed, market-dominant private media interests are
able to cast themselves as opponents of an “establishment” that comprises “institutions
hungry for power at the expense of ordinary citizens.”6
The alternative, social liberalism, rejects market liberalism‟s identification of
collective action with institutional coercion. Social liberalism emphasizes the capacity of
rational individuals to choose to act collectively, whether through voluntary organizations
such as labor unions, or, as willing taxpayers and compliant citizens, by suspending or
subordinating the competitive pursuit of individual goods in deference to public institutions
supposed to facilitate the good of all. Since a degree of self-abnegation, at least in the short
term, seems to be required if individual choices are to be pooled in this way to sustain
collective action, social liberalism needs to explain why such a sacrifice is justified, and
indeed psychologically possible, if all good is individual good. It may appeal, for example, to
a Rawlsian moral psychology, in which just institutions enjoy popular consent precisely in
virtue of their manifest justice (“justice” understood, at least in part, as the assurance of due
4
care for the welfare of all individuals including the least fortunate).7 Or it may appeal to the
recognition—most commonly expressed today in the discussion of environmental policy—
that uncoordinated choices can be self-defeating, that an aggregate of purely individuallymotivated choices can create outcomes that nobody wants.8 For social liberals, markets are
not expected to convert individual competition into outcomes more or less good for all.
Rather, the moral imperative for each of us is to aim for the best outcomes, judging whether
these are most likely to be secured by our own individual action, or by subsuming our action
into that of a group or public institution.
There can be little doubt that in the period between the election of Ronald Reagan as
US President in 1980 and the economic collapse of 2008, the market-liberal view gained
strength, winning adherents widely among the intelligentsia, in active political life, and in the
media. I will argue that the rise of VIS is intimately related to this development. It is
connected to the idea of members of society as competitively seeking their personal good, as
they themselves define it, against the background of a diminished expectation that they
should repose their confidence in public institutions.
Why would it matter if this claim proved to be true? On one view, it would matter
very little, except to historians of ideas. It would, at most, provide an example of an idea in
one field becoming a stronger candidate for acceptance because of the presuppositions it
shares with other, increasingly widely-accepted, beliefs. On another view, it would matter
considerably. It might be a bad thing for the criminal law, for example (that is, for the respect
in which it is held), that it should come to be seen primarily as an arena in which individuals
struggle to get their due.
That there is some affinity between the case for VIS and the values of market
liberalism may seem obvious, since the assertion of individual entitlements and preferences
plays a key role in both.9 The main contribution of this paper will be to analyze more fully
5
the structures of (sometimes implicit) argument that unite the presuppositions needed to
defend VIS with those of market liberalism, in particular its anti-collectivism and anti-statism.
Whatever substantive philosophical interest the paper may possess will lie in these analyses
(sections IV-VI); the much shorter sections that precede and follow these three are intended
to provide some necessary context, and to suggest, more polemically, a relation to continuing
wider political debate and conflict.
Before leaving the wider political context for the present, it is worth heading off one
misunderstanding right away. To maintain that there are logical connections between VIS and
market liberalism is not to deny that the victim‟s “voice” can be enlisted for policy initiatives
that are not “liberal” in any sense. This is the theme of Markus Dirk Dubber‟s (2004) study of
the victims‟ rights movement in the USA. Dubber argues that the political success of the
movement in the 1980s was compromised by its assimilation to “the war on crime” . . . a
“mass incapacitation campaign” aimed at perceived antisocial elements, and carried out
through an expansion of “the state‟s system of criminal administration.” Dubber traces this
development to a “state-centered, preconstitutional” model of criminal justice, inherited from
eighteenth-century England.10 But, even according to his own account, there was no logical
connection between this authoritarian project and the vindication of victims‟ rights: the
connection, as he puts it, was merely one of “fact,” not “principle,” with public indignation
over the suffering of victims providing political cover for aggressive, class-driven measures
of social control, unconnected to any direct redress for victims. 11 In contrast, when Dubber
begins to defend what he believes to be “the legitimate core of victims‟ rights” [italics added],
his own anti-statist individualism is at once apparent.
For too long, American criminal law has been run by the state in the name of
ill-defined “public interests.” . . . Crime is not a public health issue but a
6
traumatic experience shared by two persons, the offender and the victim.12
Dubber is unusual among skeptics about VIS in interpreting its rise as much in the light of the
first assertion as of the second, and in viewing it with suspicion for that reason. As we shall
see—and as might be expected—among sympathetic accounts of VIS, it is the second remark
that is more characteristic.
II Distinguishing the functions of the victim statement
An important preliminary step is to “unpack” the ambiguous concept of VIS by identifying
certain distinct aspects of victim input that may inhere in the same actual victim utterance
(1) Victim Impact Evidence (VIE)
In its aspect as Victim Impact Evidence, the function of the victim utterance is to inform the
court of the harm actually caused by the offense to its immediate victim, or to other persons
closely affected such as family members or rescue workers. Any other purposes that may be
simultaneously served by the victim utterance are not relevant to “strict VIE” as I will call it.
The victim, so far as strict VIE is concerned, has no special human status as a participant in
the court proceedings. Though it may be necessary for her to narrate her experiences, or
express psychological states such as emotions, her impact evidence is on the same footing as
non-expressive evidence, such as clinical evidence of injuries caused, or quantitative
assessments of damage to property. The victim‟s role in VIE is similar to that of a witness,
though her statements qualify as VIE only to the extent that they are directed to the harm she
has suffered as a result of the crime.
(2) Victim Opinion Statements (VOS)
In a very few jurisdictions, victims or their survivors have been permitted to express opinions
on the crime and on the proper penalty for the convicted offender. Such opinions, strictly
understood, are not evidence, but are a judgment, passed from a distinctive perspective, on
7
the implications of the evidence. In contrast to VIE, the especially relevant status of the
victim or her survivors is precisely what justifies the admission of VOS. Indirectly, of course,
VOS may reveal evidence of the victim impact suffered, and in practice (strict) VIE and
(strict) VOS may be blended in the same utterance, but the courts must be presumed to be
able to distinguish opinion from impact evidence and to treat each element appropriately.
(3) Victim Statements (VS)
This expression covers all utterances by victims in their capacity as victims that are admitted
at any stage of the criminal justice process, whether before, during or after court proceedings.
VIE and VOS are therefore specialized categories of VS. VS may include evidence of harm
suffered, opinions on the proper penalty, expressions of compassion or forgiveness towards
the offender, expressions of hatred and indignation, comments on proposals to grant bail or
parole, attempts at reconciliatory or restorative dialogue and negotiation, complaints about
the criminal justice processes themselves, and so forth.
III Justice and welfare justifications of VIS
The justifications of victim input advanced by its advocates are also varied, but they can
broadly be divided into two types, those directed to justice and those directed to welfare, or
utility. On the one hand, VIE is claimed to be of value to the courts since it makes clearer the
nature and extent of the harm done by the offense, and can therefore “enhance justice . . .
particularly in terms of sentence proportionality.”13 On the other hand, Victim Statements
generally, especially when presented in the context of some wider system such as a victim
support regime or a restorative justice program, are claimed to bring benefit to various parties:
to the victim or victim‟s survivors, to the offender, whose understanding of his crime and its
effects may enhance his rehabilitation, and to society as a whole through the reduced
alienation and increased co-cooperativeness of victims, and the introduction of a healing
element into the management of criminal justice.14 Edna Erez notes a range of therapeutic or
8
empowering effects recorded by victims. These include, inter alia: experiencing a “cathartic
effect” after providing impact information; discharging their “civil duty”; redressing the
“unequal balance” between themselves and the offender introduced by the crime; asserting
“ownership of the conflict,” which they may have “felt was misappropriated from them in the
name of the state”; being able “to remind judges of the fact that behind the crime is a real
person who is a victim”; and, in the case of the survivors of murder victims, fulfilling a
compelling need to “represent the interests of their beloved one in the case.”15
Erez mentions the rare permissions of Victim Opinion Statements only in a footnote
and without comment. One might suppose from this that victim opinion is rarely
communicated, and it is true that even in those jurisdictions that have allowed VOS, such as
Arizona, its use has been challenged on appeal, and that in most jurisdictions victim
statements may not include proposals as to penalty. However, this picture is somewhat
misleading because of the ease with which the logical distinction between (strict) VIE and
(strict) VOS breaks down in rhetorical practice. The public impression in this respect—
namely, that in some high-profile cases victim opinion has been vividly communicated in
court—is not unfounded. For example, at the trials of the Oklahoma bomber Timothy
McVeigh and the 9/11 conspirator Zacarias Moussaoui, the presentation of hours of heartrending impact evidence by victims‟ survivors, in the context of prosecution calls for the
death penalty, made it superfluous for the participants to breach the rules by formally
expressing their opinions on the appropriate sentence. They had, in effect, expressed an
opinion by their decision to appear. The same is no less true of those whose statements, as in
the case of McVeigh‟s accomplice Terry Nichols, were called by the defense, and served to
suggest that victim impact need not imply a capital sentence.16
Notwithstanding these qualms, the initial concern of many opponents of VIS—that
they would sway courts towards vengeful sentencing—does not seem to have been borne out.
9
Erez and others have produced evidence to suggest that their use has not led to a pattern of
greater severity in sentencing.17
I turn now to the three questions.
IV The rejection of the wholly public conception
The first question concerns a fundamental aspect of our conception of criminal justice.
As both supporters and critics of VIS have noted, their introduction challenges what might be
called the wholly public conception, the doctrine that crimes are to be understood as offenses
against the entire community, to be investigated and chastised by the public authorities, and
not by, or even on behalf of, individual crime victims. Though classically stated by
philosophers as different as Hobbes and Hegel,18 the wholly public conception became firmly
entrenched only recently, partly thanks to the administrative reforms that made practicable
prosecution by the state as a uniform system, and partly as a by-product of the gradual ethical
and practical repudiation of the reliance on private prosecutions associated with such criminal
justice regimes as the so-called “Bloody Code” in England.19
So firmly established in the educated consciousness has the wholly public conception
been, until quite recently, that one assumes some canonical arguments in its favor must be
ready to hand. Yet it tends in modern texts to be taken for granted rather than defended—
almost as if to defend it explicitly would be to concede the unnerving possibility of its
abandonment. In the UK, for example, the Report of the JUSTICE committee on the role of
the victim in criminal justice (1998) states, but does not argue for, the view that “the
prosecutor is prosecuting on behalf of the state, not the victim.”20 It adds that “victims can
find it difficult to understand that the prosecutor‟s role is not to present their case, but to
prosecute on behalf of the Crown,” implying, without explaining why, that they should be
brought to understand this.21 In 2004, the Irish Minister of Justice felt obliged to reminder a
10
questioner in the Dáil that “Under the Constitution prosecutions are brought in the name of
the people as a public act against the accused. In this country, as in many other countries, we
have an adversarial system of trial. . . . The two sides, so to speak, are the people—acting
through the public prosecution under the Director of Public Prosecutions—on the one hand
and the accused on the other. It is not a three-cornered contest in which the victim, the
alleged perpetrator and the people are at opposite ends of a triangle.” Again, no justification
was offered, beyond the assertion that the existing system was “fair.”22
I will therefore review what seem to me to be the strongest available arguments in
favor of the wholly public conception: these, I assume, are the arguments on which its
defenders, at least tacitly, rely.
(1) The definitional argument
Law is, by definition, a social and institutional phenomenon. A crime, by definition, is a
breach of the law, not merely an intentional or reckless harm to an individual person or
persons. (To call it a “wrong” against a person would already be to invoke either the
impersonal discourse of natural law, or the institutional discourse of positive law.) The
prosecution of a crime is therefore appropriately a social and not an individual responsibility.
Measures to repair or compensate the harms incidentally suffered by an individual victim of
crime may be morally required of the community, but these are a matter for welfare agencies,
not for the criminal justice process itself.
Like all definitional arguments, this one is open to the objection that the definition (of
crime) is not self-justifying, and a sufficiently radical rethink of our terms could lead to its
abandonment. It could be revised precisely to stipulate that a crime is a special category of
harm to a person, who may therefore reasonably seek reparation (but need not choose to do
so, just as one does not always put in an insurance claim): the institutions of criminal justice
could be reconceived as services to ensure reparation to these individuals when they seek it.
11
Criminal justice on this view would become the mission of a particular public service, and its
radical distinction from welfare would disappear.
(2) The communitarian argument
Individual personhood is at least partly constituted by relations to other persons and to groups
and communities: each person is “a part of the main,” in Donne‟s words. Conversely, every
community is at least partly constituted by its members‟ persons. Every crime therefore
harms, or wrongs, not only an individual, but the community that is interdependent with that
individual, even if there is no specific collateral harm to other individuals. The decision to
seek redress and the responsibility for making it effective must therefore, at the very least, be
shared between the wronged individual and her community.
Moreover, the expectation of the support of the community when one has been injured
is an important motive for social co-operation. And the community is in any case more
powerful than the individual. Therefore the responsibility to prosecute and punish crime, and
ensure redress for the victim, should lie primarily with the community. Because the
community is itself harmed by a crime, it may sometimes rightly decide to prosecute even
when the wronged individual would prefer that it did not.
It is obvious that in its theory of the relation of individual personhood to other persons
and to communities, the communitarian argument stands in opposition to liberal
individualism (or at the other end of a spectrum of conceptions of the relation of the
individual to society), and it is needless as well as impossible to pursue this deeper theoretical
debate here.
However, it is worth noting one vulnerable point in the communitarian argument. If
we defend the wholly public conception of criminal justice on the grounds that a harm to an
individual is ipso facto a harm to the community on which the community must act, we need
to say which kinds of intentional or reckless harm caused by one person to another should be
12
criminalized. The answer to this question cannot be “all of them” (since this would lead to the
criminalization of millions of minor interpersonal abrasions). We need a justification of the
designation of certain harms, but not others, as criminal wrongs. If in seeking this we appeal
to communal judgment, we risk making redress for an individual dependent on some
contingent sociological fact. For example, it may be argued that a self-conscious group (such
as women, or a religious or ethnic minority) will perceive a harm to one of their number as
“their” wrong as well as “her” wrong. Even against the wishes of the harmed individual, the
community might then properly insist on bringing a prosecution “on her behalf”; and this
adoption of an individual‟s harm by a particular social group as its concern might serve, by
way of analogy, to explain and justify the entire community‟s adoption of certain individual
harms as its concern. But the scope of such adoption by the community of individuals‟ harms
would always be a sociologically contingent matter (and indeed if it were not, it could not
function to select some harms and not others). The argument is then open to the criticism that
it leaves some individual rights at risk, since it is the essence of a political right, as generally
understood, that it is owned irrespective of the sentiments of the wider community. The
opponent of the wholly public conception could argue here, therefore, that the communitarian
argument robs individual victims of sovereignty over “their” cases without providing an
assured protective intervention in support of their rights. 23
(3) The participative equality argument
All citizens have an equal obligation to obey the law, and to co-operate with its processes by,
for example, furnishing information to the courts when asked to do so. Except in the case of
those holding offices within the criminal justice system, who act in those capacities and not
as private persons, no person must have a specially enhanced power in influencing the
operation of justice. This prohibition applies no less to victims and offenders than to other
13
citizens. Both are simply expected to serve the criminal justice process by furnishing truthful
evidence.
Victims and offenders do indeed have distinctive rights, but they must not be active
rights of influence over the judicial process itself. Rather they are protective rights, derived
firstly from the requirements of justice itself (as when the accused person is protected from
the disclosure of information that might prejudice a jury), and secondly from the objective of
minimizing the distress caused by the criminal justice processes (as when a vulnerable
witness is protected from exposure in open court or from aggressive cross-examination). A
victim is, of course, deserving of additional care from the public authorities, commensurate
with the harm she has suffered, but this is, again, a matter for welfare, not for criminal justice.
This argument cuts deeper. To counter it, to justify the abandonment of participative
equality in favor of giving a victim active rights of influence over the operation of justice in
“his or her” case, one would have to claim something like this: that the field of operation of
criminal justice is an aggregate of individual arenas of interest governed by a unified system
of law, rather than a single wholly public arena in which all have an equal interest. Within his
or her individual arena of interest, the victim would then have special rights of influence and
decision. The metaphor that suggests itself for this view of the victim‟s special interest is the
assertion of ownership over a certain territory, comparable to the enclosure of common land,
which creates privately owned spaces that are nevertheless subject to universal laws of
property. Indeed, the phrase „his or her case‟ already implies a private property metaphor.
(4) The impartiality argument
It is essential to criminal justice that its agents be free from any personal interest. The refusal
of active rights of influence to a victim is captured in the dictum that a person must not be “a
judge in his own case.” As Hegel puts it, the magistrates must be supposed to be guided not
by any “subjective will,” but by “the universal will of the law.”24 This applies no less to the
14
prosecutor than to the judge. Any admission of the victim, tacitly or explicitly, as coprosecutor, as a person with a special interest, is at best redundant to the work of the
magistrates, and at worst may undermine the consistent application of the law. Indeed, VIS
may threaten to become a vehicle for private revenge, throwing into reverse the social
evolution that created the (ideal) objectivity of legal trial and punishment out of the “war of
each against each,” endemic wherever private retaliation is accepted.
This argument is the most powerful. It does not deny that victims may feel very
strongly the desire to take personal action in response to the crime they have suffered. On the
contrary, it is precisely because it recognizes the power of that desire that it views it as a
threat to the most objective and consistent justice that is humanly possible. The dangers of
inconsistency and arbitrariness created by the intervention, however marginal, of victims,
who are unlikely qua victims to have either the experience or the motive to compare „their‟
cases and „their‟ offenders with those of others, are significant ones.
This fourth argument could be overturned only by a particularly radical version of the
proposition that victims must have ownership of “their” crimes. Its critic would have to
maintain that the empowerment of such “ownership” either posed no threat to, or took
priority over, the aim of achieving the most objective and consistent justice humanly possible.
It is important to note at once that none of these arguments for the wholly public conception
of criminal justice are telling against strict VIE. In strict VIE, it will be recalled, the victim‟s
evidence as to harm is simply evidence to be considered alongside other evidence of harm
(clinical, financial, etc.); the victim participates merely as a witness who is best placed to
report harm accurately, and has no privileged “voice.” The victim may or may not feel
gratified at being enabled to present the VIE; such gratification is irrelevant to its purpose.
15
Nor do the four arguments tell against many of the forms of victim support advocated,
and in many cases introduced, in recent years. In the UK, for example, Helen Reeves and
Kate Mulley summarized the entitlements they proposed for crime victims under five
headings. Four of these are: compensation (to restore victims to approximately the same
financial position as before the crime); protection (against intimidation, harassment, and
invasions of privacy); services expressly dedicated to their needs, and modeling good practice
in the treatment of victims to be emulated by other professionals; and clear information at
each stage of the case. Reeves and Mulley‟s fifth point is that victims should “be free of the
burden of decisions relating to the offender. This responsibility lies with the state.” Though
their contention here is motivated by concern for the welfare of the victim as they perceive it,
rather than by the arguments for denying the victim active rights of influence over
prosecution or sentencing, it dovetails with them. Reeves and Mulley do support a form of
VS, partly for its expressive or cathartic value, partly to ensure that relevant information is
documented, and especially to allow fears of retaliation against the victim by the offender or
his associates to be heard. They add: “This statement should be taken into consideration
whenever decisions are made about the case, including cautioning, charging and bail.”
Though the expression “whenever decisions are made about the case” might seem to
contradict their view that victims should be shielded from decisions relating to the offender,
their prime concern is with the victim‟s physical and psychological safety, and they reject the
use of VIS to influence sentencing.25
The arguments do tell, however, with varying degrees of force, against Victim
Opinion Statements, since these allow active influence over outcomes to the particular victim,
who thereby, in virtue of her special relation to the case, enjoys a power denied to all other
citizens.
16
It is notable that the counter-arguments that are necessary to negate each of the four
arguments for the wholly public conception have a common factor: they all insist that the
response to a crime, though discharged through the agency of the criminal justice system
rather than through private action, should be conceived as, at least partially, belonging to, or
being conditional on the sovereign choice of, the victim.
It is striking how prevalent metaphors of ownership are in the advocacy of all versions
of VIS. They can be traced at least as far back as Nils Christie‟s eccentrically written but
influential article of 1977, “Conflicts as Property.” Christie advocates “a court procedure that
restores the participants‟ rights to their own conflicts,” contrasting the alienating
impersonality of Scandinavian, British and American courts with an episode of domestic
conflict resolution in a Tanzanian village. “The parties, the former lovers, were in the centre
of the room and in the centre of everyone‟s attention. . . . It was a happy happening. . . . It
was circus. It was drama. It was a court case.” Christie does not state and confront arguments
in favor of the wholly public conception. Rather, he renders them irrelevant by a strategy that
is to recur in later campaigning for VIS: he represents the assumption of criminal justice by
the impersonal state as a kind of expropriation of the victims by professionals, especially
lawyers. “Should lawyers be admitted to court?” he asks. “Experts are as cancer to any lay
body.” Instead, he advocates, as an admittedly hard-to-realize ideal, a victim-oriented court,
constituted out of local community members, and focused on assessment of the victim‟s
situation and on restitution to him, ideally by the offender himself. Punishment of the
offender would be required only where his “constructive” sufferings through restitutive
actions were felt to be insufficient to meet the sentiments of the local community. 26
We should note that Christie himself, writing in the nineteen-seventies, does not
conceive of criminal cases as the private property of individuals; their ownership should, in
his view, be “shared” by the neighborhood, and it is precisely this sharing that is the benign
17
service of his ideal, community-based court.27 But it is clear how readily this notion of
neighborhood “ownership” could dissolve under the influence of a more assertively
individualistic culture, especially since, once the idea is established that the participants
should retrieve their conflict from the grasp of the state and its professionals, it is hard to
explain why they should then surrender it to their neighbors. It is notable that some, though
not all, of the victim comments quoted by Erez appeal strongly to this sense of personal
ownership.
More recently, Renee Zaubermann (2000) has drawn attention to the ways in which
both individuals and organizations have “instrumentalized” criminal justice for their own
purposes, reporting a crime to the authorities when they foresee advantage from doing so,
while adopting alternative strategies if they do not. It is not far from this to the perception of
criminal justice as a service, available for optional use like any other public service. Like
Dubber, Zaubermann does not so much engage with arguments for the wholly public
conception, as identify it with the asserted authority of the sovereign state (historically
originating in the personal sovereignty of a monarch) as against other political forces.
Similarly, much discussion of victim rights in criminology draws on a vision of criminal
justice as a space in which competing agencies struggle for influence, the courts and the legal
profession being perceived as excessively dominant and the victims, like the offenders, in
pressing need of agencies to assert their interests. Advocates of restorative justice often strike
a similar note. Charles Barton, for example, criticizes the Justices of the New Zealand Court
of Appeal who, in The Queen v. Clotworthy (1998), overturned the District Court‟s decision
to accept agreed compensation to a victim in lieu of a custodial sentence for the offender,
giving priority to the public interest in “consistency, integrity of the criminal justice system
and deterrence of others” over the wishes of victim and offender.28 Barton comments that
18
rather than showing respect to the wishes of the primary stakeholders, and especially
those of the victim, they presumed to know better how the case should be resolved. . . .
Judgments such as this only succeed in supporting calls for a substantial and urgent
transfer of power from the professionals of the legal system to the primary
stakeholders.29
The salient points here are the imputation to the “professionals” of defective
understanding, implicitly grounded in the arrogance of their professionalism itself (“they
presumed to know better”); and the market-liberal model contained in the repeated use of
“stakeholders”: a business expression that has been gradually colonizing political and publicservice discourse over the last decade or two.30
In short, insofar as they acknowledge at all the arguments for the wholly public
conception, commentators sympathetic to victims‟ voices tend to treat them as merely
strategic justifications for state power and the authority of the courts, or as necessarily
yielding at least some ground to the victims‟ right of “ownership.” The implicit slogan is:
“the crime belongs to the victim, not to the officials of the state.” As we shall see, the same
conception emerges elsewhere in the case for VIS.
V The restoration of ‘balance’
I turn now to the second question. Erez‟s respondents were not alone in suggesting the need
to correct the “unequal balance” between victim and offender, in part through the
introduction of VIS. This metaphor of “balancing,” as between the respective interests of the
individual offender and victim, or between the legal rights of accused persons and the
“rights” of the wider population, is extensively used in the wider political and media
discourse, always with the prior claim, or implication, of an existing imbalance in the
criminal justice system in favor of the offender or alleged offender.31 Whatever the general
19
merits of such claims, we are concerned here specifically with the arguments for allowing
victim input as part of the “rebalancing” strategy.
Two quite different aims of the “rebalancing” campaign need to be distinguished. One,
corresponding to the justice-based justification of victim input, is to ensure that the accused
does not benefit unduly, in the determination of his punishment, from what one might call
superior communicative entitlement as compared to the victim. The underlying assumption
here is that, prior to the introduction of VIS, the accused has enjoyed an unwarranted
superiority of communicative entitlement. The other aim, corresponding to the welfare-based
justification, is to ensure so far as possible that the presumed victim is not further afflicted by
the experience of the criminal justice process itself, and indeed to offer him or her
opportunities for healing and compensation wherever this is feasible. The underlying
assumption here is that, for many victims, their experience of the criminal justice process is
that it adds further affliction rather than bringing healing, and that they are accorded less
respect, care, and considerate attention than the accused.
The arguments that follow later in this section are directed primarily against the
justice-based justification. Clearly the welfare-based justification is confirmed by the
experiences of many victims, and no-one could reasonably deny that -provided these do not
compromise the pursuit of a just verdict and proper sentencing- efforts at comfort, healing,
and restoration of self-respect for the victim should be made. These might include the victim
statement, understood not as a medium for supplementary evidence, but as an opportunity to
express damned-up feelings to an attentive and sympathetic audience, and to make a public
affirmation of important personal values that have been outraged by the crime. For example,
the court in a recent domestic child abuse case in Australia, having heard amid other
harrowing evidence that the father had violated his younger daughter with the hilt of a
hunting knife, probably did not need, as information, to be told in the clichéd phrasing of a
20
VIS that the children‟s “home life was rotten to its dysfunctional core.”32 But it is entirely
credible that such a statement by a victim could have therapeutic value. It could help the
victim to dissociate herself, through the rhetoric of vivid condemnation, from memories that
might threaten to enslave her psychologically and to engender irrational guilt. And it might
bring her the relief that is often achieved when a hitherto private anguish is brought under a
widely-recognized public concept (“dysfunctional family”), and we feel that we are not
unique in our suffering, and that there is a system of ideas that embraces it. The cliché is itself
comforting.
The difficulty in accepting the welfare case for VIS lies with the proviso about preserving
justice. It is precisely in respect of VIS, as contrasted with other devices of victim support,
that the distinction between enhancing victim welfare and achieving just punishment of the
crime is most difficult to sustain in practice. The discourse both of the “rebalancing”
campaign, and of victim statements themselves, often conspicuously fails to distinguish a
therapeutic aim from an aim of achieving justice. How, for example, should we interpret this
passage?
I am grateful that this legal part of my brother's death will soon be over. I have realized
that no plea, no sentence, no punishment is really going to make me feel better. My
brother is still dead, and my family still has to deal with his violent death. . . . No
length of incarceration will take the pain away from my family. No sentence will bring
my brother back. All the members of my family have a life sentence of grief.33
The statement voices grief and suffering, and affirms the solidarity of the surviving family
members: in the very act of denying the possibility of consolation, it perhaps achieves a small
alleviation of pain, if only through the dignity of its utterance. At first, it seems also to
21
disclaim any voice in the punishment of the killer: “no punishment is really going to make me
feel better.” But that “really” is already a crucial qualification. “No sentence will bring my
brother back” can imply either “I am indifferent to any sentence” or “No sentence can be long
enough to equate to my loss.” On the latter reading, the denial of any quest for retaliatory
satisfaction is a mere preamble to the final hint that (for implied reasons of balance—we have
received a life sentence) the offender should receive the maximum punishment available.
Such multiple ambiguities of meaning and purpose—and this example is hardly an unusual
one—make it difficult to accept that a therapeutic “rebalancing” as between offender and
victim can be carried out without at the same time allowing the victim a communicative
entitlement that requires support from the justice-based “rebalancing” argument. To this I
now turn.
There are two main justice-based arguments that use the balancing metaphor. The first
maintains that victim input can inform a process of restitutive justice, repairing or
compensating the harm suffered by the victim, and so correcting, or mitigating, the
unbalanced distribution of goods and harms created by the crime. The second relates
specifically to the sentencing phase, and justifies the presentation of evidence about the
impact of the crime on the victim on the grounds that it “balances” evidence about the
offender‟s character and history presented in mitigation. I shall discuss each in turn.
Intuitively, a crime often does place an offender at an advantage relative to the victim.
The clearest examples are economic crimes such as theft, burglary or vandalism. Restoring
the status quo ante by reimbursing the victim at the offender‟s expense, where this is
practicable, can plausibly be said to restore a balance. But even with these crimes, direct
financial restitution has only limited restitutive power. There is more to suffering criminal
damage, for example, than a financial loss. If I find my car tires slashed, I am unlikely to feel
22
that equilibrium has been restored merely by the reimbursement of the costs of replacing the
tires: I have to cope with a psychological harm, the awareness of the hostility or contempt
that motivated the act.
Considerations of this kind have led writers such as David Hershenov (1999) to
suggest that the gratification of feelings of revenge can provide restitution where financial
compensation fails: that the victim may be satisfied that the imbalance has been corrected if
she can see that the offender has had her “comfort level” lowered proportionately to the harm
done by her offense.
A case for victim input for purposes of balance could perhaps be made along
Hershenov‟s lines. On this view, once we have moved beyond the kinds of financial harms
that can readily be documented, we will need advice from the victim if we are to assess
correctly the type or level of discomfort that the offender will have to endure in order to
correct the imbalance of harms.
To justify such an approach, we would need to have great confidence in the ability of
the courts to elicit an objective quotient of harm from VIE. Moreover, it is controversial, to
say the least, that punishment should be proportional to the harm caused, rather than to the
blameworthiness of the offender‟s action,34 let alone calibrated to correct any remaining
imbalance of comfort as between victim and offender. If, indeed, the actual imbalance
between these two individuals had to be redressed, then the aim of equal punishment for
objectively comparable cases would have to be abandoned in favor of a strict calibration of
punishment to the distress of the particular victim, who may be either more or less than
averagely sensitive. I return to this point in VI below.
Unsurprisingly, most advocacy of enhanced victim input for reasons of “balance”
does not demand this kind of scrupulous rebalancing of harms and discomforts in the ultimate
outcome. Rather, it suggests that in its process of determining just punishment, the court must
23
receive appropriately “balanced” input to its deliberations from the respective voices (actual
or representative) of offender and victim. Hitherto, it is supposed, there has been an
imbalance in favor of the offender.
The difficulty here is to see how any new communicative entitlement granted to the
victim (such as the right to a VS) could credibly be described as restoring a disrupted
“balance” in relation to a communicative entitlement of the accused, since, under the current
criminal justice process, these two parties are in asymmetric positions, with disparate
communicative needs. The accused is on trial, facing the threat of punishment, and needs to
communicate his defense point by point in response to the prosecution‟s case; the victim, in
contrast, has an ancillary role and may not even be present throughout the proceedings. The
victim‟s ordinary (non-VIE) evidence may already “balance,” in the sense of countering,
some assertion of the defense; and with the arguable exception of mitigation (see below),
other communications by the accused have no obvious equivalent from the victim‟s side. To
achieve comprehensive “balance” in communicative entitlement, the process itself would
need to change, so that offender and victim would indeed become the antagonists, or at any
rate equal parties in that “three-cornered contest” model repudiated by the Irish Minister of
Justice. In that situation, both would require full-scale legal representation and, in principle,
equal air time. The metaphor of victim-offender balance, in short, presupposes, when applied
to communicative entitlements, the substitution of an individually adversarial for the wholly
public conception of the criminal justice process.35
The main focus of this second argument for allowing victim input as part of a
balancing strategy is the claim that VIS offers an appropriate counter to mitigation evidence,
that, uncorrected, provides an unfair advantage to the defense at the sentencing stage. Here, at
least as far as the United States is concerned, the accusation of “law bowing to politics” is as
old as the Supreme Court decision in Payne v Tennessee (1991), which held that the Eighth
24
Amendment did not bar juries in capital sentencing cases from considering, alongside
evidence presented in mitigation, VIE of the victim‟s character and the emotional impact of
the murder on the victim‟s family. On that occasion, both sides alluded to the influence of
victims‟ rights campaigns on the majority opinion.36 The constitutional arguments are
complex, and much of the debate lies beyond the scope of this paper;37 I focus here simply on
the powerful rhetorical role played by the appeal for restoration of balance between the
voices of criminal and victim. Joshua D. Greenberg quotes the words of the Supreme Court
of Tennessee.
It is an affront to the civilized members of the human race to say that at sentencing . . .
a parade of witnesses may praise the background, character and good deeds of
Defendant . . . but nothing may be said that bears upon the character of, or the harms
imposed, upon the victim.38
If we conceive the court as a theatre in which two rivals, personally or by proxy,
strive to assert their dignity, this claim has force; the problem lies in its application to the
specific drama of sentencing. It is true that some of the arguments for excluding or
constraining VIS at the sentencing stage are symmetrically applicable to mitigation. As
Greenberg points out, critics of VIS object that its power to influence sentencing may depend
on whether the victim or victim‟s survivors are articulate enough to express their experiences
and feelings effectively to the court (which may in turn depend on their being socially or
ethnically similar to the judge or jury). But the same applies to statements in mitigation by
the defendant‟s allies: a defendant with middle-class, university-educated family and friends
is likely, all else being equal, to benefit from more persuasive mitigation statements than an
unloved drifter. Concerns over the difficulty in maintaining consistency from case to case in
25
the weight to be given to elements in VIS also arise no less strongly with mitigation
statements.39
However, these similarities between certain arguments applicable to the two types of
evidence do not mean that mitigation and VIS should properly be regarded as balancing one
another. Indeed, as others have pointed out, they are radically different.40 Mitigation
statements do not, for the most part, concern themselves at all with the harm suffered by the
victim. They typically assert the defendant‟s general good character, or cite his remorse, cooperation with the police, or good conduct as a prisoner. Their characteristic aim is to
convince those responsible for deciding on the appropriate sentence that the particular crime
has been an aberration by an essentially good (or at least, less bad than the crime might
suggest) individual; or, more abstrusely, but not uncommonly where there is a long delay
between crime and punishment, that the person now facing punishment is less dangerous, or
more morally regenerate, than the person who committed the crime.41 Evidence as to the
harm suffered by the victim or her associates or survivors cannot relevantly “counter” such
claims at all. The true „counter‟ would be evidence of the defendant‟s generally bad character,
lack of remorse, and so forth.
Direct contradiction between mitigation and VIS would arise only if the mitigation
statement attempted to minimize the harm sustained by the victim, or if the VIS assailed the
defendant‟s wider character or conduct, over and above the crime itself. If the idea of VIS
and mitigation “balancing” one another was enshrined in the criminal justice process, it is
conceivable that such counter-arguing (and counter-counter-arguing?) would be attempted; if
this were to occur, the distinctive functions of mitigation and of VIS would come to subserve
a contest between two individuals (or their representatives) each seeking to position himself,
on a spectrum of “deserving” character, as favorably, relative to the other, as the most
generous construal of the evidence will allow.
26
The Supreme Court judges who upheld the constitutionality of VIS in capital cases
sometimes invoked an idea that seems to be intended to fend off the objection that VIS turns
public criminal justice into a private combat between individuals. This is the idea that victim
impact evidence can demonstrate “the particularized harm that an individual‟s murder causes
to the rest of society” [italics added].42 This function of VIE may be interpreted as a response
to the mitigation evidence that suggests that the offender is of sufficient actual or potential
worth to society to merit being kept alive. Yet even in this aspect, VIE is not truly „counter‟
to mitigation evidence. For however great the loss to society caused by the death of a
homicide victim, this cannot affect the question whether the killer‟s death will represent an
unacceptable loss of worth to society. If worth to others is the criterion to be considered, then
the loss of a person even of very high worth to others does not provide a reason for the
removal of a person of lower worth. Once more, the true counter to mitigation in this regard
would be evidence that the offender is of lower worth to society than the defense claims, not
evidence of the superior worth of the victim.
As Greenberg remarks, the persuasiveness of the Tennessee Supreme Court‟s
statement is more political than judicial. It rests on a presupposition that “the criminal justice
system neglects crime victims while privileging defendants,”43 implying that every
opportunity must be taken to give the victim a voice. More fundamentally still, it implicitly
presents judicial proceedings as a contest for entitlements between two individuals, even at
the point at which the specific purpose of the proceeding is to determine the punishment of
one individual alone.
VI The determination of just punishment
The third question arises from the use of strict VIE. According to strict VIE as I have defined
it, evidence of the impact of the crime on the victim and those closely connected to her is
presented for the better information of the court, on the same footing as clinical or financial
27
evidence of the consequences of the crime, and without implying any special expressive role
for the victim in the court proceedings. It would be just as acceptable if the same evidence
could be presented impersonally, without any participation at all by the victim.
An immediate criticism of this conception is that, if the VIE is impersonal in this
sense, it is not clear why a separate ritual of presenting it should be needed, nor why it should
be presented at a separate point, such as the sentencing phase. Why should all evidence of the
consequences of the crime not be presented at once? Indeed, is it not only when all
consequences have been spelt out that we can understand precisely what the crime has been?
In answer to this last question, we need to recall that a criminal offense is defined in
terms that specify or imply certain types of actions having certain types of consequence, but
do not specify or imply other consequences that are nevertheless entirely possible in
particular cases. For an action to constitute murder or manslaughter, for example, it must be a
consequence of the offender‟s actions that someone is dead. But there is not a distinct offense
of “causing the death of the best Heldentenor of his generation, thus diminishing the pleasure
of audiences at the Bayreuth festival for the next twenty years.” Such consequences are not
sufficiently generic to form part of the definition of an offense. We therefore maintain a
distinction between those consequences of the defendant‟s actions that must be proved in
order to establish that the offense has occurred, and various other consequences that may
influence our more refined judgment of the offender‟s blameworthiness.
Let us suppose that M murders V, who happens to be the father of several young
children and the leading Heldentenor of his generation. We will find it useful to distinguish
the following:
A Direct consequences of the defendant‟s action that are a condition of the occurrence
of the offense.
28
B Direct consequences of this type of action that are a condition of the definition of
the offense.
C Indirect consequences of the defendant‟s action that he in fact foresaw.
D Indirect consequences of the defendant‟s action that he did not in fact foresee.
E Indirect consequences of this type of action, of a kind that could be expected to be
foreseen by any reasonable and averagely well-informed person.
F Indirect consequences of this type of action, of a kind that could not be expected to
have been foreseen by any reasonable and averagely well-informed person.
If we apply these to the Heldentenor case, the A and B consequences are the same: that
someone dies. These make the case one of homicide. The difference is simply between token
and type.
C consequences might, in principle, influence our sense of the heinousness of the
crime. If M knew he was creating grieving orphans or disappointed opera-goers, and
especially if he intended to do so as well as to deprive V of his life, this could only increase
his blameworthiness, since he would have envisaged, or even aimed at, additional suffering
for additional victims. Conversely, therefore, if (D consequences) M did not know that V was
a parent or a singer, we might condemn him a little less. But evidence to support such
judgments at a trial could not be presented as VIE. It would be necessary to show, not
whether in fact V had children who suffered, but whether M knew that V had children who
would suffer.
29
E consequences form the basis of most attempts to reflect in punishment the harm
done by a crime. Reflecting the principles (i) that crimes and their legal penalties should be
publicly promulgated and (ii) that agents should be held responsible only for those
consequences of their actions that they could reasonably have been expected to foresee, the
courts take account, not so much of the C and D indirect consequences of the actual crime, as
of the type of consequences (E) that predictably follow this type of act. Generalizing in this
way establishes a norm that can be applied to all cases; it invokes an understanding of the
seriousness of a given type of crime that is expected to be shared by all mentally competent
citizens. (And this shared understanding is partly what justifies the law‟s prohibiting the
offense, and the severity of the penalties applied to it.) A reasonable person should be
expected to foresee emotional distress to a murder victim‟s family and friends, and this
expectation is folded in, so to speak, to our assessment of the heinousness of this type of
crime. But just for that reason, E consequences do not require any special kind of evidence.
Indeed they function morally even if, in the particular case, the relevant consequences did not
occur. The murderer should not, where E consequences are reflected, be punished more
lightly because, as a matter of fact, V has no family or friends to grieve for him; his
blameworthiness reflects the fact that there might have been grieving survivors, and he could
reasonably be expected to have been aware of this possibility. Conversely—so far as E
consequences are concerned—he should not punished more severely because the grief of the
survivors is especially intense or widespread.
But just as a reasonable person qua potential murderer is assumed to be able to
foresee certain possible indirect consequences of the type of act he commits, so a reasonable
person qua judge or jury member is assumed to be able to foresee them. Therefore, to secure
a just level of punishment, no special presentation of evidence is required. A special
presentation would be needed only if it were true that
30
E1 Judges and jury members (where the latter participate in sentencing decisions) are,
in consequence of their roles, especially deficient in the capacity to understand and
take account of E consequences.
We would need very strong arguments to support E1, since it amounts to saying that those
expectations (of insight into foreseeable consequences of certain types of action) that the
courts apply to offenders cannot be assumed to be met by the courts themselves.
F consequences ought to be set aside by the same arguments that endorse the use of E
consequences. If a particular consequence (such as the declining standards of singing at
Bayreuth) is not of a type that could have been foreseen to result from this type of act, then (i)
it could not have entered even implicitly into the public promulgation of murder as an offense
meriting penalties of a certain severity; and (ii) to punish the offender specifically for causing
this consequence would be unfairly to hold an agent criminally responsible for a consequence
of his action that he could not reasonably be expected to have foreseen.
This last point is perhaps controversial. Jurists and philosophers have debated
the propriety of allowing the severity of punishment to reflect „consequential moral luck‟:
consequences less severe or more severe than might have been expected. This question
cannot be explored in all its bearings here.44 The crucial point for our current discussion is
that we do not need to reject argument (ii), and move in the direction of strict liability for
consequences, in order to hold serious offenders to account for serious indirect consequential
harms. Any reasonable and averagely well-informed person knows that the potential range
and seriousness of the indirect consequences of murder are very great. The epistemic
obligation—the duty to draw on one‟s knowledge of the world to envisage possible
consequences—rightly weighs very heavily on the person who intentionally kills. Admittedly,
31
no-one randomly murdering a stranger could specifically predict that he would be the world‟s
leading Heldentenor, or the lone parent of six children, or a cancer specialist on the brink of a
major research breakthrough; but anyone should realize that the murder of another human
being might have unexpectedly wide-ranging, painful or long-lasting consequences. It is not
like the unexpectedness of stealing, and then throwing away, a cigarette packet that turns out
to have contained a priceless jewel in a secret compartment.
Just because the potential range and seriousness of the indirect consequences of
murder is sufficiently predictable, we can reflect that range in our punitive judgment of the
crime of murder in general. We hold murder to be a very bad crime, not only because it
deprives one person of her life, but also because it typically causes great collateral suffering.
And this is taken to be a matter of common understanding: we expect that the offender will
be aware of it, and we expect that judges and jury members will be aware of it. We would
need a very strong argument to set aside this latter expectation, since it would amount to
saying that the expectations that the courts apply to offenders could not be applied to the
courts themselves.
There is therefore no need, in order to reflect in punishment the heinousness of a
crime, for a special presentation of evidence of the particular harm suffered by the victim or
her survivors, unless this harm is even more serious than that which (in the form of the
predictable range and seriousness of the potential consequences of this type of crime) should
be assumed to be a matter of common understanding.45
Because the predictable range of harms caused by murder are so dreadful, this need to
learn of particular harms is easier to imagine with crimes less serious and far-reaching than
murder. If T steals and discards V‟s specially adapted cigarette packet, it may be as much of a
surprise to the court as to T that it contained a priceless jewel representing most of V‟s wealth.
The court might need victim impact evidence to inform it of this indirect consequence. Such
32
consequences do not fall within the predictable range and seriousness of the potential
consequences of such petty theft, and so the standard punishments for theft do not sufficiently
reflect them. But in these cases, the force of our concerns over consequential moral luck
seems especially strong. It would be unjust to punish the thief more severely because of a
consequence he could not reasonably be expected to have foreseen or (which is the same
thing) the possibility of which is not part of the understanding of this type of crime that ought
be assumed to be shared among all citizens.
In short, if the court can assess for itself the heinousness of the crime by referring to
the predictable range and seriousness of the potential consequences of this type of crime, it
does not need VIE. If there are more serious consequential harms from this offense than the
predictable range would encompass, the court might learn something from VIE; but it would
then be unjust to punish the offender more severely on account of that information, since this
would be holding him accountable for a duty to envisage consequences that those authorizing
the punishment could not themselves normally have envisaged.
The principle underlying this conclusion is that criminal responsibility and eligibility
for punishment are bounded by common understandings—by our capability of deploying
knowledge that is accessible to and is shared, or ought to be expected to be shared, by all
citizens. (Criminal responsibility is correspondingly diminished in the case of those incapable
of achieving or deploying such knowledge.) And the two premises that would legitimize the
special presentation of VIE in spite of the arguments presented above have in common their
rejection of this principle. One is E1, the claim that the courts cannot be trusted to understand
“consequences of a type of crime of a kind that could be expected to be foreseen by any
reasonable and averagely well-informed person.” According to this claim, the courts would
need the special presentation of VIE in order to bring them up from their defective level of
understanding to that of a reasonable and averagely well-informed person, such as the
33
offender is expected to be when held accountable for his crime. Though unlikely, perhaps, to
be believed by professionals within the criminal justice system, this claim has its adherents
among the general public and in the media, convinced that courts and especially judges are
“removed from the community” and in need of continual reminders of the serious
consequences of crime.46 The continual exposure to evidence of crimes is presumed to
desensitize the courts to individual instances, rather than to inform consistent judgment
across cases in general. The best proof that this view exists and has influence is that judges
and criminal lawyers themselves defensively acknowledge it. 47
The second is the claim that E consequences, defined as they are in terms of types of
action and types of consequences, are an insufficient or inappropriate basis for determining
punishment; that actual consequences of the particular crime, even if they are less or more
severe than the average, should calibrate punishment. VIE is necessary, according to this
claim, because it helps the courts to fix punishment to counterbalance more precisely the
actual suffering of the particular victim. As Hershenov says of victims who happen to have
suffered particularly badly, or cannot be financially compensated, “since they were hurt more,
they need more compensation” (that is, in the form of more severe punishment of their
afflicter).48 But to go beyond E consequences in this way—and this is precisely the role that
VIE can play—is to move from a conception of criminal liability as founded in common
understandings that are expected to be shared by all competent citizens, to a conception much
closer to that of civil liability, in which actual “loss” must be compensated. On this point,
there is evidence that the claim is supported, not only explicitly by certain philosophers, but
implicitly by some criminal justice professionals, since the guidance to victims on completing
victim impact statements commonly encourages a specification of losses reminiscent of an
insurance claim, and an expectation of restitution.49
34
VII The two presuppositions and their political basis
The analyses in the three preceding sections all point in the same direction. The arguments
for enhanced victim input into the criminal justice process itself are open to significant
objections, unless they are reinforced by the acceptance of two tacit presuppositions.
Presupposition one is a conception of society as a collection of individuals seeking,
and entitled to, their due. This in turn yields a vision of criminal justice, not as the realm of
steadfastly maintained objective and public norms, but as a field of interpersonal conflict, a
battle among individuals for relative advantage, recognition, influence and other goods. The
crime victim is no longer conceived as a citizen with an interest in criminal justice identical
to that of all other citizens (though happening to be the occasion of one specific prosecution,
and in addition having certain specific welfare needs). Rather, he or she is conceived as an
individual contesting power over, or “ownership” of, “her” case with another individual, the
defendant.
Presupposition two is that the courts (meaning judges and jury members) are less well
equipped than the averagely reasonable and well-informed person to weigh for themselves
the enormity of the type of crime prosecuted before them. Confronted, for example, with an
act of mass murder, they cannot be left to imagine for themselves the kind and degree of
harm that it might have done—even though they expect the offender, unless excused from the
epistemic responsibilities of an averagely reasonable and well-informed person, to have
imagined it, since on just those terms they are holding him criminally responsible for it. It is
not enough for the courts to know that the corpses of small children had to be dug out of a
bombed building; they need to hear expressly of the agony of rescue workers, who noticed
that one dead child had a teddy bear on his shirt, another a brick embedded in her head.50 Or,
on the side of leniency, they need to hear a victim‟s survivor point out that “My dad is gone
now, and there is nothing that can make that enormous loss whole.”51 The enhancement of
35
their insufficient imaginings by this kind of especially vivid testimony is supposed to assist
them in judging whether, for example, the harm done by mass murder justifies a death
penalty, or merely life imprisonment.
Whether these two presuppositions are defensible cannot be resolved here. The first
involves a radical claim about the nature of criminal law; the second is an empirical
proposition to be investigated by sociologists or psychologists. What is clear is that they are
more likely to be believed, or half-believed, by the general public, at least within Anglophone
jurisdictions, today than a generation ago. The reasons for this are, once more, a sociological
question, but some clue may be given by two common factors that the presuppositions
possess. Firstly, the assertion of their truth disparages the public realm. Presupposition one
rejects the wholly public conception of criminal justice in favor of an individualistic and
competitive model reminiscent of economic liberalism. Presupposition two says that people
who take up public roles are, to the extent that they fall into their role, to be especially
suspected of being out of touch with human reality.
The second common factor is that both presuppositions are entrenched in the attitudes
and practices of the mass media.52 The clichés of victim impact and opinion statements
delivered in court echo those delivered by (or elicited from) victims or their survivors in
media interviews. In jurisdictions where the most severe penalty for murder is literal life
imprisonment, the grieving survivors of a murder victim will often say—we have already
seen an example—that they themselves have been “condemned to a life sentence.” Some of
them, at least, must now be saying it because they have heard others say the same on
television.53 Those pronouncements in turn echo, or are echoed by, leader-writers and
columnists whose mission is to campaign for the decent person to get his or her due. The
courts become most visible in this discourse when they are perceived as obstructing the
36
decent person‟s quest, either through fussy adherence to legal technicalities, or because of
failures of human sympathy from the bench.
To a certain extent this orientation of the media is inevitable because of the internal
imperatives of broadcasting and print journalism. Competing for market share, the media
need vivid human stories, and they need them as quickly as the risk of contempt of court will
allow; and they need heroes, victims and villains pitted against one another, rather than the
patient and dispassionate application of doctrines and norms. Judges, professionally obligated
to pursue the latter, looking beyond the excitements of the individual case, are always liable
to appear to understate the human factor. Juries permanently sworn to secrecy, as in the UK,
must also be a source of frustration. (Hence the eagerness with which the press seizes on
incidents of weeping or fainting among jury members.)
But the explanation, I believe, is ideological as well as commercial. In the main
Anglophone societies, even the conservative media, most conspicuously represented by the
Murdoch empire, are philosophically anti-statist. While more likely than the left-wing media
to support specific measures of “strong government,” especially in foreign affairs and in the
fight against crime, they are at least as suspicious as their leftist colleagues of the public
establishment and those who populate it. Thus the legitimate activity of the media in holding
political leaders and public servants to account hardens into a model of society as divided
between the world of established institutions, including the courts, and the world of human
flesh and blood. The individual crime victim marginalized by the legal establishment fits
perfectly into this picture. The greatly enhanced political possibility of VIS over the last
quarter-century may owe as much to its concurrence with this development, as to changes in
social values, or in the philosophy of crime and punishment.
37
NOTES
[I am grateful to John Kleinig, Terry Hopton, Nick Currie and a number of anonymous referees for invaluable
criticism, advice and encouragement.]
1
Alan Howe, “They Broke Her Heart,” Herald Sun (Australia), September 20, 2010, 22.
2
Examples of intrinsic goods would be “the good of justice,” or “the good of the existence of beauty,” in each
case conceived as independent of any benefit to persons. Examples of irreducibly social goods would be “the
honor of Japan,” or the collective worship of the patron deity of the society, or the achievement by the society as
a whole of high ethical or cultural ends.
3
By “collectively acting individuals” I mean, as explained later in the text, individuals participating in public
institutions that require the willing subordination of some immediate advantage or preference, even if each
individual believes she will, or may, personally benefit from such participation in the long run. Examples would
be the payment of taxation, or of a membership subscription to an organization; military or jury service; or
simply accepting that a particular public good to that, with others, one contributes, by payment or labor or mere
compliance, may not immediately benefit oneself. On this definition, everyone in a developed society performs
some collective actions, so the polarized formulation in the text is too glib. But the polarized ideals—of
maximum individual freedom and self-sufficiency, or maximum social cooperation and solidarity, as their
adherents might express them—are clear enough.
4
F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1976), vol. 2, 1.
5
Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001), chap. 7, 149-231.
6
Rupert Murdoch, “Free Markets, Free Minds,” Inaugural Margaret Thatcher Lecture, Centre for Policy Studies,
London, October 21, 2010,
http://www.cps.org.uk/cps_catalog/Rupert%20Murdoch%20Inaugural%20Margaret%20Thatcher%20Lecture.p
df , accessed October 28, 2010.
7
See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), chap. 8, 453-512,
especially sections 75, 490-96.
8
For classic analyses of the potentially collectively self-defeating character of merely aggregated individual
choices, see Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), Part One, especially chapts. 2
and 3, 53-86.
38
9
It is also not, of course, an original idea. For example, Anne James and John Raine have suggested, if
tentatively, that the rise of “victimology” in the UK was connected to the “customer-oriented” model of public
services that developed in Britain during the 1980s. See Ann James and John Raine, The New Politics of
Criminal Justice (London: Longman, 1998), 71. See also Renee Zaubermann, “Victims as Consumers of the
Criminal Justice System?,” in Integrating a Victim Perspective within Criminal Justice, ed. Adam Crawford and
Jo Goodey (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2000), 48.
10
Markus Dirk Dubber, Victims in the War on Crime (New York: New York University Press, 2004), 3-4.
11
Ibid., 335.
12
Ibid, 4.
13
Edna Erez, “Integrating a Victim Perspective through Victim Impact Statements,” in Integrating a Victim
Perspective within Criminal Justice, ed. Adam Crawford and Jo Goodey (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2000), 179.
14
The role ascribed to VS in restorative justice theories often seems to straddle these two types of justification.
The test that separates them is the unconstrained consent of the offender to the restorative, or reconciliatory,
discourse. A convicted offender is unlike the rest of us in that he may have certain specified things lawfully
done to him, as punishment, without his consent, but he retains various human and civil rights which mean that
his consent is required for activities that are not punishment. On which side of the line dividing the offender‟s
punishment from his sphere of unconstrained consent does the restorative/reconciliatory dialogue lie? If the
offender freely consents to the dialogue, then it belongs to the sphere of welfare not that of justice, since
whatever benefits accrue—and we can accept that there may be many—are contingent on this initial choice. It is
good if they happen, but if they do not happen, no principle of justice has been infringed. But if—or to the
extent that— the offender‟s consent is a product of coercion, or of pressure based on a trade-off against other
sanctions, the dialogue is another form of punishment, and needs to be evaluated as such. It is not necessarily
less afflicting than other forms of punishment: a person may feel more personally violated by being constrained
to take up a certain standpoint, or to listen attentively to certain information, than by being deprived of physical
liberty. See note 34 for a further comment on this point. For defenses of restorative justice that are hard-headed
about its punitive character, see Kathleen Daly, “Revisiting the Relationship between Retributive and
Restorative Justice,” in Restorative Justice: Philosophy to Practice, ed. Heather Strang and John Braithwaite
(Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2000), 33-54, and Charles Barton, “Empowerment and Retribution in Criminal
Justice” in the same volume, 55-76.
15
Erez, “Integrating a Victim Perspective through Victim Impact Statements,” 176-77.
39
16
See notes 32, 33, 47, 51 and 53 for examples. Dubber, Victims in the War on Crime, 191-92, makes a similar
point (with a more express suggestion that VIE is sometimes used by the prosecution to encourage vengeful
sentencing).
17
Edna Erez and Leigh Roeger, “The Effect of Victim Impact Statements on Sentencing Patterns and Outcomes:
The Australian Experience,” Journal of Criminal Justice 23, no. 4 (1995), 363-75; Julian Roberts, “Victim
Impact Statements and the Sentencing Process: Enhancing Communication in the Courtroom,” Criminal Law
Quarterly 47, no. 3 (2003), 365-96.
18
Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Richard. Tuck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), chap. XVIII,
214-15; G. W. F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), 21921 (sect. 102).
19
For discussions of this much-debated process, see J. M. Beattie, Crime and the Courts in England 1660-1800
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), 35-73; W. R. Cornish and G. de N. Clark, Law and Society in England 17501950 (London: Sweet & Maxwell, 1989), 544-613; Clive Emsley, Crime and Society in England 1750-1900, 3rd
ed. (Harlow: Pearson Longman, 2005), 1-20, 183-220, 253-96; Douglas Hay, “Property, Authority and the
Criminal Law,” in Albion’s Fatal Tree, ed. Douglas Hay, Peter Linebaugh, John G. Rule, E. P. Thompson and
Cal Winslow (London: Allen Lane, 1975), 17-63; John H. Langbein, “Albion‟s Fatal Flaws,” Past and Present
98, no. 1, 96-120; David Taylor, Crime, Policing and Punishment in England 1750-1914 (London: Macmillan
Press, 1998), 109ff.
20
JUSTICE Committee, Victims in Criminal Justice: Report of the JUSTICE Committee on the Role of the
Victim in Criminal Justice (London: JUSTICE, 1998), 109.
21
22
Ibid., 70.
Michael McDowell, Speech in the Dáil Éireann, 5 May 2004,
http://debates.oireachtas.ie/Xml/29/DAL20040505.PDF (accessed 16 April 2007).
23
In discussing the communitarian argument I both follow and criticize Sandra Marshall and Antony Duff,
“Criminalization and Sharing Wrongs,” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 11, no. 1(1998): 7-22.
24
Hegel, Philosophy of Right, 220 (section 102).
25
Helen Reeves and Kate Mulley, “The New Status of Victims in the UK: Opportunities and Threats,” in
Integrating a Victim Perspective within Criminal Justice, ed. Adam Crawford and Jo Goodey (Aldershot:
Ashgate, 2000), 129-30, 140. Andrew Ashworth, “Victims‟ Rights, Defendants‟ Rights and Criminal
40
Procedures,” in the same volume (185-204) draws a similar line between the proper treatment and protection of
victims, and the granting to them of rights of active involvement in influencing outcomes for the offender.
26
Nils Christie, “Conflicts as Property,” British Journal of Criminology 17, no. 1 (1977): 10-11.
27
Among Christie‟s inspirations is E.F. Schumacher‟s Small is Beautiful: A Study of Economics as if People
Mattered (London: Blond and Briggs, 1973). Cf. Christie, “Conflicts as Property,” 14.
28
The Queen v. Clotworthy 1998: Appeal Court of New Zealand 114/98. Wellington, New Zealand, 12.
29
Barton, “Empowerment and Retribution in Criminal Justice,” 68. For similar arguments see Joanna Shapland,
“Victims and Criminal Justice: Creating Responsible Criminal Justice Agencies,” in Integrating a Victim
Perspective within Criminal Justice, ed. Adam Crawford and Jo Goodey (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2000), 147-64.
30
The earliest example of this wider sense recorded in the Oxford English Dictionary dates from 1989.
31
For example: on 20 July 2006 the British Home secretary, John Reid, announced in Parliament proposals
which, he said, “all have at their core the aim to rebalance the criminal justice system in favor of the victim and
the law-abiding majority” (John Reid, Statement to the House of Commons, House of Commons Hansard 20
July 2006, col. 472.) His Prime Minister had been suggesting a “rebalancing of the system” to this effect in
speeches for at least four years (cf. The Independent (London), June 25, 2002, 14-15). American politicians have
tended to be more respectful, practically and rhetorically, of the courts‟ independence. However, as early as
1984, a Presidential Task Force reported to Ronald Reagan that the criminal justice system was “appallingly out
of balance. . . . Somewhere along the way, the system began to serve lawyers and judges and defendants,
treating the victim with institutionalized disinterest” (President’s Task Force on Victims of Crime: Final Report
(1982), http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/ovc/publications/presdntstskforcrprt/front.pdf (accessed 20 August 2006). By
1996, President Clinton was declaring that “When a judge balances defendants‟ rights in the Federal
Constitution against victims‟ rights in a statute or a state constitution, the defendants‟ rights almost always
prevail. That‟s just how the law works today. We want to level the playing field. . . . When a judge balances the
rights of the accused and the rights of the victim, we want the rights of the victim to get equal weight”
(“Remarks of the President at Announcement of Victim‟s Rights Constitutional Amendment”: White House
press release, 25 June, 1996, http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/ovc//publications/infores/62596.htm (accessed 20
August 2006).
32
“Dad Jailed for 20 Years for „Evil‟ Sex Abuse of Daughters,” Canberra Times (Australia), September 17,
2010, A1.
33
“15-year Prison Term for Killing Bagpiper: Still No Reason or Explanation for Stabbing Friend to Death,”
41
The Leader-Post (Regina, Saskatchewan), September 14, 2010, A1.
34
For a powerful criticism of this view, see Joel Feinberg, “Criminal Attempts: Equal Punishment for Failed
Attempts,” in Joel Feinberg, Problems at the Root of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 77-102.
35
Once the criminal justice process is under way, the positions of offender and victim are so dissimilar that a
benefit or power granted to the victim by that process cannot, for the most part, credibly be described as
balancing a benefit or power of the offender. (An exception is that both could be given equal protection from
vengeance by their enemies, if this protection would otherwise be more fully enjoyed by one party or the other.)
The claim to represent a restoration of “balance” is also questionable when applied to restorative or
reconciliatory dialogues, subsequent to conviction, between offender and victim. These inevitably require a
yielding of ground by the offender, and, as Barbara Hudson points out, need to be carefully stage-managed by
the authorities, to ensure that the offender cannot re-victimize the victim. Hudson imagines a self-excusing
violent offender being brought, through reconciliatory communication, to see that he „could have‟ acted
differently, to renounce his claim that he “had no choice.” (Barbara Hudson, “Victims and Offenders,” in
Restorative Justice and Criminal Justice: Competing or Reconcilable Paradigms?, ed. Andrew von Hirsch,
Julian Roberts, Anthony E. Bottoms, Kent Roach and Mara Schiff (Oxford: Hart, 2003), 183.) If this is a
voluntary and unconstrained adoption of a changed view, well and good, but it cannot be called a reestablishment of some kind of pre-existing balance: it is the acceptance by the offender of the view already held
by the victim and the state.
36
See David R. Dow, “When Law Bows to Politics: Explaining Payne v Tennessee,” UC Davis Law Review 29
(1992): 157-76. For the relevant passages in the concurring and dissenting opinions, see Payne v Tennessee,
501U.S. 833 (Scalia, J) and 501 U.S. 856 (Stevens, J).
37
The debate in, and subsequent to, Payne has been structured by the constitutional question over possible
arbitrariness in the application of the death penalty. The issue of “balance” in respect of the attention granted
respectively to offender and victim has been overlaid, and arguably confused, by the imperative of weighing the
respective, and not necessarily symmetrical, risks of (i) executing an offender who does not “deserve” death and
(ii) not executing an offender who does. The dilemma of risk created by the drastic and irreversible nature of
capital punishment also forces us to confront very difficult questions about the concept of “desert,” the
relationship between actions and character, and the identity of the self who deserves and receives punishment.
For an incisive exploration of these problems, see Evan J. Mandery, “Notions of Symmetry and Self in Death
42
Penalty Jurisprudence (with Implications for the Admissibility of Victim Impact Evidence,” Stanford Law and
Policy Review 15 (2004): 471-517.
38
Joshua D. Greenberg, “Is Payne Defensible? The Constitutionality of Admitting Victim-Impact Evidence at
Capital Sentencing Hearings,” Indiana Law Journal 75, no. 4 (2000): 1379.
39
Ibid., 1364-65, 1370.
40
See Mandery, “Notions of Symmetry and Self in Death Penalty Jurisprudence,” esp.503-8.
41
Ibid., 493-503.
42
Booth v. Maryland, 482 US 496 (1987) at 517 (White, J. dissenting).
43
Greenberg, “Is Payne Defensible?”, 1379.
44
But see, for example, Dow, “When Law Bows to Politics: Explaining Payne v Tennessee”; Feinberg,
“Criminal Attempts: Equal Punishment for Failed Attempts”; David Lewis, “The Punishment that Leaves
Something to Chance.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 18, no. 1 (1989): 53-67; Michael S. Moore, “The
Independent Moral Significance of Wrongdoing,” in Michael S. Moore, Placing Blame (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1997), 191-247.
45
The offender may, of course, intend some special additional harm, in which case, whether or not it falls within
the range and seriousness of predictable harms, that specific intention needs to be proved irrespective of victim
impact. An example is provided by hate crimes, in which it may be possible to show that the offender, in
injuring or killing V, expressed some malign intention towards a wider community, of whom the direct victim
was a representative.
46
See the epigraph and note 1.
47
“Judge Cooke told the court, „My own brother was killed by a dangerous driver.‟ The judge said it was not
a case „in which the judiciary are totally out of touch and do not understand such things.‟ He said there was,
in the general public, a feeling „that judges live in a different world, where tragedy does not touch their lives.
It is not so.‟” (Lauren Turner, “He‟s my last thought at night and my first thought in the morning, says
grieving father,” The Western Mail (Cardiff), December 13, 2007, 14.) “Many judges are out of touch with
average Australian values and increasingly isolated from the real world, according to a top Melbourne silk. . .
. David Galbally QC said part of the problem with the judiciary could lie with the pool of barristers from
which they are drawn, who can sometimes have limited life experiences. „It may be that lawyers who practise
in the law and who are barristers are out of touch because of the way they practise law, and they may need to
43
be in touch and undertake some form of education from that point of view,‟ he said.” (Richard Kerbaj,
„”Judges Not Living in the Real World,” The Australian, January 21, 2008, 3.)
48
David B. Hershenov, “Restitution and Revenge,” The Journal of Philosophy 96, no. 2 (1999): 79-94.
49
“If you are making a written statement, you may want to discuss how this crime has affected your ability to
earn a living and how it has affected you financially. We have also included a separate Victim Financial
Statement to help you fully record the financial impact of this crime. It is important to be as complete as
possible in describing your financial losses as this information will be used by the probation department and
provided to the judge for determining restitution. (Ellen K. Alexander and Janice Harris Lord, “Suggestions for
Completing your Victim Impact Statement,” in A Victim’s Right to Speak, a Nation’s Responsibility to Listen,
article from the Office for Victims of Crime, sponsored by the US Department of Justice, July 15, 1994,
http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/ovc/publications/infores/impact/impact.htm#Suggestions
accessed September 24, 2010).
50
Sergeant Alan Prokop and Inspector Sergeant Jerry Flowers, VIE in the case of the Oklahoma Bomber
Timothy McVeigh (United States v McVeigh (1997), June 4, 1997) ,
http://www.cnn.com/US/9703/okc.trial/transcripts/mcveigh.html (accessed 20 August 2008).
51
Todd McCarthy, VIE in the case of the Oklahoma Bomber Terry Nichols (Tim Talley, “Two who lost family
in Oklahoma City bombing testify for Nichols as closing arguments end,” Associated Press, June 9, 2004).
52
It is a disputed question whether, or to what extent, the mass media create or amplify, rather than merely
reflect, popular perceptions of the courts‟ leniency towards offenders and indifference to victims. There is an
illuminating discussion in Andrew Ashworth and Michael Hough, “Sentencing and the Climate of Opinion,”
Criminal Law Review (November 1996): 776-87.
53
“A grief-stricken mother delivered a powerful message against senseless violence as she faced her son's
teenaged killer and two accomplices in court yesterday. Her voice breaking with emotion, Fredricka Nickie said
the unprovoked murder of her son, Kenroy John, by strangers has “condemned her to a life sentence of
heartache‟ without parole.” (Sam Pazzano, “Teen‟s Killer Guilty,” Toronto Sun, May 12, 2005, 7.) “This month
is hard enough for Ray King, having to relive the pain and anguish of his son's murder 25 years ago at the hands
of serial killer Clifford Olson. This week will make matters even worse when Mr. King flies to Montreal to
attend Olson's first parole hearing. „We've got the life sentence—there's no parole for us,‟ he said of the families
of Olson's 11 victims.” (Neil Hall, “Victim‟s Father to Attend Olson‟s Parole Hearing,” National Post (Canada),
July 17, 2006, A6). “The mother of a British woman murdered in Japan six years ago broke down in a
44
courtroom yesterday as she described her torment over her daughter's final hours. . . . „When Lucie's killer is
convicted of this crime, for me justice demands that he spends the rest of his natural life in prison contemplating
the enormity of his crimes. I am living a life sentence because of what he did to my beloved Lucie. He should
never be released.‟” (“Mother of British Kidnap Victim Found Dead in Japan Breaks Down in Court,” Daily
Mail (London), April 21, 2006 [no by-line].)
45