U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
Pr
oo
f
Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices
1
CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHENOMENOLOGY
2
4
IN COOPERATION WITH
THE CENTER FOR ADVANCED RESEARCH IN PHENOMENOLOGY
5
Volume 64
3
7
Series Editors:
Nicolas de Warren, Wellesley College, MA, USA
8
Dermot Moran, University College Dublin, Ireland
6
Editorial Board:
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
Lilian Alweiss, Trinity College Dublin, Ireland
Elizabeth Behnke, Ferndale, WA, USA
Michael Barber, St. Louis University, MO, USA
Rudolf Bernet, Husserl-Archief, Katholieke Universiteit Leuven, Belgium
David Carr, Emory University, GA, USA
Chan-Fai Cheung, Chinese University Hong Kong, China
James Dodd, New School University, NY, USA
Lester Embree, Florida Atlantic University, FL, USA
Alfredo Ferrarin, Università di Pisa, Italy
Burt Hopkins, Seattle University, WA, USA
Jos´e Huertas-Jourda, Wilfrid Laurier University, Canada
Kwok-Ying Lau, Chinese University Hong Kong, China
Nam-In Lee, Seoul National University, Korea
Dieter Lohmar, Universit¨at zu K¨oln, Germany
William R. McKenna, Miami University, OH, USA
Algis Mickunas, Ohio University, OH, USA
J.N. Mohanty, Temple University, PA, USA
Junichi Murata, University of Tokyo, Japan
Thomas Nenon, The University of Memphis, TN, USA
Thomas M. Seebohm, Johannes Gutenberg-Universit¨at, Germany
Gail Soffer, Rome, Italy
Anthony Steinbock, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale, IL, USA
Shigeru Taguchi, Yamagata University, Japan
Dan Zahavi, University of Copenhagen, Denmark
Richard M. Zaner, Vanderbilt University, TN, USA
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
Pr
ed
ct
re
or
nc
Scope
U
35
oo
f
9
The purpose of the series is to serve as a vehicle for the pursuit of phenomenological research
across a broad spectrum, including cross-over developments with other fields of inquiry
such as the social sciences and cognitive science. Since its establishment in 1987, Contributions
to Phenomenology has published nearly 60 titles on diverse themes of phenomenological philosophy. In addition to
welcoming monographs and collections of papers in established areas of scholarship,
the series encourages original work in phenomenology. The breadth and depth of the Series reflects the rich and varied
significance of phenomenological thinking for seminal questions of human inquiry as well as the increasingly
international reach of phenomenological research.
For further volumes:
http://www.springer.com/series/5811
Francis Halsall • Julia Jansen • Sinead Murphy
46
Editors
47
Pr
Dialogues with Tony O’Connor
on Society, Art, and Friendship
oo
f
Critical Communities
and Aesthetic Practices
48
49
50
51
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
52
68
53
69
54
70
55
71
56
72
57
73
58
74
59
75
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
Editors
Francis Halsall
Faculty of Visual Culture
National College of Art and Design
Thomas St. 100
Dublin 8
Ireland
halsallf@ncad.ie
76
77
78
79
ISSN 0923-9545
ISBN 978-94-007-1508-0
e-ISBN 978-94-007-1509-7
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7
Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg London New York
U
80
Library of Congress Control Number: xxxxxxxxxx
81
82
83
84
85
© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any
means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written
permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose
of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work.
86
Printed on acid-free paper
87
Springer is part of Springer Science+Business Media (www.springer.com)
Julia Jansen
Department of Philosophy
University College Cork
Lucan Place 1-2
Western Road, Cork
Ireland
j.jansen@ucc.ie
nc
or
re
ct
ed
Pr
oo
f
Sinead Murphy
Philosophical Studies
Newcastle University
Newcastle upon Tyne
Herschel Bldg., 6th Floor
United Kingdom
Contents
oo
f
Introduction: Aesthetic Practices and Critical Communities:
Art, Politics, Friendship..........................................................................
Francis Halsall, Julia Jansen, and Sinéad Murphy
5
7
8
ct
92
93
13
96
23
97
98
49
99
100
101
102
103
63
104
105
A Note on Hölderlin Translation ...........................................................
David Farrell Krell
73
Violence and Splendor: At the Limits of Hermeneutics ......................
Alphonso Lingis
85
106
107
108
109
Critical Communities and Aesthetic Subjects:
Ethics, Politics, Action
Community Beyond Instrumental Reason: The Idea
of Donation in Deleuze and Lyotard......................................................
James Williams
94
95
Art and Edge: Preliminary Reflections .................................................
Edward S. Casey
From Reflection to Refraction: On Bordwell’s Cinema
and the Viewing Event ............................................................................
John Mullarkey
90
91
37
Part II
9
89
1
Merleau-Ponty on Cultural Schemas and Childhood Drawing ..........
Talia Welsh
U
6
re
4
In Between Word and Image: Philosophical Hermeneutics,
Aesthetics and the Inescapable Heritage of Kant ................................
Nicholas Davey
or
3
Reflections on the Hermeneutics of Creative Acts ...............................
Douglas Burnham
nc
2
Hermeneutics and Aesthetic Practices:
Art, Ritual, Interpretation
ed
Part I
Pr
1
88
110
111
112
99
113
114
v
vi
10
The Political Horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology ........................... 111
Duane C. Davis
11
Derrida’s Specters: Futurity, Finitude, Forgetting .............................. 127
Joanna Hodge
12
The Political and Ethical Significance of Waiting:
Heidegger and the Legacy of Thinking ................................................. 139
Felix Ó Murchadha
13
Othering ................................................................................................... 151
Robert Bernasconi
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
Part III Aesthetic Practice and Critical Community: Friendship
125
14
Otogogy, or Friendship, Teaching and the Ear of the Other .............. 161
Graham Allen
15
Kantian Friendship ................................................................................. 171
Gary Banham
16
Just Friends: The Ethics of (Postmodern) Relationships .................... 181
Hugh J. Silverman
17
The Art of Friendship ............................................................................
William S. Hamrick
195
132
133
Tony O’Connor Biography............................................................................
207
134
Index ................................................................................................................
209
127
128
129
or
nc
U
131
re
130
ed
126
Pr
124
ct
123
oo
f
115
Contents
Contributors
oo
f
135
ed
Pr
Graham Allen is Professor in English Literature at University College Cork. His
recent books are: Mary Shelley (Palgrave, 2008); Readers Guide to Shelley’s
“Frankenstein” (Continuum, 2008); The Pupils of the University, (ed.) (Routledge,
2006); Figures of Bloom: The Salt Companion to Harold Bloom, (co-edited with
Roy Sellars), (London: SALT, January 2007) and Roland Barthes, (Korean translation), (LP Publishing, 2006). He is also working on longer term book projects on:
theories of the university and teaching; the work of William Godwin; the relationship between P. B. Shelley and Mary Shelley.
or
re
ct
Gary Banham was Reader in Transcendental Philosophy at Manchester Metropolitan
University and is now editor of Kant Studies Online, and general editor of Palgrave
Macmillan’s series, Renewing Philosophy. Recent books include: Kant’s Transcendental Imagination (2006, Palgrave Macmillan); Kant’s Practical Philosophy: From
Critique to Doctrine (2003, Palgrave Macmillan); Kant and the Ends of Aesthetics
(2000, Macmillan).
U
nc
Robert Bernasconi is the Lillian and Morrie Moss Professor of Philosophy at the
University of Memphis. He is well known as a reader of Martin Heidegger and
Emmanuel Levinas, and for his work on the concept of race. His books include:
How to Read Sartre (New York: W. W. Norton, 2007); Heidegger in Question: The
Art of Existing (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press, 1993); The Question of
Language in Heidegger’s History of Being (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press,
1985).
Douglas Burnham is Professor in Philosophy at the University of Staffordshire.
His research areas include Kant, Nietzsche, recent European philosophy, philosophy and literature. His most recent publications include Kant’s Philosophies of
Judgement (Edinburgh, 2004), “Heidegger, Kant and ‘Dirty’ Politics” (European
Journal of Political Thought, 2005), Reading Nietzsche (Acumen/ McGill-Queens,
2007), and Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (Edinburgh, 2007), as well as a number
of papers on philosophy and literature.
vii
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
viii
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
Nicholas Davey is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Dundee and a past
president of the British Society for Phenomenology. His principle teaching and
research interests are in aesthetics and hermeneutics. He has published widely in the
fields of continental philosophy, aesthetics and hermeneutic theory. His recent book,
Unquiet Understanding: Reflections of Gadamer’s Hermeneutics was published by
State University Press of New York in 2006. He is also completing The Fiery Eye:
Hermeneutics, Aesthetics and the Imagination (forthcoming).
oo
f
171
Duane C. Davis is associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of North Carolina
at Asheville. Recent publications focus on Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and he is the editor
of Merleau-Ponty’s Later Works and Their Practical Implications: The Dehiscence of
Responsibility (Humanity, 2001). His areas of specialization focus on ethics; nineteenth
and twentieth century continental philosophy; and social and political philosophy. He
is currently in charge of the Phi Sigma Tau Philosophy Honor Society.
Pr
170
ed
169
Francis Halsall is lecturer in the history and theory of modern/contemporary art at
the National College of Art and Design, Dublin. His research focuses on theories of
art after modernism (and in particular the systems-theoretical approach such as that
of Niklas Luhmann). He is the author of Systems of Art (Peter Lang, 2008) and
co-editor (with Julia Jansen & Tony O’Connor) of Rediscovering Aesthetics,
(Stanford University Press, 2008). Recent articles include: ‘One Sense is Never
Enough’ Journal of Visual Art Practice (October, 2004); ‘Art History versus
Aesthetics?’ in Elkins, J, (ed.) Art History Versus Aesthetics, (Routledge, 2005); and
‘Chaos, Fractals and the Pedagogical Challenge of Jackson Pollock’s ‘All-Over’
Paintings’, Journal of Aesthetic Education, (2008)
ct
168
re
167
or
166
Edward S. Casey is Distinguished Professor for Philosophy at Stony Brook
University and current President of the Eastern chapter of the APA. He works in
aesthetics, philosophy of space and time, ethics, perception, and psychoanalytic
theory. His published books include The World At a Glance (Indiana University
Press, 2007); Earth-Mapping: Artists Reshaping Landscape (University of
Minnesota Press, 2005); Imagining: A Phenomenological Study (Indiana University
Press, 2000); and The Fate of Place (University of California Press, 1999).
nc
165
William Hamrick is Professor Emeritus at Southern Illinois University. He holds a
Ph.D. from Vanderbilt University (1971). Dr. Hamrick’s last book was Kindness and
the Good Society: Connections of the Heart (Albany, NY: State University of
New York Press, 2002). In 2004, that work was the winner of the Edward Ballard
Prize from the Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology. He is also the coeditor, with Suzanne L. Cataldi, of Merleau- Ponty and Environmental Philosophy:
Dwelling on the Landscapes of Thought (Albany, NY: State University of New York
Press, 2007). Since retiring, he has remained professionally active as a member of the
Editorial Board of the Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, as a member of the Executive Council of the Metaphysical Society of America (MSA), and as
the representative of that group to the American Council of Learned Societies.
U
164
Contributors
Contributors
ix
Joanna Hodge is Professor of Philosophy at Manchester Metropolitan University
and immediate past president of the British Society for Phenomenology. Recent
publications include: Derrida on Time (Routledge, 2007); “Authenticity and
Apriorism in Husserl’s Phenomenology”, for Gary Banham (ed.): Husserl and the
Logic of Experience, (Palgrave: London, 2005); “Walter Benjamin on elective affinity”, for Andrew Benjamin and Beatrice Hansen (eds.): Walter Benjamin on Time,
(Continuum: London, 2005); “Ethics and Time: Levinas between Kant and Husserl”,
Diacritics: Journal of contemporary criticism, Vol. 32, number 3, Spring 2004. She
is on the Editorial Boards of Angelaki: Journal for Theoretical Humanities and of
the Journal for the British Society for Phenomenology.
ed
Pr
oo
f
Julia Jansen is current Head of Philosophy at University College Cork, Ireland. Her
current research explores the intersections of Kant’s Philosophy of Mind, Husserlian
Phenomenology, Aesthetics, and Cognitive Science. Her recent publications include:
‘Imagination in Phenomenology and Interdisciplinary Research’ In: Shaun Gallagher
and Daniel Schmicking (eds). Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science
(Springer, 2010) and “Husserl’s First Philosophy of Phantasy: A Transcendental
Phenomenology of Imagination,” in: Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences
(2005). She is the co-editor (with Francis Halsall & Tony O’Connor) of Rediscovering
Aesthetics (Stanford University Press, 2008) and author of Imagination in
Transcendental Philosophy: Kant and Husserl Revisited (forthcoming).
nc
or
re
ct
David Farrell Krell is professor of philosophy at DePaul University in Chicago and
the founding director of the DePaul Humanities Center. He has written eleven scholarly books, translated six volumes of philosophy, and published three novels. His
most recent work is an annotated translation of Hölderlin’s mourning-play, The
Death of Empedocles (SUNY Press, 2008). Among his other books are: The Tragic
Absolute: German Idealism and the Languishing of God (Indiana University Press,
2005), The Purest of Bastards: Works of Mourning, Art, and Affirmation in the
Thought of Jacques Derrida (Penn State Press, 2000), Contagion: Sexuality,
Disease, and Death in German Idealism and Romanticism (Indiana, 1998), and The
Good European: Nietzsche’s Work Sites in Word and Image, with Donald L. Bates
(University of Chicago Press, 1997).
U
Alphonso Lingis is an American philosopher, writer and translator, currently
Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at Pennsylvania State University. His areas of
specialization include phenomenology, existentialism, modern philosophy, and ethics. His publications include: Excesses: Eros and Culture (1984); Libido: The
French Existential Theories (1985); Phenomenological Explanations (1986);
Deathbound Subjectivity (1989); The Community of Those Who Have Nothing in
Common (1994); Abuses (1994); Foreign Bodies (1994); Sensation: Intelligibility in
Sensibility (1995); The Imperative (1998); Dangerous Emotions (1999); Trust
(University of Minnesota Press, 2004); Body Transformations (Routledge, 2005);
The First Person Singular (Northwestern University Press, 2007); Violence and
Splendor (Northwestern University Press, 2011)
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
x
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
Felix ó Murchadha is Director of Graduate Studies in Philosophy, NUI, Galway.
Recent publications include: Being Alive: The Place of Life in Merleau-Ponty and
Descartes, Chiasmi International; ‘Glory, Idolatry, Kairos: Revelation and the
Ontological Difference in Marion’ in E. Cassidy & Leask, I (eds.): Givenness and
God. Questions of Jean-Luc Marion (New York: Fordham University Press); ‘Ruine
als Werk. Die Grenze des Handelns als Urmoment der Geschichtlichkeit’, in H Hüni
& P. Trawney (eds.): Die erscheinende Welt Berlin (Duncker und Humblot 2002);
‘The Time of History and the Responsibility of Philosophy. Heideggerian Reflections
on the Origins of Philosophy’, Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology,
Vol. 30, No. 2, (1999).
oo
f
254
Pr
253
Sinéad Murphy lectures in Philosophy at the University of Newcastle, Ireland. Her
background is in Aesthetics, Hermeneutics and literary theory, and her current
research is into the extent to, and manner in, which hermeneutic philosophy exemplifies a constructive mode of philosophical practice. She has published on Kant’s
sublime, on feminist literary theory, on style and fashion, on literature and other
related themes. She is author of Effective History: On Critical Practice Under
Historical Conditions (Northwestern University Press, 2010).
ed
252
ct
251
re
250
Hugh J. Silverman is Professor of Philosophy and Comparative Literature and
Executive Director of the International Association for Philosophy and Literature
(IAPL). The inaugural Fulbright-Distinguished Chair in the Humanities at the
University of Vienna (2001), he has also been Visiting Professor at Warwick and
Leeds (UK), Turin and Rome-Tor Vergata (Italy), Vienna and Klagenfurt (Austria),
Helsinki and Tampere (Finland), Sydney and Tasmania (Australia), Trondheim
(Norway) and Nice (France). In 1998–2000, he was President of the Stony Brook
Arts & Sciences Senate. Author of Textualities: Between Hermeneutics and
Deconstruction (Routledge, 1994, German ed:, 1997, Italian ed:, 2004) and
Inscriptions: After Phenomenology and Structuralism (2nd ed., Northwestern,
1997), editor of the Routledge Continental Philosophy series, including Philosophy
and Non-Philosophy since Merleau-Ponty (1988/1997), Derrida and Deconstruction
(1989), Postmodernism, Philosophy and the Arts (1990), Gadamer and Hermeneutics
(1991), Questioning Foundations (1994), Cultural Semiosis (1998), Philosophy and
Desire (2000) and Lyotard: Philosophy, Politics, and the Sublime (2003), his many
edited/co-edited books include studies of Piaget, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Derrida,
hermeneutics, deconstruction, postmodernism.
or
249
John Mullarkey is Professor in Film and Television at Kingston University London.
His recent books include: Refractions of Reality: Philosophy and the Moving Image
(Palgrave- Macmillan, 2009); Post-Continental Philosophy: An Outline, (Continuum
Press, 2006); Bergson and Philosophy, (Edinburgh University Press, 1999) and
(ed.) Henri Bergson: An Introduction to Metaphysics (Bergson Centennial Series),
Palgrave-Macmillan, 2007. He is also co-editor (with Beth Lorde) of The Continuum
Companion to Continental Philosophy (Continuum Press, 2009).
nc
248
U
247
Contributors
Contributors
xi
Talia Welsh is associate professor in Philosophy at University of Tennessee at
Chattanooga. She has a Ph.D. from State University of New York. Her main areas of
research are philosophy of psychology, phenomenology, nineteenth and twentieth
century European philosophy, and Feminist Theory. In particular, she writes on the
connection between phenomenology and psychology. She has published articles in
French, German, and English. She is the translator of Merleau-Ponty’s Child
Psychology and Pedagogy: The Sorbonne Lectures 1949–1952 (Northwestern
University Press, 2010). In the past few years she has presented over 15 conference
papers in Honolulu, Belgium, Boston, Philadelphia, Ottawa, and at several other venues. At UTC, she is a core faculty member in the UTC Women’s Studies Program.
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
Pr
oo
f
James Williams is professor of Philosophy at Dundee University. He has published
widely on contemporary French philosophy (Deleuze, Lyotard, Foucault, Kristeva,
Derrida, Badiou, Postmodernism and Poststructuralism). His most recent book is a
study of Gilles Deleuze’s Logic of Sense (Edinburgh University, 2009). The book
explains and evaluates Deleuze’s philosophy of language, philosophy of events, philosophy of thought (as opposed to philosophy of mind) and moral philosophy. The
work develops ideas from his earlier book on Difference and Repetition, also with
Edinburgh (2004). He is also author of Lyotard and the Political (Routledge, 2000).
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
Author Query
Chapter No.: 16
0001335159
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please confirm chaper title for chapters 1, 3, 5-9, 12, 14.
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
Pr
oo
f
Query
Chapter 1
1
Introduction: Critical Communities
and Aesthetic Practices
2
3
Francis Halsall, Julia Jansen, and Sinéad Murphy
4
At the 2008 Venice Biennale, Sophie Calle filled the French Pavillon with responses,
by more than 100 women, to a personal letter that had originally been addressed
to her; an email, to be precise, with which a boyfriend informed her that he would
leave her. ‘Take care of yourself,’ the email ends. This phrase became the title for the
piece in which each participating woman responded to the email in her individual
way and according to her profession.
‘Take Care of Yourself’ raises important questions an it challenges the expectations that are commonly brought to artworks. It also throws an interesting light on
this book. Why would an artist make her own personal life public? Is it legitimate to
turn the personal into art and to make art personal? Precisely four decades after
Roland Barthes pronounced the death of the author,1 can we allow Calle to be a
‘first-person artist’?2 Suspicions arise. Is this first-person really her? Is the email
authentic? Is the personal that Calle so readily reveals in her work (but not in interviews, we might add) real, or is it just a clever fiction?
More interesting than answers to these complex questions is the possibility that
these answers need not matter. What does matter is that the ‘personal’ origin of
Roland Barthes, “La Mort de L’Auteur” 1968, in Essais Critiques IV, Le Bruissement De La
Langue (Paris: Seuil, 1984), 61–66.
2
Alfred Pacquement, “Preface,” in Sophie Calle, M’as-tu vue, ed. Christine Macel (Paris: Centre
National d’Art et de Culture Georges Pompidou, 2003), 15.
1
F. Halsall
National College of Art and Design, Dublin, Ireland
e-mail: halsallf@ncad.ie
J. Jansen
School of Sociology and Philosophy, University College Cork, Cork, Ireland
e-mail: j.jansen@ucc.ie
S. Murphy
Philosophical Studies, Newcastle University, Newcastle upon Tyne, UK
e-mail: sinead.murphy@ncl.ac.uk
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_1, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
1
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
2
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
Calle’s work enables something to emerge which could not have been without it; the
collage of voices, performances and texts exhibited as ‘Take Care of Yourself’ can
only be because of the personal; however ‘real’ or not, this may be.
The same is true of this book – with the important difference that we do know
of the real existence of the philosopher Tony O’ Connor, in honour of whom it was
conceived.
Festschriften such as this, although meant as tributes to especially esteemed colleagues, are often considered of lesser academic value. Articles come together in
them, it is said, only arbitrarily; that is, as random selections of texts written by
groups of people linked only by their personal connections to the tributee.However,
the articles in this book have been arranged to highlight coherent themes which are
shared by the contributions and which always informed Tony’s thought and work;
these are: the hermeneutics of art, politics and ethics, and friendship. And there are
two themes running throughout the book as a whole and contributing to the sense of
community amongst all authors.
First, all papers are, broadly speaking, phenomenological in outlook and demonstrate how contributions to phenomenology are always applied to particular and
practical examples. Second all papers engage in questions of aesthetics broadly
conceived. It is for this reason that we that we have chosen have chosen to open this
introduction with the example of a work of art. Sophie Calle’s work suggests a different perspective on this very personal book. What matters is not only its real occasion – Tony’s retirement from University College Cork in Ireland – but what emerges
from this occasion. Here, we find a rare openness and experimental spirit among the
contributors, which perhaps is only possible in this more personal (although still
public and academic) context in which one feels justified in leaving (some) institutional conventions and constraints behind.
Douglas Burnham’s contribution to this collection emerges from the research
project at Staffordshire University, in which he collaborated with Tony and others to
interrogate the similarities between making art and making philosophy. The commitment to inquiry is, Burnham explains, central to this project, to the extent that
making art and making philosophy – if conceived of primarily as processes of
inquiry and less centrally in terms of the objects they produce – can be understood,
together. They are both modes of interaction, engagement and dialogue. Market,
institutional, career pressures tend to obscure the potential of philosophy as a process
of inquiry. Reflecting on the practice of philosophy, in conjunction with art practices
(as in the Staffordshire ‘Inquiry in Art and Philosophy’ project) can have the effect of
reducing these pressures and restoring to philosophy its potential as inviting process
and open exchange. The articles in this book demonstrate this last point.
Thus, like Sophie Calle’s ‘Take Care of Yourself’ artwork, this philosophical book
brings together individuals who are united in their attempt to respond, with care and
according to their expertise. They all respond to Tony O’ Connor as philosopher and
person, all in different ways: by interpreting Tony’s work, by thinking through
issues they know are on Tony’s mind, by offering their own work for discussion, and
by addressing Tony personally. What emerges in this open, inviting, but by no means
uncritical, context reflects the breadth of processes that, as David Krell in this
21
F. Halsall et al.
1
Introduction: Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices
3
collection puts it so succinctly, ‘have almost all their life ahead of them,’ processes
that, as Krell describes, are not only not limited by original conditions – by an
author’s intention, by strong notions of text, by career interests, by personal circumstances – but live into the future in a manner that both foregrounds our human finitude and gestures towards the unbounded possibilities for interpretation that are the
effects of this condition.
This is not, however, to deny that processes of inquiry, open and inviting as they
may be, have their particular directions. And this book is no exception, collated as
it is around its central concern with ‘aesthetic practices and critical communities.’
These two themes ‘regulate’ the articles in this volume and lend the book its focus
and systematic character.
The theme of aesthetic practices has its starting point in the rich and suggestive
openness of aesthetic experience, but reaches far beyond a preoccupation with art or
issues of aesthetic appreciation. It rather addresses practices from the full range of
human interests which involve views, values, and norms that are not settled, for
once and for all, but do, by appeal to particular communities, still claim validity
beyond their relative standpoint. Like Kantian aesthetic judgments, these views,
values and norms are taken up ‘freely,’ that is, with a degree of independence from
cognitive and moral laws. These judgements appeal to shared, contextual and communal, criteria, and not to universally objective standards. They do not function in any
neutral and aboslute way, but as interlocutary, argumentative and open to agreement
or dissent. Thus, aesthetic practices and critical communities are the two sides of a
historical and social, hermeneutical, process from which common standards emerge
and in which practices and communities are themselves continually co-constituted.
This process has its dangers, of course. It can, as Alphonso Lingis shows here,
bring us to the very edge, even to the breakdown, of conventional conceptions of
meaning. Ritualistic collective performances, such as initiations, ceremonies, parades,
dances, do not just establish meaning by means of shared cultural symbols (identifiable by anthropologists); they can also open up a, potentially disruptive, space for
creativity fuelled by feelings, movements and rhythms. It is not primarily through
words and laws, then, but also through such concrete ‘aesthetic’ practices, that humans
are able to partake in a ‘historical consciousness’ and, to borrow Nietzsche’s term,
‘eternally repeat’ and reappropriate the frames and conditions of the communities to
which they belong. Hence, as Lingis concludes, meaning is ‘not just intellectual, conceptual meaning, grasped in conscious acts,’ but also embodied, ritualised, and performed. Meaning is potentially transcendent not only of the conscious individual and
the present in which the performance takes place, but also – in experiences of joy and
splendour – of any attempt to grasp meaning with a settled interpretation.
The concern with ‘aesthetic practices and critical communities,’ then, immediately
involves the basic insight that communities and critique are, given our irreducibly
historical natures, inextricably associated. That is, critique is not an achievement
abstracted from historical conditions and communities, and communities are neither
established nor identified outside of conditions that are subject to, and constitutive
of, possibilities for critical appraisal. When there is no single perspective available
from which absolute judgments can be made and absolute laws established,
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
4
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
what remains is a ‘sensus communis’ – a sense shared – an appeal to which one
cannot force assent but must use the available means of negotiation and persuasion.
In the best cases, these practices of negotiation and persuasion, which rely upon and
appeal to a sense of community, give rise to a critical sense of a community whose
members are not only critical of the claims they are presented with but, in an awareness of the fundamental corrigibility of any adopted position, also self-critical.
Critique, then, can never be abstracted from historical conditions and particular
communities. Communities, likewise, are neither established nor identified outside
of conditions that are subject to, and constitutive of, possibilities for critical appraisal.
This means that no critical communities can ever be politically neutral. It is for this
reason that the contributors investigate politics, not in terms of laws, parties and
state constitutions, but of critical communities of embodied, desiring human beings.
In short, they discuss the politics of audiences, peers and friends.
Above all, the contributions share the hermeneutical commitment to dialogue,
which has motivated the process of editing this collection and which most characterises
Tony O’Connor, as a philosopher, colleague, and friend. James Williams’ contribution to this collection convincingly demonstrates how communities without a
strong, pre-given, or tenaciously assumed, identity reveal other modes of beingwhich can be experienced as valuable and important, in spite of (perhaps because of)
their fragile and fragmentary qualities. Our hopes for this project have centred on
the possibility that just such a valuable and important community might surface: a
community constituted by association with Tony’s philosophical interests and activities; a community that has been years (a professional philosopher’s lifetime) in the
making but only fleeting; and only here, in its full realisation. This is a community
whose members, already in the business of being critical, might, by the juxtaposition
of their voices, open up new and surprising possibilities for critique and anticipate a
long and varied life out ahead.
The critical importance of the fragmentary communities that Williams describes –
communities constituted, as in the case of this project for instance, around the occasional or personal – really comes to light with the philosophical acknowledgment
that contexts, communities and contingencies affect even highly reflective practices.
Critique occurs, as Foucault describes it, somewhere ‘between the high Kantian
enterprise and the little polemical professional activities,’3 somewhere, that is,
between the expectation that properly critical practices are beyond historical effect
and the interested immersion of strongly purposeful pursuits. In this regard, Foucault
directs us to Kant (Nicholas Davey’s reference to the ‘inescapable heritage of Kant’
expresses well the extent to which the contributors to this collection are, in different
ways, already there), specifically to Kant’s ‘What is Enlightenment?,’ in which the
title question is addressed, indirectly it would seem, via a series of reflections on
111
F. Halsall et al.
Michel Foucault, “What is Critique?,” in The Politics of Truth, ed. Sylvère Lotringer, trans. Lysa
Hochroth & Catherine Porter (Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2007), 42.
4
Immanuel Kant, “What is Enlightenment,” in On History, trans. L. White Beck (Indianapolis:
The Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1963), 9.
3
1
Introduction: Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices
5
‘the century of Frederick.’4 Kant defines critique, not by defining critique but by
defining something else.5 Under historical conditions, critique exists, first and
foremost, as a relation to something other than itself – it is not ‘pure critique’
(the ‘high Kantian enterprise’), but it is an attitude to people, events, institutions
(to ‘little polemical professional activities’) that partially annuls the effects of their
prejudices and purposes.
The critical importance of engaging – with different disciplines, ‘outside’ interests,
‘practical’ and ‘personal’ concerns, and always with others – is, then, central to the
hermeneutical commitment to what Hans-Georg Gadamer calls ‘effective history.’
Engaging accounts for the enthusiastic persistence with which Tony has, throughout
his philosophical career, conducted a highly productive engagement, in particular
with literature and film. This engagement has generated interdisciplinarity in his
teaching and his research; constituted communities within the university and
beyond; and provided Tony and his interlocutors with a whole set of possibilities for
critique, where what is at stake is not simply the ‘illustration’ of abstract ideas but a
genuine education of (his and others’) philosophical practices in the ways of more
conventionally creative experiences.
Those who know Tony will also know that this manner of dialogue with him
can often be, in more than one sense of a word so provokingly discussed by Edward
S. Casey in this collection, ‘edgy.’ Casey, very fruitfully, distinguishes between
edge and limit; the limits, of a dialogue for instance, are its conditions of possibility,
which are very difficult even to recognise let alone to submit to critical scrutiny.
Philosophy, certainly since Kant, has placed many of its hopes on questioning its
limits, but Casey very interestingly draws our attention to the, more accessible to
‘everyday’ philosophical dialogue but still hugely formative, operations of
edges, which designate not so much the limit conditions of a particular discourse
as its internal angles and props. To expose these to question, one does not require
a radically different perspective; indeed, one must enter into the spirit of their particular commitment in order to address them at all. And, characteristically from an
edge of the assembled crowd – from some corner in the back row and near the
door – and often from deep within his own ‘edge’ philosophical interests in 1940s
films and contemporary soap operas, this is precisely what Tony is so good at.
Tony will generously enter into the particular question or commitment under the
discussion but be always interested in exploring its edges, the ways in which it juts
out in places, its repercussions for practices not immediately at stake. Edgy and
engaged, with different disciplines, with ‘outside’ interests, with ‘practical’ and ‘personal’ concerns, and always with others.
But this engaged, this edgy, philosopher, is not any new and original figure, of
course. Indeed, it returns us to the very beginnings of Western philosophy when, as
Gadamer shows us, for Plato the questions that engage philosophers are not to be
treated as constituting objects in themselves that can be ‘held in safekeeping,’ but
are defined ‘as referring to something else that alone really “exists” and is really
5
Foucault, “What is Critique?,” 47.
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
6
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
“good” – and they are defined as something that really exists only in this referring,
that is, as something depending on what they refer to.’6 In short, the distinction
between theory and practice – and between the academic and the personal – which
removes the philosopher from responsibility for the application of her ideas, from
engagement, is one we must continually throw open to question, in a general way
and also in the more particular inquiries. Such particularities are demonstrated by
John Mullarkey’s interesting analysis in this collection of the contextual nature of
standard theories of film that distinguish between the realism of Hollywood, and the
reflexivity of European cinema. Such theoretical designations of films, Mullarkey
shows, are contingent upon the conditions of their audiences, in a manner that thoroughly upsets any straightforward ‘theory’ of films, conceived as somehow removed
from (highly contextual) practices of viewing them.
Cinema is a reference point in this collection in honour of Tony, who, intermittently and very entertainingly, shares with students and friends his interpretations
of Hollywood classics – especially from the 1940s and 1950s. He is interested in
films precisely as reflections on themselves, on their medium, on their resources,
and on their audiences. An avid film goer from his early youth, Tony’s love of cinema
began under conditions highly conducive to the development of such interpretive
skills: packed into standing-room-only theatres among many for whom the occasion
presented a chance to share (loudly!) their portion of weekly gossip, and often arriving
half-way through the main feature which meant one had to stay until the next showing if one wanted to catch the beginning. An earlier start on a career of hermeneutical interpretation, a greater encouragement towards the experience of realist cinema
as a highly reflexive genre, and a more convincing reminder that ‘theory’ must not
forget ‘practice,’ could hardly be deliberately devised.
What all of this brings to light, in the end, is that philosophy as critique is not,
on any level, a single identifiable, homogenous activity. It is, we might say, in no
sense itself. Rather, to the extent that it exhibits the kind of challenge to conceptions
and foundations of identity that historical conditions pose to posited identities
generally, it has suffered, and continues to suffer, from conventional definitions of
‘philosophy’ and ‘critique’ that have prevailed in our Western philosophical, and
particularly Western Enlightenment, tradition. In this context, Duane Davis’s project
here of examining the provenance of Merleau-Ponty’s ontological philosophy and
the importance of reading a particular philosophy in terms of the horizon – in Davis’
case, the political horizon – of its emergence, suggests a welcome corrective to the
over-determinations of notions of ‘critique’ that make part of our philosophical
provenance. Such analyses are energising of philosophy. Hermeneutical selfcritique – so long as it is undertaken on the understanding that even critique is never
itself – must open possibilities for critique and diminish possibilities for presumption in a manner that is less likely to privilege one critical possibility, and therefore
one critical community, over any other.
192
F. Halsall et al.
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Plato’s Dialectical Ethics: Phenomenological Interpretations Relating to
the Philebus, trans. Robert M. Wallace (New Haven/London: Yale University Press, 1991), 3.
6
1
Introduction: Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices
7
Naturally, opening up possibilities for critique and diminishing possibilities for
presumption, in this hermeneutical manner, tests many of our established tendencies,
not least our tendency to isolate and objectify communities in such a way as to produce
dangers and injustices at their margins. As Robert Bernasconi shows in what follows, one of the most important prejudices to be abandoned about processes of
‘othering’ is the notion that they are generated by a self-identical individual or group
that turns against an other. Rather, ‘othering’ (through stereotyping, discrimination,
persecution, and so on) constitutes as other not only the other (the Jew, the Arab,
the African) but also the self (the Christian, the Westerner, the White) who, in these
processes, acts precisely not as individual but in relation to an underdetermined
group of others (Christians, Westerners, Whites) in whose name the self feels justified, perhaps compelled, to act. Thus, in order to understand the insidious mechanisms of ‘othering,’ our concepts of community must be rethought in terms of what
Sartre calls ‘seriality.’ That is, a critical community is constituted not by individual
selves but by the practices of selves who always already think and act in relation to
others whose views and actions they can neither know nor predict.
One of the implications of this complexifying account of our identifications of, and
interactions with, communities is that we cannot conceive of critical interventions that
would redress the injustices and dangers of constituting communities as inevitably
active, purposeful, and forward thinking rather than passive, purposeless, and laden
with tradition. Felix O’Murchadha’s identification of the critical force of waiting
provides a considered and convincing rebuke to such binarist thinking. Opposition
not only lies in action and in a new future but it also needs to wait and look at the
histories and traditions in whose names we think and act. The association of waiting
with uncritical resignation belies the value in what Gadamer refers to as ‘tarrying
with,’7 and what Kant so influentially describes as the ‘playing with’ of interpretive
judgments. In fact, the extent to which the model of non-purposive rationality, which
makes such an increasingly exciting aspect of our Kantian inheritance, provides
fruitful focus for the essays in this collection. Such a model indicates how our
practices of aesthetic judgement are bound up with our efforts as philosophers to
adapt ourselves and our objects of interest to the inescapably historical and indeterminate conditions of experience. Talia Welsh’s discussion of the manner in which
Merleau-Ponty’s analysis of perceptual experience as constituted by a shifting range
of resistances to cultural categorizations, and as therefore challenging of conceptions
of conscious and unconscious as separate, provides us with one example of the extent
to which our experiences generally are much closer to the conditions that have
traditionally been identified as aesthetic experiences than has yet been fully recognized. This insight suggests that the distinctions between determinate and indeterminate, between purpose and purposelessness, between moving and waiting, must
undergo serious re-evaluation.
7
See Gadamer, “The Relevance of the Beautiful,” in The Relevance of the Beautiful and Other
Essays, ed. R. Bernasconi, trans. N. Walker (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986).
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
8
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
The waiting the waiting around, the ‘tarrying with,’ most conventionally associated with our appreciation of artworks, but now emerging as more generally operative, is associated by Gadamer with a temporality that is very different from the
future oriented linearity presupposed by certain traditional accounts of enlightenment.8 What O’ Murchadha refers to as ‘time beyond instrumentality’ accounts,
Gadamer shows, for our experiences of festivals in which duration is felt less as the
accumulation of units of measured time and much more as internal to the festival
itself. Does Christmas ever feel like the 3 days, or the 14 days holiday, that it, in one
sense, is? Does a career in philosophy ever feel like the 30 years, 8 months and 7 days
that it, in one sense, is? To the second, we must, perhaps, answer ‘yes!’ Gadamer
describes the manner in which ‘youth’ and ‘old age’ have an ‘autonomous’ temporality, internal to the experience of youth and old age and not easily determinable
in any strong sense, a temporality that trumps conventional measurement; but a career
in an academic institution – particularly when one is retiring from that institution – is
(and, we might think, painfully) counted out as the accumulation of days, months
and years. Whether it is or has been experienced as such is open to question, and
certainly subject to contingencies; the aim of this collection is to, in many senses,
restore Tony to festival time and to honour the more autonomous, more playful,
temporality that goes to define our experiences of youth and old age, of engagement
and retirement. In Tony’s unflagging enthusiasm for dialogue with, and support of,
those around him, and in his so-impressive desire to continue to learn, is certain
evidence of a temporality that defies conventional assignations and a philosophical
life lived, hermeneutically, as if all of it is, in an important sense, ahead of it; we hope
that the essays collected here will provoke the kind of tarrying, playful, hermeneutical
reading and re-reading that will best pay tribute to this.
And Tony is not excused from his share in this process. Four of the essays in this
collection – those by Graham Allen, Gary Banham, William Hamrick, and Hugh
Silverman – directly address the theme of friendship. How appropriate! It is, after
all, a book of essays written and collected by friends of Tony O’ Connor, friends he
has made within and between academic institutions, friends he has made – interestingly, given Allen’s view here of the crucial role Philosophy must play in our resistance to today’s increasingly techno-scientific regulation of institutional relations
– primarily through the discipline of Philosophy. Of course, since these friends of
his conceived, contributed to, and collated this project as a surprise, Tony has, in one
sense, been excluded from it. However, if we take as our model model Silverman’s
conception here of friendship as ‘postmodern,’ we must acknowledge that the
responsibility for what happens between friends is constituted less by some external
standard of Justice, Law, or Friendship, or Fairness, and, more convincingly, by the
relation between friends. Indeed, Tony’s call, to which Hamrick responds so well
here, for ‘a more empirical approach’ to the historical and cultural conditions of
friendship than a Derridean deconstruction of extant definitions of friendship, taken
on its own, can achieve, would seem to position Tony’s philosophical response to
273
F. Halsall et al.
8
Ibid.
1
Introduction: Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices
9
the theme of friendship firmly within the broadly ‘postmodern’ acknowledgment
that responsibility between friends is precisely that: between friends and, to that
extent, shared, particular, and on-going.
If so, however, Tony must realise that, although he has not contributed to this
collection, undertaken as it has been by his friends and in friendship, he is certainly
responsible for its effects. And its effects are uncertain, largely indeterminate, and
above all partial – which is to be expected. As Banham demonstrates here through
Kant, this is a show of friendship that aims at something other than an institutional
giving to Tony his ‘due.’ For these effects, Tony too is accountable. They are the
effects of his philosophical past, of his life lived, of his tradition entered into and
critically fulfilled. But they are effects, too, for the future and presents the possibilities
of alterity that Joanna Hodge identifies in Derrida’s ‘a-venir’ and engagingly juxtaposes with the always-to-be-accomplished process of remembering, where ‘that
which arrives, for good or ill, may arrive as much through the permissiveness
of a certain forgetting as through the accumulations of memory.’ Thus, since it is
almost all yet to be done – the future that lies ahead but also the past that has yet to
be remembered – this project places on Tony a continuing responsibility; not an
imposition on him, we hope, but an invitation to him, a request of him, a gesture
towards him. In friendship.
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
Part I
Hermeneutics and Aesthetic Practices:
Art, Ritual, Interpretation
1
2
3
Chapter 2
1
Reflections on the Hermeneutics
of Creative Acts
2
3
Douglas Burnham
4
2.1
5
Introduction
Do the practices of art making and philosophising have any interesting similarities?1
One key example might lie in the concept of ‘inquiry’. Can and should fine art
(at least some forms of contemporary practice) be understood as a kind of inquiry in
a way meaningfully similar to philosophical inquiry? Before one could even begin
to address such a question, however, it becomes necessary to turn away from the fine
art or philosophical outcome (the image, the installation, the book) towards the
activity or process behind it. Now, this is something that philosophers are used to
doing with respect to philosophy. Thus, for example, philosophy departments will
generally offer courses in logic. This is mainly because logic is considered a kind of
tool for philosophical activity, rather than an end in itself. Oddly, though, philosophers
who think about art tend not to be interested in what happens behind the scenes, so
to speak. Philosophical aesthetics has tended to start from the experiences of the
viewers of finished (and historically preserved) objects, and think about concepts
like judgement, taste, classification of objects, truth, and so forth. Arguably, this is
like studying footprints even though the person who made them is standing next to
you. This was not always the case. Greek philosophers, with their interest in the type
of knowledge appropriate to practices, often addressed themselves to the process
To our great delight, Tony has joined as a founding member the “Critical Inquiry in Art and
Philosophy” research group. This group comprises researchers and practitioners in philosophy, art
and art history/theory departments from Cork, Dublin, Staffordshire, Loughborough and beyond.
One of the questions that this group was set up to examine is whether the practices of making art,
on the one hand, and making philosophy on the other, have anything in common. interesting
similarities.
1
[AU1]
D. Burnham (*)
University of Staffordshire, Staffordshire, UK
e-mail: H.D.Burnham@staffs.ac.uk
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_2, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
13
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
14
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
of making (Plato with ‘inspiration’ in the Ion and then ‘mimesis’ in the Republic;
Aristotle with his Poetics which was effectively a handbook for aspiring writers
of tragedy).
The philosophical tradition of hermeneutics – which Tony has espoused and
advanced, even though he prefers to call it ‘historical ontology’! – is no less culpable.
This is hardly surprising since it spends so much of its energy on the concept of interpretation. More generally, because it has grown out of an inquiry into the method
proper to the ‘human sciences’, which study already given historical or cultural
artefacts. Such artefacts are encountered as alienated – coming from another person,
culture or era – and understanding them means somehow dealing with that alienation.
Hans-Georg Gadamer, in Truth and Method, writes illuminatingly about the process
by which a viewer of art must become involved in the ‘play’ offered by the work of
art. The encounter with art is not a momentary, isolated ‘experience’, but an event in
the ongoing process of meaning creation and understanding which spans the work’s
history.2 Similarly, the historian’s professional practice should enter into a dialogue
with his or her subject, not treating it either with the objectivity of an entomologist
viewing a bug in amber, or with the solipsism of someone whose only real concern is
with the present (and thus themselves). That is, the appropriate historical encounter
with alienation needs to remain simultaneously open to the possibilities of both past
and present. Gadamer famously calls this reciprocal structure a ‘fusion of horizons’.3
The same dialectical structure can be found in the French hermeneutician Paul
Ricoeur, who for example analyses the strategies of any meaningful narrative as
borrowing both from the professional historian, and from fiction.4
As a consequence, philosophical hermeneutics shares the tendency of philosophical aesthetics to focus on completed objects and their reception. To be sure,
the proper object of interpretation is not a thing (understood objectively) but an
‘effective history’; and the interpretative moment becomes part of the effective
history of the object. The object is not a dead thing, but living, growing. Nevertheless,
hermeneutic analysis seems to assume that some kind of object or thing comes to
me, demanding interpretation, from elsewhere. About that ‘elsewhere’ itself, it seems,
hermeneutics is and must be quiet. Quiet for good reasons, of course, to do with
the historical situatedness of the understanding. If understanding is a mode of my
being in the world, then an ‘understanding’ of another’s world as such and as it is
for that other is a hopeless idealisation.
But there’s more. In his history of hermeneutics and aesthetics, Gadamer gives
particular attention to the period immediately after Kant. Kant belongs pretty clearly
to the tradition of philosophy that focuses on products. Nevertheless, he also gives
an important account of genius; that is, the capacity of an artist to create, and thus
23
D. Burnham
2
Cf. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd rev. ed., trans. rev. J. Weinsheimer and
D. G. Marshall (London: Continuum, 2005) Part 1, II, 1.
3
Ibid. p. 269.
4
Cf. Paul Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, vol. 3, trans. Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer (Chicago:
Chicago University Press, 1988).
2
Reflections on the Hermeneutics of Creative Acts
15
Kant is close here to talking about practice. Romantic aesthetics took this notion of
genius from Kant and made it central. Thus, romantic aesthetics is one of the exceptions to the general tendency of philosophy to focus on products and viewers. As far
as Gadamer is concerned, however, this is an extreme point in the subjectivisation
of aesthetics. Rather than art being a dialectical relation between the viewer (and the
viewer’s context, world or horizon) and the work (and the work’s world), instead
with the concept of genius everything is shoved onto the miraculously creative
interior life of a human subject. Art is removed from the world, from the situation
of alienation and from real history, and is located merely in the consciousness of
(initially) the artist, and then (in, at best, an imitation) the viewer. Gadamer thus sees
the notion of genius as the death-knell of any proper account of art.5
Romantic aesthetics bucked the trend and gave an account of artistic practice.
Moreover, the concept of genius is quite explicitly seen as the achievement of philosophical ends but in the domain of art. This notion is the core of Schelling and
Coleridge’s account of artistic creativity, for example, and it is still important to
Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. Artistic and philosophical practices do have important
similarities for romantic thought. Because of this, one might have been tempted to
have recourse to it for our project of a hermeneutics of artistic practice in its relation
to philosophy. But, it was not to be. The creativity embodied in the genius turns
out to be a truncated or shrivelled account of art, incapable of grasping the dialectics
between self and other, present and past, consciousness and world which are central
to the hermeneutic account of what it means to exist as an understanding being.
Or is it?
In this paper I shall argue that there is something in the account of the creativity
of genius that Gadamer overlooked. This ‘something’ I will call, for reasons that
will hopefully be clear, the ‘dark materials’ of creation. I suggest that through this
analysis the concept of the creative genius becomes much richer, such that the concept is no longer repugnant to the dialectical ontology of hermeneutics. We shall
have no time to pursue the matter, but it is also conceivable that the new ontology of
genius might consequently have a role to play in the hermeneutic task of describing
the dialectic of understanding and interpretation that is involved in practices of art
and of philosophy.
2.2
Back to the Origin
Hermeneutics teaches us to be suspicious of any attempt to recover the authentic,
in-itself meaning of the past. We should be doubly suspicious of a move towards an
origin, a first opening, as if that move were even possible as such. In the history of
concepts, however, this is sometimes permissible as a provisional strategy. That is
because certain concepts, found in certain texts, have a normative force that serves
5
Cf. Hans-Georg Gadamer, op.cit., Part 1, I, 2.
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
16
D. Burnham
107
to control, shape and limit subsequent interpretation. In such cases, the original
moment may indeed have something important to tell us about the subsequent
history of the concept, and of what kinds of latent potential might still lie within it.
No text is more normative for European culture than the Bible; and no part of the
bible more than the first book of the Old Testament, Genesis; and no part of Genesis
more than its first few verses. These first few verses are about creativity, obviously
enough. They also talk about the breath, wind or spirit of God, and thus have a
concrete historical relation to the later notion of genius. So, do they have something
to tell us about these over-familiar and under-rich notions?
108
109
110
111
112
In the beginning, when God made heaven and earth, the earth was formless and void, with
darkness over the face of the abyss, and God’s spirit/mind/wind swept over the face of the
waters. God said, ‘Let there be light’, and there was light; and God saw that the light was
good, and he separated light from darkness. He called light day and the darkness night.
So evening came, and morning came, and this was the first day.6
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
In best hermeneutic style, I claim that proper interpretation must begin both with
something that is most familiar (and what is, if not this passage?) and something
quite alien. The first aspect of alienness is that the passage that as a whole and in a
strict sense, doesn’t exist. Genesis is seen by modern scholarship as a kind of collage or palimpsest of contributions from many different sources separated by centuries of time and intent. Thus, if (wearing the hat of an objective historian) we think of
the text as a coherent expression of the thoughts of one human mind, or even one
historical civilisation, we will be disappointed. However, that is modern scholarship; for more than 2,000 years, this passage has been interpreted as if it were a
single, coherent (albeit encoded, perhaps) message, not to mention divinely inspired.
That mode of interpretation goes hand in hand with the normative force of the
content of the message, which could have had no greater sanction. Since we are
interested in the history of the concept, we are entitled to stay with this presumptive,
fictional unity of text and meaning. So, I wish to pursue the alienness in a different direction. Let me pose a few questions about the first few verses of Genesis that,
I hope will alienate them from us in a quite productive manner.
We are, I believe, used to thinking of these first verses as constituting a single
(in the sense of simple) act of creation. In fact, though, the text requires us to think
of no less than five discrete moments. The most famous one is the second of these,
the creation of light; in the third, light is judged to be good; fourth, the separation of
light and darkness; and fifth, the naming. The first act of ‘creation’, if it should be
so termed, is not represented: we just have ‘when God made’, and everything begins
as spirit on the surface of the water, but where did the water (which throughout the
Old Testament frequently stands in for the abyss) come from, or for that matter that
spirit/wind? Since we have positioned ourselves as interpreters of a text whose
organic unity is presumed (though fictional), it seems contradictory to then ignore
99
I make no pretence of being a Biblical scholar. The above is my ‘translation’, which is basically
what I hope is a plausible combination of various recent translations, but especially the New English
Bible which I use elsewhere unmodified.
6
2
Reflections on the Hermeneutics of Creative Acts
17
this division into moments as a mere textual accident. Instead, we are compelled to
ask what concept of creation is such as to require precisely such a division. There
are two apparent answers compatible with our overall strategy here of unearthing
the potential of a historical concept. First, the articulation of the act of creation is
how the single divine act must be interpreted by finite human thought. This resembles
a negative theology; and anyone who has read Kant’s distinction between the
intellectus archetypus and the intellectus ectypus would be tempted by this approach.
For example, calling the abyss both ‘formless’ and ‘void’ – it’s hard to imagine a
language that wouldn’t flounder if confronted by the task of describing nothingness.
Or again, the time sequence implied by the verses may be an interpretation of a
timeless ‘event’, inexpressible as such. This is an interesting strategy, and we should
certainly keep it in reserve as a fall back position.
The second answer tackles the issues head-on: we could attempt to take seriously
such an articulation of the act of creation itself, and inquire as to its ontological
meaning. To do so will require a certain anachronism. We will have to borrow
concepts from later philosophy in order to explicate the meaning of the mythic
terms in Genesis. This is justified only because our aim is not the interpretation of
Genesis, but rather the detection in later thought (specifically, romanticism) of a
way of conceiving of creativity and genius that can enrich hermeneutics.
The first act of creation listed above is notable because it pre-dates command:
‘let there be light’ is the second moment. This is our primary clue to the ontological
significance of the passage. Again, of course, it is usual to interpret this creation as
‘out of nothing’. But the ‘out of nothing’ is itself ambiguous, especially when
confronted with the text of Genesis. Here, the spirit, water, abyss and darkness are
indeed nothing, and thus their existence or form cannot yet be commanded, but yet
the materials of creation are there. At this first moment of creation, even the spirit
of God is also dark, and among these materials (right upon the surface of the water).
This allows us to explain an apparent textual anomaly: how can that which is
‘formless’ have a ‘surface’? There is no meaningful separation between God and
the ‘materials’ of creation that are also ‘nothing’. The water, we might say, has a
surface only with respect to God as the as-yet-unrealised potential for command.
God as spirit (breath, wind) is thus included among the primordial materials of
creation, only virtually distinct from them. The creator has not yet self-formed, has
not yet begun to be something rather than among those things which are nothing.
God effectively becomes created in commanding light: No longer merely a dark
spirit, but the one who commands light, and who is then and therefore capable of
judging, separating and so forth.
In these verses, light is the possibility of form (the possibility of something
being something – including something being God). Light, then, is the new
presence of creator to creation as a spirit that has transcended. No longer along
the surface of the nothing, but having ‘pulled back’ so as to judge or separate – that
is, to create in an ordinary sense of the term. The light of spirit is the possibility of
form insofar as it permits of the invention, making or judging of form. The next act,
though, is not the first act of separation (light from darkness), which would be
the first act of making or creating in that ordinary sense. Rather, the next act is the
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
18
D. Burnham
211
212
213
214
215
216
When the Lord God made earth and heaven, there was neither shrub nor plant growing wild
upon the earth, because the Lord God had sent no rain on the earth; nor was there any man
to till the ground. A flood/mist used to rise out of the earth and water all the surface of the
ground. Then the Lord God formed a man from the dust of the ground and breathed into his
nostrils the breath of life. Thus the man became a living creature. Then the Lord God
planted a garden in Eden away to the east…7
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
210
judging that it (light) is good. Now, goodness here is generally interpreted as the
correspondence of the newly created with the idea of God, the achievement of
an end or purpose. However, light is not yet a thing, but the possibility of things,
and effectively equivalent to the transcendence of God. What is ‘good’ (light) then
is not a thing (corresponding to an idea), but the possibility that things could
correspond to ideas, and this is the very transcendence of spirit to the field within
which things will come to be. The goodness of light, then, is the transformation of
an immanent potential or virtuality (spirit on the surface of nothing) into a possibility
(transcendent spirit contemplating a creation that is about to be). Now there are
possibilities, and these possibilities can then be actualised as the separation of zones
or the forming of creatures.
Light happens, is judged, and then is partially withdrawn when light is separated
from darkness. The first forming act is this separation, the first act in which some
thing comes to be, a thing that can for the first time bear a name: day or night.
Now, one could easily here become distracted by the fact that things, names and
time (‘and this was the first day’) occur on the scene together. Fascinating, yes,
and worthy of further meditation – but we mustn’t miss something I believe more
important still: that this is not the first appearance of darkness. Darkness has, in fact,
reappeared. Is the dark that is formed by the withdrawal of light the same as the dark
of the first, unrepresented, act? On the one hand, of course not: this darkness is a
kind of thing (about to be named ‘night’), formed by an act of separation. The text,
however, does not distinguish the first and second darkness. Are there any other
reasons for taking seriously the idea that the original darkness has reappeared in
some way?
There are, of course, two different creation accounts in Genesis. The second
begins at 2.5; the usual scholarly opinion is that this second one is of an earlier date.
It begins like this
184
Here, there appears to be no mention of primordial materials and the unrepresented first act of creation. Instead, a recognisable heaven and earth are created (one
hesitates to say ‘in a straight-forward manner’!) and then things upon the earth. But
what is this ‘flood’ or ‘mist’? It is (as we suggested already above, with respect
to the ‘water’ in the first account) the abyss. ‘… [O]n that very day, all the springs of
the great abyss broke through, the windows of the sky were opened, and rain fell on
the earth for 40 days and 40 nights’. This is how the great flood is described at 6.11-2.
That flood cleanses the earth by returning it to the abyss, by recreating it from
7
Samuel Sandmel, general ed., The New English Bible with the Apocrypha (New York: Oxford
University Press/Cambridge University Press, 1976).
2
Reflections on the Hermeneutics of Creative Acts
19
primordial materials. So, in the second account of creation, as in the first, there must
be an unstated first event (or situation) of creation that pre-dates command: God,
and with God, differentiated only virtually, the waters of the abyss. Water is, of
course, both destructive (ultimately destructive, since it dates from a time before
things to be destroyed) but also nourishing (‘the Lord God had [yet] sent no rain’;
and also the river that nourishes Eden and thence the whole of the known world).
Twice in a few verses the text tells us that the production of life requires two
things: the working of the earth (tilling, planting, tending), and water. What about
growing a man, though? Here we find two things also: the activity of working the
earth (‘formed a man from the [dry] dust of the ground’) and then not water but
spirit as breath (‘breathed into his nostrils’). The rhythms of repetition in the passage force us to see the breath of life as akin to water, here as nurturing. God’s spirit,
when breathed out into creation (in the second narrative of creation), is no longer
transcendent spirit, but that original spirit that was along the dark surface of the
abyssal waters (in the first narrative).
In the act of creating man, God has put back into creation something of the
primordial inseparability of spirit and the abyssal waters; something that is of
the dark potentiality or virtuality of the first material condition of creation. In the
second account of creation, the implications of this ‘putting back’ are drawn clearly.
The ‘most clever’ serpent belongs to this creation; and from the first, human beings
harbour the potentiality to deviate from God’s plan, requiring first expulsion from
the garden and then the great flood. The implications are drawn clearly, but
narrowly, in the second creation narrative, for it is a narrative of sin, not of a general
cosmology.
In the first account of creation, this ‘putting back’ means that the darkness
of the first forming act (the night) must not be entirely distinguished from the
darkness of the primordial materials. The potentiality of the origin has returned
to the earth. A forming creative act involves the giving back to material (which
has been stripped of virtual spirit and is mere material, inert and awaiting command from newly transcendent spirit) its dark potentiality. This new dark is the
withdrawal of light in an act of separation. But light, we said, was the possibility
of things due to the transcendence of God. Thus the reintroduction of God as
undifferentiated spirit is also the withdrawal of God qua transcending spirit.
This back and forth motion is elegantly figured in the second creation narrative as
respiration. In the second narrative too the withdrawal is, again, stated most clearly
(though narrowly): it is human beings who are given the privilege of naming.
That is, human beings have the potential to take on the role of transcending their
materials as creating spirits and proposing new possibilities for creation (including,
of course, sin).
The withdrawal of God qua transcending spirit means that God has returned to
earth as the primordial, dark, pre-formed spirit. This mode of God’s being is all
along the surface of existence. So now, things (forms) in general can be dark. In the
first creation narrative this account of things is generalised to all things, qua created,
and not just human beings. Things are inhabited by the dark potentiality that is prior
even to the separation of spirit and matter.
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
20
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
2.3
Kant, Romanticism and Genius
The history of European aesthetics is littered with the after-effects of the Genesis
narratives. Thus, there are many examples in Renaissance thought, for example,
where the artist is conceived of such that he or she does not merely copy nature, but
surpasses it (i.e. is capable of a genuine creation). The artist has the ‘divine breath’,
as Sidney expresses it in the Defence of Poesie,8 making clear the connection.
From here it is a small step to the concept of ‘genius’. The genius is a ‘small god’
who creates, and who also judges to be ‘good’. That is, who creates and with creation
creates a new law of judgement. Accordingly, with genius comes the notion of
originality, although it receives variable stress. All these concepts can be outlined
with respect to the Genesis narratives, but without having recourse to the first,
unrepresented act or situation of creation. The Renaissance notion begins with what,
above, we called the second act. It is only in German Idealism that something like
the full potential of the Genesis account is unfolded (though Blake’s First book of
Urizen and the Song of Los should not be overlooked 9).
This can be illustrated in Kant by mentioning only two notions. First, what is
strikingly new in Kant, and which determines the philosophy of selfhood to this day,
is the problem of the constitution of the self. Kant starts from the insubstantiality of
the self. This comes from Hume, but Hume is unable to draw the ultimate conclusions (‘I am sensible that my account is very defective’, appendix to A Treatise of
Human Nature10). On Kant’s analysis, the self is not given in advance, it is formed
in and through the very acts by which its intentional objects become given. The self
exists because its world does; the world exists for a self. The second idea we need
is that the beautiful is ‘purposive without purpose’.11 That which is encountered as
beautiful lacks the conceptual determination which, for every other act of cognition,
is its minimum condition. To be sure, the beautiful thing is also something
else, something ordinary. The beautiful sunset is, also, a sunset; the beautiful music
is, also, the sound of four pieces of wood with tensed strings. We have generic or
conventional handles to fall back on. Nevertheless, beauty can be presented at all
only because the principle of purposiveness, the legislating principle of judgement,
serves it as a concept. (Although there are dramatic differences, on this point the
sublime is similar. Failure of presentation is rescued by the rational idea of totality.)
Things can be encountered as beautiful (and sublime), and the self is thereby
constituted as the self that encounters them … albeit just barely. Thereby the door
is opened to a later account of artistic experience as disruptive of the self.
270
D. Burnham
Philip Sidney, Works, vol. 3 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1923).
The Illuminated Books of William Blake, vol. 6, ed. David Worrall (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1998).
10
David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. David F. Norton and Mary J. Norton (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2000), 400.
11
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgement, trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987) §§
10–11.
8
9
2
Reflections on the Hermeneutics of Creative Acts
21
But what of genius? The genius is capable of constituting him or herself as a
genius not through the presentation of already existing entities (as in the case of an
observer judging beauty), but through the creation, over and over again, of art.
The same problem recurs: where is the determining concept that allows the entity to
be completed and presented as such? But the problem is much more radical here.
Not only is this concept lacking, but because of the requirement of originality,
so are the helpful handles of generic, conventional or other ‘ordinary’ concepts.
The requirement to create law, not just things, marks the genius out and makes
especially perilous his or her self-constitution. Moreover, the genius cannot stop at
one creation but, qua genius, must commence another immediately. In a creative
act, the genius-self cannot complete its world – and thus cannot complete itself.
In Kant, these ideas are not pursued this far to be sure; but they are so pursued
in multiple forms shortly thereafter. In romantic self-mythologising, genius is
‘tormented’, putting his or her ‘sweat and blood’ into the work. The self is bound to
or embedded in its creation.
This account of genius is broadly characteristic of romantic thought. I suggest,
however, that it also owes a great deal to a reactualisation of the Genesis account of
creation, one that takes seriously what we above called the first act. (This connection
is particularly clear in Schelling, for example, in the Philosophical Inquiries into the
Essence of Human Freedom from 1809.12) God comes to exist as transcendent
spirit – withdrawing from the surface of the dark materials of the abyss – through
the act of commanding light. So, here, the genius comes to exist as a constituted
subject – escaping the fate of the ‘many-coloured and diverse’ self, as Kant puts
it13 – through the making of new things and the new criteria by which they are
judged. Again, God’s transcendence of the world is partially negated when abyssal
darkness and potentiality is restored in the first act of forming or separating, and
thereby the dark spirit, prior to its formation as transcendent, is replaced in things.
So, here, the genius is ‘tormented’ by the fact that the ‘little god’ cannot simply create;
rather, power over emergent selfhood is placed in the hands of the created, which is
itself liberated from the concept. Finally, God’s creation is given the potential to
self-transcend and create, for itself, new possibilities that deviate (as world history)
from the idea of creation. So, here, the work of genius in its liberation from the
concept is open to a history of alienation and ‘fusion of horizons’. This leaves
the self-hood of the artist, as if umbilically tied to the work as its child, still more
vulnerable, indeed constantly and from the beginning a being alienated from itself.
Such reflections are one reason why Heidegger famously commences with the
dialectic of art and artist in ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’.14 It allows him to
F. W. J. Schelling, Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom, trans. Jeff
Love and Johannes Schmidt (Albany: State University Press, 2006).
13
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996),
B134.
14
Martin Heidegger, “The Origin of the Work of Art,” in Basic Writings, ed. David Krell
(San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1993).
12
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
22
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
dispense quickly with that way of thinking about origin. More famously still,
such a potentially destructive dialectical relationship is the metaphysical meaning
of Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein: Or the Modern Prometheus15 (the subtitle is
particularly significant) – a gothic, darkness-focused critique of the romantic genius
as a ‘little god’.
Gadamer accused the romantic aesthetics of genius of locking up the nature of
art in momentary subjectivity, removing it from history and from any dialectical
relationship with interpretation. However, genius (as reinterpreted using the Genesis
account as a kind of mirror) is no longer incompatible with historical ontology,
but can enrich it. Genius is a mode of the historical dialectic of understanding.
The genius exists only insofar as the work’s historical trajectory reciprocally permits
him or her to exist as a genius (even after death). Reciprocally, the work exists only
insofar as it offers potential meanings to history – that is, insofar as it is encountered
as an effective history. Ontologically, the genius is not the first being that is the
origin of a chain of beings leading up to events of interpretation. Rather, the genius
is the last existence, and moreover the being that is always too late (cf. Genealogy
of Morality, Preface 1).16 That genius is not an origin also means it cannot be
considered a self-contained and ahistorical subjectivity. The alienation (the world of
the work failing to coincide with the world of its reception) that hermeneutics
addresses with the concept of ‘fusion of horizons’ does not begin when the work is
torn from its self-contained creator and delivered into history. It is a commonplace
that the artist is merely the first interpreter, already alienated. What is new here is to
think of this alienation as belonging to the structure of the practices of genius as
such. Alienation doesn’t begin anywhere. Instead, using the concepts from our
analysis of Genesis, the creative genius is akin to the first condition of God, spirit
all along the dark waters. Alienation is already there, virtually, immanent within the
first condition of creation.
So, the next question is: how does this virtual alienation manifest itself in the
practices of art?
342
D. Burnham
Oh dear, ran out of space. Fancy talking further about this, Tony? I’m buying!
371
Mary Shelly, Frankenstein: Or the Modern Prometheus (New York: Random House, 2000).
Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, trans. Maudemarie Clark and Alan Swensen
(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1998).
15
16
Author Query
Chapter No.: 2
0001327760
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please provide department name in the affiliation for the author
“Douglas Burnham”
Query
Chapter 3
[AU1]
1
In Between Word and Image: Philosophical
Hermeneutics, Aesthetics and the Inescapable
Heritage of Kant
2
3
4
Nicholas Davey
5
3.1
6
Introduction
Gadamer’s aesthetic theory emerges in large part from a penetrating critique of
Kant’s grounding of aesthetic judgement. The indisputable attractiveness of his
theory is its recognition of the spectator’s deep involvement and participation in the
subject matters of aesthetic experience. Yet, as we shall argue, Gadamer’s account of
aesthetic participation is seriously compromised if it does not embrace a version of
what it adamantly rejects, namely, Kant’s notion of aesthetic disinterestedness. Our
principal thesis is, then, that Gadamer’s hermeneutical account of the openness of
aesthetic experience is practicable only if it incorporates an element of methodological disinterestedness. Such a claim contravenes a great deal of received Gadamer
scholarship. Not withstanding, we shall substantiate it. We will do so, however, not to
discredit Gadamer’s central thesis about aesthetic participation but rather to strengthen
it in terms of its philosophical credibility and its hermeneutical practicality.
Philosophical hermeneutics proffers an understanding of our reactions and
responses to art and, indeed, of what lies within them art works retrieve, reassess
and re-appraise what we have laid to one side or have come to take for granted in
memory and the habitual. This hermeneutical Hintergrund is that stock of tacit
knowledge (or what Gadamer’s also calls prejudice) which effectively orientates us
towards art works and their sense in the first place. Not only do seminal works have
the capacity to make us rethink what we take for granted but they can also initiate a
major change in the sub-conscious paradigms (Weltanschauungen) from which we
negotiate experience.1 Heidegger has accustomed us to the idea that a great work of
See Robert Pippin, The Persistence of Subjectivity, On the Kantian Aftermath (London: Cambridge
University Press, 2005), 68.
1
[AU2]
N. Davey (*)
University of Dundee, Dundee, UK
e-mail: j.r.n.davey@dundee.ac.uk
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_3, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
23
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
24
N. Davey
45
art is not so much of a period but initiates an historical epoch.2 In addition, it can be
plausibly argued that the canonical art work is a paradigm shifter, changing previous
pre-conceptions of a genre and dominating subsequent conceptions. The key point
remains: it is our hermeneutical Hintergrund or setting which the experience of art
disrupts and transforms. In this respect, Gadamer’s criticism of Kant’s account of
aesthetic judgement is compelling. Aesthetic responses to art are not grounded in
fleeting preference but in the extra-subjective, that is, in the hermeneutical sensibilities of a given tradition (which in no way implies as our essay will show, that
aesthetic experience is based upon merely conservative norms). Yet, a central question
remains. How do art works probe and provoke the terms of our understanding?
We shall borrow a phrase from Kant and argue that philosophical hermeneutics offers
a critique of our experience of art, a critique in the sense of enquiring not only into
the ontological pre-conditions of aesthetic experience but also into its communicative
structures. In this essay We shall argue that Gadamer’s aesthetic theory actually
needs the intervention of disinterested interpretive method in order to (1) avoid
unquestioning complacency within one’s own hermeneutical setting and (2) to
provoke precisely the unexpected responses to an art work that his theory strives
to both stimulate and articulate.
46
3.2
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
The Ambiguous Image
Philosophical hermeneutics builds itself upon the immediacies of experiential
encounter. (Schleiermacher once remarked that he hated all theory that did not
emerge from practice.3) Hence a hermeneutic critique of aesthetics must consider
what an art work does and how it does it. To this end we will turn to some of the
images of the Scottish Artist Ian Hamilton Finlay who, like Gadamer, was a student
of Classical Philosophy.
Hamilton Finlay is an artist who works in thematic series. Weaponry is a favoured
motif in his early works not because of boyish delight in military paraphernalia but
because such slight aphoristic imagery handles highly serious and complex subject
matters with a simplicity and directness. For Hamilton Finlay, images of weapons
have a neo-classical ambivalence: they signify order and chaos, law and anarchy,
destruction and renewal (Fig. 3.1).
The print “Arcadia” refers in title directly to Nicolas Poussin’s two masterpieces of the same name. the title has functioned as a momenti mori and derives
from Virgil’s Eclogues V 42. Hamilton Finlay’s title places the image of a military
vehicle into various fields of classical meaning and by so doing raises several
Martin Heidegger, “Origin of the Art Work,” in Poetry, Language and Thought, trans.
A. Hofstadter (New York: Harper, 1971).
3
Gadamer makes this remark in the (untranslated) essay “Word and Picture”, 1992 (See Gesammelte
Werke, J. C. B. Mohr, Band 8, s 374).
2
[AU3]
In Between Word and Image…
25
this figure will be printed in b/w
3
Fig. 3.1 Ian Hamilton Finlay and George Oliver, Arcadia
[AU4]
Fig. 3.2 Ian Hamilton Finlay, Thunderbolt Steers All
[AU5]
disconcerting questions. We might ask, “Death and destruction are supposedly
absent from paradise but, on reflection, can death actually be absent from Arcadia?
Does the wolf never prey upon the lambs of Poussin’s shepherds? If the military
vehicle roamed Arcadia, what was the misdemeanour that led to its fall?
By inserting the image of an armoured vehicle into a set of hermeneutical horizons
rich in classical nuance, Hamilton Finlay prompts a re-thinking about what we have
come to think of Arcadia. he visual devices he uses to build on such hermeneutical
associations are (1) the choice of forest green for the tank, (2) the leafy camouflage
on the vehicle invokes Arcadia’s glades, and (3) the form of the image itself, its
simplicity, detail, and location on the page, is reminiscent of late eighteenth Century
folios of flora and fauna illustrations. The association with documenting primal
archetypes is clear (Fig. 3.2).
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
26
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
The title of Hamilton Finlay’s print “Thunderbolt Steers All”, is a direct reference
to Heracleitus, Fragment Nr 64 (Hippolytus) “Thunderbolt steers all things”.4
The three words suggest that the fire power of the vehicle has (at least) two
symbolic meanings: the words invoke the status of power, the power of a dominant
battlefield weapon and the metaphor of fire and its power to govern the universe.
The ambiguity of the image is increased by the fact that that “thunderbolt” also
refers to Zeus. The vehicle can therefore symbolize a violent guarantee of divine
order in the cosmos.5
The speculative charge of word and image which the ‘force’ of Finlay’s work
relies on, pushes into deeper and, perhaps, more sinister complexes of meaning and
association. As the Ancients knew, art marks on the one hand the collision of the
forces of order and discipline with the disruptive energies of violence and disorder
on the other.6
Of course, there is no one interpretation of Hamilton Finlay’s images. Their possible meanings are indeterminate and multiple. Neither do they invent the meanings
identified: they invoke them, establish an aesthetic space out of which significances
present themselves. More to the point, many of these meanings are already at
play within personal and collective memories. They constitute points of reference,
way-markerswithin our hermeneutic fields. They illuminate living tissues of meaning
taken for granted the nexi of meaning in which we as social and historical beings
are immersed are, as Gadamer recognises, an ontological pre-condition of any
experience of art. They constitute what we call after Ricoeur, the proper plurality
of interpretation.7 There is no need for interpretation to seize a (supposed) essential
unchanging meaning. Rather, interpretation elicits different combinations and
recombinations of meaning.
Hence we gain an insight into how images such as Hamilton Finlay’s operate
hermeneutically. We note that (1) their effectiveness pre-supposes the existence of
an established set of semantic horizons in which a variety received shared and
personal meanings and associations are accepted (although, as we shall argue, such
horizons are inherently unstable). (2) What the well placed word or the carefully
honed image does is to effectively disturb the web of established meaning and facilitate new combinations of meaning. Though Finlay’s works are not “great art”, they
are simple effective, craftsman-like devices which function as visual aphorisms. And
yet, precisely because of such modesty, they reveal their working more explicitly.
The hermeneutical Hintergrund in which all art operates is made manifest.
75
N. Davey
G. S. Kirk and J. E. Raven ed., The Presocratic Philosophers (London: Cambridge University
Press, 1957), 199.
5
See Yves Abrioux, “Ian Hamilton Finlay,” in A Visual Primer (London: Reaktion Books, 1895), 106.
6
In this respect, Terry Eagleton follows Nietzsche in seeing the Dionysian and the Apollonian in
art as reconciling energy and order, individual and universal, flux and stillness and, as such “is a
riposte to political absolutism … ” (and) “an argument against anarchy”. See his Holy Terror
(London: Oxford University Press, 2005), 87.
7
See Richard Kearney’s observation about Ricoeur’s though in Paul Ricoeur, On Translation
(London: Routledge, 2004), xx.
4
[AU6]
3
In Between Word and Image…
3.3
27
Openness and In Completeness
Neither Kant nor Gadamer question the fact of aesthetic experience. What concerns
us in this essay is not, however, the fact of aesthetic experience, but the economy
of semantic and hermeneutic elements which activate and animate aesthetic
experience.
When Gadamer argues that a creative, intellectual practice is always more than
it knows itself to be, he is not merely arguing that it holds unreflected foreunderstandings. His argument implies something potentially more disruptive. Any
interpretative practice can be both blind to what lies within it and vulnerable to the
play of language circumscribing its outlook. The important insight here is that any
interpretative practice formed within language or functioning in a language-like
manner, will be based upon loose and unstable alignments of meaning and convention because of their linguistic nature, they will be implicitly connected to other
configurations in ways unknown to the practitioner. It is impossible to anticipate
what all these connections are, when, where and how they will be revealed. As is
well known, philosophical hermeneutics emphasises the ontological primacy of
language and its play. It insists that both the interpreted subject and the interpreted
other participate in that play and are, as a consequence, reciprocally vulnerable to
an alteration of perspective because of that mutual participation.
Why, then, are we drawn into exchanges with the other be it a person or art work?
It is, arguably, precisely because we have a deep involvement with the tensions,
ambiguities and incompleteness of our individual horizons (wanting to see beyond
them) that we are willing to be drawn out by that involvement and be drawn towards
the other and, indeed, towards the risks that such openness entails. It is our involvement
in our own incompleteness that draws us to art: immersion in its play of signs and
symbols allow the sets of relations which constitute our understanding to be shifted
into new syntheses and permutations. It is the participatory nature of our being and its
language-like structure which makes it almost impossible (though callousness and
selfishness have their power) for us to disassociate our individual understandings
and narratives from those of others. It is not merely that we participate with others
in common communicative frameworks but that we are sometimes drawn towards a
deep involvement with others and their work contrary to our willing and expectations.
A dialogical exchange, an unexpected remark, a surprise encounter with an image,
may suddenly intimate a different way of thinking about ourselves, may reveal
something not fully understood or something unresolved in our narrative and may
even point to new and unanticipated ways of configuring the tensions within how we
think of ourselves. That philosophical hermeneutics has its foundations within the
play of communicative frameworks suggests that understanding involves not just an
openness towards the unusual and the foreign but also entails an acceptance of risk
and the “negativity of experience” at its most challenging.
Our involvement with art and its subject matters may promise transformation
and transcendence but precisely because it does so, it will also bring with it the
inevitability of disorientation and disquiet. Art is enlivening, but it can also disturb.
Philosophical hermeneutics accounts for the openness of both the linguistic horizons,
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
28
N. Davey
156
offers an insight into the intelligible economy of the hermeneutic exchange between
spectator and work and, indeed, proffers an explanation of how spectator and work
are vulnerable to each others hermeneutic intervention.
157
3.4
154
155
The Instability of Aesthetic Understanding
183
184
185
186
By an aesthetic idea I mean that representation of the imagination which induces much
thought. It induces much thought because it is without the possibility of any definitive
thought whatever, i.e. a concept being adequate to it, and which language can never quite get
on level terms with or render completely intelligible (Critique of Judgement, 175, 314).
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
187
188
189
190
182
Because it is primarily linguistic in nature, understanding’s struggle for an ever tighter
conceptual closure with regard to a work’s content serves to promote, somewhat
paradoxically, only a greater indeterminacy. The more it strives to seize a work’s
concept, to fill it out, and to complete its determinations, the more it stumbles upon
words and yet more words. When it strives for a concept (which if fully grasped would
bring interpretation to an end), understanding invariably only succeeds in dissipating
its quest into a plethora of yet more words. Derrida argues that the linguistic slippage
of meaning is due to linguistic difference and deferral. We suggest that it is more to
do with the associative and dis-associative functions of interpretation itself.
Interpretation strives to overcome the gap between the intentional referent of a
work (its concept) and its expression. Closing the gap obviously renders interpretation needless. Yet the quest for closure actually maintains the gap.8 Thus it might be
more helpful to think of interpretation as filling out a work’s subject matter than to
conceive it as seeking out the ground concept of a work. To speak in terms of a work
being adequate to its concept suggests that there must be some determinate notion
underlying a work which, were it astute enough, interpretation could lay bare.
This makes interpretation reductive; it is designated to seek a specific conceptual
determination. This view is quite contrary to what philosophical hermeneutics
grasps interpretation as being about, namely a generative procedure which opens
rather than closes lines of thought. Kant is correct to argue that no work can fully
exemplify its concept. No work will ever be adequate to its subject matter since the
latter is an ever shifting alignment of meaning rather than constitutive of a specific
concept. Such alignments are more a plurality of associated meanings and as such
can never be reduced to one. In this respect, subject matters are comparable to
Kant’s notion of an “aesthetic idea”. Kant notes,
158
Aesthetic ideas have intelligibility insofar as they aspire to be concepts (or have
an intelligible dimension) but concepts do not constitute art. Insofar as aesthetic
ideas are sensible ideas they can never (according to Kant) be reflective ideas, but
insofar as aesthetic ideas are ideas they have an element in them which denies their
Wolfgang Iser is eloquent about this feature of interpretation. See his The Range of Interpretation
(New York: Columbia University Press, 2001), 147, 153.
8
3
In Between Word and Image…
29
sensibility. This notion of straining after something lying beyond the confines of the
given is an element of Kant’s argument we wish to retain. We would like, however,
to move away from the broader Kantian framework. However, whereas the straining
of aesthetic ideas is a straining to be other than themselves, the straining of subjectmatters is a straining to be more than themselves. Subject-matters do not strive to go
beyond sensible experience (pass into pure reflection) but to extend the very boundaries of experience and alignments of meaning they spring from. Subject-matters like
words have a speculative charge: they invariably point to something unsaid which is
not equivalent to leaving sensible experience but, importantly, to extending it. This
is why we would prefer to speak about interpretation filling out a work’s subject
matter rather than seeking to determine its grounding concept.
Accordingly, a subject-matter in Gadamer’s sense of the term is not to be understood as an entity with a determinate meaning but as a constellation of meanings
which cross relate, interpenetrate and, sometimes, disrupt one another. Wittgenstein’s
image of a word as having a shared core meaning with a variety of peripheral associated meanings is appropriate here. We all have a grasp of the commonly shared
meaning of the word “lamp” but we will have different associations with it and will
configure it in various ways. Subject-matter matters arguably operate in exactly the
same way. They have numerous actual and possible determinations of meaning.
The process of interpretation will of itself bring different determinations of meaning
in relationship to one another, causing disruptions of previous configurations and
generating new ones. Now we come to what is the crucial point.
The subject-matter of a work is not only that which we seek to grasp in a work
but it is that which guides us towards a work. In so far as we have expectancies
about death and love we have a pre-understanding, a pre-disposition towards works
which take on such subject-matters. We find ourselves implicated in them and in turn
they insinuate themselves into our existential interests. Subject-matters are matters
of significance: they are zones of vulnerability. Precisely because we are disposed
towards such spheres of mattering, we find the appearance of a subject-matter to be
of consequence and something to which we are vulnerable. The appearance will
have its blanks, have its inconsistencies and tensions and we will strive through the
interpretation to fill them in, clarify their ambiguities, to body them forth, to make
them completer to eye and mind. But it is precisely in this interpretative striving that
something can happen contrary to our willing and doing.
When the hermeneutic imagination strives to penetrate the subject matter of a
work on the basis of being guided by a pre-understanding of that subject-matter,
the hermeneutic imagination can meet in the work and its horizons other satellite
meanings not met before, satellite meanings which when encountered cause a disruption of what had previously been understood. Language, it would seem, is viral.
Its subject matters can mutate in linguistic or interpretative encounters irrespective
of the initial interlocutor’s intentions or expectancies. Such a viral nature suggests
that language is autopoetic. When certain linguistic configurations meet, a mutation of
subject-matters becomes highly probable. Interpretation is an agent of transgression.
In seeking more, it encounters more than it might expect and in that rupture, its
initial interpretative coordinates vis à vis a subject matter are disrupted.
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
30
236
N. Davey
3.5
In Between Word and Image
240
In a famous section of the Critique of Pure Reason, which, quite contrary to Kant’s
original intentions, became seminal to the development of aesthetics, Kant argues
that if a concept was to have a significant reference it must refer to sensible or experiential content.
241
242
243
Without sensibility no object would be given to us, without understanding no object would
be thought. Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind.
(Critique of Pure Reason, A 51, B 75)
237
238
239
270
3.6
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
271
272
273
269
Let us propose the relevance of this argument to aesthetics and our understanding
of art. A great deal of what is termed art occupies precisely the terrain in between
the sensible and the idea, that is, it occupies the in-between space of Kant’s aesthetic
idea. Art works which deal only with the sensible would function not as signs
or symbols. They would have no intelligible content and be stripped of their ability
to communicate. Equally, art works which strive only to invoke concepts become
untrue to their sensible nature. They serve only as vehicles for thought. It is this
tension between sense and idea which marks out art as occupying the unstable of the
in-between. The nature of this instability is easily understandable in terms that not
only Kant and Gadamer but also Adorno would recognise.9
No matter how clearly a sculpture might invoke a conceptual referent, its sheer
sensibility will eventually disrupt our contemplation of the piece as being an expression of “motherhood” or of the “heroic”. The sensible object will, after a while, resist
whatever conceptual architecture we try to impose on it. This in-betweenness can be
presented as the appropriate domain of much art. It is essentially that unstable space
in which (1) the sensible remains sensible and yet more than sensible in so far as it
is pregnant with the ideational and (2) the idea, in as much as it is instantiated in the
sensible, remains less than a pure concept albeit it that it is through such incarnations
that concepts secure their relevance in the world.
Art cannot be involved with the pure realm of ideas alone for then it would become
philosophy. Neither can art reside solely in the realm of the sensible since it would
not be able to refer to anything beyond immediate sensation. Art is, then, definitively
of the in-between. Similarly, Kant’s aesthetic idea remains rooted in the sensible and
cannot take flight into the purely conceptual. It is an inhabitant of the inbetween: Its
nature is, therefore, exactly like that of the word and the subject-matter, inherently
unstable, forever oscillating between the sensual and the intelligible.
244
The Need for Interpretation
Gadamer is openly emphatic on three matters. (1) In the experience of art, the
artwork speaks to us directly. It is not a matter of deciphering something ambiguous
and then arriving at an understanding of it. The art work addresses us directly.
9
Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973), 135 ff.
3
In Between Word and Image…
31
(2) When the artwork addresses us, all interpretation ceases. (3) Being attentive to the
artwork’s address is not the result of a methodological stratagem but of acquiring
the appropriate mode of discernment towards the work. The general consensus of
Gadamerian scholarship is that there is something inimical between the application
of method and being receptive to the address of the artwork. The artwork addresses
us contrary to our willing and doing whereas the deployment of method requires a
wilful decision and, as such, speaks according to Gadamer of a certain alienation
from the subject matter being analysed.
Pace Gadamer, we will claim that a version of Kant’s disinterestedness and an
element of methodical detachment is vital to philosophical hermeneutics if it is to
succeed in enriching our experience of art. This implies another quite un-Gadamerian
position: the need for the interpreting spectator to distance herself, to stand back
from a work in a disinterested fashion in order to negotiate the enigma that constitutes it. This is the principal reason why we contend that within any hermeneutic
orientation towards art, the influence of Kant is inescapable. We will strengthen the
point shortly. However, certain qualifications in our argument are needed.
It is clear that when Kant talks of disinterestedness, he speaks of it in relation to
the actual existence of the object represented in an art work. The aesthetic interest
of the work lies in its manner of representation and not in the actuality of the object of
representation. Philosophical hermeneutics takes a quite different stance. Gadamer’s
aesthetic theory eschews the representational account of images and opts for a presentational account: an artistic image does not re-present, copy, distort or enhance
its objective co-relative. Whereas in the representational account, the object remains
ontologically independent of its artistic depiction, in the presentational account, the
subject-matter comes forth from within the image. It is not ontologically distinct from
the work but increases its being in and through that work. Though the subject-matter
is always more than any single depiction of it, it does not exist, historically speaking,
apart from the totality of its depictions. We may choose out of ignorance or callousness
to be indifferent towards the existence of subject-matters but Gadamer’s position
suggests that disinterestedness towards their existence is not an option. The fact that
we are shaped by cultural subject-matters, that our self-understanding depends on
them and, more important, that the incompleteness of our self understanding makes us
deeply vulnerable to their claims, means that our being and the being of subject-matters
are deeply entwined and interdependent. We will argue that it is because of such
involvement that a degree of disinterested detachment is necessary. In so far as we are
hermeneutically vulnerable to the incursions of other, new and challenging meanings,
we cannot be indifferent towards the subject-matters which shape the horizons of
our being. This, we argue, is precisely why a degree of detached methodological
disinterestedness within Gadamer’s aesthetics is necessary.
If we contend that we need disinterested method to unravel the enigma of a
work, and if we believe that disinterested method in art interpretation unequivocally
targets the meaning of a work, a meaning that method might establish independent
of our subjectivity, then our argument would be completely and utterly at odds with
philosophical hermeneutics. But why suppose that the supposed meaning of a
work is what method targets? Why should we suppose that the aim of methodical,
disinterested, distanced interpretation is objectivist: i.e. that it aims to seize the
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
32
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
supposed definitive meaning of a work? To suppose this is indeed to fall back onto
precisely those objectivist accounts of meaning which philosophical hermeneutics
and, indeed, deconstruction rightly berate. Underlying Niezsche’s remark that it is
not so much method that is critical but the insights its deployment gives rise to10 is
a sound point. Method is important not because it offers a privileged and zealously
guarded gateway to the “truth” but for those unexpected insights that arise in the
course of its application. In other words, it is not method per se that is crucial but its
hermeneutical spin offs.
The deployment of method as a device to induce the emergence of serendipitous
insights can be explained by reference to certain of our initial remarks about the
work of Hamilton Finlay. It was argued that artwork and spectator are placed within
a nexus of hermeneutical associations many of which will not be fully apparent to
us. Such positioning within a plurality of interpretations and cultural commitments
(many sub-conscious) is precisely that which enables the hermeneutical exchange
between work and spectator to take place. It is such hermeneutical contiguity that
makes work and viewer vulnerable. The deployment of method can, in effect, cause
a disturbance in the hermeneutical fields of work and viewer. The aim however is
not just to expand the number of insights available to us but to create circumstances
in which the serendipitous insight can challenge received pre-suppositions and
opinion. Methods are needed, then, to set the plurality of interpretation around work
and viewer into play. This case for a deliberate methodological approach to the
enigmatic nature of the art work which seems initially so un-Gadamerian can be
properly defended in hermeneutical terms. Let us summarise the main argument.
We exist within hermeneutical fields of meaning and association. Though,
ontologically speaking, such meanings and associations are never closed, our interaction with them can become static. Habit, laziness, unthinking expectancy conspire
to close horizons and limit responsiveness to the challenges of art and the other. Long
standing involvement in ways of thinking and seeing can make us all unreceptive and
blinkered. This, then, is the basis for the case for method as outlined. The disruptions
they potentially induce act as a check against the blinkeredness of our involvements
in received horizons of meaning. Philosophical hermeneutics should not belittle
Kant’s disinterestedness for two reasons. Granted that philosophical hermeneutics
could never be disinterested with regard to the existence of those subject-matters
which define our existential horizons, the case for detached aesthetic contemplation
of art works is that without it the existence of a being whose understanding is
based upon accumulated experience would be dangerously compromised. Not to
question what is habitually taken for granted would be detrimental to such a being.
Disinterested methodic intervention in our experience of art activates interaction in
the horizons of meaning within which work and spectator are placed. Such interventions can expose the overlooked and the unseen within our pre-suppositions.
The seminal point is that in order to set the nexus of meanings and associations
in which we are hermeneutically grounded into play, it is necessary to distance
320
N. Davey
10
F. Nietzsche, “The Most Valuable Insights Are Arrived at Last: But the Most Valuable Insights
Are Methods,” in Will to Power (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1968), sect. 469.
3
In Between Word and Image…
33
ourselves from our initial involvements with them. Such a posture of distanced
disinterestedness has nothing to do with any illusory attempt to objectify the
pre-suppositions of understanding but with activating them in such a way as to both
challenge customary juxtapositions and generate hitherto unseen possibilities.
An invocation of method and disinterestedness seems very un-Gadamerian but
we shall claim that when seen from a wider hermeneutic perspective, the invocation
is far from heretical. Though enabled by deliberate methodical intervention, a new
alignment of meaning will often arise independent of the intentions or expectations
of the interpreter. We saw how Hamilton Finlay’s images insert themselves into well
established nuances of meaning, disturb them and induce new alignments to emerge.
We contend that method and its interventions can achieve the same creative disturbances. By virtue of the everyday play of language, sudden insights can, of course,
occur serendipitously. Our discussion of Wittgenstein made this clear. Though it is
unable to predict the emergence of transformative insights, method can deliberately
seek to prompt unexpected fusions of meaning. Deliberate intervention will not
guarantee the emergence of new understanding. It will just make it more likely.
Without it, the occurrence of insight will depend upon the contingencies of whether
the art works “speaks” to a viewer or not, or whether the chance and circumstantial
play of language can achieve it.
If insight is achieved, a poignant hermeneutic reversal takes place. In any attempt
to negotiate the enigma of a work, the work is subject to the methodological inquisition of the viewer. However, when an art work “speaks”, the position is reversed.
The spectator is subjected to the work. This is a key position in Gadamer’s argument.
When the engagement between work and spectator gives rise to a new alignment of
meaning, its does so contrary to the willing and expectation of the viewer. The
emergent re-alignment by no means confirms the primary hypothesis of a method but
can promote insights quite contrary to its initial suppositions. Furthermore, when the
emergence of a new alignment of meaning occurs, the distanciation and disinterestedness associated within the methodical also disappear and are replaced by the all
encompassing address of the work. In the moment of its address, the work abolishes
distance. Interpretation ceases. The enigma of a work is temporarily dissolved. In this
experience, the horizons of the work and the viewer achieve a new fusion which can
transform the way we think of ourselves and the work. Viewed ontologically, of course,
such understanding is not an experience of the meaning of a work in any pejorative
sense. Gadamer’s ontology recognises that such moments certainly enhance the
being of the subject-matters instantiated in the work. Now let us conclude.
3.7
Conclusion: Philosophical Hermeneutics
and Kant’s Inescapable Heritage
We claim that with regard to philosophical hermeneutics and its specific approach
to the experience of art, Kant has an inescapable heritage. Firstly, Kant’s aesthetic idea oscillating between word and image is like Gadamer’s subject-matter,
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
34
N. Davey
Fig. 3.3 Unattributed Soviet image, Stalingrad, possibly by Olga Lander (www.datadat.org)
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
inherently unstable. Yet what Kant regards as the indeterminacy of the aesthetic idea
is from a hermeneutical point of view, always the promise of further transformative
alignments. Just note how the proper plurality of interpretation which clusters around
Finlay’s “aesthetic idea” can be altered and transformed by key hermeneutic variations
on a similar image. The Soviet photograph of a woman walking past a seemingly
wrecked tank raises nuances that force one to review those that orbit around
Hamilton Finlay’s images. Perhaps the gentle simplicities of daily life expose the
fanciful violence of Greek mythology (and Finlay’s masculine interest in it) as fundamentally harmful or, worse irrelevant. Or, does the image substantiate elements of
that mythology by revealing the terrible price of everyday placidity? Perhaps there
is a more sinister association still. just as Hamilton Finlay’s Arcadia images disturb
a plurality of associations and meanings, so a photographic image can, in its turn,
realign the lines of nuance implicit in Hamilton Finlay’s works (Fig. 3.3).
Secondly, Kant’s heritage is inescapable in as much that a dispassionate, disinterested approach to aesthetic objects is needed in order to bring the instability of
word and image into further play. Here we clearly argue against Gadamer: methodical
interpretive intervention is indeed necessary but neither as an end-in-itself and nor
as a privileged road to truth. It is necessary to disturb our presuppositions about a
work so as to activate and animate (in the way that Finlay’s images do in their context) the network of associations which we are undeniably placed within. Methodic
intervention may have as its first moment a disruptive, component but within that
negativity there is the precondition of something which from a hermeneutic point
of view is much more positive. It creates the possibility of new configuration of
meaning when the subject is no longer in control, a moment when the work “speaks”
and the spectator is once again spoken to.
[AU7]
3
In Between Word and Image…
35
Method, we argue, does not have to be anathema to Gadamer’s aesthetic theory.
Can it not be argued that methodic intervention might achieve a better attentiveness
to a work, that it can encourage us to a degree to step aside from our most immediate
prejudices many of which are ossified in institutional practices? To the contrary,
given the openness of word and image and their consequent vulnerability to contiguous hermeneutic fields, methodic intervention can not only encourage a proper
attentiveness to a work but also establish the conditions whereby as a result of its
interventions, new structures of meaning can be prompted to emerge.
It remains the case that though such hermeneutic emergences might be prompted
by methodic interventions, they arrive independent of the intentions of those who
apply them. This suggests how method might be re-assimilated into a Gadamerian
hermeneutics. Methodic intervention, as we have outlined it, is not a matter of subjugation or control but a question of achieving a point of entry into the enigma that
is a work of art without knowing what the establishment of such an interpretive
bridgehead could give rise to. Methodic intention and control appertain only to the
application of the method: what emerges from the application remains serendipitous.
Without the deliberate decision to engage a work, the occurrence of aesthetic
experience will depend upon both the arbitrariness of exposure to artworks and
exposure to chance happenings of language. The argument for methodic intervention
has nothing to do with seeking control of the serendipitous but, on the contrary, with
accelerating the likelihood of its occurrence. The languages of sign and symbol
through which the aesthetic idea and subject-matter articulate themselves, afford a
glimpse of the economies of meaning and association which sustain aesthetic
experience. Just as Hamilton Finlay’s images alter that economy, so methodical
intervention can prompt new alignments of insight. Methodical intervention drives
not towards an impartial disinterested description of the elements of aesthetic
experience but towards its enhancement and deepening.
However, let us not mislead ourselves, revelatory moments are never final.
Never will they arrive at the meaning of a work. All such meaning is essentially
unstable. Yet that instability is the precondition of new accruals of meaningfulness.
The revelatory moment must pass to be born again in new configurations. Hamilton
Finlay’s images touch on the deep pre-occupation that all art has with the primeval
forces of order and disorder. What both our hermeneutic engagement with art and
the instability of word and image reveal is something of the despair and hope at
the ground of our being. Unavoidable losses of meaning are inseparable from the
hope of new life and meaning. Through their phoenix like achievement of ever new
alignments of meaning, it is perhaps art and aesthetic experience which redeem the
ever present flaw in Arcadia.
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
Author Queries
Chapter No.: 3
0001327761
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please confirm chapter title.
AU2
Please provide department name in the affiliation for the author
“Nicholas Davey.”
AU3
Please confirm the inserted citations for Figs. 3.1–3.3.
AU4
No. 1, No. 2 and No. 4 have been changed to Fig. 3.1, Fig. 3.2
and Fig. 3.3 respectively. Please check if this is fine.
AU5
Closing quote is missing in the sentence starting “We might
ask, “Death and destruction are supposedly....”. Please check.
AU6
Please check the term “nexi” in the sentence starting “They
illuminate living …” for correctness.
AU7
Please check the usage of “sinister association still. just” for
correctness.
Queries
Chapter 4
1
Merleau-Ponty on Cultural Schemas
and Childhood Drawing
2
3
Talia Welsh
4
4.1
5
Introduction: Tony O’Connor and Merleau-Ponty
Tony O’Connor writes that Merleau-Ponty uses the unconscious to allow for a present
and temporal but non-thematic experience. In particular O’Connor draws our attention
to the fact that Merleau-Ponty’s published writings continue the phenomenological
tradition of viewing the unconscious as an aspect of intentional experience. Not
necessarily less important or less meaningful than conscious intentional experience,
the unconscious lives at a non-explicit, non-thematic level occurring alongside or
intermixed with conscious experience:
In phenomenology, particularly developed under the influence of Merleau-Ponty, stress is
laid on the active, intentional behavior of man in his reciprocal interaction with a human
environment. This leads to the view that the unconscious is reciprocal to consciousness in
some way. It is a region of the psyche which is present in some manner but which has not
yet been brought to explicit consciousness. (O’Connor 1981, p. 78)
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
Yet, this idea of the unconscious brings it close to Edmund Husserl’s idea of passive synthesis (Husserl 2001) or even Leibniz’ idea of petit perceptions (Leibniz
1996). It is inarguable that there are non-thematic elements to conscious experience,
in other words not all consciousness is “conscious.” We can view the unconscious
as the infinite span of various perceived, but non-thematic, experiential elements;
the sedimented and “forgotten” elements that create, surround and support what we
naively take to be our conscious experience.
Freudian theory disputes such a conception of the unconscious. The unconscious
is a collection of drives and desires that are formed upon childhood fantasies. These
early experiences sharply determine our later behavior, often coming to odds with our
T. Welsh (*)
Department of Philosophy & Religion, University of Tennessee at Chattanooga,
Chattanooga, TN, USA
e-mail: Talia-Welsh@utc.edu
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_4, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
6
37
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
38
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
conscious desires since their formation was only loosely tied to reality. In Freudian
terms, the “unconscious” affects our conscious experience but often runs contrary to
what our lived experience tells us. We have a kind of battle between the unconscious
“pleasure principle” and the conscious “reality principle” (Freud 1962).
We certainly can find both—the phenomenological unconscious and the psychoanalytic one—in our everyday experience. I can concentrate on a Helen Frankenthaler
painting on the gallery’s wall. A complex variety of non-thematic elements of my
situation—the room, the lighting, my education, my previous experience with her
work, the woman sneezing to my right—co-determine my perceptual focus on this
particular piece. I might also realize upon reflection that my desire to appear interested in this famous artist comes from my upbringing where appearing to be of a
certain class was stressed, i.e., appearing to be member of the group of people who
appreciate fine art. I cannot separate out what part of my interest in Frankenthaler is
“authentic” and what is part of my bourgeois education. Realizing this, I could
admit that other parts of my behavior and my very experience are determined in
ways I cannot recognize but that I assume exist. In a certain sense, these two kinds
of unconscious experience—one stressing the unconscious aspects of the present
lived experience and the other emphasizing underlying affective and conditioned
experience—would seem to have radically different methods of investigation. They
also appear to reside in different parts of our experience, one created by highly
personal experience and the other by a general human perceptual experience.
Indeed, my desire to appear a certain way has everything to do not just with my
parents and my own personal story, but with a historical, social and cultural situation where aesthetic-appreciation is valued. My parents have imparted to me their
culturally-determined morals, ones they may or may not be aware of and able to
articulate. The fact that gallery-going seems to be a highly culturally and historicallyrelative experience, makes the “psychoanalytic” unconscious elements that constitute my perception appear even more removed from present lived experience. They
seem to be hidden, symbolic forces—caused by cultural, social, linguistic, economic and historical forces. While integral to understanding my experience, it is
difficult to see how we could approach their essence in the same way we could
discuss the essence of lived embodiment.
In the face of these different kinds of non-thematic elements of perception,
unconscious drives and historical contingencies, Merleau-Ponty takes what one
might call a cheerful and positive view of our intrinsic engagement with the world.
He, unlike a Edmund Husserl and like his contemporaries, agrees that the psychological and historical theories of thinkers like Sigmund Freud and Karl Marx are watershed theories that require acknowledgment. Indeed, he cites them as predecessors
of phenomenology.1 We cannot assume that phenomenology can place aside these
aspects of our experience and answer them at a later date or that somehow a traditional
28
T. Welsh
“It [phenomenology] has been long on the way, and its adherents have discovered it in every
quarter, certainly in Hegel and Kierkegaard, but equally in Marx, Nietzsche and Freud” (MerleauPonty 1996, p. viii).
1
4 Merleau-Ponty on Cultural Schemas and Childhood Drawing
39
4.1.1
Childhood Art
phenomenology will inevitably capture them. To do so would fail to capture how
intimately psychological and historical situation constitutes not only the individual’s
experience but philosophy itself.
Nonetheless, in Merleau-Ponty’s descriptions of childhood drawing, he does
return to a more traditional phenomenological exploration of the unconscious, as
O’Connor postulates. He lectures that our earliest expression of engagement with the
world shows a freedom from cultural schemas. And, in the normal non-traumatized
child, a real independence from parental overdetermination is demonstrated. As
O’Connor notes in his article “Categorizing the Body,” Merleau-Ponty does remain
an essentialist despite more fully integrating the cultural and the psychological
(O’Connor 1982). While aware and interested in considering cultural elements in
childhood drawing, Merleau-Ponty sees in it a more general reflection of our experience
rather than a particular expression of an individual child’s family dynamics. Thus
the child’s unconscious experience is that of the first phenomenological order: a
co-determining part of lived experience. With effort, modern painters have rediscovered this intimate phenomenological connection with experience.
Merleau-Ponty writes, that “the efforts of modern painting grant a new meaning to
children’s drawings”. We can no longer consider perspectival drawings as the only
‘truth’…. The child is capable of certain spontaneous actions which are rendered
impossible in the adult due to the influence of, and obedience to, cultural schemas
(Merleau-Ponty 2010, p. 132).2 Due to the linguistic limitations of children, psychologists use their drawings as diagnostic tools. For instance, psychologists note
that when a child is being abused by a relative, her graphical depictions of that relative will likely be indicative of abuse. The abuser may appear in a threatening position compared to the child—she may be overly large or have harsh marks surrounding
him. Or, the child might refuse to depict the abuser, almost in a kind of fear she will
surface through the very two-dimensional image itself.
Such practices lead us to think of children’s drawings as largely expressive of
internal states: fear, happiness, boredom, etc., and not as representative of the external
world. Thus, children draw what they feel rather than what they see. In the case of
unexplainable events, such as magic tricks, the child is expected to rely upon beliefs
in magic and fantasy. For instance, when a rabbit is pulled out of a hat, a child is
expected to easily accept, if not even prefer, the “magical” explanation. What one
might call the “scientific” or “philosophical” understanding would have to be provided to the child because, naturally, the child tends toward an internal, affective
Merleau-Ponty held a professorship in child psychology and pedagogy at the Sorbonne from 1949
to 1952. (Merleau-Ponty, 2010)
2
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
40
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
and superstitious worldview. As a result, we understand children as not seriously
engaged with the world around them. Their experience is overrun with an unconscious affectivity that bars them from being fully present.
Merleau-Ponty’s Sorbonne lectures in child psychology and pedagogy reject
this view. Instead, he finds that children’s comprehension of surprising events and
their depictions and descriptions, albeit different from adult ones, arises from an
engaged relationship with the world. Merleau-Ponty argues that we need to find a
neutral language when considering our early interpretations and expressions of
the world (Merleau-Ponty 2010, p. 143). Otherwise, our investment in scientific
and philosophical concepts will cause us to misunderstand the uniqueness of the
child’s experience.
A phenomenology of perception, the exploration Merleau-Ponty is perhaps most
famous for, reveals that our perceptual experience is far more critical to our cognition than we had previously assumed. Few psychologists or philosophers deny the
obvious foundational role perception serves, but many treat it as a type of physiological collecting of experiential givens. The challenging question is how the proper
intellectual or cognitive judgment applies itself to perception. Thus, a child might
have the physical apparatus to collect the givens but since the child obviously lacks
the intellectual and mental skills to process that data, her engagement will be limited. Merleau-Ponty argues strongly against interpreting perception in such a fashion. In the case of the child, Merleau-Ponty acknowledges that the child is
unsophisticated and lacks many cognitive skills. However, since perception precedes intellectual judgments about the objects of perception, the child is not partially or minimally experiencing the world. The child might not judge an object or
be able to name it, but her perceptions are not therefore lacking. Childhood drawing
provides an insight into the nature of childhood perception and, thereby, the basis of
adult perception.
The child’s experience also provides a counterpoint to aid us in analyzing certain
unquestioned assumptions about adult experience, providing an insight into the
workings of the adult psyche. Merleau-Ponty affirms the traditional conception that
children draw expressively, but does not suggest that this means their drawing is not
perceptual. Rather, it is the false premise that perception is only the psychologicalphysiological collecting of sense-data that is then interpreted by intellectual processing that permits one to draw a line between affective, internally motivated
drawing and drawing as solely the representation of the perceived world.
While often connected to the givens that lie outside the body, artistic representations are always at the same time modified by the artist. Adults have often
been trained to associate photographic representations as “realistic” depictions
of our perceptual experience. While we may admire abstract art as aesthetically
richer, it is the Norman Rockwell style artist who more accurately recreates
what we see. However, as Merleau-Ponty goes to lengths to argue, this very idea
that photo-realistic art is more accurate is itself a cultural, and not a perceptual,
product. We do not actually encounter the world as a series of moving snapshots.
Our experience of reality is not akin to a movie projected before our eyes. Adult
ideas about art and perception are overdetermined by “conventional attitudes.”
104
T. Welsh
4 Merleau-Ponty on Cultural Schemas and Childhood Drawing
41
Regarding our perceptual experience, the child’s artistic representation of the
world is more revealing:
The study of the role of drawing leads us back to the capacity which it serves as its ground:
perception. We have seen that drawings express affectivity rather than understanding.
Consequently, we must pay close attention to what the child’s perception—and even that of
the adult when it can be stripped of conventional attitudes—consists of when encountering
things not only as objects of understanding, but also as affective stimulants. (Merleau-Ponty
2010, p. 171)
In many passages, Merleau-Ponty argues that childhood drawing possesses
unique advantages to understanding the nature of perception in comparison to adult
drawing, painting, and discourse. Merleau-Ponty lectures that children express a
more sensually-integrated experience in their drawings than adults do. Not only do
children use their sense of time, hearing, taste, and touch in their depictions, they
also do not distinguish between what they feel and what they see. The characteristics
of childhood drawing arise directly from the child’s experience in an unmediated
fashion, since children are not as integrated into the system of styles of representation. From accumulated experience witnessing paintings, photos, film, and being
schooled in what “good” painting consists of, adults tend to be more occulocentric
in their representations. In everyday experience, visual perception does not occur in
a vacuum where sight is extracted from the other senses.
The traditional adult conception of drawing is a two-dimensional representation
of a three-dimensional visual object. One should draw a “thing” in a moment of
time—the landscape, the chair, the person. Children weave context, time, and perspectives, as well as their affective life, into their depictions. When diagnosing
children’s disorders, psychoanalysis and psychology use the fact that children do
not separate their affective relations with persons from their depictions of them.
While adults latently retain this affective nature in their drawings and certainly artists
endeavor to create beyond the concept of representing objects two-dimensionally as
“faithfully” as possible, children’s drawings reveal much about how adult drawing
has become overlaid by socio-cultural determinations.
Psychologists often use drawing to measure the development of the child’s
visual and motor systems. Can the child successfully put a torso onto the body, or
does the child merely draw a tadpole man? When asked to draw an object, does the
child capture the main components of it? Merleau-Ponty considers the emphasis on
such skills to misread child perception as a function of adult perception (i.e. the
child’s drawing is only valued as an expression of how far the child is on the path
to adulthood). Such a conception does acknowledge that children’s drawings possess unique characteristics (contrasted with a more outdated view holding child
drawing as psychologically irrelevant), but it still views “children’s drawings as
imperfect sketches of adult drawings which are the ‘true’ representation of the
object” (Merleau-Ponty 2010, p. 132). Thus, their interpretative model constrains
them to always find within the child what is present in the adult, not considering
that the child may possess unique structures that are not merely miniature or
reduced versions of adult ones. Consequently, such a conception of child drawing
assumes that what is “wrong” in children’s drawings is the lack of attention to the
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
42
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
real way in which the object appears. In fact, Merleau-Ponty counters, child
drawing can often reveal the elements of the object’s being (and one’s own being)
that adult repress.
Picasso’s use of multiple perspectives in one human figure can be understood as
grasping a truth about the perspectival nature of our perception. Likewise, the childhood tendency to flatten perspective illustrates how our eyes do not tend to focus
only simply on a one-point perspective but wander from place to place within a
visual field. Children also distort comparative sizes of objects and persons depending
on their affective relations. Merleau-Ponty credits psychoanalysis with discovering
how childhood drawing demonstrates the manner in which affective associations
are depicted, even when these objects are not in the visual field of the child. MerleauPonty cites Sophie Morgenstern’s Psychoanalyse infantile: symbolisme et valeur
clinique des creations imaginatives chez l’enfant which describes how “drawing is
sublimation for both the child and the adult” (Merleau-Ponty 2010, p. 175).3 But in
adults, one must search the painting for latent content that was deformed by psychic
resistances—“However, in children, it is impossible to imagine that such a censor
mechanism exists; rather than discovering a simple duality of manifest content and
latent content, one finds a single text of undetermined meaning” (p. 175). For
instance, we can understand how adult repression might occur in sexually-charged
but taboo representations. However, given the child’s nature, there is no sexual
content “as sexual” to be repressed and then symbolized. We can say that for the
child there is nothing distinctly sexual, rather sexuality is one color of the child’s
entire experience.
Merleau-Ponty returns to Politzer, citing his critique of Freudian notions of latent
content and manifest content (for Politzer this distinction isn’t operative in the child
or the dreamer) (p. 175).4 As written above, objects do not represent for children
what they might for adults—“The child’s symbolization does not stem from an
understanding separated by the terms object and symbol, but rather sexual meaning
is immanent in the drawing” (Merleau-Ponty 2010, pp. 175-176). Thus, affective
relations are not behind or beneath children’s perceptions (occasionally causing certain kinds of depictions); they are intrinsic to perception itself. The concept that
194
T. Welsh
Sophie Morgenstern, a child psychoanalyst, wrote on the relevance of childhood drawing and
other creative acts. Merleau-Ponty writes, “As a means of considering the psychoanalytic exploration of drawings, let us consider Sophie Morgenstern’s (1937) Psychanalyse infantile; symbolisme
et valeur clinique des creations imaginatives chez l’enfant. Morgenstern’s interpretation of
children’s drawings stems from her observation of a particular child whom she could explore by
no other means. The boy was mute and quite reticent and was capable of expressing himself only
through the drawings which he produced. The doctor would interpret these drawings while the
child nodded or shook his head at the interpretations provided. Morgenstern cites some of the
child’s productions to include: birds, tall animals, stick figures with hats, individuals with
three arms, with a pipe, with a knife, men in the moon, wolfmen, parents without heads, etc.”
2010, p. 174
4
Merleau-Ponty continues, “If someone dreams a house, they are not dreaming of sexual organs;
they are thinking directly of the house which is immediately a sexual expression” (p. 175).
3
4 Merleau-Ponty on Cultural Schemas and Childhood Drawing
43
emotional states “cause” the child to draw in a certain manner—a theory of drawing
as an expressive function—has a certain truth to it, but an incomplete one. It is true
that children are expressive, emotional artists. However, it isn’t the case that they
have an emotion and subsequently are forced by this emotion to draw in a particular manner. This interpretation argues that the child’s affective states are internal,
removed from their perceptual experience. Children do not have a deep unconscious
that motivates their experience, but a non-conscious, direct manner of perceiving
with their entire being. We learn to create divisions between affects and the senses;
we are not born with such distinctions.
We might object that such a position reifies childhood experience as if it were not
influenced by the contingencies of the child’s situation: her culture, social class and
family. Merleau-Ponty acknowledges that “it is impossible to separate culture’s
influence from what properly speaking belongs to the child. Sociological, even ideological considerations always intervene in any discussion about drawing” (MerleauPonty 2010, p. 163).5 At the same time, Merleau-Ponty considers this kind of
objection a false problem. Naturally, children are affected by their situation, others’
attitudes toward them, the cultural norms of the society, etc. We need to ask now:
What does such an admission entail? For Merleau-Ponty, such a statement is merely
a truism and would not affect our ability to investigate the child’s structures of perception. “Even a total absence of milieu (if this is conceivable) would affect the
child as any particular milieu does” (Merleau-Ponty 2010, p. 164). It is a given that
environmental conditions shape any being that lives within that environment. The
point of Merleau-Ponty’s child psychology is to demonstrate to what degree cultural
differences demonstrate plasticity in child development and which behaviors expose
structural traits. Without such traits no comparison between cultures can be possible,
for a comparison requires a framework, or form, that is similar enough in both to
afford a comparison. Merleau-Ponty finds that cultural differences reveal structural
similarities. In fact, anthropological investigations support the view that processes
by which children perceive are similar (although the content of their responses varies
widely due to class and culture).
Structural traits are not context-independent. Yet, they do allow for one to leave
the description of the cultural, historical situation and consider the theoretical
implications of childhood drawing, especially how it reveals childhood perception. Thus, to understand how childhood drawing is more than just a test or measure of motor development, one must recognize a “positive meaning within the
child’s drawing” (Merleau-Ponty 2010, p. 132). Pointing out similarities with
modern art, Merleau-Ponty writes that child drawing and modern painting
challenge the postulate that “the geometrical perspective is truer” p. 132). He
continues by noting that, “the efforts of modern painting place this postulate in
question and accord a positive significance to other manners of seeing (For example,
for Picasso the plurality of profiles is a means of expression.” p. 132).
Merleau-Ponty continues by citing a Marxist example of the over-determination of cultural experience, “thus, certain Marxists would see the child’s non-figurative drawings as stemming strictly
from the influence of the bourgeois cultural milieu” (p. 163).
5
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
44
T. Welsh
283
284
285
286
287
288
We can see proof of children’s freedom from our cultural postulates in their drawings. We
do understand that a perceptual-motor insufficiency does in fact exist; children are not artists.
However, the efforts of modern painting grant a new meaning to children’s drawings. We
can no longer consider perspectival drawings as the only ‘truth’…. The child is capable of
certain spontaneous actions which are rendered impossible in the adult due to the influence
of, and obedience to, cultural schemas. (Merleau-Ponty 2010, p. 132)
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
282
Modern artists abandon traditional methods of creating the illusion of perspective
within a two-dimensional canvas, and explore a variety of styles to compose their
works. Since traditional Western, perspectival drawing and photography are considered to be more “accurate” visually, modern art is often analyzed in terms
unrelated to accuracy or truth (for instance, one can discuss the use of color and
line, social commentary, visual effect, etc.). Merleau-Ponty argues that, like childhood drawing, modern art better emphasizes the truth of perception. Additionally,
we must realize that the idea that photographic representation of an object—its
visual stimuli—is itself an intellectual exercise of isolation that always occurs
post-perception.
Naturally, adult distinctions cannot be too hard and fast. Like children, we cannot
be trapped in our own culturally overdetermined views lest we fail to recognize the
ambiguous nature of children’s perception. Because the modern artist (or psychologist
or philosopher) calls into question unreflective assumptions about perception and
representation, she achieves a degree of freedom from cultural norms. Although
there is no complete liberty, there are greater and lesser degrees of independence
and, thus, creativity with respect to social-cultural standards:
266
To explore the world of child drawing and how it reflects child perception, one
must find a method that integrates both the historical events of the child’s life as
well as the responses of the child to its environment. Merleau-Ponty takes a stance
contrary to any kind of functionalism or strict developmental schema where children are viewed as either possessing or not possessing age-appropriate skills and
behaviors—“Positive contents must be incorporated into explorations of the functional aspects of the child’s behavior”2010, p. 132). Childhood drawings represent an expressive grasp of nature that reflects the child’s global perception of the
world. A global perception is the general manner in which one relates to the
world—one’s vision, history, and emotive nature. Thus, what a child sees and
what a child draws “are not exactly the same” (Merleau-Ponty 2010, p. 164
Children do not separate their “internal vision of things” from the sight of the
object.
The expressive nature of children’s drawing means that the object-representation
and the affective state are not separate categories of intellect and emotion. MerleauPonty lectures that, for children, drawing is as much about self-expression as it is
about thing-representation, but, as argued above, this is not to say that the child is
motivated by some kind of internal state to express herself. Merleau-Ponty distinguishes himself from the child psychologist G.H. Luquet by denying the thesis
that the child’s drawing is a combination of an internal, affective model and a
4 Merleau-Ponty on Cultural Schemas and Childhood Drawing
45
direct representation of the child’s vision.6 Luquet assumes that drawing is about
transmitting visual givens. Hence, both the child and the adult “see” the same way;
it is a matter of attention that distinguishes their representations. Since he adheres
to a notion that the object is constant (the “constancy hypothesis”), Luquet thinks
perception is only a matter of paying attention well or poorly (Merleau-Ponty 2010,
p. 348).
We must move away from object-constancy toward an analysis of perception’s
immediate meaning. Attention often does reveal more aspects of a particular experience. Yet, this isn’t to say that when I consciously and carefully focus my attention
on an object that I am thereby physiologically absorbing more visual givens in my
perceptual field. We do not experience the world in a type of cloudy fog until we
decide to focus on objects. Attention doesn’t make me perceive “better” although it
does re-structure my perception.
Merleau-Ponty lectures that “The child’s drawing springs from a mode of communication different from our own; one which is thoroughly affective” 2010, p. 170).
The object to be drawn is perceived as temporally, spatially and affectively immersed
in its environment. In this sense, children are capturing the thing as it truly exists—
with shifting profiles, contextual situation and one’s intentions toward it meshed
inextricably together. At the same time, the child includes her own feelings about the
object within a drawing because, as stated previously, children do not take their emotions as belonging to them. Their lives are continuous with the world. Children’s
drawings are thus “at one and the same time more subjective and more objective than
those of adults: more subjective because they are liberated from appearance, and
more objective because they attempt to reproduce the thing as it really is, while
adults only represent things from one point of view—their own” (p. 170).
Adult perception, tied to judgments received from prior experience, is also intractably tied to social-cultural significations. The child is also influenced by socialcultural conditions. But these conditions do not constitute child experience in the
same manner as adult experience. On this topic, traditional psychologists are right
to note the immaturity of the child. The child does not have a complete and functioning grasp of language and cultural norms. The mistake of traditional psychologists is to assume that it also follows that children have a chaotic, incomplete
perceptual system because they do not articulate their experience clearly. MerleauPonty agrees with Koffka, among others, who affirms the notion of a constancy
phenomenon within perception (and not, as in Luquet, an object-constancy).7
Georges Henri Luquet (1972) wrote an influential text on the relevance of childhood drawing. In
Merleau-Ponty’s view, “Luquet contradicts himself by stating on the one hand that the child draws
according to an internal model, and on the other hand that the child’s drawings are not schematic
or idealist” (p. 167).
7
Kurt Koffka (1886–1941) was an early Gestalt psychologist who worked with Wertheimer and
Köhler. His text Principles of Gestalt Psychology (1935) is often cited by Merleau-Ponty.
6
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
46
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
Returning to the field-figure notion of Gestalt psychology, the constancy phenomenon
states that perception always occurs in an organized field; there is no “chaotic”
perception—“In the child, thanks to the phenomenon of constancy, a non-chaotic
and structured vision of the perceptual field exists (though this is not to say that the
structuration is the same as, or as perfect as, that of the adult)” (2010, p. 147). What
children do not possess, given their immature state of linguistic development, is an
interpretive system of judgments with which to symbolize their perceptions. For
children, “[t]here is no secondary work of interpretation” (p. 147).
Merleau-Ponty reiterates many times that this thesis doesn’t argue that
everything one finds in adult perception is entirely nascent within the child.
Gestalt psychology’s notion of the constancy of perception argues that infantile
perception is not identical to adult perception—“But, to say that infantile perception is structured from its first moment is not to declare the infant’s perception and adult’s the same. Rather, it is a question of a summary structure replete
with lacunae and indeterminate regions, and not the precise structuration that
characterizes adult perception” (2010, p. 148). As he argues in The Structure of
Behavior, to declare that the child or the animal has a meaningful way to organize its experiential world is not to say that its mode of structuration is always
an immature, less developed style of our own. Children must have an organized
meaningful relationship between their various experiences, their past, present
and future; however, this must be significantly different in many respects from
adult perception. For adults, a thing has a certain intellectual judgment attached
to it, even when the judgment is simply “this is an unknown thing I am witnessing.” In Gestalt theory, things also have a pre-intellectual unity, indicating that
a child can interact meaningfully with a thing without having any comprehension of it “as a thing”8 Development brings with it significant transformations
and re-structurations; these intellectual, linguistic developments are integrated
into everyday mature experience. Infantile perception does possess a “worldview” insofar as it presents a whole, structured perceptual field—“In the
developmental course of the child’s perception a number of transformations
and reorganizations occur. However, from the beginning certain totalities
(which merit the name of things) do exist and together they constitute a ‘world’”
(pp. 148-149).
344
T. Welsh
“In conclusion, we find that according to classical psychology the thing (perceived by the subject)
is wholly intelligible for it is the intellection of certain functional relations to variables. According
to Gestalt theory, the thing has a pre-intellectual unity. It can be defined for perception as a certain
style. For classical psychology, a circle is a law conceived by me while producing this figure. For
Gestalt theory, a circle is a certain physiognomy, a certain curvature. We learn to see the unity of
things. For example, the yellow of a lemon in connection with its acidity reveals a structural community which renders the particular aspects (yellow, acidity) synonymous. Thus, all of this confirms the fact that the infant’s experience does not begin as chaos, but as a world already underway
[un monde déjà] of which only the structure is filled with lacuna” (p. 148).
8
4 Merleau-Ponty on Cultural Schemas and Childhood Drawing
4.2
47
Conclusion: Cultural Spaces
377
O’Connor points out that Merleau-Ponty’s work can be critiqued by later figures,
such as Michel Foucault, who argue against Merleau-Ponty’s faith in the foundational nature of perception. We should acknowledge that “interpreted objects are
constituted, and not merely described, by interpretation itself, and always within a
specific epistemic and cultural space” (O’Connor 1994, pp. 14–15). Such a discussion is a direct challenge to a phenomenology which thinks that through careful
examination, our descriptions can reveal essential, or at least general, truths about
how we constitute objects. Post-structuralist, post-Freudian psychoanalytic and
postmodern approaches call such a claim into question. The “cultural and epistemic
space” in which I live not only contributes to the content of my judgments about my
perceptions, it also constitutes the form of how I perceive and the method of my
analysis of perception. Phenomenologists agree that our cultural world shapes our
value judgments, but a post-structuralist argues that the cultural world intrudes
deeply into our experience to the point where not only is a complete reduction
impossible, the desire to even perform a reduction is itself as thoroughly “cultural”
as my desire to appear to enjoy abstract art.9
We certainly can find this phenomenological faith in our ability to say something general about our experience in Merleau-Ponty’s discussion of childhood
drawing discussed above. His lectures on child psychology could be read as a kind
of overly romantic view of a childhood where the child “really” experiences,
whereas we must muddle through interpretive schemas. However, childhood art
can rightly be understood as expressing a more general experience than the adult’s.
Children are less aware of the complexities of interpretative schemas, have less
distance from any childhood traumas which will dictate their future models of
repression, and thus less subject to having enough distance from their lived experience to overlay it. Merleau-Ponty takes up Piaget’s discussion of childhood egocentrism and emphasizes it is not an egocentrism borne out of internal preoccupation,
but one where one is unaware of the existence of subjectivities at all. Thus, the
child has not yet acquired the same set of norms and expectations that arise from
others’ judgments since others qua “other subjectivities” are not yet a category for
the child. (Merleau-Ponty 2010, p. 176)
While acknowledging that a certain cultural influence exerts itself on the child,
Merleau-Ponty contends that we can generalize about the experience itself from the
depiction of that experience in the child’s drawing because the “cultural space” and
the interpretations of that space have not yet removed the child from the immediacy
of her perceptual experience. In addition, in order for us to recognize this immediacy
we too must retain a connection with that pre-cultural world. In child psychology,
Merleau-Ponty is famous for his assertion that Husserl himself did not think a complete reduction
possible. He writes “The most important lesson which the reduction teaches us is the impossibility
of a complete reduction” (Merleau-Ponty 1996, p. xiv).
9
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
48
T. Welsh
418
References
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
Freud, S. 1962. The ego and the Id. New York: W.W. Norton.
Husserl, E. 2001. Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental
logic. Trans. A. J. Steinbock, vol. 9. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Koffka, K. 1935. Principles of Gestalt psychology. London: Lund Humphries.
Leibniz, G.W. 1996. New essays on human understanding. Trans. P. R. J. Bennett. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Luquet, G.H. 1972. Le dessin enfantin. Paris: Delachaux et Niestlé.
Merleau-Ponty, M. 2010. Child Psychology and Pedagogy The Sorbonne Lectures 1949-1952.
Trans. T. Welsh. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. 1996. Phenomenology of perception. Trans C. Smith. London: Routledge.
Morgenstern, S. 1937. Psychanalyse infantile; symbolisme et valeur clinique des créations imaginatives chez l’enfant. Paris: Les Éditions Denoël.
O’Connor, T. 1981. Merleau-Ponty and the problem of the unconscious. In Merleau-ponty, perception, structure, language: A collection of essays, ed. J. Sallis, 77–88. Atlantic Highlands:
Humanities Press.
O’Connor, T. 1982. Categorizing the body. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology
13(3): 226–236.
O’Connor, T. 1994. Foundations, intentions and competing theories. Journal of the British Society
for Phenomenology 25(1): 14–26.
416
417
then, we find support for an existential phenomenology. Acknowledging our immersion
in the cultural, historical world, nonetheless, we are able to see our primordial precultural selves in the child.
415
1
Art and Edge: Preliminary Reflections
2
Edward S. Casey
3
I
4
Jackson Pollock said that painting for him had “no limits, only edges.” I shall take
this as a leitmotif for reflecting on how edges inhabit and haunt artworks, especially
paintings but also sculpture and earthworks, in an effort to grasp better this continually elusive entity, the edge, as it figures into these three forms of art.
[AU1]
Chapter 5
No limits: what can this mean? Aren’t artworks always delimited – by frames most
obviously but also by the walls they hang on or the museums in which they repose?
Aren’t sculptures and earthworks limited by their sheer extent, bulk or site? However
sizeable some of them are, no piece of sculpture or earthwork goes on forever: it
comes to a stop somewhere in a sculpture park, in the desert or even in the water.
But Pollock meant something else by lack of limit. He meant that the visual dynamics of an artwork could not be contained by any finite frame or wall or building;
these dynamics are constituted by vectors of felt force that leap over, beyond, or
even through, constraining structures – by the creation of a force field that is not
strictly physical or electromagnetic but a kind of visual energy that catalyzes the
viewer’s vision and makes it something more than mere observation: an active
visioning that knows “No limits.”
Sometimes a painter will carry a painting directly into the frame itself: Seurat, Marin,
and Harry Hopkins have done this. Sometimes the frame itself is omitted: that was
Pollock’s own preference, as it was Rothko’s and de Kooning’s. But these overt gestures do not tell the whole story. Pollock’s paintings of the late 1940s and early 1950s,
though not originally framed, now for the most part reside in frames on their owners’
walls or in museums. But the presence or absence of a frame does not matter: the
E.S. Casey (*)
Stony Brook University, Stony Brook, NY, USA
e-mail: escasey3@aol.com
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_5, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
49
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
50
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
swirling masses refuse to be delimited; they press “onward and outward… and
nothing collapses” (Walt Whitman, “Song of Myself”). They do not go outward to
infinity – as Mondrian claimed of the stripes in his elegant rectilinear paintings. We
do not need to assert this much; it is aesthetic overkill. (Infinity, in any case, exists
at quite another level, and is not an apt aim in art).
So too for earthworks. Part of their revolutionary fervor was to break out of
frames – and of galleries and museums as institutional enclosures. Robert Smithson
took the artwork outdoors, not in order to be himself in the presence of nature (like
nineteenth century plein air painters) but to situate the work in a non-cultivated
wildscape. In this case, the only limits were those of the natural forces to which the
earthwork was exposed: gravity, erosion, corrosion. The materials of such a work –
whether rock or earth or sand – were not limits but means of creation; and the earth
on which the work was set (or into which it is dug) was undelimited: but again, not
infinite (that predicate may apply to the universe but not to any cosmic whole such
as the earth embodies). For in any given landscape (or seascape) the earth stretches
out indefinitely, going outward through its horizons, which do not restrict (as would
a border) but open up (as does a boundary).
And the edges in all this? What was Pollock talking about when he said that painting
was about edges, “just edges”? An edge is technically defined as a “convex dihedral
angle.” What does this have to do with edges in art? More than one might think. For
one thing, it signifies that something angular is at stake – something that juts or jars,
that emerges noticeably and in a linear or quasi-linear fashion. Lines delineate edges;
they present them to the eye. It is revealing that Pollock refused to distinguish between
drawing and painting in his work, as if one were merely preliminary to the other. The
two are not just coeval; they were for him the same act altogether. Thus edges in his
work are linear in format and are convex to the extent that they are seen from their
outer side, so to speak – just as we discern the edge of a table by looking at, or touching
it, from beyond its physical substance as such. We look or feel around edges –
whereas we look or feel our way into corners, which are the converse of edges (they
are, topologically considered, concave dihedral angles).
The importance of line to edges in art is already evident in the caves of Altamira
and Lascaux – arguably the first artworks in the West. They are at once paintings
and earthworks, defying the usual distinction between these two genres of art by
their forceful collaboration of the raw earth (i.e., the cave walls with their existing
edges) with applied lines and colors (applied precisely to these walls, respecting
their edges but also creating further edges at the level of the image).
In Pollock, we witness lines becoming painted images before our very eyes –creating
palimpsests of traced and erased edges that finally cohere as whole works. In their
complex internal differentiation, the edges in Pollock’s paintings distinguish painted
areas from each other, and at the same time they adumbrate directional vectors in
the work. In their convexity, they open outward from within their own angularity in
a show of pure visual display. The combinations of edges are endless – even within
a single work, as we see in the case of Pollock’s “action paintings.” The active gesture of the artist’s hand creates a nexus of lines that drips and flow on their own
recognizance. In de Kooning’s paintings of the 1960s the line is largely replaced by
27
E.S. Casey
5 Art and Edge: Preliminary Reflections
51
areas of vibrant color that constitute gestures of their own; the edges of these areas
are for the most part those which the color fields themselves bring about in their
brash and subtle juxtapositions.
In the earthworks of Smithson and others, edges appear as folds – folds into, and
of, materials taken from the earth. These folded edges open inward – in the earth or
sea. The ultimate fold is that which folds back upon itself, as in Smithson’s Spiral
Jetty, which is at once finite and unbounded since it can be traversed backward and
forward indefinitely. But edges in earthworks can also be abrupt, as in the case of
the Jetty itself. Neither a line or a fold as such, these brute edges serve to demarcate
one elemental substance from another: say, rock from water. At the same time,
edges of/in earthworks are edges of particular places or even entire regions.
II
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
I start by considering three paintings by Edward Hopper, archetypal American realist and regionalist. Despite them being initially appealing they are also disturbing –
even “dangerous” as Wim Wenders describes one of them, “Nighthawks.”1 This is
because of their depiction of edges – in people’s lives, landscapes, and seascapes.
Take, for example, this painting of 1939, “New York Movie.” Here the interior wall
of a movie theater acts as an occluding edge that separates the usherette from the
movie patrons, allowing her the space in which to ponder her life. We know from
Hopper’s preparatory sketches that he carefully studied the inner architecture of
New York movie “palaces.” Prominent is the thick wall in the approximate middle
of the painting – in virtually every sketch, it is a dark and opaque mass, unrelieved
by decorative detail and drawn with insistent thick lines. It is as if he had been seeking
an exemplar of a kind of edge that allows human beings to keep their own space – so
as to realize their own brooding solitude.
Quite another sort of edge is present in “Nighthawks” (1942): Here the darkness
is of the night itself. Rather than a dimly illuminated theater, we are shown a garishly lit café whose light source is not depicted but which creates a clearing for the
four lonely figures who sit or stand in its glare. Edges are vanished or vanishing in
this eerie scene. The apartment buildings recede from view, while the glass window
of the café is so transparent as to be virtually non-existent. As glass, we know that
it has distinct edges; but these have melted down in the luciferous nightlight. Rather
than cutting off from view, as in the previous painting, here they provide viewing:
we see through them, rather than having to move around them as in the theater.
Once more, sketches for this emblematic work emphasize the openness of the scene:
they feature no human figures but only the outer edges of the café’s window, as if
they are frames for an otherwise unfettered seeing.
Wim Wenders, interview on audio guide at Whitney Museum of Art, Hopper Exhibition, Fall,
2006.
1
72
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
52
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
Still another variation is found in a late painting of Hopper’s: “South Carolina
Morning” (1955): We notice immediately the greater luminosity overall, thanks to
the outdoor setting and the daytime hour as well as to a higher-keyed palette and
more thinly applied paint (both characteristic of Hopper’s later work). But even
more striking is the platform in the middle space, which mediates between the
implicitly lurid enclosure of the cabin on the left (the prostitute has emerged from
there to advertise herself) and the open marshes and broad horizon. The entire
deck acts like an extended edge, left conspicuously empty to allow the daylight to
be collected in it. It becomes something like a Lichtung in Heidegger’s sense of
the term: a disclosure space in which Being appears, though in no determinate
form. As viewers of this extraordinary painting, we sense that almost anything
could occur in this open-edged place: making love in the sunlight, a murder,
whatever.
(The sinister edge is more apparent in “Nighthawks,” which is Wenders’ point:
he imagines a car driving up and hired killers coming out to shoot the patrons of
the café. The sense of threat in “South Carolina Morning” is more subtle but no
less powerful.)
I have begun with three works by Edward Hopper to show the diversity of
edge representation that can occur within the work of a single painter who is not
known for focusing on edge as such. It is as if the presence of edge is irrepressible there – as if it cannot but come forward into painting that is representational
in character. But the same is true of work that is overtly non-representational.
For instance, Picasso’s analytical cubist drawings and paintings, his collages,
and his later synthetic cubist works, feature edges in striking and highly formative ways. In effect, the figure in “Standing Female Nude” (1910), (charcoal on
paper Metropolitan Museum, NY) is nothing but edge: a series of edges (each
indicated by a single line) that stack up vertically to convey, in abstracto, the
structure of a standing figure, her out-lines or exo-skeleton. No space is left for
flesh, much less for the psychic loneliness of the usherette or the nighthawk
people or the prostitute in Hopper’s paintings. There is no room for interiority;
all has become exterior, a matter of surface – and even then, surface as deconstructed into fragments. Looking at such a sketch, one thinks of Lacan’s notion
of “le corps morcelé,” the fragmented body that precedes the mirror stage in the
human infant. As if to supplement this lack of continuity and solidity – so
noticeable in his pre-World War I works – Picasso undertook after the War a
series of collages and paintings that put the pieces back together again, literally
“synthetic” in their conception and composition. In such work one observes an
adroit presentation of edges, in this case those of the several picture planes from
which the total image is constituted. Each such plane is a surface or, better, a
“plane of immanence” in Deleuze’s term for a place where things and events can
co-exist in a vibrant co-existent union – in Picasso’s case, a wholly visual union.
All that distinguishes one such plane from another, beyond the differences in
color (and in the case of the full-fledged collages, material and texture), are the
edges that surround it: its effective outer limits, where it ends and ceases to be. At
the same time, the various planes act to occlude parts of each other. This returns
109
E.S. Casey
5 Art and Edge: Preliminary Reflections
53
us to our beginning in Hopper’s “New York Movie,” but also to this claim in
Merleau-Ponty’s “Eye and Mind”:
The enigma consists in the fact that I see things, each one in its place, precisely because
they eclipse one another, and that they are rivals before my sight precisely because each one
is in its place – in their exteriority, [they are] known through their envelopement, and their
mutual dependence [arises from] their autonomy.2
Although Merleau-Ponty is speaking of things as they relate to each other in
depth, it is clear that pictorial depth requires recession of surfaces and their overlap
in depicted space for this “illusion” to emerge. This is an illusion that is no illusion
at all, but something phenomenally present and actually seen: for such surfaces,
effecting such depth, must be girded by edges – there are no infinite surfaces in
painting. These edges act at once to define and to obscure: they reveal and yet cover
over. This double destiny is shared by edges in painting as in perception of the surrounding world.
Given that all such edges appear around (at the limit of) surfaces, they are both
self-standing and parasitic, autonomous and heteronomous. This peculiar pairing
of seemingly incommensurable traits constitutes the First Antinomy of edges in
art. If it is not resolved, it is at least understood when we keep in mind that edges
of every sort are edges of surfaces and that surfaces, as the very basis of depth
perception, must overlap and stand free of each other – the two together, one
because of the other.
III
A Second Antinomy, closely related to the First, is found in the fact that edges, so
construed, constitute a place as well as a surface. Yet, how can anything so slender
as a mere edge make up a place? Aristotle suggests that for a place to be a place, it
must have a strict “surrounder” (periechon) that is in effect its container or outer
limit. In his own words: “a body is in place if, and only if, there is a body outside it
which surrounds it… What is somewhere (pou) is both itself something and, in
addition, there must be something else besides that, in which the thing is, and which
surrounds.”3 If so, then edges will generate and maintain a place, for the body contained in that place has edges (like any physical thing).
In terms of painting, think only of the way in which Hopper presents to us not
just figures in indifferent space but as forming part of a certain very specific place – a
movie theater, a nocturnal café, a shoreline house in South Carolina. Such placement is integral to the impact of these paintings, and the edgework I have described
2
M. Merleau-Ponty, “Eye and Mind,” in The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader: Philosophy and
Painting, trans. C. Dallery, ed. G. A. Johnson (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1993), 140.
3
Aristotle, Physics 212 a 31–2; 212 b 14–16; Edward Hussey’s translation in Aristotle’s Physics,
Books III and IV (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), 29–30.
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
54
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
E.S. Casey
is constitutive of the placement itself. Edges make good places, we might say. And
the same is true for Picasso’s drawings and paintings of his entire cubist period:
these, too, put places before us. The fact that they are abstract and nameless does not
disqualify them as valid visual places. For representational and abstract artist alike,
then, placework depends on edgework.
For an even more convincing case of the collaboration of edge and place, consider the cave paintings found at Lascaux. Dating from Paleolithic times, they are
remarkably suggestive combinations of edges and places.
At least three senses of edge are at stake in works such as these edges of surface,
medium and line.
205
206
207
The rift-design is the drawing together, into a unity, of sketch and basic design, breach and
outline… What is to be brought forth, the rift, entrusts itself to the self-secluding factor that
juts up in the Open. The rift must set itself back into the heavy weight of stone…4
200
201
202
203
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
204
1. edge of the surface. These works cling precariously to, and constitute the outer
edges of, the inner linings of limestone caves. The paleo-artist took express
advantage of the contours and patterns inherent in these walls by fitting images
into their naturally given fissures and fracture lines – while also creating independent forms. The result is a dense dialectic of the found and the constituted
that observes the logic of the “rift-design,” their Riss in Heidegger’s term:
199
As rifts, the edges of the surfaces are already established by entirely natural
means – long before the creator entered the scene. As designs, however, they are
the devising of this tribally sanctioned artist or thaumaturge. The resultant edges
are a complex commixture of the given and the meant, their subtle coincidence
in a visual Deckung (in Husserl’s term for the convergence of the intended and
the provided). The scene is double-edged.
2. edge of the material medium. The first sense of edge is that of the outer surface
of the cave wall, which offers itself from below; on the basis of this offering, the
rift-design of the imagery arises upon the surface. But any particular image has
its own edge: the place where the image comes to an end.
This coincides with the termination of the paint or charcoal as the material
medium employed by the maker: its edge as such, where it gives out. Heidegger
might designate this as the Umriss, the ‘common outline’ as this term could
be translated: the rift-design, says Heidegger, brings the opposition of measure
and boundary into their common outline.”5 We can also call it the contour of the
image. It is where the material medium of the image begins and ends in a particular place. As Heidegger adds, what we call “figure, shape, Gestalt” is “thus fixed
in place.”6 The design is put into place on the obtrusive surface of the cave walls.
Martin Heidegger, “The Origin of the Work of Art,” in Poetry Language Thought, trans.
A. Hofstadter (New York: Harper & Row, 1971), 61.
5
Ibid.
6
Ibid., p. 62. My italics. Heidegger italicizes “figure, shape, Gestalt.”
4
[AU2]
5 Art and Edge: Preliminary Reflections
55
If the paradox of the first kind of edge is that it belongs both to the surface and
to the image that lies upon it, that of the second sort of edge is that it is where a
given figure simultaneously stops and starts. For it is indifferent whether our eye
moves from the external edge inwards or darts outwards to its outer limit. These
are simply two directionalities of vision which the spectator can assume at their
volition (whether the original participant in cave rites had the same visual freedom is a moot matter).
3. edge of the line as such. I say “the line as such” in order to emphasize that it is a
matter of any line, whatever exact form a given line may take: distinct and separate, continuous with a visual mass (as in a “border-line”), thick or thin, colored
or not, etc. In each case the line is itself an edge: this is the corresponding paradox of this third avatar of edge. For a given visual phenomenon of this sort is
equally well characterized as “line” or “edge.” In view of this dual characterization, the very phrase “edge of the line” becomes pleonastic, and we could just as
well speak of “the line of the edge”: i.e., the line at least implicitly formed by a
given edge. The fact is that by tracing out an edge we are very likely to produce
a line, with only rare exceptions.
This points to, if not to a coincidence between edges and lines, at least to their
extremely close alliance. I say “extremely close” and not “exactly equivalent,” as
the relationship between lines and edges is certainly reciprocal yet not precisely
symmetrical. That is to say: although every line is an edge, not every edge is linear.
Some edges are so blunted or smooth that it is difficult to find for them an adequate
linear representation (examples include cartographic symbols for the slopes of
mountains and other precipitous but non-angular geological entities: such symbols
are typically gridded or shaded in suggestive ways). But in the instance of the
images at Lascaux we witness a strong overlap between edges and lines: the pictorial line not only represents the edges of animals or humans: it is their edge,
embodying and materializing them. It is perceived as both the edge of a recognizable figure and the line that presents that edge, the two interfusing in a single act of
perceptual recognition.
A corollary is that edges as lines are not just depictive but in effect “lines of
flight” – once more in Deleuze and Guattari’s term for that aspect of lines that carries
with it a special vectorial directionality – an intentionality of the line, as it were, by
which it seems to aim itself somewhere in particular and at a certain non-quantifiable
velocity, and that opens whole new dimensions by their energetic trajectories. Such
lines deterritorialize space itself: “Each advances like a wave, but on the plane of
consistency they are a single abstract Wave whose vibration propages following a
line of flight or deterritorialization traversing the entire plane [of consistency].”7
Without pretending to understand fully this dense statement – which would require
a careful discussion of what “dimension” and “deterritorialization” signify – we can
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans.
B. Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), 252.
7
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
56
E.S. Casey
273
agree that lines of force are not merely delineative or depictive, that is, they are not
“representational” in the sense of being pictorial icons of certain pre-existing actualities. They have their own élan – their own vitality. Which is just what so many
experience in viewing the animal and human figures at Lascaux even if these are
conveyed solely by photographic images (the cave is now closed to direct viewing).
These figures are not so much “life-like” (that is, accurately representational) as
beings in vital movement, seemingly generated by the very lines by which they are
drawn or painted – which is to say, by their bare edges: edges in full flight.
274
IV
267
268
269
270
271
272
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
In truth, the paleolithic caves were among the first earthworks – along with the earth
mounds in Ohio and the Nazca Lines in Peru (which, in their quasi-geometric form,
are composed of pure edges). But these ways of being edge were abandoned, lost to
the world, and only rediscovered by chance many millenia later. (Lascaux was
chanced upon by two boys in 1940.) But the very idea of an earthwork was to be
revived, and quite recently. In an extraordinary move in the art world of New York,
Robert Smithson and others began to create their own earthworks, partly with an eye
on the ancient world but mostly in a spirit of raw innovation that was spurred by a
rebellion against the art market of the 1960s in its passion for minimal and pop art
(itself a rebellion against the abstract expressionism of the 1950s).
What is different in the new earthworks is that they were not set exclusively
within the internal folds of the earth as at Lascaux. Now the fold of the work folded
outward, ex-posing itself to the public, whether in a brightly lit gallery or in a wholly
natural setting such as a desert under the bright eye of the sun. In either case, we
have to do with an open scene – a scene of exposure in the light.
Suggested here is the term “Open” from Heidegger, who finds an alliance
between the Open and the notion of rift-design discussed earlier. In another passage
from “The Origin of the Work of Art,” he writes this: “As the earth takes the rift
back into itself, the rift is first set forth into the Open and thus placed, that is, set,
within that which towers up into the Open as self-closing and sheltering.”8 The idea
here is not just that something previously concealed is now revealed – brought into
the light of day. Rather, it is that that which, as belonging to earth, is inherently
withdrawn is brought forward in its very self-seclusion – put into the Open in its
own unopenness: “What is to be brought forth, the rift, entrusts itself to the selfsecluding factor that juts up into the Open.”9 If we read “rift” as edge, we have the
following formula: the edge that is brought forth brings with it a factor of selfseclusion that is shown as such in the work of art.
266
8
9
“The Origin of the Work of Art,” p. 61.
Ibid.
5 Art and Edge: Preliminary Reflections
57
This powerful and particular way in which artworks enter the Open – or still better,
“the openness of the Open,” as Heidegger also puts it10 – can certainly occur in
painting. One thinks of El Greco’s “View of Toledo” as a case in point.
In this earth-painting, we witness the earth opening itself to the sky from out of
its very depths. Its depths are on its surface, as Wittgenstein might say. But it remains
a two-dimensional work in which the pictorial surface, the picture plane, is resolutely two-dimensional, however rich its visual contents. What is different about
earth-works, ancient or recent, is the fact that the solidity, the very volume, of the
earth comes forward on its own account as it were. Otherwise put, the place that
such works constitute is a place no longer represented somewhere else, say, Toledo,
Spain, or the island of Patmos (where St. John lived in a cave), to which we would
have to travel in fact or in fantasy, but a place that our own body can occupy or at
least circumnavigate. The earthwork invites us into its own space, whether this be
the underground space of a limestone cave or that of an earth mound we can walk
around. The place they constitute has room, a word that connotes an openness of the
spatial such that a lived body can occupy it, however briefly.
Take, for example, the early earthworks of Robert Smithson. He had collected
rough rocks in New Jersey to exhibit in New York, sometimes simply dumped on
the floor of a gallery and sometimes encased in wood containers that act as threedimensional frames. These frames are in turn located on gallery floors, in turn set
within the walls of the gallery space:
A work such as this is meant not just to be seen as would a painting attached to a
wall but circumambulated. In fact, the latter is virtually irresistible. The whole body
of the viewer, and not just the optical system, is engaged, including touch, given the
very strong temptation to reach out and stroke the stone. This engagement is not just
of the body taken in isolation but of the body in place. The gallery goer is conscious
of being in a room in which the work is set: more so than when viewing a painting,
since the action of walking around the work is a condensed or schematic retracing
of the enclosed space of the room itself – its own rift-design, as in Heidegger’s original
description: “it is a basic design, an outline sketch, that draws the basic features of
the rise of the lighting of beings.”11 Now the design or sketch takes the form of
spontaneous bodily movements.
As if to reinforce these bodily-placial-roomful movements, Smithson often
included a map in these early earthworks – as if the cartographic image attached to
the work might guide the ambulations of the gallery goer.
In another phase of his earthworks, Smithson contrasted two versions of the same
basic form, the spiral. One of these was highly geometric, as in “Gyrostasis” (1968).
This is a piece of steel sculpture and thus in three dimensions; but its major
importance for Smithson was to suggest, in its formal shape, a contour that he
wished to inscribe in the earth, with materials drawn from the earth itself, and not
“The openness of this Open, that is, truth, can be what it is, namely, this openness, only if and as
long as it establishes itself within its Open.” (Ibid., p. 59; his italics).
11
“The Origin of the Work of Art,” p. 61.
10
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
58
E.S. Casey
361
362
363
The shore of the lake became the edge of the sun, a boiling curve, an explosing rising into
fiery prominence. Matter collapsing into the lake irried in the shape of a spiral. No sense
wondering about classsifications and categories, there were none.15
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
360
constrained by any precise geometry. He wished to embed the spiral in the earth – or
rather, that part of the earth designated as a salt lake: to consider is “as a crystallized
fragment of a gyroscopic rotation, or as an abstracta three dimensional map that
points to the SPIRAL JETTY, 1970, in the Great Salt Lake, Utah.”12 Hence the genesis of his most famous earthwork
Spiral Jetty arises from the placid surface of a remote corner of the Great Salt Lake
in Utah in an abrupt set of stones, now coated white in their salt coating. The spiral
itself is broad enough to be traversed, and invites the visitor to do so – again and again,
in an ever-narrowing circumambulation. The first-hand experience of the Jetty sets
forth (in Smithson’s own words) “the elemental in things.”13 Or rather, the elemental
in place, the place of the earthwork itself, an Open turning away from the water and
toward the sky as their pivot. The folding of the spiral, arising from earth’s “stony
essence,” un-folds toward the cerulean heights. Thus it “towers up into the Open as the
self-closing and sheltering.”14 It brings elemental things of the earth – the very rocks
that make up the interior of caves – into this Open but only as still retaining the intrinsic enclosedness of stone, whose interior is closed in each and every case.
Differently regarded, the Spiral Jetty places one set of edges over against another:
those of the Jetty contrasted with the edge of the shore from which its first and outer
spiral extends. As Smithson put it himself:
342
Let us say that Smithson is here creating not just “the elemental in things” but an
elemental edge that belongs to earth, lake, and sky – all at once and through the
same three-dimensional gyrostatic rift-design. Such an edge is made of elements
and is to be experienced through them, and by a body that is moving in a place – a
place that did not pre-exist the creation of the earthwork itself but arose from it and
is re-created in each re-traversal by a visitor to its site. Smithson himself demonstrated the way this happens in a film that shows him walking to the tip of the Spiral
and then back to its base in a rapid set of movements that seems to increase in speed
with time.
Thanks to such body movements that constitute genuine lines of flight across the
surface of the Great Salt Lake, we can see how Smithson’s earthwork is simultaneously
primitive and contemporary. As he put it with characteristic archness: in the Spiral Jetty
“the prehistoric meets the posthistoric,” for in this work he has made “a map that would
show the prehistoric world as co-extensive with the world [I] existed in.”16 Between
Cited in Edward S. Casey, Earth-Mapping: Artists Re-shaping Landscape (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 2005), 19.
13
Cited in Earth-Mapping, p. 7.
14
Ibid., p. 61.
15
Cited in Earth-Mapping, p. 18.
16
Cited in Earth-Mapping, p. 24.
12
[AU3]
5 Art and Edge: Preliminary Reflections
59
Lascaux and the Spiral Jetty we come a long way: half way around the earth, and over
most of known human history (from circa 20, 000 B.C. to 1970 A.D.). We move
between two kinds of Open, two sorts of earthwork that occur as edgeworks, each with
its own form of folding and distinctive genius of rift-design and each providing a place
for the viewer’s active bodily engagement.
V
379
380
381
382
383
I have been bringing art not just to its particular edges – ranging from Hopper’s
comparatively circumspect edges to Smithson’s wilder ones – but art to its own
edge. Just as David Wood writes about “Thinking at the Limit,”17 so I’ve been trying
to take art to its limit – to that particular limit called “edge” in English. (“Limit,”
you see, is the supreme genus for edge itself: another future investigation.)
I began with Jackson Pollock’s warning that in art there are, strictly speaking,
“no limits, only edges.” Pollock had it right: limits are further out than edges;
they serve best as conditions or contexts or containers; no wonder they become
such primary terms in epistemology and metaphysics – as we see most markedly
with Kant’s emphasis on “the limits of reason alone.” Edges are better suited for
experiencing and understanding the art world, for they are the outermost extensions of things, where their external surfaces end (and, sometimes, where their
inner surfaces intersect). Artists, including earth artists, labor at getting edges to
work, bringing the surface of the canvas to a certain kind of formal perfection,
attempting to complete the earthwork by attending to its outer surface once the
materials have been put into place. In the wake of Pollock’s inspired remark, I
am saying this: artwork is edgework. All artists, in one fashion or another, are
working at the edge – putting themselves on the edge and drawing us as appreciators into that same edge once established.
The plot thickens, however, when we take account of the two antinomies I earlier
identified. That of surface and edge – how can surfaces constitute edges? This is the
question that Hopper’s work raised for us. It was resolved by reference to various
artists from Paleos to Picasso, each of whom made of the pictorial surface a tapestry
of edges, whether those of animals and hunters engaged in a ritual of chase and
death or those of a deconstructed cubist female figure. In the end, we saw that edges
are essential to many, if not all, sketched or painted surfaces, either by way of their
out-lines (the edge of the page or canvas; the frame) or their even more constitutive
in-lines (those that define the identity and limits of that which is presented, or represented, on the picture plane of the art work).
The other antinomy, that of place and edge, took still more of our attention as we
strove to think of edges of voluminous things, fully rounded human bodies and
17
378
This is the first chapter in David Wood, Thinking After Heidegger (Cambridge: Polity, 2002).
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
60
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
roomy places in which these bodies move. Certain paintings are on the very edge of
this antinomy yet they still hang on the wall of some museum and offer us a flat
surface to observe. It may be a painting of a particular place – yet it does not give us
a place itself, just as it does not engage our bodies fully in its apprehension. For
these two things to happen, and for the antinomy of place and edge to be more completely explored, we have to move to earthworks.
Smithson’s Spiral Jetty is emblematic of the intimate relationship of body,
place, and edge in art. It does not just suggest that we are at the edge of water; to
take it in, we must put ourselves at the actual edge of an actual body of water, the
Great Salt Lake. It is a work in a particular place; or more exactly, it constitutes a
place in that place, fold or pocket within it. Once there, we are drawn, irresistibly,
to walk its spiral arm and the helical shape keeps us on the edge of water as
we wend our way inward. The enclosing frame of the painting is replaced by the
opening of the environment: standing on the Jetty, one looks out across the Lake,
one sees around in an act of literal circum-spection that mirrors and extends the
circumambulation of one’s walking body on the rocks of the Spiral itself. The
limits of this place are far out, even if its edges are held closely within – within
the body that moves on the outer surface of the work that is in turn set within a
larger landscape world.
415
E.S. Casey
*
*
*
*
*
*
Even if we are not coming to the end of art as Hegel thought, we are at least coming to its edges here. By this I mean that art emerges in its edges. It occurs in other
ways as well – for instance, as event and boundary. But when we emphasize edges
in art, we take up aspects that have been neglected for the most part in aesthetics and
art theory: aspects such as fold and surface, ambulation and room, and above all
place. Art as place signifies art as edge – and vice versa, edge as art: an instance of
“reversibility” in Merleau-Ponty’s term (though his leading instance is the reversibility of the visible and the invisible, rather than art and edge).
And the earth in all this? Rilke identified earth and invisibility: “O Earth!
Invisible! What, if not transformation, is your urgent command?”18 How to make
you visible once again in art? Perhaps Merleau-Ponty was pointing to the right path
for us after all. Earth is certainly not origin or source alone; much less is it sheer
material mass only; it is something closer to the “self-secluding,” a close cousin of
the invisible. I have been arguing, after Heidegger, that it is just as such, as withholding itself, that earth comes into the Open. Otherwise put, it is as a deep matrix
that it comes forward in the elemental edges that are such prominent features of
earthworks and of certain paintings such as those of El Greco. These are edges that
18
Rainer Maria Rilke, “The Ninth Elegy,” in The Selected Poetry of Rainer Maria Rilke, ed. Stephen
Mitchell (New York: Vintage Books, 1980).
5 Art and Edge: Preliminary Reflections
61
exist between identifiable things – such as objects and persons – and that allow them
to be demarcated from each other, thus to be differ-entiated in a sufficiently rich
sense of this past participle.
Kant proclaimed that “nature makes itself specific,”19 and if so this happens all
the time in the differ-entiation effected by edges: all the time in nature, but also all
the time in art as “second nature.” Once we move beyond regarding edges as occlusive or obtrusive, we shall be able to embrace them openly – as if for the first time,
with philosophical open arms which match those we extend to works of art that
surprise and delight us by their novelty and vigor.
19
Immanuel Kant, First Introduction to the Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 1987), 403 (Ak. 20: 215).
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
Author Queries
Chapter No.: 5
0001327763
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please confirm chapter title.
AU2
Opening double quotes is missing in the sentence starting
“Heidegger might ....” Please check.
AU3
Should “classsification” be changed to “classification” in the
quoted text. Please check.
Queries
Chapter 6
1
From Reflection to Refraction: On Bordwell’s
Cinema and the Viewing Event
2
3
John Mullarkey
4
6.1
5
Introduction
From his early 1985 work, Narration in the Fiction Film, through to the more recent
The Way Hollywood Tells It (2006), David Bordwell has persistently argued for one
filmic constant: that there is an enduring style of ‘classical narration’ originally
created by and subsequently sustained through Hollywood film-making. It is a
narrative style composed of individualised character-psychology, local agency as
primary plot motivator, cause and effect logic, and canonical story-telling (from
equilibrium through disequilibrium to a new equilibrium). This consistent style can
even be found in contemporary Hollywood concept films and blockbusters, despite
their increasingly exotic plotting, cinematography, acting, and editing. Moreover,
other modes of narrative, especially those of the modern European ‘art film’, are
equally defined and characterised by Bordwell in relation to this abiding Hollywood
norm. Whereas Hollywood cinema has always had a realist trajectory, European
film, since the 1950s at least, has mostly been reflexive, being less about the world
than about itself, about the nature of film per se (Jean-Luc Godard’s work being the
prime example of this).
It is the purpose of this short essay to muddy these waters by showing how neither
Hollywood nor European cinema have ever been so consistent, because any putative
realism and reflexivity are insubstantial, temporal forms: whether a film is classical
or avant-garde is a product less of the film than of its relationship with a viewing
audience. Such temporal tags as ‘classical’, ‘modern’, or even ‘postmodern’ are
themselves contextual rather than absolute, depending on the ‘audience’ (in the
J. Mullarkey (*)
Kingston University, London, UK
e-mail: J.Mullarkey@kingston.ac.uk
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_6, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
63
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
64
J. Mullarkey
30
largest sense of the word) a film receives. The impact of film is not located solely in
the film but also in its viewing event – the time and place where it is viewed, who is
viewing it, and how it is viewed. Each of these contextual variables of where, when,
who, and how, refract the pure dualism of realism versus reflexivity.
31
6.2
28
29
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
Bordwell on Classical Cinema: Hurray for Hollywood
Of the core tenets of Bordwell’s approach to cinema, the key one is the centrality of
the Classical Hollywood style of narration. The clear use of events and actors; individuated characters who are psychologically rather than socially motivated; linear
chains of cause and effect; the division between main and secondary plots; the use
of mostly unrestricted narration, itself structured with a beginning, middle and end;
the provision of a proper (often happy) resolution at the end; and the use of continuity
editing: all of these principles are firmly rooted in the Hollywood mode of filmmaking such that even the more experimental strategies of plot and style, found in
recent Hollywood output, actually only deviate from the norm at their margins.
Indeed, even their deviations have precedents in the Hollywood norm, the peculiar
use of extended travelling shots in Gus Van Sant’s Elephant (2003), for example,
being already pre-figured in films by ‘Max Ophuls, Stanley Kubrick, or the Alfred
Hitchcock of Rope (1948) and Under Capricorn (1949).’1
The Hollywood style of telling stories with ‘classical continuity’ is the rule
against which other kinds of cinema, like the 1960s Art Film, for instance, characterised themselves: ‘art-cinema narration has become a coherent mode partly by
defining itself as a deviation from classical narrative.’2 Jean-Luc Godard’s adage
that films should have a beginning, a middle and an end (though not necessarily in
that order), gives some indication as to how that artful margin deviates from the
norm for Bordwell too. If one doesn’t follow the well-established laws for creating
a ‘fabula world’ – flouting ‘the most common assumptions, the most valid inferences, the most provable hypotheses, and the most appropriate schemas’ – then one
is in the realm of self-conscious art. But even art has its norms, be they extrinsic to
the particular film (as part of the art genre), or intrinsic to it (as what it builds up
gradually during its own development). In other words, a norm-breaking film can’t
break every norm – the art film too must abide by some norms: if ‘every card is wild
you can’t play cards at all’.3
27
David Bordwell, The Way Hollywood Tells It: Story and Style in Modern Movies (University of
California Press, 2006), 119: ‘What has changed, in both the most conservative registers and the
most adventurous ones, is not the stylistic system of classical filmmaking but rather certain technical devices functioning within that system. The new devices very often serve the traditional
purposes. And the change hasn’t been radical.’
2
David Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film (London: Routledge, 1987), 228.
3
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, pp. 80, 39, 151.
1
6 From Reflection to Refraction: On Bordwell’s Cinema and the Viewing Event
65
A specific example of Bordwell’s approach to art cinema can be seen in his
analysis of Godard’s Tout va bien (1972), though he might easily have chosen any
one of Godard’s works. He alights immediately on the Brechtian elements of the
film, especially in regard to the film’s dilemma of a left-wing film-maker having to
work within a Capitalist film industry.4 In particular, Godard uses the Brechtian
‘principles of separation’ to describe how the audience of Tout Va Bien is prevented
‘from being wholly absorbed in the illusionary aspects of the action’. These principles heighten the viewers’ awareness of the artificiality of the film that they are
actually watching, and so block any tendency they may have to naturalise its depictions as genuine realities. In this reflexivity, therefore, it is a typical art-film. It is a
film about watching (a) film. Seeing that the reality depicted in a film is an effect
allows us also to imagine alternative realities. It awakens in us the possibility of
thinking about ourselves historically, the contingency of the status quo (the ‘everything’s fine’ that is just a surface effect), and so the possibility of change.
In all, Tout Va Bien uses three principles of separation in its narrative – interruption,
contradiction, and refraction. Here is what they mean. In a classical (Hollywood)
film, the cause and effect chain of narrative links scene to scene, ‘thoroughly’ motivating each event. Interrupting this cause and effect series functions to confuse us
as to the relation between one event and another. Yet such interruptions are common
in Tout Va Bien, as with Susan’s interview with the factory women, which is interrupted by another worker singing a radical song, or when Susan confronts Jacques
with her dissatisfaction with their relationship, which is interrupted with scenes of
their working lives.5 We soon lose the plot or ‘narrative causality’ because of these
interruptions. Secondly, contradictions arise when discontinuous editing is used to
create spatial and temporal ambiguity, as when Susan sits down twice to begin her
confrontation with Jacques at breakfast. Mismatches between visuals and soundtrack (often we hear a voice but don’t see the character’s mouth move) have a similar
effect. But of the various modes of separation, it is the third of refraction that both
stands apart and subsumes the prior two. It is defined as what
…draws our attention to media that stand between the depicted events and our perception
of those events. We do not seem to see a series of ‘natural’ events, as we might in a
Hollywood style film. Rather, Tout Va Bien takes the media as part of its topic.6
Refraction works explicitly on various levels: in terms of the plot (Susan and
Jacques both work in the media industries of film and radio); in terms of the narration (some of the film’s voice-over narration is provided by factory-workers, some
by a broadcaster, emphasising how the narration itself is ‘arbitrarily selective, even
capricious’); and in terms of symbolism (the mode of production of the media is
clearly compared with that of a meat factory). Yet refraction can also be said to
subsume contradiction and interruption given that these two phenomena, in their
This analysis was written in collaboration with Kristin Thompson in Film Art: An Introduction,
fourth international edition (McGraw-Hill, 1993), 437.
5
Bordwell and Thompson, p. 438.
6
Bordwell and Thompson, p. 439.
4
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
66
J. Mullarkey
118
119
120
…in analysing typical art-cinema or parametric narratives Bordwell only seems to want to
rationalise them. Radical cinema is reduced to principles, systems, all towards trying to
bring artistic cinema into the rational fold of classic cinema.10
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
117
own way, alert us to the artificiality of the medium by breaking with its conventions
of seamless editing, synchronous sound, and cause-effect plotting. (Or so it appears.)
As Bordwell puts it: ‘the emphasis on Tout Va Bien as a “film about cinema” makes
refraction an overriding principle as well.’7 And, commensurately, this use of refraction is what makes Godard the ‘art-cinema’ filmmaker – his ‘authorial presence
hovering over the text’, the ‘superauteur’ playing cinema.8
As a refractive film, Tout Va Bien breaks the rules in Hollywood in typical fashion, for this knowing transgression marks it out as ‘art-house’. If there wasn’t the
norm, there could be no disobedience to the norm. Admittedly, Bordwell does seem
on the point of conceding something more intrinsic to the art film when he discusses
Roland Barthes’ idea of a ‘third meaning’ beyond denotation and connotation comprised of ‘casual lines, colors, expressions, and textures’.9 These are what Bordwell’s
colleague, Kristen Thompson, calls ‘excess’ materials. Art equals excess. Yet
Bordwell admits that he is not interested in such excess, only in the central ‘process
of narration’. Some have argued, however that the division of filmic material into
norm and transgression is illegitimate, and, moreover, disrupts the idea of a central
process of narration outside of which an excess can be isolated. The art of film saturates every part of it. Yet the taming of the aesthetic dimension of cinema, be it in
terms of transgression or excess, is absolutely necessary when trying to isolate and
essentialise particular forms of narration. As Daniel Frampton notes:
98
The inherent aspects of an ‘art film’ really are inherent and are not just relative
to the classical norm.11 And their ‘excess’ is not gratuitously exotic either, but must
be understood as a different form of realism. Yet these are not thoughts that
Bordwell is willing to support. Claims by the filmmakers themselves that new
forms of realism are being innovated through film are dismissed by him as attempts
to ‘justify novelty’ and cultivate ambiguity. The real offering of the art film is to
inform the spectator of its reflexivity – it is a meta-level communication only: ‘put
crudely, the procedural slogan of art-cinema narration might be: “interpret this
film, and interpret it so as to maximize ambiguity”.’12 For a science of film such as
Bordwell’s, therefore, ambiguity in film cannot be realistic because life really is
clear cut. If there is any ambiguity, then it must be because the film is saying something about itself.
Bordwell and Thompson, p. 441.
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 332.
9
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 54.
10
Daniel Frampton, Filmosophy (London: Wallflower Press, 2006), 104.
11
Frampton, p. 108: ‘Following Bordwell we might just get analyses of stylistically innovative
films as simply deformed or abnormal’.
12
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, pp. 206, 212.
7
8
6 From Reflection to Refraction: On Bordwell’s Cinema and the Viewing Event
6.3
67
From Reflection to Refraction
133
Let us consider this rendering of film a little further. The very opening of Tout Va
Bien enters us into a realm of apparent reflexivity created through repetition: we
hear the recurrence of the spoken title of the film while being shown images of endless cheques being writing to cover the production expenses for this film. The form
of repetition supposedly reflects the content’s own reflexive nature – showing us
how a movie is made. Yet one can also see that, at another level, there is a new content created for an audience inured to this effect (which doesn’t take very long in
this particular case): this film becomes a film about making other films. After all,
who believes that the actual cheques for the film were signed in just this manner,
when the signatory already has a film-camera hovering over his shoulder recording
the act? The signatures become a performance, no matter how subtle, and so a sign
of another reality (how films are made) rather than that reality itself – the actual film
being made. In other words, this film’s attempt to reflect on itself is itself refracted
such that it remains outside of its own reflection and misses its original target (itself):
what we see is a film that is really about making (political) films. The ‘really about’
or referentiality of the film is not a failing on Godard’s part, but stems from the
tendency of any audience to naturalise what it sees over time. Presumably Godard
did hope to highlight the artificial, constructed, and economic nature of his own
creation, and yet, in doing so, he, or the film-and-audience, does eventually refer to
something real, viz., the naturalising, alienation effects of either film-making in general
or other particular films. Alternatively, perhaps this is all that Godard wanted – to
say something about other films. If that is the case, though, then perhaps we should
also try to rethink Bordwell’s depiction of self-reference in the realm of avant-garde
film (and with that, the classical realism in Hollywood’s output too).
Of course, the possibility that art-films are not about themselves (and thus, by
proxy, about Hollywood or classicism) but about other realities, cannot be countenanced by Bordwell. He dismisses their redefinition of the real with scare quotes
and condescension: their ‘new aesthetic conventions claim to seize other “realities”:
the aleatoric world of “objective” reality and the fleeting states that characterize
“subjective” reality.’ Claims for a new realism on the part of artistic filmmakers, like
Alain Resnais for instance, are subverted by having their “realism” (in scare quotes
again) downgraded as ‘wholly arbitrary’.13 Yet, as Stanley Cavell for one notes,
Godard’s strange camera movements in Contempt (1967), for instance, while making
‘an original and deep statement of the camera’s presence’ are also ‘about its subjects, about their simultaneous distance and connection, about the sweeping desert
of weary familiarity.’14 These films are not essentially rebuffs to Hollywood – they
are also real.
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 219. He is referring to La guerre est fini here.
Stanley Cavell, The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film, Enlarged Edition
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979), 129.
13
14
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
68
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
This reality is not something that is localisable, however, in either some subjective
world (where Bordwell places art) nor an objective world (where he places the hardwired cerebral dispositions that underwrite Hollywood’s versions of realism). It is in
the relationship between all the phases of the film process in as much as, through the
process of time itself, they each can become real. In and of themselves, though, each
phase is as real or unreal as the next. There are conventions for producing, distributing
and consuming films that are conventions, symbols or metaphors that we have
become inured to, that we have forgotten were conventions, symbols or metaphors.
As Paul Douglass notes, everything about cinema was once an ‘oddity’ that has now
lost its strangeness with time, from the two degrees angle of vision that it presents us
(of our normal 200-degrees of vision), to all the other perspectivist conventions that
we have internalised through repeated exposure.15 Likewise, the interruptions and
contradictions that Bordwell’s own work analyses in Godard are just a more recent
set of distortions of time and space. But such distortions are not new, as Bordwell
knows, pointing to Jacques Tati’s amazing ability in Playtime (1968) to present 6 h
of story time in just 45 min of screen time, even though he uses continuity cuts
throughout.16 Even more bizarrely, Andy Warhol’s supposedly real-time films, like
Empire (1964), were actually taken to be avant-garde on account of their ultra-realism,
that is, their continuity, regarding time. Indeed, the consequent question arises automatically: when has a film ever represented real, continuous time?
The answer, of course, is ‘never’, but not because film lacks the ability to capture real time so much as film itself being just one instance of the myriad forms of
time: there is no pure continuous time to capture, or rather, real time just is the host
of different kinds of time being continuously made. Continuity versus discontinuity
or ellipsis is a false opposition when time actually comes in different varieties,
when there is no one ‘objective’ time that can be taken as bedrock. The ellipsis is
there in every film, only in some it has been normalised to seem real and continuous
on account of the conventions of cutting internalised by the spectator. Most classical
(that is, unreflexive) films are incredibly elliptical in their treatment of time –
abbreviating conversations, actions, travel times, and so forth. They also lengthen
time when necessary (think only of any action film where we count down to the
171
J. Mullarkey
See Paul Douglass, “Bergson and Cinema: Friends or Foes?,” in The New Bergson, ed. John
Mullarkey (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1999), 209–227: p. 216: ‘The “key-hole
effect” of the very tight shot maximises awareness of this limitation, which does not disappear as
the shot widens – rather, it becomes simply less occlusive, leaving us less consciously aware of our
dependence upon the camera’s movement to disclose what lies out of frame. As [William] Wees
says, the peculiar thing is how desensitised audiences are to film’s distortions: “The situation has
become so thoroughly institutionalised that the dominant cinema, its audiences, and most critics
who write about it happily accept perspectivist norms”.’ Conversely, it is now said that Imax is not
good for narrative (faces are too large, cuts must be limited, there cannot be too much movement,
close-ups are too grainy, and the overall effect is nauseating). But the same was said of Cinemascope
at first – no doubt we’ll get over it.
16
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 82.
15
6 From Reflection to Refraction: On Bordwell’s Cinema and the Viewing Event
69
bomb exploding in 60 s – it usually takes much longer than that). Films also shorten
and lengthen spaces through the intercutting of long, medium and close-up shots,
shot-reverse shots, and so on. But the supposed seamlessness of such editing is an
acquired, that is learnt, convention that has become the sign of reality.
Though Bordwell obviously knows that the classical norms of editing are not
actually continuous, his treatment of their transgression by ‘art films’ belies the
presupposition that they are. I quote:
These … factors go some way to explaining why the classical Hollywood style passes relatively unnoticed. Each film will recombine familiar devices within fairly predictable patterns and according to the demands of the syuzhet. The spectator will almost never be at a
loss to grasp a stylistic feature because he or she is oriented in time and space and because
stylistic figures will be interpretable in the light of a paradigm.17
But how does this orientation in ‘time and space’ succeed? Is it because it conforms to the natural, Euclidean space of our everyday surroundings, or because it
conforms to habituated forms of space and time that were once, nonetheless, inventions? Bordwell opts for the former view, taking realism to be some variant of the
neo-classical unities of space, time, and action (with distinct cause and effect).18
When it comes to Godard’s famous discontinuities, for example, they yield ‘the
impression that footage has been excised from within a shot. …[but] the device
signals one thing unequivocably: the intervention of the filmmaker at the editing
stage.’19 Art as reflexive again.
Yet many supposedly conventional action films today use both elliptical and
overlapping editing (repeating part or all of an event, like an explosion, by showing
it multiple times from different angles – an especially popular Hollywood import
from Hong Kong cinema). But does the target audience or these films, adolescent
American males, believe that there were five events instead of one when exposed to
overlapping cuts? Of course not. Do the filmmakers worry that this recurrent editing
will jar with the serial editing of the rest of their films? Obviously not, because they
are both as equally ‘real’ as each other. What were once the hallmarks of experimental or avant-garde cinema have been domesticated as real, despite their huge
deviations from previous versions of real or continuous editing. These devices no
longer serve to reflect, but now, even in adult cinema, to forward the story. The jump
cuts used throughout Thomas Vinterberg’s Festen (1998) or sporadically in Martin
Scorcese’s Taxi Driver (1976), for example, neither impede the narrative nor signal
the author’s presence: in both cases they propel the story forward and possess huge
expressive powers. The fact that Festen can ‘get away’ with so much discontinuity
is because it expresses the highly strung, enervated, and neurotic nature of the characters and situations, as well as how much we have been inured to the oddity of
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 164. My emphasis.
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, pp. 157, 158: ‘Spatial configurations are motivated by
realism (a newspaper office must contain desks, typewriters, phones) and, chiefly, by compositional necessity).’
19
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 328.
17
18
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
70
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
jump cuts. Indeed, the commercial success and normality of the ‘independent’ films
of 1990s, which appropriated everything they could from European art-house
cinema of the 1960s and 1970s, is a testament to how well popular audiences have
internalised and naturalised the artistic style as a new realism.
Even as regards causal logic, it too is a mutable category. According to Bordwell,
the causal chain is typically broken in art films such as Michelangelo Antonioni’s
L’Avventura (1960), where the crucial search for a lost woman eventually drops out
of the plot as the story meanders to a inconclusive finale: when ‘the recovery of
Anna is no longer the causal nexus of the action’, we have a ‘loosening of causal
relations’.20 Leaving aside the fact that most Hollywood searches are pretexts for
adventure (Hitchcock called their objects ‘MacGuffins’), in the strict terms of ostensible cause and effect, ‘what happens next’ rarely follows a linear mode, or rather,
what counts as a linear pursuit is always an acquired taste depending on the film and
its audience. Films like Roman Polanski’s Frantic (1988) and Paul Schrader’s
Hardcore (1979) are both classical in many ways, yet they also renege on their
ostensive search in favour of other narrative pleasures. The search-object is a pretext
for journey-entertainments (Frantic) and/or education (Hardcore). Like L’Avventura,
both films have a man and a woman searching together for another missing woman,
a man’s wife and daughter respectively. The major difference is that in L’Avventura
the search ostensibly ends while in the others it does not (indeed, they are ultimately
successful). Yet the non-search pleasures, as we know from the genre-conventions
of this kind of film, are central (these are films about what happens when you don’t
find what you’re looking for). In Frantic, for instance, the sexual frisson between
Richard and Michelle (especially during their dance at the club), the physical comedy of Richard (knocking his head twice in the interior of the barge where they hold
up afterwards), and the situation-comedy created by Michelle (whose inopportune
avarice leads to further capers and danger) – all these joys are narratively motivated
by the genre (the search that is not a search). By the end, one wonders whether the
pair really ought to find his wife Sondra (and whether the fact that he does find her
is not a inconclusive ending for the film). It is not so much that cause and effect are
totally absent, but that this is a different type of genre-causality, one often motivated
by a regular, rather lifeless man encountering either a femme fatale or muse that
inspires him into a new life of adventure: Peter Bogdanovich’s What’s Up Doc?
(1972) and Jonathan Demme’s Something Wild (1986) evince this type of causality
too, but so does, in its own way, L’Avventura.
The fact that Antonioni’s is serious and European does not render it any less
‘realistic’ than Hollywood-output. The meanderings in these films are examples of
what Jacques Rancière describes as movements ‘deflected by the imposition of
another movement’ (rather than movements brought to a ‘fictional end’).21 There is
always movement, only sometimes of a different, more adventurous kind. Conversely,
240
J. Mullarkey
20
21
Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 207.
Jacques Rancière, Film Fables, trans. Emiliano Battista (Oxford: Berg, 2006), 13.
6 From Reflection to Refraction: On Bordwell’s Cinema and the Viewing Event
71
we should also recall that Michael Curtiz, whilst directing the Hollywood classic,
Casablanca (1942), reassured those with doubts as regards the film’s illogical storyline with the following disclaimer: ‘don’t worry what’s logical. I make it so fast no
one notices.’22 He knew how important time is to belief, not simply as regards masking an illogic with speed, so much as creating a new logic with time. Paraphrasing
Nietzsche on truth and metaphor, we might say that continuity (like space, time, and
causality) is a worn out, forgotten ellipse. Or as Christian Metz writes: ‘what is
experienced as a simple figure of speech today was quite frequently, for the first
spectators of the cinematograph, a magic “trick,” a small miracle both futile and
astonishing.’23
6.4
Conclusion: Towards the Viewing Event
In sum, I cannot think of any contravention of a so-called norm of film-making that
cannot itself become a sign of reality. The formalistic transgressions of Tout Va
Bien, far from only and ever alienating us from an identification with its ostensible
characters’ and narrative’s motivations (by short-circuiting any reality-effects), have
become but one other set of conventions for creating a message or depicting a reality
(however strange it might be at first glance). Any one convention can come to mean,
because form refracts through its associated content to create a different, though
affiliated, content. And this ‘coming to mean’ is processual, because form and content is not a fixed duality but a dynamic tension of entities in continual exchange. In
other words, we must not forget to think of the viewing context when assessing any
film. By that, I don’t simply mean the audience in isolation from the film (and
embedded instead within its own separate social and economic sphere), but the
audience in relation to the concrete context of the viewing event. The viewing event
mutates with time and must be thought ‘historically’ (as Godard would say): we
learn to read some of the formal incongruities encountered in avant-garde cinema
as expressive of content, we can immerse ourselves in a film, no matter how abstract,
because the ‘reality-effect’ is not the sadistic power of a film over us, but an
exchange, refraction, or mixture within any one viewing event between audience
and film. In other words, no method of separation or distancing is guaranteed its
effect for long, because, with time, its novelty dissipates. To make the point even
more striking, lens-flare – an artefact of ‘conventional’ film-making that was once
avoided but eventually became a stylistic cliché of the 1960s and 1970s – is these
days reproduced artificially in animation (both CGI and non-CGI) and computer
software games. It is a token of realism. It has become what Baudrillard would call
22
Cited in Richard Maltby, ‘“A Brief Romantic Interlude”: Dick and Jane Go to 3 1/2 Seconds of
the Classical Hollywood Cinema’, in Post-Theory: Reconstructing Film Studies, ed. David
Bordwell and Noel Carroll (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1996), 434–459: p. 434.
23
Christian Metz, “Trucage and the Film,” Critical Inquiry 4 (1977): 657–675: p. 665.
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
72
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
a sign of the hyper-real, the artifice of media becoming a sign of the real that also
‘eclipses the real’, that is even better than the real thing.24
If refraction is thought through rigorously as relational rather than substantive,
then any film can be avant-garde – it all depends on its relationship with the audience, and their context, on their natural or adopted naivety. A film’s avant-garde or
Modern status is not independent of its audience, for there is nothing natural or fixed
about the conventions of the Classical mode. If modernism concerns itself with
breaking those conventions by representing them, denaturalising them, then the
‘postmodern’ film, on this view, embodies a further refraction of that very act of
representing representation to bring us back to see every filmic image in its raw
specularity. The non-referentiality of the postmodern image does not indicate its
lack (of referent), but its own visceral immediacy, though as an event rather than as
an object.
However, while some film theorists like Steve Shaviro believe that this is de facto
true of every film, I believe that it is only de jure true, and mostly untrue of actual
films, or rather of most actual film viewing events.25 This is again because of the
differing nature of the audience: sometimes it will be open to the radical impact of
a film (if only because of being rarely exposed to film, be it ‘officially’ avant-garde
or not), but also at times because the audience can be jaded with and inured to the
effects of classical or modern film. In other words, the impact of film is not located
solely in the film, but in the film viewing event. Indeed, the postmodern image that
fully refracts modernism’s own representation of representation may not even be a
film image at all or belong anymore to film as an art form, but may well proceed
from new forms of media. If classical Hollywood has an opposite, it will not be in
another form of film but in another form of image altogether.26
315
J. Mullarkey
William Merrin, “Did You Ever Eat Tasty Wheat?: Baudrillard and The Matrix,” Scope: Online
Journal of Film Studies, June 2003, http://www.nottingham.ac.uk/film/journal/articles/did-youever-eat.htm
25
Despite claims (see Steven Shaviro, The Cinematic Body (University of Minnesota Press, 1993),
65, 266) for a restricted scope for his theory, he applies it most often to ‘film’ as such.
26
For further discussion of this other image, see my Refractions of Reality: Philosophy and the
Moving Image (Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan, 2009).
24
Chapter 7
1
A Note on Hölderlin-Translation
2
David Farrell Krell
3
[Editors’ note: What follows is a letter, written to Tony by one who has sworn never
to produce another article. At its opening, its author recalls with some nostalgia
those Warwick Workshops of the early 1980s, in and around which there was possible a mode of philosophical engagement more or less free of the professionalism
that so often dominates such enterprises and that, as his post-retirement vow never
to produce another article implies, the author regards as, at some times at least, more
of a stay upon philosophical thought than anything else. At Warwick, the work,
which took place also over meals and in pubs, was personal, and it is in honour of
the liveliness and the productivity of this kind of work that the author writes his letter, that most personal of communications: apparently “higgledly-piggledy” in form
but in fact tightly bound up in the particular interests shared and developed by the
Warwick friends; so unprofessional in tone and appearance but never for a moment
unphilosophical in its import and sphere of reference.
And yet this letter, unlike the other contributions to this volume, is being given a
preface, a professional garb, thrown over its shoulders at the last minute that it may
be deemed to, in the least important of ways, “fit in.” The irony is that, in this, it “fits
in” best of all, being part of a Festschrift whose personal character has had to be in
some sense excused in, and by, the editors’ introduction; there, the suspicion that a
Festschrift is, by virtue of being personal, a merely random (because unprofessional!) collection of texts, is undermined by the very evidently strong philosophical ties that bind the contributions to this collection. What, after all, could be less
random than the interests shared and enhanced by a set of friends over decades of
philosophical dialogue? And what could be more fitting than a letter, written between
two whose friendship was founded on a set of philosophical problems for which the
D.F. Krell (*)
DePaul University, Chicago, IL, USA
e-mail: davidfkrell@gmail.com
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_7, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
73
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
74
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
intimate account of a practice in practice – which is what this letter provides – cannot,
without serious inconsistency (and consistency is valued by the profession, is it
not?), be considered a merely personal concern?
“Never retouch a happy accident,” we quote Picasso as saying: with the humblest
of apologies for having retouched this happy accident by as much as we have done
here, we invite the reader not fortunate enough to have been in Warwick in the early
1980s, to get a sense for what was possible there that generated such a set of professional and, much more importantly and not always coincidentally, philosophical
lives. —F. Halsall/J.Jansen/S.Murphy]
Dear Tony—though this is an odd way to begin a note on Hölderlin translation, but
then again I myself retired this past June and I vowed I would never write another
article, and I know that you would not want me to break a vow—herewith a sort of
open letter on translation, more specifically, translation of Hölderlin. Inasmuch as it
will be a letter rather than an article, I may be permitted a few recollections that
stray from my theme. That’s the way letters go, is it not, one thought chasing after
another, fairly higgledy-piggledy?
Was it at Warwick University, at David Wood’s “Workshops in Continental
Philosophy,” that our paths first crossed? And was one of your earliest contributions
to that group—Robert Bernasconi, John Llewelyn, David Wood, and you were the
mainstays, as I recall—a paper on Merleau-Ponty’s Eye and Mind? I no longer
remember exactly what I was expecting, but I suppose reading a name like O’Connor
on the program I was anticipating a lilting Hibernian rhapsody on Merleau, who was
after all a fellow Celt. (And why should I not anticipate this? My mother’s name,
and my own middle name, derives from O’Fearghail.) Yet what I heard from you
was not a cloudburst of emotions; I need not have feared the storm. It was neither a
eulogy of Merleau-Ponty nor an elegy on the art of painting that you provided.
Rather, it was a sober, painstaking reading of L’Œil et l’esprit, a work, I suspect,
that you have never ceased studying, teaching, and enjoying.
From the beginning, then, it was the work of art that fascinated you. I remember
your papers at each of the Warwick Workshops, serious, precise, quietly eloquent,
with a very understated wit that came out in our discussions and especially in our
more leisurely chats over meals. That was in the early 1980s, a time I recall with real
nostalgia. I cannot say how these events struck you, but for me they were congenial
occasions—devoted to work-in-progress, tentative and experimental, not without
intensity, but altogether free of the professionalism that for me at least has marred
almost all the philosophical gatherings of subsequent years. A kind of modesty
prevailed there—what the Germans call Bescheidenheit—a willingness to listen and
learn rather than score points. If David Wood ever decides to retire, Tony, you and I
will have to write something in greater detail about the Warwick Workshops.
However, I’m not about to give you assignments—presumably, that is what you are
retiring from. Yet I did want to begin by saying how sad it is to me in retrospect that
our ways parted: Robert, David, and I went Stateside, as though Reagan were an
improvement over Thatcher, and not knowing that much worse was to follow, and
the workshops (as far as I am aware) ceased.
28
D.F. Krell
7 A Note on Hölderlin Translation
75
Back in those days I was already translating, mostly Heidegger, but the gods
alone know how or why. I certainly was not ready for it. In fact, each time I begin a
translation project, I wonder when I’ll ever be up to it. Does Dante reserve a circle
of hell for translators? Well, at least you’ll know where to find me. And now I’ve
sinned more egregiously in thought, word, and deed: a verse translation of Hölderlin’s
Der Tod des Empedokles, in all three versions, along with the related essays, published in 2008 by SUNY Press. A year earlier I had begun an English translation of
Hölderlin’s translation into German of Sophocles’ Oedipus the Tyrant and Antigone.
I’d planned to have the English set alongside the 1555 Juntina or Brubachiana Greek
text and Hölderlin’s 1804 German text: a kind of triptych. Several scenes into the
translation of Oedipus, however, David Constantine’s translation appeared in
England, and so, with a sense of disappointment and relief,
I stopped. Not long after that, Dennis Schmidt (in whose series the translation of
Der Tod des Empedokles appeared) encouraged me to take up the Empedoclean
challenge. After I’d finished a first draft of all three versions, I became ill and had to
have surgery. Much of the polishing and refining, and almost all the editorial work
on the volume, the notes and introductions, was a work of convalescence. I discovered that one of the advantages of the fountain pen is that you can write with it while
flat on your back. Yet the work got done, somehow or other, and what I would like
to do here, with your colleagues’ (my editors’) concurrence, is to reflect a bit on the
experience. What I’m really wondering is how much my own experience of translation dovetails with Hölderlin’s. Delusions of grandeur, perhaps.
Hölderlin himself has little to say about the process of his translations from the
Greek, whether of Sophocles or of Pindar, but one of his most assiduous and knowledgeable editors, Friedrich Beissner, tells us that one can distinguish four different
“stages” in Hölderlin’s translations of Sophocles. I’ve discussed these “stages” in a
book called The Tragic Absolute (Indiana University Press, 2005, 261; for Beissner’s
own remarks, see the Stuttgarter Ausgabe of Hölderlin’s works, 5:451), and in rough
outline they are as follows:
1. A relatively free formulation of the sense or meaning of the Greek lines, without
a great deal of attention being paid to the weight of the particular words chosen
by Sophocles.
2. A stage in which Hölderlin revises his German lines in order to capture as faithfully as he can the prosody, meter, and rhythm of the Greek lines. By this time in
his career, Hölderlin is an expert at capturing the rhythm and form of various
Greek styles, for example, his rendition of Alcaean and Asclepiadic odes; even
the most astute and experienced of his readers, Schiller and Goethe among them,
acknowledged the young poet’s extraordinary skill in this regard.
3. Beissner now identifies a stage of revision that is more difficult to understand: he
calls it, after Hölderlin, the “procedure of attentive listening,” die “hinhörende
Verfahrungsart.” But listening to what? To the particular words. One suspects
that Beissner may be influenced by Heidegger in his description of this third
stage. For Heidegger, from Being and Time onward, suggests that a Zugehören
founds and enables all Zuhören. That is to say, we do not belong to a poet’s work
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
76
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
until we have practiced the kind of listening that the work requires. Analytical
philosophers have always hated this facet of Heidegger’s thinking, scorning it as
word fetishism and obfuscation. Yet the more one is plagued by the usual sorts
of language analysis—think of Searle’s unstoppable blab—the more one is compelled to accept the need for listening, even if it should seem mantic, manic, or
maniac. At least, to come back to Hölderlin, there is no doubt that this poet took
Sophocles’ text to be a religious text—Karl Reinhardt is surely right about this
(see The Tragic Absolute, 330). One listens very carefully to a sacred text before
blabbing; indeed, as far back as the Orphics and Pythagoreans, blab is proscribed.
So, then, the “procedure of attentive listening” is what Beissner sees as a third
stage in Hölderlinian translation, and the primary earmark of such a heeding of
the particular words, rather surprisingly, is an effort to restore in the German
lines the word order of the Greek. One would have thought this to have been
characteristic of an earlier stage: surely, as one polishes and refines a translation,
one accepts the genius—and the word order—of the “target” language, the language into which one is translating? I would especially like to have heard Walter
Benjamin’s views on this third stage. A bit later I’ll come back to Benjamin’s
“Task of the Translator,” though only for a brief allusion or two.
4. Beissner identifies now a late stage of revision in Hölderlinian translation, thinking no doubt about the poet’s final alterations to his Antigone in the autumn of
1803. At this late stage, Hölderlin takes ever greater risks, demanding the impossible of the German language of his time, stretching his own language to the point
where the urbane German stylists of the day, reviewing the final product, could
declare him mad and his work risible. Hölderlin himself, explaining the delay to
his publisher, wrote about the need to translate in a “livelier,” lebendigeren, fashion. Only a “more lively” translation could convey Sophoclean scripture to the
modern Hesperian ear. Oddly, and decisively, Hölderlin identifies this livelier rendering with an Orientalizing of the Greek. Whereas the Greeks themselves suppressed their Oriental heritage—and for Hölderlin that heritage derives principally
from the cult of Asian Dionysos—the modern translator must seek it out and
bring it to bear on the translation. To put it in the form of a paradox: For the sake
of a livelier translation, that is, one better suited to the modern ear, one must push
farther back behind Greek antiquity to a more arcane and more archaic past. This
is perhaps Hölderlin’s most pervasive and most astonishing gesture. More than a
gesture, it is a concerted praxis of translation. It has to do with the famous brotherhood of Heracles, Christ, and Dionysos, which we find invoked in the late hymns.
However, the best Hölderlin scholars have written at length about this, so that I
feel abashed at merely mentioning it in a letter, as though it were the most obvious
thing in the world. Obvious it is not: even the young Nietzsche (recall in The Birth
of Tragedy from the Spirit of Music his anxiety in the face of the Oriental, his fear
of all things Babylonian, especially the Sekaean orgies) and even the mature
Heidegger (recall his readings of the Presocratics, which remain resolutely
Hellenic, with nary a reference to Ancient Near Eastern Texts, avoiding all confrontations with either Gilgamesh or what Yeats calls “Galilean turbulence”) are
not up to it. Now, both Nietzsche and Heidegger are informed admirers of
116
D.F. Krell
7 A Note on Hölderlin Translation
77
Hölderlin, to say the least; yet both seem to have resisted and even repressed this
crucial Orientalizing procedure (not in Said’s sense, and not in Benjamin’s, either)
in Hölderlin’s poetizing. I myself, influenced principally by Nietzsche and
Heidegger, have never been receptive enough in this regard, although Postponements
and Daimon Life both seem to me now to be signs of nervousness. In short, the
third stage (attentive listening to the particular words and to the word order) and
the fourth stage (seeking the livelier, more Oriental liquor of language) are the
stages that most intrigue me. My question to myself is whether in my translation
of Der Tod des Empedokles and even in those initial sketches toward a translation
of Hölderlin’s Sophocles I have undergone anything like these four “stages.”
My response is inhibited by the fact that I no longer possess the notebook that
contains the earliest drafts and revisions of the Empedokles translation. (My notebooks have gone into the archive at DePaul University’s Richardson Library, an
honor that pleased me primarily because otherwise I would have thrown them away
and then promptly regretted having done so.) Yet the translation process is still present to my mind. Concerning the first stage, in which the general sense of the lines is
rendered in the “target” language without much attention to the import of particular
words—in either the original or the “target” languages, one must add—I have to
make a confession. Among the very last changes I made to the Empedokles translation are a number that pertain precisely to the sense or meaning of certain lines.
These were lines in which the “hard rhythmic jointures” (Beda Allemann) so baffled
the syntax of the sentences, clauses, phrases, segments, or lines that I had to appeal
to capable friends for help. In the case of Empedokles the friend was Ulrich
Halfmann, emeritus professor of American Studies at Mannheim University, whose
English equals mine and whose German far outstrips mine, to say nothing of his
acuity as a reader in these two and many more languages. Here is one example of
Halfmann’s unraveling of the meaning of the rebarbative lines—a matter that ought
to have belonged to stage one, but which occurred at stage five, if you will.
In the third and final version of the drama, the character called “the old man,”
later given the name Manes, chides Empedocles concerning his decision to take his
life. In the course of his soliloquy Manes says:
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
Der Tod, der jähe, er ist ja von Anbeginn,
Das weißt du wohl, den Unverständigen
Die deinesgleichen sind, zuvorbeschieden.
192
193
194
It was the last six words that gave me trouble. I first wrote:
195
For death, the sudden steep, is there from the beginning,
You know it well; the ignorant, your contemporaries,
Have not been given it to know so soon.
196
197
198
I misunderstood the meaning of zuvorbeschieden, taking it to mean the knowledge of death which characterized Empedocles but not his besotted contemporaries.
This had the effect of emphasizing the contrast between Empedocles and the
citizens of Agrigent. Halfmann was able to convince me that the sense of the lines
is that death itself is allotted to all mortals from the start, and that Manes is telling
199
200
201
202
203
78
204
205
D.F. Krell
Empedocles that in this respect he is precisely akin to his fellow citizens. This
insight produced the following revision:
206
207
208
For death, the sudden steep, looms from the beginning,
As you know well; and to the baffled ones, to those
Who are your kin, it has long since been allotted.
209
A second example. In Empedocles’ reply to Manes the following appears:
210
211
212
Und staunend hört ich oft die Wasser gehn
Und sah die Sonne blühn, und sich an ihr
Den Jugendtag der stillen Erd entzünden.
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
The phrase sich an ihr . . . entzünden confused me, and at first I had the sun
catching fire on the surface of the waters:
Astonished oftentimes I heard the waters’ flow and saw
The sun in bloom and catching fire upon the waters’ skin
All through the youthful day on our reposeful earth.
Halfmann was able to show me that what Empedocles saw at sunrise was the
youthful day of the silent earth being ignited by the sun:
Astonished oftentimes I heard the waters’ flow and saw
The sun burst into bloom; I saw our silent earth
At youthful day catch fire from that sun.
213
There are doubtless dozens of other lines that I misconstrued at first, finding my
way—with or without help—toward a more accurate reading of the sense.
With regard to stage one generally, I will only remark that in Hölderlin the most
astonishing poetry sometimes flows like lava, hot and irresistible, such that the
holograph shows virtually no emendations; sometimes, it is also true, my translations
of him seem to have compressed all four of his stages into one. Those were instances
of what Reiner Schürmann, in a letter to me decades ago, called trouvailles. One simply finds one’s own language delivering the gift of a rendering that will endure all the
later reexaminations and will smile upon all desires to improve. In these cases, the
sense of the lines is given as the French sens, whereby not only the meaning but also
the direction and flow of the words is given—by the ears and nose, as it were.
Otherwise, Beissner is surely right: in Hölderlin’s holograph one often finds that when
the flow of the line(s) seem(s) entirely natural, automatic, and “just right,” that flow
was achieved only after endless alterations. I recall the case of the first three lines of
the soliloquy that opens the third version of Der Tod des Empedokles, lines that in
their Duktus seem so inevitable that they must have come all at once: however, in the
holograph we find eight lines intervening after the second of these first three, eight
lines that are later struck, allowing that third line to pretend that it was always there in
place. True, as Picasso says concerning the lines of a drawing, Never retouch a happy
accident. The problem is to know in what “happiness” consists. (Philosophy, anyone?)
Stage two, paying heed to the prosody of the original, occurred for me when I
undertook a line-by-line comparison of my revised text with Hölderlin’s German. In
other words, a stage of revision occurred for me between stages one and two. Before
I undertook a line-by-line comparison with the German, I worked through my
7 A Note on Hölderlin Translation
79
English version at least twice. Here I was preoccupied principally with the English
text in my notebook, laboring on it in order to see if the English made any sense, and
going back to the German only when things blurred or became hopelessly awkward.
It was this twice-revised English text that was then read against the German, read
with an ear to meter and rhythm. Those were days of iambs and nights of trochees,
with visions of dactyls and anapests galloping in my head. Daylight iambs prevailed, of course, but even there it was essential to respect the meter while avoiding
sing-song. “I think that I shall never see/A poem lovely as one of the multitudinous
species of dendrites.” That became my motto. I had never been very conscious of
Hölderlin’s meters, but now I had to train both ear and eye for them. And even
though iambic is as native to English as Shakespeare is to Stratford, I had to learn
the native as though it were foreign; this made me think of that amazing letter that
Hölderlin writes to Casimir von Böhlendorff, on the need to explore the foreign
precisely in order to develop one’s native gifts. Perhaps for the first time in my life
I had to practice the craft of poetry. I cannot say how well or ill I’ve done. Maybe
you’ll do me the kindness some day of letting me know. As for my own judgment
of the matter, I found myself writing a funny line about my tinkerings in the little
shop of iambs—what the French, I am told, now call va-VOOM-cinq—and I put that
funny line into the preface of the translation: “To those skeptics who wonder why I
have here attempted the impossible—a verse translation of Hölderlin—and who
may feel that I am not fit for the task, that I haven’t got a poetic bone in my body,
I insist that there is such a bone in me, just one, a thigh bone wrapped in endless
folds of prosaic fat. I have burned that bone in joyous desperation on the altar of
Hölderlin’s Empedocles.” I still don’t know about that purported poetic bone of mine,
and cannot be sure that I even made it as far as stage two of Hölderlin’s itinerary.
At this point I keyboarded my translation into a computer—and wouldn’t
Hölderlin have smiled over that verb, “keyboarded,” although he was no Luddite
and would have keyboarded gleefully had the technology been there. The computer
version is a translator’s blessing, if only on account of the search-function. (During
the 1970s and 1980s, when I was translating Heidegger, I certainly would have
benefited from a PC. I started using one, a Mac, in the late 1980s, with Daimon Life,
precisely at the time I stopped translating. I never could get my life poised.) The
resulting typescript, pace Heidegger, helped me to get a sense of the “flow” and the
“balance” of the lines. Yes, even the word order of original and “target” became
more apparent to me. After a hasty correction of the printout, pretty much with
attention to the English alone, a second line-by-line reading of the German and
English occurred. No, not exactly line-by-line, but a reading aloud, or at least over
the lips, of a varying number of lines of Hölderlin’s text, anywhere from one to five
or six lines, with a reading of the English following right on its heels. I recall trying
to make my head roomy enough to hold these German and English lines together.
Here, if I may make so bold, something like a belonging-to Hölderlin’s lines transpired, a listening-to the words and to the sequence of the words, their tumult and
their tranquillity. The first line of Empedocles’ soliloquy in the first version reads:
In meine Stille kamst du leise wandelnd,
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
80
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
and I avoided both tranquillity (a word that I love, as you’ve seen) and every temptation
to transpose the words, winding up with the simplest possible rendering:
Into my stillness you came softly wandering.
As the German text became more and more familiar to me—I mean, the sound of
it—I found myself listening out for possible parallel sounds in English. Walter
Benjamin’s figure is here quite apt: we do not inhabit language, neither the “original”
nor the “target” (the scare-quotes tell you, Tony, that I’m getting fed up with both
“originals” and “targets,” as though translation were a shoot-out between languages);
rather, we stand on the outside of even our own language, as though at the edge of
an impenetrable forest. We call out, call into the forest, to see whether anything will
come echoing back to us. Not the noise of calling but the silence of attunement-tothe-echo is important. Muffled noises, the falling of leaves, the scratchings of birds
and rummagings of squirrels, interrupted every now and then by the echo of a word
that seems to be the right word. Hölderlin calls this the pure word, das reine Wort.
By this time, va-VOOM meant less to me than the sequence and flow of the words,
with special attention to the line-breaks and enjambments, the continuities and caesuras. I became more attentive to those moments when Hölderlin’s Swabian dialect
punctuated the high diction that otherwise prevailed. (A whole treatise would have
to be written on Hölderlin’s use of dialect: as one north-German mother complained
when her daughter brought home a boy from Stuttgart, “Aber er schwäbelt so!”)
This listening-and-belonging process is not exactly an identifiable “stage,” at
least not in my case. It was in play from the beginning, albeit imperfectly. Indeed,
something in my handwritten text, all the way back at stage one, was important for
this listening, as though the cadence were in the pen. (Everything I have ever written,
whether book or translation, prose or poetry, nonfiction or fiction, was first written
and revised in fountain pen.) In spite of the excellent chances of self-deception here,
I feel that my capacity to listen did improve over the months of work on the translation.
If the listening was good enough, especially in the later “stages” of the work, there
was something like a dancing of the words and phrases, accompanied by assonance
and alliteration; there was both a sweet familiarity and an unheard-of uncanniness,
simultaneously.
Is there a fourth stage in my case? To make the American (up to now I’ve been
writing English, dear Tony, but one Celt will call a half-Celt to order and to greater
honesty!) more lively—yes, that is surely an unspoken imperative. Heidegger once
said, I believe in his 1935 Introduction to Metaphysics, that poetry is the sounding
of a word as though for the first time. I became excited this past summer by Thomas
Hardy’s use of the word purling, as in “purling waters,” a word I did not know.
I heard its echo for the first time this summer. I plan now to insert it into one of two
places in the translation that have been waiting for it, places that were tired of the
waters flowing and streaming.
Lebendiger. It means much more than “with increased sparkle, animation, and
vitality.” It has to do with Hölderlin’s conviction that life itself is a unity of circles, or
of expanding rings, from the so-called inorganic (his friend Schelling has taught him
to be suspicious of this category of physics) to plants, animals, humans, spirits, and
gods—though even to list them in this way is wrong. Poets and thinkers, Empedocles
291
D.F. Krell
7 A Note on Hölderlin Translation
81
included, seek these greater unities of life, without being so adamant about making
distinctions. Historically speaking, poets and thinkers try to enliven the past, to give
it the vibrant colors of myth, even if they have to “mistranslate” in order to do this.
For example, Hölderlin deliberately alters the apparent sense of Sophocles’ lines
concerning Danaë’s “reception” of Zeus as a shower of gold. Rather than simply
“receive” Zeus, Hölderlin’s Danäe teaches him something essential:
336
337
338
339
340
341
Sie zählete dem Vater der Zeit
Die Stundenschläge, die goldnen.
342
343
She counted off for the father of time
The strokes of the hours, the golden strokes.
344
345
Hölderlin’s “mistranslation,” which is actually closer to the Greek than the usual
translations, brings Zeus, the father of the earth, down to earth. Danäe brings the father
of time into time. For the ears of modern mortals, and perhaps of postmodern mortals
as well, she teaches the lord what it is he sees in her, why he is so taken with her. She
teaches him the fecundity of mortality (see The Tragic Absolute, chapters 9–11).
Once again, however: lebendiger, molto vivace. Among the most lively emendations in Hölderlin’s translation of Antigone are those in which he translates the
names of the Olympian gods back to their more Titanic origins—perhaps even to
their Oriental origins. Thus Zeus is “the father of time and the earth,” Aphrodite
“divine beauty,” Hades “the future site of the dead,” Persephone “furiously compassionate—a light,” and her mother Demeter “that which is impenetrable.”
It is not difficult for me to find examples of the final stage, the search for the
livelier expression, in my own translation, although I am uncertain as to whether
and how the word Orientalizing applies to my task. (Recall, however, my excitement over Thomas Hardy’s lively purling.) The livelier echoes that come from
the forest of language almost always come late in the process. Apart from those rare
trouvailles, one has to let the unconscious do its work for many days and nights.
The seemingly endless reading and re-reading of the German and the American,
always over the lips, the endless polishings and touchings up, the ceaseless scratchings of the pen, as in Melville’s Pierre. . . . So, how do we know when it is done?
That is the question we put to every culinary genius, and the answer is always, “It’s
done whenever more cooking would harm it.”
The time does seem to come when—to alter the metaphor—one is merely
rearranging the furniture of a translation, scratching out proposed emendations and
restoring earlier solutions. Perhaps it all comes down to exhaustion? One can stand
at the forest’s edge only so long. The stamina to stand and call comes from love of
poetry, and that love intensifies, does not diminish, but in the end even lovers have
their limits.
One of the thoughts that hovered as a shadow over all the stages of my work was
that of failure. Not the failure of my own translation, which always seemed to be a
given, but the failure of the “originals.” The three versions that Hölderlin produced
were for him botched efforts: he set each one aside, giving up all hope of completing
them, publishing them, seeing them performed. It seemed important to me to understand the nature of the failure, of the botching, if you will; important to understand
the caesura or counter-rhythmic interruption that revealed to Hölderlin, as though in
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
82
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
epiphany, the impossibility of the project. Why important? Certainly not so that
I would translate “down,” as it were, so that the failure would become palpable to
my readers. For each of the versions contains magnificent poetry and trenchant dialogue, and these invariably surpassed my ability to render them. The failure, it
seemed to me, had to do with the suicide itself, the “one full deed at the end” of
which the hero dreams; the failure had to do with the reported suicide itself, precisely the death of Empedocles. Not simply the fact that the voluntary death of the
thinker could not be dramatized: many such deaths in Greek tragedy are reported
rather than shown. No, the problem had to do with Empedocles’ death as an ostensibly affirmative act, one in which nature and art would successfully fuse. Perhaps
that is why, in my view at least, the most powerful poetry comes in the third version,
with the Egyptian priest’s challenge to Empedocles, and Empedocles’ highly
charged yet futile response. Indeed, by the time I was in the final stages of the translation, it seemed to me that Manes’s challenge to Empedocles, a challenge that
frustrates both Empedocles and Hölderlin, produced the very best poetry. This paradox never resolved itself, but only deepened as my work advanced. Philippe LacoueLabarthe was right to say that the three versions of the play lacked théâtralité. What
Hölderlin in effect had produced was an oratorio without music—though also without a happy end, without what Lacan called “salvationist choirs.” How did this
failure of the Trauerspiel—of the tragedy or mourning-play as such—affect my
translation? I’m not sure. But the failure to bring Empedocles—the man and the
play—to his and its resolution did not mar the language; instead, it enabled the finest flowers of the work to flourish.
Here are a few lines from the speech of Manes, the Egyptian priest or “old man.”
From Hölderlin’s holograph we see that these lines did not give him a lot of trouble,
no matter how much difficulty they caused Empedocles. Very few emendations
here, even though Hölderlin left about a third of his page (the left-hand margin) free
in order to accommodate eventual alterations. The speech ends with some questions
put to Empedocles that have all the directness and force of dialect:
381
D.F. Krell
Nur Einem ist es Recht, in dieser Zeit,
Nur Einen adelt deine schwarze Sünde.
Ein größrer ists, denn ich! denn wie die Rebe
Von Erd und Himmel zeugt, wenn sie getränkt
Von hoher Sonn aus dunklem Boden steigt,
So wächst er auf, aus Licht und Nacht geboren.
Es gärt um ihn die Welt, was irgend nur
Beweglich und verderbend ist im Busen
Der Sterblichen, ist aufgeregt von Grund aus,
Der Herr der Zeit, um seine Herrschaft bang,
Thront finster blickend über der Empörung.
Sein Tag erlischt, und seine Blitze leuchten,
Doch was von oben flammt, entzündet nur
Und was von unten strebt, die wilde Zwietracht.
Der Eine doch, der neue Retter faßt
Des Himmels Strahlen ruhig auf, und liebend
Nimmt er, was sterblich ist, an seinen Busen,
Und milde wird in ihm der Streit der Welt.
7 A Note on Hölderlin Translation
83
Die Menschen und die Götter söhnt er aus
Und nahe wieder leben sie, wie vormals.
Und daß, wenn er erschienen ist, der Sohn
Nicht größer, denn die Eltern sei, und nicht
Der heilge Lebensgeist gefesselt bleibe
Vergessen über ihn, dem Einzigen,
So lenkt er aus, der Abgott seiner Zeit,
Zerbricht, er selbst, damit durch reine Hand
Dem Reinen das Notwendige geschehe,
Sein eigen Glück, das ihm zu glücklich ist,
Und gibt, was er besaß, dem Element,
Das ihn verherrlichte, geläutert wieder.
Bist du der Mann? derselbe? bist du dies? (358–388)
The lines that gave me the most trouble and that required alteration at each stage
of my work, appear toward the end, with the line Und daß, wenn er erschienen ist,
der Sohn, on to the end. Two lines that had an immediate impact and whose sense
was immediately clear to me, but whose prosody and power called for change upon
change in my translation, were these two—as stark as though they were written in
the Greek of Sophocles:
Doch was von oben flammt, entzündet nur
Und was von unten strebt, die wilde Zwietracht. (370–71)
I cannot take you through all my lucubrations, and I do not know if what follows
is enlivened or Orientalized sufficiently, but here is where I am so far—for the
“stages” of translation, as you know, will not come to an end until I do:
For one alone in our time is it fitting; one being
Alone ennobles your black sin.
That one is greater than I am! for as the vine
Bears witness to the earth and sky when, saturated by
The lofty sun it rises from dark soil, thus
This being grows, a child of light and night.
The world around him bubbles in ferment, and all
Disruption and corruption in the mortal breast
Is agitated, and from top to bottom; whereupon
The lord of time, grown apprehensive of his rule,
Looms with glowering gaze above the consternation.
His day extinguished, lightning bolts still flash, yet
What flames on high is inflammation, nothing more;
What strives from down below is savage discord.
The one, however, the newborn savior, grasps
The rays of heaven tranquilly, and lovingly
He takes mortality unto his bosom, and
The world’s strife grows mild in him.
The human being and the gods he reconciles;
Again they live in close proximity, as in former times.
No sooner has the son appeared, that he may not
Surpass his parentage, and that the holy spirit
Of life may not remain in shameful fetters
On his account, forgotten up above, the unique one
Now turns aside, although he is the idol of his times,
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
84
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
Destroys himself, so that a pure hand executes
Whatever of necessity befalls the pure one;
He shatters his own fortune, now too fortunate for him,
Restores whatever he possessed unto the element
That glorified him, gives it back now wholly cleansed.
Are you that man? the very one? are you this?
If there is a touch of the Orient here, and that means of Dionysos, then it may be
in the “bubbles” of fermentation, or in the “glowering gaze” of the lord of time, or
in the “inflammation” in which the fire of heaven goes out. Or perhaps in the strange
yet overwhelming challenge, spoken in dialect, “are you this?”
But it is time now to close. Translations appear to be acquisitions, at least when
they show up as bound volumes on library shelves, but they are there only to encourage young persons to begin studying languages they do not yet know. All the beauty
of a translation has this pedagogy as its goal; all the flaws of a translation are
forgiven if the pedagogy succeeds. From time to time there must be a reader who
says, in the present instance, “I need to be able to read this in German, I have to start
now, there is another world awaiting me.” Not acquisitions, then, but works, or
settings-to-work. Works of art, then?
Perhaps translations are works of art in Merleau-Ponty’s sense, which is the
sense that for all their limitations, all their finitude, they at least gesture toward
the unbounded, toward the greater freedom. Allow me, dear Tony, to paraphrase
the final lines of Eye and Mind, which you know so well. If no translation accomplishes translation-as-such, and if no individual work of translation is ever itself
accomplished once and for all, is never completed absolutely, then each work of
translation alters, clarifies, deepens, confirms, exalts, recreates or creates in advance
all the others. If translations are not acquisitions, it isn’t only because like all
things they are transitory and will pass, but also because they have almost all
their life ahead of them.
477
478
479
480
481
482
D.F. Krell
Chapter 8
1
Violence and Splendor: At the Limits
of Hermeneutics
2
3
Alphonso Lingis
4
From as far back as we can see into our history and across the planet, rituals, initiations,
ceremonies, processions, dances have been celebrated. They were performed,
anthropologist Victor Turner explained, to promote and increase fertility of men,
crops, and animals, domestic and wild; to cure illness; to avert plague; to obtain
success in raiding; to turn boys into men and girls into women; to make chiefs out
of commoners; to transform ordinary people into shamans and shamanins; to “cool”
those “hot” from the warpath, to ensure the proper succession of seasons and the
hunting and agricultural responses of human beings to them.1 These performances
were also animal and cosmic epiphanies, and often awesome and terrifying revelations of dark compulsions and cruelties that are unleashed in tabooed places and
sacred times. They called down plague and disaster on the leaders of enemy peoples, and curses on their children and livestock. Collective performances were also
entertainments; people laugh freely at the grotesqueries in Balinese shadow plays,
in African rituals, in Papuan initiation ceremonies so lavish in cruelties to the initiates; they laughingly recognize village louts arrayed in fancy costume and spouting
pompous declamations, they gossip and feast on lavish meals.
Collective performances cannot be understood only from the intentions of the
organizers, participants, and bystanders, and from their historical, political, economic, and ideological contexts. A cultural performance closes in on itself, its
scenes and movements adjusting to one another, and evolves with its own logic, that
of ceremony and festival.
1
Victor Turner, From Ritual to Theatre: The Human Seriousness of Play (New York: PAJ,
1982), 32.
[AU1]
A. Lingis (*)
Pennsylvania State University, University Park, PA, USA
e-mail: allingis@hotmail.com
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_8, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
85
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
86
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
Did not Jean-Jacques Rousseau also provide an essential insight when he wrote
that the dispersed families of hunter-gathering antiquity assembled for the collective
joy of song and dance, and that this collective joy first gave them the ecstatic experience of collective humanity? Human society was not first assembled out of fear, but
out of collective joy.
Interpretive anthropology views rituals, ceremonies, and dances, collective performances, and cultural systems generally as symbolic complexes that have meaning, and function to give meaning to human thoughts, feelings, and actions. Indeed,
it is this meaning of cultural symbols that, Geertz affirms, first articulates, generates
and regenerates thoughts. To think is to identify things and relate them with words
and other cultural symbols. Further, indignation, a feeling of injustice, of frustration
of our expectations and plans, envy, jealousy, triumph—words and cultural symbols
make them possible. Words and cultural symbols determine what we laugh over and
what we grieve over. Georges Bataille argued that it is taboos that produce extreme
emotions, which burst forth through the transgression of taboos. “Not only ideas,
but emotions too, are cultural artifacts in man,” Geertz declares.2 This thesis establishes a radical distinction between humans and the other animal species.
With the thesis that cultural performances, and cultural systems generally, have
meaning, and produce effects through their meaning, goes the thesis that anthropology
understands them by translating their meaning into that system of cultural and
linguistic symbols which is the anthropological interpretation.3 “The meanings that
symbols, the material vehicles of thought, embody are often elusive, vague, fluctuating,
and convoluted, but they are, in principle, as capable of being discovered through
systematic empirical investigation—especially if the people who perceive them will
cooperate a little—as the atomic weight of hydrogen or the function of the adrenal
glands,” Geertz declares.4
The anthropological discourse laying out the meanings of a cultural system and
then of another, and the comparisons between them and between successive systems, is part of the general modern project that we can call our historical consciousness. The emergence of scientific history and the social sciences in the nineteenth
century was borne by the conviction that if we could represent the forms human
societies and events took across the centuries, and the relations between them, we
would produce an encompassing and integrated knowledge of the meaning of social
events and understand their consequences.
The concept of meaning, central to cultural hermeneutics, is, however, not very
clear. It is not simply intellectual, conceptual meaning, grasped in conscious acts.
Geertz reports that when the Javanese speak of their sense of rituals and ceremonies they speak of rasa, a term uniting taste, touch, and emotional feeling with
26
A. Lingis
Ibid, 81.
“The study of other peoples’ cultures… involves discovering who they think they are, what they
think they are doing, and to what end they think they are doing it…” Clifford Geertz, Available
Light (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000), 16.
4
Ibid, 362–363.
2
3
8
Violence and Splendor: At the Limits of Hermeneutics
87
“meaning”—but “ultimate significance”—the deepest meaning at which one
arrives by dint of mystical effort.5
Yet if, as Geertz asserts, the meanings that symbols, the material vehicles of
thought, embody are, in principle, capable of being discovered, they are not fundamentally different from the intelligible meaning formulated in the anthropologists’
concepts.6 Indeed, collective performances have the same function as the anthropological discourse: the Balinese cockfight is for Balinese a sentimental education,
Geertz explains, a text that articulates for and reflects to the Balinese the emotions
with which individuals are put together and society is built, the look, uses, force of,
and fascination with the violence in their highly stratified and ceremonious society.7
That historical sense that we acquire through the objective representation of the forms
of society and culture provided by our social sciences, among them anthropology,
prior societies acquired or produced in and through their collective performances.
Geertz did find that most Balinese worshippers, and the priests themselves, have
no idea who the gods in the temples are or what the sanskritic chants mean,8 and
Donald Cordry found that in the vast majority of Mexican masked processions,
neither performers nor audience understood much at all of the costumes’ significance.9 Is not the concept of meaning here being stretched to designate only the
patterns and periodicities of behavior that rituals impose, and perhaps also certain
sentiments of group solidarity, awe, or fear? Pragmatists and rationalists, and religious reformers denounce behavior regulated by “meaningless rituals.” Barbara
Babcock notes that in carnivals and fiestas fireworks, exuberantly fantastic clothing,
patchwork colors, the multiplication of apparently irrelevant masks and costumes
“to the point of indeterminate nonsense,” suspend customary meanings. Yet she
says that “a surplus of signifiers… creates a self-transgressive discourse which
mocks and subverts the monological arrogance of ‘official’ systems of signification.”10 But it is hard to argue or verify that “transgression” is the meaning that
shaped these irrelevant and nonsensical masks and costumes. Is not this meaning
indeed a cultural construction—of the interpreter?
The concept of meaning does not seem to designate the essential in the spectacularly theatrical Rangda-Barong cultural performance in Bali that Geertz depicts as
an endless, inconclusive clash between the malignant and the ludicrous. Its effect is
that people of both sexes fall into trance and rush out to stab themselves, wrestle
with one another, devour live chicks or excrement, wallow convulsively in the mud,
sink into a coma—“an orgy of futile violence and degradation.”11
Ibid, 134–135.
“Symbols… are tangible formulations of notions, abstractions from experience fixed in perceptible forms, concrete embodiments of ideas, attitudes, judgments, longings, or beliefs.” Ibid, 91.
7
Ibid, 449.
8
Ibid, 177, 179.
9
Donald Cordry, Mexican Masks (Austin/London: University of Texas Press, 1980), 23–31.
10
Barbara Babcock, “Too Many, Too Few: Ritual Modes of Signification,” Semiotica 23: 296.
11
Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures, 118–119, 181.
5
6
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
88
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
Could not some of the meanings the interpreter detects in cultural performances
be absurd, designate nothing but blind pain, or indeed designate a world full of
sound and fury, signifying nothing?
Collective performances do not only exhibit effigies and icons; they continue in
throbbing, energizing, and transforming music, song, and dance. The interpretive
movement of the mind that constructs meanings is different from, and clogged up
by, deactivated by the rhythmic and melodic periodicities of movement.
Over and beyond, or beneath, meaning, there is power generated in collective
performances. Victor Turner ponders over “what I have often seen in Africa, where
thin, ill-nourished old ladies, with only occasional naps, dance, sing, and perform
ritual activities for 2 or 3 days and nights on end.” Collective performances release,
in music, song, and dance and also in trance, resources of pleasure, pain, and expression
in our bodies and in unconscious processes that are untapped in everyday life.
Equally striking, and equally enigmatic, is the production of splendor in collective
performances. Here the concept of meaning breaks down. The Byzantine iconoclasts and the Protestant Reform denounced the splendor of gilt, color, form, music,
and sumptuous liturgical processions for obscuring and engulfing the meaning of
the religious symbols.
While collective performances have been much studied as generating political
decisions and spiritual trances and visions, there is little about how they generate
splendor, and little about that splendor. A people are transfigured in glorious adornments and movements; their experience as they perform is transfigured; exalted
emotions surge in them; their assembling becomes dramatic, epic, cosmic.
Now that anthropologists no longer study tribal peoples to exhibit primitive
stages of human cultural evolution, when the agricultural and technical skills they
studied have little relevance to our industrial mass-production of food and commodities, will not the splendor produced in their collective performances be ever
more important to us, in the petulant venality our global mercantile culture?
In 1964, in Papua New Guinea, some Australian colonial administrators, remembering the Highland festivals in Scotland they or their immigrant fathers told of,
organized the first Mount Hagen Show. The Papuans, they thought, love body
adornment and spectacle, it would be a joy to behold and a joy, for them, to celebrate their beauty: a Carnival in the Pacific answering the Carnaval in Brazil on the
opposite side of the planet. They summoned the tribes of the Western Highlands,
who they perceived to be living in suspicion and hostility with one another, to come
in ceremonial dress and parade together under Mount Hagen. The men came in triumphal war dress and with their weapons. But the Australians organized the show
as a celebration of the end of tribal hostility, a festival of the new Pax Australiana.
Before the Second World War, the Australian colonial administration was very
thinly staffed, and no effort had been made to extend control or even explore the
mountainous tropical island. Then the European war extended to the Pacific, and
Australians, Americans, and Japanese fought in New Guinea. The Australians
enlisted Papuans in their war, and some 50,000 of them were killed. After the end of
the war, as the Australians returned to their colony, they seriously set out to pacify
the country. Not to put down armed opposition to them; from their first arrival their
99
A. Lingis
8
Violence and Splendor: At the Limits of Hermeneutics
89
guns had quickly showed the Papuans the futility of that. Pacification meant that
conflict among the Papuans was not to be settled with weapons, but by recourse to
Australian administrators and courts. The million-strong highlands Papuans, discovered so late, only in 1930, had been a journalistic sensation, where the Papuans
were called Stone Age people and savages. When it was discovered that each high
valley had its own language—eventually 867 languages were identified—and the
societies so individualistic that defense of one’s land was up to the individual and
his kinsmen and clansmen, it was easy to imagine them as in a constant state of war.
The Australian colonial administration did so depict them and made pacification its
overriding priority.
In fact highlands men sought their wives from the neighboring tribe; this
exogamy maintained contact with and negotiations between the big men of adjacent tribes. When battles did break out, they were so constrained by rules and
fought with weapons so ineffective—the arrows that are without fletching are
really inaccurate—that it would be rare that anyone was actually killed. If someone were killed, the big men immediately demanded and negotiated compensation. If compensation—in the form of pigs, foodstuffs, and shells—were refused,
then the fighting would resume until someone of the opposing side was killed
and balance restored. Although sickness that resulted in death was attributed to
ancestral ghosts, spirits, or sorcery, most often material compensation was
arranged if sorcery was recognized to be the cause.
For the Australians, these last, as for the first white imperialists, Cortez and
Pizarro, the colony was seen as a source of gold. Later, of silver, copper, oil, and
natural gas. The problem was that the prospectors and miners depended on large
trains of native bearers to carry their equipment and supplies, and they found that
again and again the bearers would not cross boundary lines into the territory of
the next tribe. The boundaries were protected not so much by arrayed enemy
warriors as by sorcery. To break down the tribal boundaries, the Australians, as
they advanced into areas where gold panning or dredging was promising, decreed
that all tribal conflicts be referred to the administrators and the courts they instituted
and sent military patrols to punish tribes where conflicts being settled in the
traditional ways.
The Mount Hagen Show was organized to demonstrate, to the United Nations
Trusteeship Council and the home government, that pacification had been achieved.
And to extend the forced pacification into highlands societies, since the clans and
tribes of the highlands would be assembled where they could meet and communicate with their respective enemies. It was also organized to bring in tourists, for by
now tourism had become a major industry around the world. An airstrip was laid
out, several hotels were built, and 850 mostly Australian tourists were flown in.
The Australian organizers had announced prizes for the best costumes, the best
drummers, the best marchers, the best dancers. However, as soon as the prizes were
awarded, fights broke out between the losers and the winners; the prizes were subsequently suppressed. The show was to occur every other year, but it proved difficult
to get the big men of enough clans and tribes to agree for a date, so that it was difficult for tourists to plan to get there.
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
90
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
Now the government of independent Papua New Guinea, whose army and police
are effective only to protect the mines of multinational corporations, supports the
Mount Hagen Show to affirm the national identity of the Papuan clans and tribes
and to display to the outside world their cultural diversity. Last year there were only
some 200 tourists, most of them flown in for just the 2 days of the Show by tour
companies. After 30 years of independence, Papua New Guinea is judged by foreign
chanceries and tour companies alike to be a primitive and violent place; indeed
tribal war was raging across most of the highlands and in the capital, Port Moresby,
all the bus companies and even taxis had been immobilized for the past 2 months by
the conflict.
A local man I had come to know points out a Member of Parliament. I remark
that there do not seem to be many government dignitaries here. My companion
tells me that this man is the representative from this district. He introduces me to
the Parliamentarian; I congratulate him on the splendor of the Show. He looks
down. “It is getting hard to get young people interested in it,” he says. I had noted
that some participants in the Show were wearing fake kina shells of painted
cardboard. The government-sponsored Show was beginning to produce its kitsch
offspring. Later I think the Parliamentarian was thinking of the situation in Port
Moresby and the coastal towns. I remembered that in Lae the arriving tourist is
rushed by airport police into a van with steel plates bolted over its body and a
heavy steel mesh grill over its windows; three armed soldiers are seated in the van
as it speeds through stop signs to the tourist hotel. A government report had found
that fully 50% of the inhabitants of Port Moresby live by theft.
Before the Second World War, the Australian colonial authority had refused to
grant permits for missionaries in most of the territory; its military patrols were too
few to protect anything but the places where mining companies were prospecting
and dredging. After the war, when Australia set out to regain control of its vast
colony, the missionaries were seen as effective and permanent agents of pacification. Catholic, Lutheran, Baptist, Seventh Day Adventist, and other fundamentalist
missionaries quickly spread across the whole island, building churches and schools
and clinics. They are the principal source of cash wages for most villages. Everywhere
the missionaries enjoined their parishioners to demolish the men’s house, and husbands and wives to live together as nuclear families. They ridiculed the taboos that
had prohibited sex for the 5 years each child was weaned, and that limited most
women to two children in their lives. The missionaries staffed clinics and inculcated
hygiene; the population quickly doubled. Occupancy of the narrow fertile valleys in
the mountainous highlands had always been the principle motive for conflict; now
all the valleys are overpopulated. The export prices for what agricultural products
and coffee that is raised continues to fall. Young men go down to Port Moresby,
the coastal towns of Madang and Lae, where the great majority do not find work.
The foreign gold, copper, silver mining companies, the US Interoil refinery, and the
Australian Gas Light Company laying a pipeline to bring natural gas from the
highlands across the Torres Strait to Australia are state-of-the-art high-tech projects
that employ very few local people. With the abolition of the institution of the men’s
189
A. Lingis
8
Violence and Splendor: At the Limits of Hermeneutics
91
house, these young men have not been acculturated with the loyalties, rituals, and
duties and obligations of their tribe, and the village and clan elders have lost their
authority over them. In the highlands communities men who lie in wait for travelers
and kill them were feared rather than admired; they did not become respected leaders,
organizers of exchanges, and orators, did not become big men, but “bad men.” Now
the term is “raskals.” Those who return to the highlands do so to plant marijuana,
coca, and poppies for the smugglers in the coastal towns. Some of these earn enough
money to buy guns. The tribal wars that break out now result in far more deaths and
the tribal big men are far less able to negotiate compensations.
At the Mount Hagen Show the marching groups bearing the now obsolete and
purely ceremonial weapons, the presence of representatives of the government, and
the large contingent of police and army affirm that henceforth violence is the
monopoly of the state. However, the Westminster-style parliamentary government
set in place by the Australians does not succeed in establishing political parties with
national, or even provincial programs for development or even, malaria-researcher
Dr Ivo Müller explained to me, for public health. The 109 parliamentarians are in
effect tribal big men, working to divert some of the national budget to enrich themselves and their tribesmen. Corruption is rampant in the ill-trained and ill-paid army
and police, who readily sell their guns to fellow-tribesmen in times of conflict and
allege that their outposts had been raided. During the last elections, there were
known cases of politicians arming their supporters; six of the nine Highlands electorates were invalidated by the High Court due to violence and intimidation. Once
again individuals and clans take responsibility for exacting compensation for or
avenging aggressions done to them.
With the dwindling number of tourists in attendance, the entrance fee for tourists
has been increased from $30 to $100. Coca-Cola advertised itself as a sponsor this
year, meaning, I suppose, that it contributed some money. The participating tribes
are given 5 kina—about US$5—per performer to help in transportation costs. But
some groups have come from the coastal towns of Madang and Lae, and even some
from the outlying Bismark Archipelago. So they do not come for the money, but for
the experience. I greet a doctor I had met in Madang; he had long practiced here and
retired to New Zealand upon Independence. He tells me he had attended the first
Mount Hagen Shows in the 1960s. I ask him how this one compares with the first
ones. “Oh, it’s much bigger now,” he says.
Despite what the Parliamentarian said, there are indeed young men marching in
the Show; the majority of the men are young. You watch them, holding on to archaic,
but fearful weapons, chanting war chants the length of the day, and you think that this
show, far from demonstrating the pacification of the highlands, celebrates a warrior
culture, which continues in new dimensions in independent Papua New Guinea. In
these marching groups of men without leaders zigzagging across other groups in the
field, you see what warfare was to the highlands peoples, where battles were fought
without leaders or strategies, each warrior darting and shooting his arrows where
he could, exposed to volleys of arrows and spears, exposed not only to cunning
and hostile humans but also to supernatural powers and the weapons of sorcery.
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
92
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
Battles where no territory was taken, nor women captured or wealth plundered. You
are, despite all your ethics and your civilization, enthralled by the vision. You feel in
your throbbing legs and arms the vulnerability and audacity of their bare legs and
ballistic arms, not protected by camouflage and body armor but adorned with the
most ostentatious plumage. The exultation of their battle cries and chants echoing
across the mountains invades you and escalates in you. It is the fever and compulsion
that in our civilization of computerized, robotized warfare and high-tech high-altitude
surgical strikes, returns in the thousands of soldiers of fortune who go off to fight
conflicts in Congo, in Sierra Leone, in Nigeria, the thousands of mercenaries in
Iraq, conflicts in which they have no stake and for causes they do not believe in or
understand; it is the fever and exultation of the commando with no army or nation
behind them, their bodies driven by the pure force of their will, that crashed the
jetliners into the command centers of the world’s only superpower.
Here the tribal wars of today—the ragged young men defending with guns their
drug smuggling, the bands of raskals holding up trucks on the roads, occasionally
able to rob a foreign company manager or a tourist—give energy and passion to the
spectacle of phalanxes of magnificently arrayed men holding ten-foot long lances,
bows and arrows, and battle axes that are truly works of art. To the rages and
triumphs of today are joined hopes and despairs, terrors and audacities, rages
and triumphs from across thousands of years past. They are transfigured with a
splendor that closes in upon itself and expands with its own logic.
These extravagant headdresses of plumes, these shell necklaces, these boars
tusks and wigs were not only arrayed for war; they were donned for all the decisive
events of the lives of individuals and community—for births, for initiations, for
deaths, for the great pig feasts to which surrounding tribes, even enemy tribes, were
invited. Traditionally, highlands young men did not have obligations to share in the
work of building houses or work in the fields until they are married and set up their
own household. Before marriage, young men have few interests in gardening, pig
raising, payments or exchange; they spent their time in group festivities and displays.12 All-night singing and courting parties were frequent; young women dress in
their finery and invite young men who come unrecognizable in the extravagance of
their facial painting and body decorations, singing long-rehearsed songs in the falsetto voices of birds. The Huli young men, wearing their red wigs decorated with
flowers, their faces painted red and yellow, wearing the iridescent blue breast shield
of the Superb Bird of Paradise over their bodies painted red, spent a year parading
through the whole territory. They long to be like birds, fleet, brilliant, untamed.
Today too one cannot wander in the highlands without coming upon groups gathering in splendor for such events. And some churches, especially the Catholic ones,
now allow them.
277
A. Lingis
Paula Brown, Highland Peoples of New Guinea (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1978), 156.
12
8
Violence and Splendor: At the Limits of Hermeneutics
93
In the Mount Hagen Show the highlands tribes assemble with all their different
languages and cultures and conflicts and also with their past ordeals, combats, and
triumphs and face the present and the uncertain and menacing future before them.
Anyone who manages to experience the history of humanity as a whole as his own history
will experience in an enormously generalized way all the grief of an invalid who thinks of
health, of an old man who thinks of the dreams of his youth, of a lover deprived of his
beloved, of the martyr whose ideal is perishing, of the hero on the evening after a battle that
has decided nothing but brought him wounds and the loss of his friend. But if one endured,
if one could endure this immense sum of grief of all kinds while yet being the hero who, as
the second day of battle breaks, welcomes the dawn and his fortune, being a person whose
horizon encompasses thousands of years past and future, being the heir of all the nobility of
all past spirit—an heir with a sense of obligation, the most aristocratic of old nobles and at
the same time the first of a new nobility—the like of which no age has yet seen or dreamed
of; if one could burden one’s soul with all of this—the oldest, the newest, losses, hopes,
conquests, and the victories of humanity; if one could finally contain all this in one soul and
crowd it into a single feeling—this would surely have to result in a happiness that humanity
has not known so far: the happiness of a god full of power and love, full of tears and laughter, a happiness that, like the sun in the evening, continually bestows its inexhaustible riches,
pouring them into the sea, feeling richest, as the sun does, when the poorest fisherman is
rowing with golden oars! This godlike feeling would then be called—being human.13
This historical sense that Friedrich Nietzsche here invokes is not produced by an
intellectual operation of constructing linguistic representations of the forms and
meanings of past social structures, inventions, and conflicts; instead it is produced
by a return of the passions that created them—the grief over suffering and mutilation and killing, over lost causes and defeats, over ideals one has betrayed, the courage that has endured all these, the hope that opens long-range horizons, the sense of
honor that despises self-interest and cynicism. It is not the individual that willfully
constructs these feelings in himself; the ancient passions themselves return.
Nietzsche’s oldest and most fundamental source of his doctrine of the Eternal
Return was his conviction that our emotions are not simply excited by the stimuli
and cultural symbols at hand in our environment; they are transhistorical and animal
in us and the most archaic emotions can return in the socialized modern man. It was
the conviction that governed his first book: the conviction that he, and not the academic literary critics, understood the Greek tragedies because the passions of
Aeschylus and Sophocles pounded in his heart. In the late nineteenth century of
scientific, industrial, and mercantile Europe, he saw men and women in whom the
instincts and passions of hunters and gatherers, of warriors, of sixth-century-BCE
sages, and of Dark Ages saints return.
Nietzsche thinks that these ancient passions return in their full force when the
representations a people now make of themselves no longer elicit them. Sigmund
Freud found that when anxieties and cravings that date from some trauma or from
infancy are brought to the light of consciousness, fixed in conscious representations,
they lose their force to drive the individual. When those conscious representations
13
Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1974), § 337.
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
94
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
fade out, or are lost in some traumatic event, then the old anxieties and cravings
return. In Nietzsche’s conception, when a people represents itself as wholly civilized,
when its economy, political system, and ethics present only occasions for civilized
behavior, here and there the old instincts of hunters and of warriors returns; when it
represents its future as that of consumers in the global mercantilist economy that,
here and there, the instincts of sages and of saints return. More profoundly, the instincts
and emotions of our animality return. Behind instincts and emotions that are generated by culture Nietzsche found the wolf, cave bear, camel in us; Zarathustra’s overman has the instincts of lion, serpent, and dove crowded in his soul.
Nietzsche sees in the specific historical sense acquired in collective performances
the production of creativity, a creativity of splendor. In the crowded favelas of Rio
full of immigrants from the Mato Grosso and from the Amazon, former slaves from
Africa and wanderers from the old Inca provinces, invalids, old women, desperate
lovers, martyrs of vanquished causes, defeated guerrillas, but also men and women
who descend to the heart of the cidade maravilhosa and make it theirs, dressed in
the garb of the old emperors and aristocrats but still more glamorous, full of nothing
but alegria that pours out over the city and upon strangers from far-off lands—what
is produced of splendor. The return of so many nonintegrated and conflicting passions, crowded together such that each intensifies the others, produces the discharge
of excess forces, which are not channeled into economic or political projects but
discharged without recompense, released gratuitously. It is this collective situation
that is creative of splendor, for splendor is excessive and gratuitous.
The men and women marching, dancing, filling the air with cries and chants
under Mount Hagen, are splendid with the nacreous shells of mollusks, the skeletons and fangs of serpents, the tusks of boars, the teeth of flying foxes, the plumes
of birds. It is not humans who invented splendor. Everywhere humans have observed
the dances of antelopes, sea lions, emperor penguins, ostriches, pheasants, butterflies, crabs, understood them in their own bodies, and taken them up—dancing crane
dances, impala dances, oryx dances. “‘O Zarathustra,” the animals said, “to those
who think as we do, all things themselves are dancing: they come and offer their
hands and laugh and flee—and come back.’”14 Since our brother apes do not sing,
and indeed virtually no mammals sing, some anthropologists have speculated that
we must have picked up song from birds. Charles Darwin separated natural selection for fitness from the sexual selection for splendor, and ornithologists today have
experimentally verified that female peafowl, sage grouse, birds of paradise select
for their sexual favors males that display with the most elaborate dances the most
spectacular plumage, even though their ostentatious colors and entranced dances
makes them easy prey for predators, and the males of these species contribute nothing to the nest building and guarding and nurturing tasks that ensure the reproduction of the species. Contemplating the spectacular plumage and 6-month-long
359
A. Lingis
Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. Walter Kaufmann in The Portable Nietzsche
(New York: Viking, 1968), III, “The Convalescent,” 2.
14
8
Violence and Splendor: At the Limits of Hermeneutics
95
dances of the Malay Great Argus Pheasant, Darwin conceded that he could not find
any functional meaning in these excesses of splendor.
We shall not define with one concept the splendor that glitters and resounds
under Mount Hagen, in the liturgical processions in Byzantium and the high mass
of Mediaeval cathedrals, in the Negara, the theater-state of old Bali, in Carnaval in
Rio de Janeiro—in the plumage and dance of the Great Argus pheasant, in the sun’s
gold blended into the blue oceans, in the fisherman rowing with golden oars. But is
not the drive creative of splendor nature in our nature? We are mesmerized by beauty
as birds of paradise are mesmerized by their glittering plumes in their courtship
dances; we create beauty as in the primordial ocean mollusks create the iridescent
colors and intricate designs of their shells.
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
Author Query
Chapter No.: 8
0001327766
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please provide department name in the affiliation for the author
“Alphonso Lingis.”
Query
Part II
Critical Communities and Aesthetic
Subjects: Ethics, Politics, Action
1
2
3
Chapter 9
1
Community Beyond Instrumental Reason:
The Idea of Donation in Deleuze and Lyotard
2
3
James Williams
4
5
6
7
No less than a determination of signification, nonsense operates a donation of sense. But
this is not at all in the same way. Since, from the point of view of sense, the regressive law
no longer connects the names of different degrees to classes or to properties, but distributes
them in heterogeneous series of events.2
8
9
10
11
Passibility, as possibility of undergoing (pathos), presupposes a donation. If we are passible,
it is because something happens to us, and when that passibility has a fundamental status
donation is itself something fundamental, originary.1
9.1
“197.5”
12
It’s your results: “197.5,” written in a small box on the output from the doctor’s
printer. As the explanation begins, in the dispassionateness learned not from theories about objectivity but long experience of the mutual needs for distance and for
the clarity of simple repetition, the number begins to take its place in longer series
of meanings. Event turns into sensory effects. Effects coagulate into affects. Affects
generate phantasms and images. We have come to expect more though – some of us,
not all of us, and only very recently on any great scale. What will be done? How can
the number become part of a chain that defuses its power to terrify and doom? How
can the event be defused, rather than spread through our lives and over those we love
and hate? Where is the cure? Images must become real.
Jean-François Lyotard, ‘Quelque chose comme: “communication sans communication”’ in
L’inhumain: causeries sur le temps (Paris: Galilée, 1988), 119–130, esp. 121–122.
2
Gilles Deleuze, Logique du sense (Paris: Minuit, 1969), p. 87.
1
J. Williams (*)
Philosophy, School of Humanities, Dundee University, Dundee, UK
e-mail: j.r.williams@dundee.ac.uk
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_9, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
99
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
100
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
So how could some philosophers in our hopeful scientific age call that small
phrase, this fatal number, a donation? I do not want to be donated “197.5,” give me
“122.33”. It’s not a donation anyway. It’s a curse, cruel revenge, fate, blind necessity, stupid chance, but not a gift, not a generous contribution to my lifecycle.
Donation: the meaning of the word has become banal, in the way most of our words
are now chained to dominant behaviours or scenes, snapshots from visual and aural
media, rather than the products of a slower, more disciplined but perhaps also more
free textual research. I’ll make a donation. Have you donated? Please donate now!
Your gesture will make a difference! (It’s also tax deductible…) When Gilles Deleuze
and Jean-François Lyotard used the French word, donation, 20 years apart in the
Logic of Sense and ‘Something like “communication without communication”’, in
order to capture an important characteristic of events, perhaps even the essence of
events, they not only relied on a different etymology than our young charitable
meaning, but also took the word and bent it to different understandings of events.
The stakes here then are not directly about the meaning of donation, but rather about
whether events can properly be called donations, as opposed to facts, to meaningful
information, or to ‘particular things that happen to us’.
The scale of Deleuze and Lyotard’s task can be measured against the tenacity and
long tentacles of the current images. Today, a donation is from a subject: we give a
donation. This giving is not symmetrical, though (something Deleuze and Lyotard
understand very well and will make important use of ). The modern charitable donation never goes to a subject. Who really wants to be the recipient of a donation?
Who would not rather be in a possible world where the need for donation was
absent, or where they were in the luxurious position of benefactor? The donation
does not therefore go to a counter activity. It goes to a lack, or to a cause, or towards
an image, or to a projection generated by the giving subject: my good kind heart and
their suffering; my conscience and those pictures with their unwanted power to
haunt the most superficial levels of the unconsciou, and shape deeper ones. A donation is a gift, not the gift of legend implying authentic self-sacrifice, but the simulacrum of an offering, the holiday gift, the childhood bribe, the phantasm of boxed
happiness, cleaned slate, unambiguous message. “With this broach I love you.”
“With these regular 72 florins, I express my humanity and make it universal.” “With
this 14 billion I change the world.” A donation is good. Never good enough though,
but relatively so; yet not wrong for all that, it is another of our modern accommodations with something like community without commonality, or community without
equality. A donation is therefore always measurable and measured, weighed not for
its absolute value (“I will always be your servant”) but to set position within modern
manners and self-analysis (“Is this enough?” “The tithe has always been more in
this parish, of course if that’s what you are comfortable with…” “Oh! You are too
generous. No – it really is too much, really!” “I have worked hard in order to be able
to give and there lies my superior value and salvation.”)
This measurement or calculation and its relation to effectiveness and to objective
facts, laid out before and after the act of giving, is one of the main worries behind
Deleuze’s and Lyotard’s work. The latter says it best in the title of his short article:
23
J. Williams
9 Community Beyond Instrumental Reason...
101
‘Something like “communication without communication”…’ Lyotard is discussing
the possibility of art that does not depend on the communication of meaning and on
the exchange of measurable goods and outcomes. He does not mean art without
community. Rather, in a reading following Adorno, Kant and Heidegger,3 Lyotard
searches for a community presupposed by art when it interpolates, introduces a new
event into the flow of phrases, and thereby connects, creating some kind of community, but without communicating a meaning or measured substance.4 This community is a precondition for art as unmediated communication, where mediation
must be understood as the presence of a representation in the transmission process
of information. In the mediated art of representative communication, something is
exchanged through the art-work – a message, a picture of an original, a perception,
an experience, an affect, a monetary value, a concept. The event of art is therefore
subsumed under the fact of that communication and the community called for by the
artwork depends on ‘getting’ the communication. It is therefore a restricted community; some will ‘connect’, some will not, dependent on possession of the right
meanings, feelings, prior experiences and interests (economic and libidinal).
Communication in this representative form leads to a community of competing
interests and calculations. According to Lyotard, in such a state art disappears. But
is there ever a community dependent on the event as donation without measured or
meaningful exchange?
9.1.1
La volonté du Ciel soit faite en toute chose
The original context of Lyotard’s article was a conference on art and communication. His contribution, written in his ironic phase where a top-line message is undermined by subtle yet devastating counters, is a three-phase critique of the chosen
topic. First, Lyotard makes the point that art has to be ‘communication without communication’ for otherwise it cannot differentiate itself from other modes of exchange,
advertising or commentary. Second, Lyotard points out that in our postmodern age
it has become much harder to achieve this communication without communication
because the modes of art and its contexts have become largely conceptual. Not only
is the artwork itself conceptual, where any material presence is mediated by a conceptual account, from the near-ubiquitous commentary label, this work is an evocation of the fissure running through contemporary civilisation, to the mass media and
marketing demands on artists’ lives, tell us about your background and intentions –
and the sex and desire – and then pose for the photo… The work also depends on a
conceptual environment for its transmission, commercial success, measure of value,
3
4
‘Quelque chose comme: “communication sans communication”’ p. 119–122.
Ibid. p. 120.
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
situation within society, and position as political. As communicators the works must
enter a pre-existing flow of ‘discourse’ standing as a condition for their being as
what is to be recognised as art. The artwork thereby bathes in conceptual mediation
and one of Lyotard’s questions is whether we can remove it from this discursive
fluid yet keep it alive, that is, in a living relation with its community as resistant to
mediated communication and representation.
Finally, Lyotard adds the most powerful ironic twist – indicated by the suspension points at the end of his title. There is nothing definite in this communication
without communication; it is a question or a wager; itself a risky donation left hanging not only in his title but also the last lines of his text. In an era of electronic communication, of email and mobile phone, is there space for something like
communication without communication?5 Can those forms of communication
achieve it: ‘Can something happen through it? Can something happen to it?’6 For
Lyotard, the artwork does not presuppose a community of subjects based around
shared meanings, a shared essence or properties, shared values, or even shared feelings. The presupposed community is determined by an inseparable dispossession
and passibility, where the feeling of pathos is not a specific sensation that we could
positively describe and value, but rather a negative state where we are shorn of
meaning and direction. That’s why he is interested in donation, not where we are
subjects of the verb to donate, but where something is donated to us, something
registers in our sense apparatus, but we know not what, ‘something like communication without communication’. However, the fact that something arrives resistant
to representation means that a community is created as the group of those capable
of registering the arrival and the lack of set information. In registering this, the
members of the community – in principle any being open to a combination of sensation and questioning – are obligated to the event. The sensation and questioning are
that obligation.
In art we have a donation free of representation but not free of obligation. There
is a remnant of this sense in our usage of the verb ‘to donate’, but it is one associated
with everything tawdry about donation, where the donated to are supposedly obligated or beholden to those who give. I would not want to be beholden… I’d rather
die… The subtlety of Lyotard’s position is in its avoidance of an archaic, cap-doffing
gratitude and debt, because nothing positive is demanded in the donation, it comes
before exchange and active subjects, as a condition for any such representation or
activity. There has to be a donation – an event, an arrival – before we can speak and
act upon any happening thing.7 The artwork in its materiality reveals the event prior
to communication and thereby depends upon a community of those who can be
donated to. Matter is therefore important for Lyotard as something that is given
prior to signification. It is also important because in any communication there has to
102
J. Williams
Ibid., p. 127.
Ibid., p. 129.
7
Ibid., p 122.
5
6
9 Community Beyond Instrumental Reason...
103
be a material support – even in virtual media where sounds or colours are required
to translate code into sensations.
The universality of the community addressed by this materiality is not empirical
for Lyotard (nothing could be) but it is transcendental. The universal community is
a condition for material communication. His argument goes through a series of
steps that replicate the kind of transcendental deduction of community in his subsequent readings of Kant.8 First, the community of those addressed must not have the
contingent limitations of possession and capacity associated with meaning, because
this would set signification as a prior condition for being addressed. Any member of
the community must be able to register a difference beyond representation independent of their capacity to understand a meaning or assess an exchange. Second, in
response to the question ‘Why a community rather than a monadic individual or set
of individuals?’ those addressed must form a community through their obligation to
the donation or event. It is a community of obligation but not of specific answers to
that obligation. ‘Why is this community in principle universal? If we accept that any
communication depends on a material donation prior to signification, then, independent of whether those addressed acknowledge the donation, they must have been
donated to if they are addressed in any way. The only restriction on the community
is that its members must be capable of being donated to. Lyotard’s argument is that
underlying all communication there is a material event and, because this event is not
itself significant, it is an invitation to decipher or respond to a donation that cannot
be satisfactorily responded to. Any communication conceals a failure to communicate as its condition. This failure determines a universal community.
The original meaning of the French term donation is legal, signifying a gift
without preconditions or a free gift (gratuitous, in its first non-pejorative sense).
The Littré dictionary cites Molière’s use in Tartuffe (Act 3 Scene 7) where the
hypocritical manoeuvres of Tartuffe over his master, Orgon, come close to attaining their final goal in Orgon’s donation of all his worldly goods to Tartuffe, the
scheming false-zealot. Molière is then more of a cynic than Lyotard: the donation
has been manufactured and is part of a struggle over wealth and influence (Tartuffe
has just feinted to leave Orgon’s family to save Orgon’s relation with his wife who
he also desires). For the playwright, donation is never unconditional and the sign
of ever-present calculation is Tartuffe’s duplicity in a smarmy thanks to a God he
does not believe in, the guarantor of the unconditional, and a conspiratorial wink to
powers he does give allegiance to, human gullibility and his own greed and their
place in the operations of instrumental reason: ‘La volonté du Ciel soit faite en
toute chose.’9 Is Molière closer to the truth here than Lyotard? There are no free
donations and everything is calculation and rational distribution? There is no
8
9
Jean-François Lyotard, Leçons sur l’analytique du sublime (Paris: Galilée, 1991).
Molière, Le Tartuffe (Paris: Gallimard, 1999) acte 3, scène 7.
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
104
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
otherworldly power that can guarantee a free act? Even in law, a donation can
always be rescinded? He was not in his right mind, your honour.
Lyotard’s answer is a threefold challenge. First, he writes to convey the arrival of
an event free of representation and therefore to show how communication can occur
without having to be the communication of meaning or information. This writing is
critical in showing the limits of representation; it shows what is missed if life is only
communication taken as representation. When a determined fact, whether calculable or interpretable, is represented we miss the ethical and political import of differences we should be obligated to testify to rather than reduce to identities. Lyotard’s
writing is creative in fragmenting ideas and genres, thereby making disjointed
spaces and times for experiences of events through ironic overlapping of inconsistent ideas and sensations. This disjointedness is designed to make way for the material side of any event, where matter is distinct from message. Many of his essays
collected in The Inhuman therefore focus on the difficult task of forging times and
spaces that are not those of unifying representation, that is, forms of space and time
that contain representations and organise them into coherent order according to
series of ideas (such as progress towards ideas such as the good or scalar increases
in important measures such as profit, productivity or growth). The collection and
its title are therefore misunderstood if taken as advocating inhumanity in the sense
of an ethical value. The point is instead to reveal the role of instrumental reason,
teleology and representation in the concept of the human. It is also to advocate
forms of ethical community free of the demands and consequences of representation
and measured equivalences and exchanges. If to be human is to follow an unconditional ethic, beyond even the Kantian test of universalisability, then Lyotard’s
inhuman is still humanist.
Second, according to Lyotard, events necessarily register initially through passivity by stunning us and forcing us into series of tentative questions. To follow
these events is necessary; to follow them in a way that does justice to the form of
donation is an obligation. The challenge is then how to respond and find new ways
of testifying to the events and to the differences they gesture to. If we are to be true
to the events that happen to us, we must not bury them under final representations
and subsequent communications of information.
So, third, this is not to say that there must be no representative communication,
but any claim for the sufficiency of the communication of meaning must be resisted.
This resistance takes the form of an extension of the donation found in art into any
phrase, at least as a possibility. There has to be an event in any representation and
the challenge is to draw this out and thereby to draw out the ethical and political
stakes underlying ‘mere’ communication. The obligation resulting from donation is
then to sense and then to struggle to testify to the multiple and irreducibly different
stakes in any event. The necessity of donation is that we cannot escape having to
follow the donation. Donation is not therefore to be simply passive to events, but
rather to be passive to the sensation that any given model of what the event means,
of its value and future path, is necessarily insufficient and in a struggle with different models, despite the fact that following the event is necessary. This combination
179
J. Williams
9 Community Beyond Instrumental Reason...
105
of necessity and obligation allows Lyotard to claim that we can never have done
with donation or with differends (the irreducibly multiple and agonistic side to any
event). To follow is not an obligation, but to testify is.10
9.2
Points, Lines and Process
Le différend, p. 260.
James Williams, Lyotard and the Political (London: Routledge, 2000), 133–134.
12
Maria Prodromou, “Writing, Event, Resistance” (PhD thesis, University of Essex, 2008).
11
224
225
226
This essay started on the doctor’s couch. Lyotard’s prescription as outlined above
can seem perverse and unsatisfactory when viewed from the urgency conveyed by a
portentous number and a poor prognostic. His point though has never been to turn
away from the message, context and rational understanding of any given phrase. It
is rather that in addition to these are the many tracks competing for the legacy of the
phrase. We also have to be aware that the phrase – even the diagnostic number –
does not allow for a resolution of this competition. That’s why it is a donation. Of
course we should seek cures. The point is not to conceal the struggling pressures at
work in any given choice, whether this be in terms of social equity, existential
choices, balances of pain and longevity, awareness of our strength and fears and –
above all – the differences these carry with them in our relations to others (In the
end it’s my decision! – No it is not…) Simply stated, Lyotard appeals to the obligation conveyed with the donation of an event in order to insist upon the political and
ethical responsibility following on from any phrase. This appeal is a resistance to
the way in which communication as representation tends towards the hegemony of
a particular set of values.
It is a mistake to think that Lyotard’s description of the event as a donation is
incoherent, nihilistic or lacking in guidance for activity. It is reasonable to indicate
the limits of instrumental reason. There is no nihilism or implied passivity in defending the obligation to difference and to insoluble conflict in the event, since part of
that obligation is still to do something. In earlier writing, I criticised this work on the
event for the nihilism implied by the lack of specific structures for activity to take
place.11 I now realise that the demand to testify has some such structures through the
multiplication of genres and the effort to write forms of communication resistant
to communication (as representation). This point is made forcefully and with
great precision by Maria Prodromou in her thesis Writing, Event, Resistance.12
Nonetheless, these structures are thin and dominated by aesthetic considerations.
Perhaps though these are not necessary limitations and we can see a possible extension of Lyotard’s use of donation in Deleuze’s earlier use of the term in relation to
the event. The problem with an aesthetic approach to the event lies in the line/interruption model it depends upon.
10
223
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
106
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
For Lyotard the event breaks a concatenation of phrases, flow of images, train of
conceptual understanding, cycle of exchange, or indeed combinations of all of these
linear developments.13 Thus when he uses the term donation it is associated with a
stop combined with a remnant of forward momentum. The silent actor teeters over
the precipice shocked into a halt by its sudden appearance yet still shakily propelled
towards the void. Whether before the paintings of Barnett Newman or in the ingression of a misplaced phrase, the sublime event in Lyotard combines this external
ambiguous trigger and an internal sensual conflict: rupture and invitation; lack and
desire; terror and pleasure; obligation and absence of rule.14 The pragmatic effect of
this structure is the concern to act in a state where no rules exist as to how to act.
This lack invites the accusation of nihilism, but can be countered by the response
that there is an invitation to create such rules in writing after the event. The fact that
no rules exist does not mean that we cannot act.
However, the resulting line/interruption/creation model still seems to narrow
down real situations. Life is rarely determined by all encompassing events, such as
a transforming shock. It is not that such events do not occur (Lyotard is right to
tenaciousness remind us of such devastating yet obligating events in his work on
Auschwitz). It is rather that life is not always like this. So it could be that the form
of any event depends on a more complicated and less linear background. Sublime
events, on a grand scale, do occur but they do so within ongoing lines that can be
pushed into the background yet continue. As you leave the doctor’s office ordinary
life continues, changed for sure, but not in a uniform manner and not such that the
event can be taken as the key either to understanding its broad context, or even its
own status as sublime interruption. The problem is therefore that in the paradoxical
interruption put forward by Lyotard nothing is communicated other than a necessity
to begin communication anew and an obligation to be faithful to the sublime event.
His account of donation is extreme in repudiating that there is anything at all
donated. This extremism has the strength of resisting the return of utility and
restricted signification in communication (that it is about outcomes and particular
transfers of meaning) yet it has weakness in setting out a narrow and implausible
model for how the many lines of communication and creative thought take form
around and through events. Real events are multiple and complex, as are real sentiments, they are neither linear nor defined according to dualistic opposition such as
terror and pleasure, or repulsion and attraction around a single occurrence.
In Logic of Sense, Deleuze studies the relation of events to language and instead
of situating the event as a break in a concatenation of sentences he extends the event
as a process along multiple lines themselves divided into four linguistic forms:
denotation (or reference), signification (or meaning), manifestation (or utterance)
and sense (not meaning, but intensity).15 An event therefore changes from the model
258
J. Williams
Le différend, p. 103.
See L’instant, Newman’ in L’inhumain, pp. 89–100.
15
Logique du sens, pp. 22–35.
13
14
9 Community Beyond Instrumental Reason...
107
of a line punctuated by breaks to a process that travels along a series back and
forward in time. The event therefore resonates, rather than interrupts. It creates
interferences and disjunctions, rather than cuts and new beginnings. For instance,
the mark on the note handed to you by the doctor has a well-defined denotation and
this allows the note to refer to ulterior and future denotable things (your past body
and future one, for example). Yet this denotation is incomplete unless it is accompanied by a signification, something that adds meaning to the denoted things (dying,
suffering, growing). Without the signification the denotation is mere neutral fact.
Again, this meaning travels back and forward along series (you thought you were
dying, but you were not; you thought you had this future and it became that one).
Yet this meaning is itself incomplete unless it is situated with respect to what manifests it. Without such manifestation we cannot judge the truth and falsity of the
connection of denoted thing and signification. The manifestation gives the here,
now and who which transform a statement such as ‘a body has this property’ to ‘this
body has this property’, or ‘I love you’ to ‘I love you’. Finally, neither denotation,
nor signification, nor manifestation have any value unless they are associated with a
sense, that is, a felt and expressed intensity turning brute fact into individuated
significance, shared meaning into a singular effect, and manifestation by a welldetermined individual into a process of becoming.
Deleuze calls this process ‘the circle of the proposition.’ It is movement from
denotation, to signification, to manifestation and back to denotation via the role of
sense. In other words, language is generated by the search for value and significance
defined as the production of sense (as opposed to signification). The event works as
sense unlocks paradoxes in language and its relation to the world: What is denotation
without meaning? What is meaning without who and where that meaning is for?
What is that location and identity without value? How can there be genuine value,
if not through the transformation of those identities? The astonishing inventiveness
of Deleuze’s study of language in relation to the event lies not only in the claim that
the paradoxes are what allows language to work without being reduced to the
priority of one or other of its components, strictly to denoted facts, or to manifested
intentions, for instance. The brilliance is also in the generating role of sense, that is,
in the claim that the world referred to, the meanings about it and the individuals
arise out of the production of sense and value, out of the intensities occurring in the
world. Moreover, these values are themselves incomplete unless they are expressed
in the world. The figure “197.5” is only complete when it is associated with a meaning, itself associated with an individual (or series of individuals), where all of these
require the intensity of a value that transforms each one forward and back in time,
or along series – since Deleuze claims that time is constituted by events, rather than
events occurring in a pre-given time. An event is a transformation generated by the
expression of a change in intensity.
So why does Deleuze use the term donation in the passage quoted in exergue?
How can he respond to a critique based on Lyotard’s intuitions that the event must
somehow be beyond representation and exchange, if Deleuze’s processes can be
charted and evaluated? The answer is that sense is a donation for Deleuze. The process of generation cannot be represented, traced or repeated and, instead, sense and
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
108
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
the other components of the proposition are involved in asymmetrical processes
where they determine one another but are neither reversible nor subject to rules and
functions allowing for inductive moves or secure predictions.16 That’s why his work
in Logic of Sense is so dependent on paradoxes to ensure that no logic comes to
flatten denotation onto signification, or sense on to manifestation. This means that
despite its character as process the event is still a donation in Lyotard’s usage as
resistant to interpretation and free of transcendent rules. The challenge for both
thinkers is how a singular event is to be worked with or replayed in the absence of
rules. Yet, for Deleuze, there is much more precise material to work on forward and
back in time in terms of the structures that are transformed by the event. We are not
hit by a wall that stops time and disrupts space, but rather by a series of waves or
folds travelling through us, initiating transformations and demanding creative solutions. These will necessarily be creative in the radical sense of having to create
themselves without external guidance and with the demand for genuine novelty
(a thoroughgoing and detailed transformation of a world).
There is hence great closeness between Lyotard and Deleuze in their use of the
concept of donation, because for both a donation is beyond meaning and beyond
exchange. The discussions of language in Le différend and Logique du sens have
many fascinating parallels, extending from the critique of the dominance of reference, through the importance of paradox for understanding how language works, on
to the search for a domain of language beyond reference and meaning. For Deleuze,
the donation of sense or value occurs through nonsense, an occurrence that registers, setting off puzzles and thereby having an effect, but where this effect resists
incorporation into preset meanings, or forms for the reception of facts. Nonsense
though is not rare; it a potential for any phrase, where its utterance has the effect of
disruption and transformation (It’s a girl! But it has to be a boy. You failed. I cannot
afford to fail. Never speak to me like that again. Life is nothing without you.
I cannot believe anymore. What is my life without belief?) For Lyotard, the donation occurs whenever a phrase resists the incorporation into genres such as a given
account of the proper form of knowledge in its relation to progress, or a given
discourse on the form and value of art. The difference between the two philosophies
is therefore in the detailed effect of donation, rather than its essential form as disruptive, obligating and inviting creative responses. This leaves two pressing questions:
What is at stake in these remaining differences? Are these differences so great as to
mean we have to choose between the two models, or is at matter of inflexion and
appropriateness for different situations, where Lyotard is the thinker better adapted
to the reception of Newman’s paintings, Kant’s sublime and Adorno’s aesthetic
theory, but where Deleuze allows for a more intricate and open response to the relations between Bacon’s figures and triptychs, Nietzsche and Foucault’s genealogies
and Hume’s account of the role of repetition and the inventiveness of the imagination in habit and the passions?
342
J. Williams
16
Ibid., pp. 217–218, 226–227.
9 Community Beyond Instrumental Reason...
9.3
109
Withdrawal and Donation
383
The question of the sublime is tightly linked in some way to what Heidegger calls the
withdrawal of Being, the withdrawal of donation. The welcome paid to the sensible, that is,
to sense embodied in the here-and-now before any concept would no longer have place and
moment. This withdrawal would signify our current destiny.17
Lyotard follows Heidegger up to the withdrawal in donation: any phrase is a withdrawal even when it is also a communication of meaning and the basis for an
exchange. Even a phrase as simple as a command such as “Do your duty” is a withdrawal. In setting out an exchange of rights and responsibilities, of relations of
belonging to a community and exclusion, of acts sanctioned and forbidden, of
rewards and punishments, the phrase also invites questions about the justice of these
rights, rewards and punishments, of the limits of community; the clashes occurring
at those limits; and within any given community (which is never homogeneous.)
These questions and our desire to answer them have no intrinsic limits and there are
no rules as to their propriety or for determining the number or value of any questions. Questioning comes after a donation and can never determine it; on the contrary, that the questions remain undetermined depends on the donation defined as a
withdrawal rather than a giving of any well-determined thing. For Lyotard the phrase
can never simply command obedience and to give or receive it as such is to ignore
what withdraws in the phrase as it is uttered and received. This ambiguity and openness of the phrase in all its linguistic relations (reference, meaning, manifestation
and sense) is however not a fate for Lyotard, and this is where he departs from
Heidegger. It is instead a political problem and state of affairs. We have to respond
to the tension between what we can understand in the phrase, but also to what is
beyond knowledge and understanding and therefore calling for new responses –
ones that neither pretend that withdrawal is an inevitable fate, nor an eliminable
passing phase.
Withdrawal is a translation of the French word retrait, or retreat. It can seem that
if we think of donation as retreat we are ceding too much to ideas of abandonment
and cessation, when action is called for and failure to act is a betrayal of life, desire
and community. A joint reading of Lyotard and Deleuze’s versions of donation
allows the idea to move away from any association with retreat. Withdrawal becomes
part of a creative and affirmative process. For Deleuze donation is dual: a withdrawal of sense and a donation of sense according to a division in structures between
a placeless occupant signified by our questions and the intensities that fire them, and
an empty space signified by our efforts to identify novel solutions to recurrent problems.18 The occupant and the space run back and forward along parallel but separate
series; each series is incomplete without the other, but whenever one is referred to
the other it commences a disjunction within it. The new question splits answers to
17
18
‘Quelque chose comme: “communication sans communication”,’ p. 124.
Logique du sens, pp. 54–56.
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
110
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
old ones and those answers transform old questions and demand new ones. Placeless
occupant and empty place never finally coincide because they belong to asymmetrical
processes and series; as the question finds an answer it changes into a new question,
or, in Lyotard’s terminology, each new phrase is itself an event and a donation.
Everything is in the creative search, which is politically active but never secure, nor
finished, nor satisfied. The event is always a donation, but this donation does give
something: a problem.19 The problem generates a creative search for its solutions. It
also sunders those solutions and demands new ones. Lyotard’s work defines phrases
such that they are singularities as defined by Deleuze and, in turn, Deleuze defines
events as problems determined by these singularities. A donation is then the gift of
a problem, not an insoluble puzzle, but the genesis of series of temporary solutions
invited to affirm multiplicity and impermanence.
422
J. Williams
19
Ibid., pp. 68–69.
Chapter 10
1
The Political Horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s
Ontology
2
3
4
Duane H. Davis
5
ro
of
To Tony O’Connor, in memory of Martin C. Dillon*
P
Ange, plein de gaeité, connaissez-vous l’angoisse,
La hante, les remords, les sanglots, les ennuis,
Et les vague terreurs de ces affreuses nuits,
Qui compriment la coeur comme un papier qu’on froisse?
Ange, plein de gaeité, connaissez-vous l’angoisse?1
ct
ed
Certainly, Merleau-Ponty was no angel, despite the conflicting testimony you may
have heard from Sartre. In his 100-plus page eulogy of Merleau-Ponty, Sartre said
Charles Baudelaire, Les Fleurs du mal, “Réversibilité,” (Paris: Garnier-Flannarion, 1964), 69.
U
1
nc
or
re
* I dedicate this essay to my friend and colleague Tony O’Connor. From an outsider’s perspective,
Tony has done more than anyone to animate the venerable British Society for Phenomenology by
painstakingly calling for dialogue between orthodox phenomenology [if indeed there is such a thing]
and more contemporary Continental work. And please note that it is not the sort of stultifying dialogue
of compromise and “meet in the middle” that I have in mind here. His spirit of friendship complements
his infectious passion for philosophical argument. I am forever indebted to Tony for opening my eyes
to new possibilities in the work of Michel Foucault. I salute Tony’s generosity and dedication to
philosophy and to his friends. I am proud to contribute this essay to this volume in his honor.
One very important mutual friend of ours was Martin C. Dillon, who died in spring 2005.
I shall always cherish the memories with Tony of feasting and spirited conversation long into the
night at the Dillons’ house. The memories are as sweet as the loss is painful.
Angel full of happiness, do you know the anguish,
The shame, the remorse, the sobs the ennui,
And the vague terrors of these frightful nights
That compress the heart like a paper one wads up?
Angel full of happiness, do you know the anguish?
[All translations are mine unless noted.]
D.H. Davis (*)
Professor of Philosophy, The University of North Carolina, Asheville
Distinguished Scholar in Residence [Visiting Research Professor of Philosophy],
Pontificia Universidade Católica do Paraná, Curitiba, Brasil
e-mail: ddavis@unca.edu
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_10, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
111
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
112
D.H. Davis
34
10.1
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
35
36
37
38
39
P
20
ed
19
ct
18
Means
re
17
Each of us was trying to understand the world insofar as he could, and with the access at his
disposal. And we had the same means—then called Husserl and Heidegger—since we were
similarly disposed.6
or
16
To begin, let us briefly assess Merleau-Ponty’s existential-phenomenological
approach. This will show how he came to develop his situated ontology. I will
nc
15
U
14
ro
of
33
that his contemporary’s philosophy was hopelessly optimistic and insufficiently
radical because he, Merleau-Ponty, “had never recovered from an incomparable
childhood.”2 But Merleau-Ponty’s ontology is not a warm existential hug, a nostalgic return to mother, a naively optimistic account of a unifying ideal Being, nor a
pure foundation of any kind. Instead, it is my conviction that Merleau-Ponty’s
ontology is an account of an existence fraught with anguish,3 remorse, dread, conflict, an existence where there be monsters. Without lapsing into a pessimistic
“l’enfer, c’est les autres”4 cartoon agon, where “each consciousness wills the death
of the other,”5 Merleau-Ponty nonetheless portrays an unstable existence, which
we actively destabilize and disturb just by being together; and there is both promise
and peril in this instability.
Here, by demonstrating the means, the motive, and the opportunity, I want to establish that Merleau-Ponty is “guilty” of crafting a compromised, contingent account of
Being. (It will not be beyond the shadow of a doubt, but within it.) That is, contrary to
the commonplace view initiated by Sartre, Merleau-Ponty’s later work is not innocent
or naïvely optimistic, nor does it eschew politics. Of course, Merleau-Ponty’s ontology did not emerge in a vacuum. I will argue that his account of Being is best understood when we attend to its provenance, that is, when we situate it within the continuous
development of his thought over his career. More specifically, we need to call attention
to the political horizon of this ontology as it emerged in Merleau-Ponty’s thought; this
has received insufficient attention in secondary literature.
13
2
Jean-Paul Sartre and Merleau-Ponty, Situations, trans. B. Eisler (Braziller: New York, 1965),
228.
3
Cf. Maurice Merleau-Ponty and F. Alqui, eds., Les Philosophes Célèbres (Paris: Mazenod, 1956),
250–251; “La découverte de l’histoire,” where Merleau-Ponty concludes that the structure of
history is anguish. [Cf. also my translation: Man and World 25, no. 2 (April 1992):203–209]. Here
I translated the aforementioned piece as well as “Les fondateurs.” These short pieces were introductory blurbs that Merleau-Ponty wrote for the sections of the anthology he and Alqui edited
together. He gathered all of the introductory blurbs—save these two—and published the rest as the
essay “Everywhere and Nowhere,” which appeared in Signes (Paris: Gallimard, 1960), 203–258.
4
Jean-Paul Sartre, “No Exit,” in No Exit and Three other Plays, trans. S. Gilbert (New York:
Vintage, 1989), 45.
5
Simone de Beauvoir, L’Invitée (Paris: Gallimard, 1943), 8 [quoting Hegel].
6
Sartre, Merleau-Ponty (op. cit.), p. 228.
[AU1]
10
The Political Horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology
113
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
provide an indirect description, in keeping with Merleau-Ponty’s modus operandi.
Thus, I will proceed by considering four philosophical approaches, or means,
each of which Merleau-Ponty rejects while allowing it to partially inform his own
position.
First, Merleau-Ponty rejects any straightforward idealism (“spiritualisme”) that
maintains that the truth of the world is strictly a product of the human intellect. He
rejects this position without trivializing it, but by pushing it as far as it can go toward
accounting for our existence in the world. The promise of idealism, for MerleauPonty, is that it captures the activity we undertake in perceiving our world literally
as we make sense of it. And Merleau-Ponty worked with this means of accounting
for our labor of living until he drew his last breath—collapsing while reading
Descartes in May of 1961. Nonetheless, idealism forsakes lived experience; and we
do not seem to have direct, immediate access to the ideals through consciousness,
as idealists of various sorts maintained.
Second, Merleau-Ponty rejects the straightforward empiricism (“mechanisme”)
that accounts for our sentient experience by explaining it away as a mechanical byproduct or epiphenomenon. Once again, Merleau-Ponty tarries alongside empiricism throughout his career—from his youthful interest in psychophysics and
psychological research in perception to his emphasis upon the bodily comportment
of the artist and the materiality of painting in his last published work, l’Oeil et
l’Esprit. Nonetheless, there is something more to life than the partes extra partes
means of accounting for our existence in the world as “one damned thing after
another.” I do not seem to have immediate access to empirical truths. Life is situated
empirically but is not reducible to empirical objectivity.
Third, Merleau-Ponty empirically rejects the brilliant innovation of transcendental idealism, which emerged from a productive tension between the aforementioned
dogmatic idealism and dogmatic empiricism. This critical alternative safeguards the
truth of Being in universal a priori conditions for the possibility of experience, and
regards the self that dwells in the muck and mire of contingent experience with great
suspicion. However, while a transcendental foundation for the truths of experience
remedies the skepticism that one naturally adopts upon recognition of the contingency of experience, it does so a little too well, and lapses into a new form of idealism. Perhaps Merleau-Ponty acknowledges that a transcendental turn is the essence
of the future of philosophy itself; but transcendental reflection cannot lay claim to
truths that are pure. The magic of synthetic a priori judgments casts too powerful a
spell upon a problem that Merleau-Ponty desperately wants to own up to: how to
envision ideals and truths in the context of our mundane existence; in short, how we
share a world that matters to us.
Finally, Merleau-Ponty rejects (transforms!) traditional Husserlian phenomenology. This, from a starting point of embracing the fundamental insight that consciousness is intentional, an insight that implies that consciousness had previously
been too narrowly defined; consciousness, properly re-defined, is “consciousness of
something.” The first sentence of Merleau-Ponty’s first book indicates that his
research plan, which he carried out for the rest of his life, was precisely to pursue
this insight: he states that he is investigating “the relations between consciousness
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
114
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
ro
of
92
P
91
ed
90
ct
89
re
88
or
87
nc
86
and nature—organic, psychological, or even social.”7 True to his word, during the
first part of his career, Merleau-Ponty focused on a radical reconfiguration of consciousness, stressing an embodied consciousness. And the last part of his career can
be seen as a radical reconfiguration of nature, as we shall see later in this essay.8
Taken as a whole, then, Merleau-Ponty’s life’s work, his phenomenology of perception (the project), placed a new emphasis upon embodied consciousness, and called
for a bodily intentionality; the body is situated within its world, conforming to a
world that it shapes through its actions.
Thus, Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology is a departure from his predecessors’.
He recognized within traditional phenomenology aspects of the idealism it was
designed to overcome. Traditional phenomenology purported to approach phenomena through the epochē, or bracketing, of any theoretical and natural presuppositions. This led to a reduction of the phenomenon to its essence, with necessary and
certain knowledge still as the expectation or goal. In contrast, Merleau-Ponty
famously states that, while the traditional phenomenological approach was generally right-minded, “the greatest teaching of the reduction is the impossibility of a
complete reduction.”9 Thus, apodictic knowledge, the promise of traditional phenomenology, is compromised in Merleau-Ponty’s approach, which determines
rather to “put essences back into existence.”10 Historically, of course, only God’s
essence is said to entail its own existence. So there is something vaguely heretical
about the project of so closely relating the two terms in human experience.
Most often, Merleau-Ponty’s reinsertion of essences into existence is read as a
corrective response to Husserl’s traditional phenomenology. And surely, an important aspect of its contex is precisely that Husserl’s phenomenology, in spite of its
own avowed goal, demonstrates its relevance in its failure, that is, when we realize
the inexhaustibility of the project. However, Merleau-Ponty’s move can also be seen
as an anticipatory response to Sartre’s slogan that our “existence precedes our
essence,”11 for putting essences back into existence renders them contingent. Sartre’s
overstated claim that there is no essence to our existence, that we are essentially
nothing at all, is more accurately stated as the claim that our lives are indeterminate.
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, La Structure du comportement (Paris: Quadrige/PUF, 1990), 1.
But cf. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, La Nature (Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1995), 263: “For us, it is not
a question of a theory of consciousness of nature….” This is consistent with various critiques of a
philosophy of consciousness in the working notes to Le Visible et l’invisible. However, although
Merleau-Ponty seemed to critically recast his own earlier work in Phénoménologie de la perception in this light, most of Merleau-Ponty’s early work on consciousness is, contrary to his own
account, consistent with the explicitly ontological reflections of his later work. His inquiry into
consciousness was always very radical and ineluctably situated in the pre-personal. Cf. also La
Nature (op. cit.), p. 267, when Merleau-Ponty calls for “a rapport of the nature in us with the nature
beyond us.”
9
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la perception (Paris: Gallimard, 1945), viii.
10
Ibid., 10.
11
Jean-Paul Sartre, “Existentialism is a Humanism,” in Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre,
ed. Walter Kauffman (New York: Meridian, 1975), 348.
7
U
85
D.H. Davis
8
10
The Political Horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology
115
Motive
P
10.2
ro
of
(That is surely what he meant by describing our lives as projects; but a book entitled
Being and Indeterminacy would never sell!) Indeterminacy must be seen here in an
ontological sense, and not only in an epistemological sense. That is, it is not only
that we are uncertain about our existence, but that our existential state is indeterminate, or, as Merleau-Ponty sometimes preferred, ambiguous. The discrete moments
of our lives are determinate indeterminacy. Thus, Merleau-Ponty “puts essences
back into existence,” rather than denying them altogether.
Merleau-Ponty developed a unique transformation of phenomenology, by: (1) situating consciousness in the body; (2) compromising the aim of the phenomenological reduction; and (3) firmly calling attention to the world in which we live by
grounding the essences of phenomena within existence. These aspects of his existential phenomenology were the means at his disposal, by which he later developed a
situated ontology that is mired in impurity and contingency. Having established the
means, let us now turn our attention to the motive presented to Merleau-Ponty.
ed
Until now, we only silenced the collaborators and the objectionable nationals…. You tell
me about your friendship…. How can you, if not condescendingly, speak about friendship
when you are putting an end to this work?12
U
nc
or
re
ct
Next, we shall examine how Merleau-Ponty, using the existential phenomenological
means at his disposal, was motivated to develop a situated ontology by his political
reflections—most especially by his disassociation from his long-time ally and
friend, Jean-Paul Sartre.
An exchange of letters, written between Merleau-Ponty and Sartre during 1953,
was discovered and published in the mid-1990s, in which each expresses his
opposition to the other. The controversy was ignited by Sartre’s insistence that
Merleau-Ponty should not publish in their journal an article he had written that was
highly critical of Sartre’s political and philosophical position. This article was most
likely a version of the chapter of Adventures of the Dialectic that bears the title,
“Sartre and Ultra-Bolshevism.”13 Merleau-Ponty draws a connection between the
dualistic ontology of Sartre’s early work and Sartre’s political position, specifically
as it is articulated in The Communists and the Peace. Merleau-Ponty presents
Sartre’s position as the latest adventure of the dialectic, as defining the dialectical
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Letters of the Break-up, trans. B. Belay and, ed. Duane H. Davis,
Merleau-Ponty’s Later Works and Their Practical Implications (Amherst: Humanity Books,
Prometheus Press, 2001), 49.
13
Cf. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Adventures of the Dialectic, trans. J. Bien (Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 1973), 95–201. There is some uncertainty about what the piece was that MerleauPonty sent in to Les Temps Modernes. Also, Merleau-Ponty mentions another essay to follow along
later. Claude Lefort could not remember exactly which essay was rejected when I asked him about
this in 2003.
12
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
116
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
ro
of
154
P
153
ed
152
ct
151
re
150
or
149
quest for freedom in the ontological terms of Being and Nothingness, and squarely
addresses Sartre’s political philosophy as a new stage of development of the Marxist
dialectic. This, in Merleau-Ponty’s view, has indeed transcended the mediating
problems of: (1) Weber’s “politics of understanding”; (2) Lukács’ reconstrual of
this critical engagement as a subjective engagement; (3) Lenin’s corrective realism;
and (4) Trotsky’s idealism.14 Merleau-Ponty portrays Sartre as transcending
Bolshevism, yes, but only to introduce an “Ultrabolshevism” through his reduction
of Marxism to existentialism, where the agency of the proletariat is defined as an
absolute negation, and solidarity is reduced to a cult of personality. Despite this, and
to compound Merleau-Ponty’s criticism of Sartre, for Sartre philosophical critique
remains external; this why he refused to join the Communist Party and assumed the
role some French Marxists perceived to be one of the sympathetic spectator posing
as an activist. (For Sartre, it seems that there was a spectator haunting Europe…)
When Merleau-Ponty submitted his article to Les Temps Modernes, Sartre censored it. Merleau-Ponty resigned his position of co-editor. Their opposition is
expressed passionately in the three letters of 1953. The first, from Sartre, informs
Merleau-Ponty that the article will not be able to be published in their journal, since
publishing it would, in effect, be counter-revolutionary. Sartre writes that MerleauPonty should not take this personally, and that they will always, of course, be friends.
In the long second letter, Merleau-Ponty, who has resigned his position as co-editor,
states explicitly that the logic by which Sartre justifies the suppression of the article
is an example of what is wrong with his political position in general, and that Sartre
can only speak of friendship in condescension, as he has silenced Merleau-Ponty’s
voice. This letter of Merleau-Ponty’s is really a valuable document, insofar as it
allows Merleau-Ponty the opportunity to take a philosophical stance on the importance of critical political expression; furthermore, it shows Merleau-Ponty putting
into practice his philosophical position. The third letter is Sartre’s terse response.
Sartre reiterates his accusation, his rationale for censorship, and his hope for their
friendship. After the exchange of these letters, Sartre and Merleau-Ponty rarely
spoke except at conferences and public lectures. Perhaps it was the fact that they
never reconciled their differences that moved Sartre to write a scathing and spiteful
100-page obituary for his former friend after Merleau-Ponty’s death in 1961. This
might be seen as a sublimated anguish…15
nc
148
U
147
D.H. Davis
Whether any of these stages of dialectical development accurately represent the positions of the
individuals Merleau-Ponty names is a matter of great contention. I do not think that this discounts
Merleau-Ponty’s position, so long as one keeps in mind his penchant for using creative readings of
his interlocutors as dialectical mediations. His analyses are brilliant; but I would not look to
Merleau-Ponty as a paragon of hermeneutic fidelity.
15
It is important to note that Albert Rabil stated long ago that Merleau-Ponty and Sartre later reached
a “partial rapprochement.” Rabil, who could not have had access to these letters in 1967, speculates
that Sartre and Merleau-Ponty “put aside their intellectual differences” in 1958 to rekindle their
friendship. Admittedly, Rabil notes that Sartre is surely overly optimistic—even downright revisionistic—in his reflections about the friendship after Merleau-Ponty’s death; nonetheless, I think
Rabil still relies too much on Sartre’s reflections in his own account of the relationship.
14
10
The Political Horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology
117
ct
ed
P
ro
of
It is telling that Sartre retrospectively described his entire friendship with
Merleau-Ponty as a “quarrel which never took place.”16 In an interview with Simone
de Beauvoir, Sartre claims that Merleau-Ponty never was much of a friend, that they
never were comfortable with one another.17 And in his long eulogy for MerleauPonty, he is obviously still troubled by their relationship. At any rate, the passionate
tone of the 1953 letters reveals the degree of anger both Sartre and Merleau-Ponty
were experiencing. This shows that both in some sense regarded the betrayal of
their friendship to be intolerable. O, my friends, there is no friend. But, as interesting as this may be, their conceptions of friendship are not our principal topic here.
What is relevant here is that we see the way in which this split with Sartre motivated
Merleau-Ponty to develop his situated ontology. Let us look more closely, then, at
the exchange of letters.
Merleau-Ponty explicitly states to Sartre, “I am no angel.”18 By this, he tries
to respond to Sartre’s charges that he has withdrawn from the practical world of
politics to some sort of pure philosophical reflection. Sartre, in his first letter of
the exchange, castigates Merleau-Ponty for absenting himself from taking political positions and for offering a philosophical perspective that Sartre thought was
intended to do more than justify Merleau-Ponty’s disengagement. According to
Sartre, Merleau-Ponty’s philosophical justification issued a nihilistic universal
imperative for all people to disengage; he writes: “you remove yourself from
politics…, you prefer to dedicate yourself to your philosophical research…”19
U
nc
or
re
Rabil is not entirely accurate in his speculation that it was the somewhat friendly exchange at a
1958 conference that occasioned their partial rapprochement. There was a partial rapprochement,
but the first steps toward that took place at a colloquium at the École normale supérieure. Alain
Badiou, who was a student there at the time, and quite close to Jean Hyppolite, the Director of the
Philosophy Program, told me that Hyppolite probably wanted to see Merleau-Ponty and Sartre
mend their relationship. Badiou suggested to Hyppolite that he invite Sartre—the notorious antiacademic—to speak at the École normale. Hyppolite offered the invitation, and Sartre accepted.
Perhaps Hyppolite privately suggested to Merleau-Ponty that he should attend. According to
Badiou, no one knew that Merleau-Ponty was coming, especially Sartre. Apparently Sartre was
moved by Merleau-Ponty’s unexpectedly conciliatory gesture. So Sartre, Merleau-Ponty,
Hyppolite, Badiou, and one or two others, went to a café where the crucial conversation took
place. According to Badiou, it was clear that they had not spoken except in the most formal ways
since the 1953 break-up. And, after a long conversation, they parted—not as friends, as Rabil
suggests—but at least with a newfound tolerance and renewed respect for one another. Mme.
Merleau-Ponty confirmed this story when I spoke with her in 2002. She remembered vividly
Merleau-Ponty’s animated description of the conversation when he came home and told her about
the evening. I asked her why she thought Sartre had written in his eulogy of Merleau-Ponty that
the latter had died “unreconciled” with Sartre. Her response was immediate and visceral—even
after more than 40 years: clenching her fists, her face turning red, she said, “Certainly they were
unreconciled—after what Sartre did to him!”
16
Jean-Paul Sartre, Merleau-Ponty (op. cit.), p. 227.
17
Simone de Beauvoir, Adieux, trans. P. O’Brian (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984), 269.
18
Davis ed. (op. cit.), p. 47.
19
Ibid., p. 33.
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
118
D.H. Davis
202
In short, Sartre strongly criticized Merleau-Ponty’s choice of philosophy over
politics:
203
204
205
In a word, the philosopher today cannot take a political stance. This amounts to not so much
criticizing my position in the name of another one as trying to neutralize it, to bracket it in
the name of a non-position.20
201
209
210
211
212
My conclusion: Your attitude is neither exemplary nor defensible; it is the result of
your right to choose for yourself what suits you best. If you mean to criticize anybody
[i.e., Sartre] from the perspective of this attitude, you play into the reactionaries and anticommunist game—period.21
207
ro
of
208
Sartre’s anger shows in his declaration that Merleau-Ponty not be allowed to use
Les Temps Modernes to criticize Sartre and to offer his counter-revolutionary philosophical position:
206
216
217
218
219
Only those who have satisfied these demands can criticize one in return, i.e., begin in a critical dialogue. In a word, I ask of my critics a preliminary question: You, what do you do
today? If you are not doing anything, you do not have the right to criticize politically, you
have the right to write your book, and that’s it.22
ed
214
P
215
According to Sartre, Merleau-Ponty has retreated into pure philosophy, thus
abnegating his political responsibility and, therefore, his freedom to offer the proposed critique of Sartre:
213
228
229
Sartre was a retrograde, pure and simple, a political dinosaur, and to the day he died, a living
(albeit a somewhat fossilized) relic of the darkest days of the Cold War.24
225
226
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
re
224
or
223
nc
222
Madison has his own agenda, which I do not share, but it is certainly correct to
say that Sartre saw no irony in silencing, in the name of politics, the voice of his
friend’s political critique.
Merleau-Ponty’s immediate response, in his letter to Sartre, is important insofar as it shows this split with Sartre as the motive for the development of MerleauPonty’s situated ontology. The letter, one might say, is the immediate response
that motivated the larger response—the direction of the rest of Merleau-Ponty’s
U
221
ct
227
On this basis, Sartre refuses Merleau-Ponty’s work: “I vigorously and unhesitatingly condemn your attempts at condemning me. I will not accept them into Les
Temps Modernes, for I might then risk confusing my readers.”23
One sees immediately why Merleau-Ponty sought to articulate a position that
diverges from Sartre’s dogmatic self-importance and from the politics of “continued
engagement” that led to the censorship of any political/philosophical critique of
Sartre’s position. Gary Madison puts this rather forcefully in his fine essay, “The
Ethics and Politics of the Flesh”:
220
Ibid., p. 36 (my emphasis).
Ibid. (my emphasis).
22
Ibid. (my emphasis).
23
Ibid. (my emphasis).
24
Gary B. Madison, The Ethics and Politics of the Flesh, in Davis (op. cit.), p. 175.
20
21
10
The Political Horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology
119
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
philosophical career. Merleau-Ponty pulls no punches in his rejection both of
Sartre’s decision and of Sartre’s fundamental misrepresentation of Merleau-Ponty’s
philosophical position regarding politics. In short, Merleau-Ponty did not abandon
political engagement for philosophy. He instead called for a critical engagement.
Anything less—and Sartre had just advocated and demonstrated much less—was
rash and irresponsible. Merleau-Ponty writes to Sartre, “You take a stance without
worrying much about studying the content.”25 Indeed, this was a problem MerleauPonty had addressed before. As early as 1945, Merleau-Ponty criticized action for
action’s sake: “As Marx said, it is true that history does not walk on its head; but it
is also true that it does not think with its feet.”26 And, no doubt hastily written down,
Sartre’s position does seem somewhat pedestrian here. Merleau-Ponty summarizes
their differences thus: “I did not want events to decide for me, and you did not want
to take a step back.”27 It is crucial to see that taking this critical step back does
not, for Merleau-Ponty, aim to provide a purely objective perspective on political
events, some God’s-eye view of the situation, pure and comprehensive. Nor is it a
pure, apathetic disinterest in political events. Again, at least 7 years prior to this,
Merleau-Ponty emphasized that we are “condemned to meaning.”28 Consistent with
the means Merleau-Ponty has at his disposal, he is not calling for a step into a pure,
ideal world, a pure world of immanence, a pure transcendental reflection, nor a pure
phenomenological laying-bare of the essences of the political situation. Indeed,
there is nothing pure about this critical stepping-back at all. This is the uniquely
transformed transcendental posture of Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology, as introduced in the first part of this essay.
Merleau-Ponty says that he has “decided, since the Korean War, to stop writing on
events as they happen.”29 He explains to Sartre that “it is artificial and deceptive to act
as if problems appeared one by one, and to take apart what is a historical set into a
series of local questions”30; one can avoid missing the forest for the trees, by attending to human historicity from within history and from nowhere else. Merleau-Ponty
wants to refrain from Sartre’s “bellicose use of the situation,” by which, once again,
he is not advocating a withdrawal from the “political” to the “philosophical,” as
Sartre would frame it, which conjures up some pure realm of philosophy that would
be as impotent with respect to politics as it is philosophically pure.
U
Thus, I do not accept the benefit of this pure goodness that is generally bestowed upon
animals and the sick, and which inspires you to let me do philosophy at the condition that
it be only a pastime.31
Letters of the Break-Up, in Davis (op. cit.), p. 48.
Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la perception (op. cit.), p. xiv.
27
Letters of the Break-Up, in Davis (op. cit.), p. 47.
28
Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la perception (op. cit.), p. xiv. [Sens: that is directed
meaning.]
29
Letters of the Break-Up, in Davis (op. cit.), p. 41.
30
Ibid.
31
Ibid., p. 44.
25
26
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
120
D.H. Davis
295
10.3
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
or
298
In short, Merleau-Ponty found the opportunity to develop his situated ontology
through his interrogation of our historical, dialectical, situation in nature. We can
see evidence of this in the progression of his courses at the Collège de France, as
well as in the few examples of the ontology as he began to articulate it at the very
end of his career. Merleau-Ponty’s courses at the Collège de France trace out a dialectical parcours from political issues to ontological reflection through two steps of
mediation: history and nature.
Merleau-Ponty taught three courses explicitly about history, during 1953–1956:
Materials for a theory of History, Institution in Personal and Public History, and
finally Dialectical Philosophy. The course notes for Materials for a Theory of
nc
297
Opportunity
U
296
re
ct
293
P
274
ed
273
ro
of
294
Sartre seems to perceive himself as bravely leading the way into the future while
Merleau-Ponty self-indulgently gazes at his navel. Indeed, he implies that MerleauPonty is wasting his time by accepting the highest honor France can bestow upon
academics, a chair at the Collège de France. However, Merleau-Ponty explains
carefully, if impatiently, that, for him, “philosophy is an attitude in the world, not an
abstention.”32 Furthermore, Merleau-Ponty points out to Sartre, “I do not need to separate philosophy from the world at all to remain a philosopher and I never did so.”33 It
is the critical step back that keeps Merleau-Ponty from being an “écrivain d’actualité”—
a mere current events writer34—and avoids Sartre’s error of willingly extricating his
brand of engagement from the critical space that provides “a right of rectification that
no serious action ever renounces.”35 Again, reclaiming this right to rectification is the
fruit of Merleau-Ponty’s unique brand of existential phenomenology.
Merleau-Ponty saw the need to engage in a productive interrogation of our historicity in order to account for practical directedness, in order to see how events can
be understood critically from within a historical context in a manner that outstrips
the “trap of the event” and is not mired in the moment in an inhuman way. MerleauPonty is motivated by his split with Sartre to reconsider at greater length and in a
new way, a theme he saw as important, as early as his Phenomenology of Perception:
the restoration of subjectivity to its inherence in history.36
And so, ladies and gentlemen, we have established the motive we were after.
Merleau-Ponty, using the means of his existential phenomenology, finds the motive
to develop a contingent, situated ontology in his political/philosophical rift with
Sartre. We turn our attention, accordingly, to the opportunity.
272
Ibid.
Ibid., p. 43.
34
Ibid., p. 40.
35
Ibid., p. 42.
36
Cf. John O’Neill’s careful explication of this point in his Perception, Expression, and History
(Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1988), 47.
32
33
10
The Political Horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology
121
History are missing from the collected notes and transcripts on reserve at the
Bibliothèque Nationale in Paris. But, from what we can see in his resumés de cours,
it appears that Merleau-Ponty, in this course, closely followed the line of argument
he adopts in parts of Adventures of the Dialectic—no doubt he was working out this
line of argument in the process of preparing the course. In Adventures of the
Dialectic, Merleau-Ponty provides readings of works by Weber and Lukács, in
order to push dialectical materialism to allow for creativity and freedom in historical praxis.
ro
of
History is therefore a logic within contingence, a reason within unreason, where there is a
historical perception, which, like perception in general, leaves in the background what cannot enter into the foreground but seizes the lines of force as they are generated and actively
leads their traces to a conclusion.37
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
As we saw in the previous section, Merleau-Ponty wishes to account for the possibility of a kind of value within historicity that escapes the traps of subjectivism
and historicism. The passage above is interesting because Merleau-Ponty begins by
re-appropriating his familiar phenomenological critique of Gestalt psychology from
his earliest work. He would further investigate the foregrounding/backgrounding of
themes within history in terms of restructured institutions in his next course,
Institution in Private and Public History. These fascinating course notes have
recently been published. Here, Merleau-Ponty articulates the structure of institutions to be a productive and destructive oscillation that accounts for the relation of
public and private historical perspectives; there is instituting, which establishes
institutions. Once these institutions exist as institutions, they at once call for their
own destruction through further instituting.
Merleau-Ponty’s next course was The Problem of Passivity, in which he turns his
attention back to Spinoza’s themes of activity and passivity, and thereby begins to
hint at interests in the theme of nature. But it is his 1955–1956 course notes for
Dialectical Philosophy that constitute the most interesting of Merleau-Ponty’s
course material remaining to be transcribed. This course marks the transition
between the mediation of history to nature. What I found most surprising about
these course notes is that this transition is in no way indicated in his résumé de
cours. Merleau-Ponty begins as announced, by posing the question of whether there
is, in history, one dialectic or many dialectics. One can see that this picks right up
where the Institution and Passivity courses leave off. However, Merleau-Ponty here
frames these familiar themes in a way that is explicitly political. He says that it is
necessary to reflect upon dialectical philosophy “to see what it is to act.”38 Having
introduced the theme of dialectical philosophy explicitly in terms of praxis, he
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, “Themes from the Lectures at the Collège de France,” in In Praise of
Philosophy and Other Essays, ed. and trans. J. O’Neill (Evanston: Northwestern University Press,
1988), 97–98
38
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, La Philosophie dialectique, vol. XIV, course notes in manuscript form
on reserve in the Occidental Manuscripts Reading Room in the Bibliothèque nationale in Paris,
France, p. 5 [my emphasis].
37
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
122
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
ro
of
350
P
349
ed
348
ct
347
re
346
or
345
proceeds to look at the role of dialectic in various philosophers’ works: Plato, Fichte,
Schelling, Hegel, Feuerbach, Marx, Sartre, Husserl, and Heidegger. Surprisingly,
given the résumé, and providing a foreshadowing of the ontological direction of his
thought, he links Heidegger’s framing of the history of philosophy, as the forgetting
and retrieval of the Seinsfrage, with dialectic, that is, with the framing of history as
the dialectical relation of being and non-being.39 After, once again, asserting that
dialectical philosophy is not an attempt at escaping contingency,40 Merleau-Ponty
outlines the rest of the course as a dialectical interrogation of: (1) the being of
things; (2) being in the world; and (3) the being of the universe.41 There is a priceless
section entitled “Dialectic and Subjectivity,” which initiates an analysis over several
pages that employs for the first time terms that will inform his situated ontology in
coming years, such as “écart” and “the non-unity of subjectivity,”42 and even “a
being that is reversible.”43 It is in terms of the third aspect of his dialectical investigation, “the universe as a whole,” that he really bears down on the idea of nature in
very careful readings of Hegel and Marx. There is a fascinating passage on the ontological status of capital. It is interesting that these pages were found among MerleauPonty’s 1961 notes. He had pulled out and revisited these notes while working out
the ontology at the end of his career.
Next, Merleau-Ponty taught the courses on nature, which have finally been
published in English, and translated by Bob Vallier.44 Once we see the direct progression of Merleau-Ponty’s thought, we see how the courses on nature are not
digressions between his political thought and his ontology, but crucial steps along a
single path. Merleau-Ponty’s extended analysis of nature has been seen by Renaud
Barbaras to have significance because of Merleau-Ponty’s rich dialogue with
natural science and social science. Barbaras celebrates this dialogue, reminiscent of
early work in The Structure of Behavior, and reads it as a departure from what he
criticizes as the idealism of phenomenology. On the contrary, I prefer to situate
Merleau-Ponty’s analysis of nature as an integral transition in the political horizon
of his ontology. (It would require another essay to address Barbaras’ interesting but
I think misguided approach.)
Having established this crucial transition from history to nature, we will gloss the
details of the final courses written by Merleau-Ponty and only hint at the transition
from nature to ontology. [There are courses that focus on the thought of Husserl,
Heidegger, the limits of phenomenology, and the status of contemporary philosophy.] To do this, let us turn our attention briefly to the explicitly ontological work.
nc
344
U
343
D.H. Davis
Ibid., p. 8.
Ibid., p. 11: “Nothing exists in a pure state.”
41
Ibid., p. 13.
42
Ibid., pp. 22f.
43
Ibid., p. 28.
44
Vallier has also pointed out the influence of Schelling on Merleau-Ponty’s account of Nature.
Given what we have just observed above of the course in Dialectical Philosophy, we can see
even better why Schelling’s dialectic is crucial to understanding the transition of the mediation of
history to nature.
39
40
10
The Political Horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology
123
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
In the unfinished manuscript of The Visible and the Invisible, Merleau-Ponty
describes his project as an “interrogation of physis.”45 He turns his attention to nature
in order to sketch an ontology focusing on Being as écart, or the divergence of
beings, rather than the identity of Being. He articulates a latent reversibility of the
flesh of things, where Being is not so much a given whole but an implied horizon of
differentiation. About the only clue to the implied political horizon of this text lies
in its lengthy analysis of dialectic and hyper-dialectic, in which Merleau-Ponty was
working in dialogue with Sartre’s position once again, although not in any explicitly
political sense. There are many working notes published along with The Visible and
Invisible. Merleau-Ponty’s student and assistant, and an important political philosopher on his own account, Claude Lefort, painstakingly sorted through the working
notes, selecting some for inclusion alongside the incomplete manuscript. He selected
these notes on a variety of grounds, including the publisher’s demands for a work of
reasonable length, the importance of certain themes in these notes, and the condition
and legibility of some of the notes.46 Many of the notes that remain untranscribed
deal directly with Sartre’s work.
But let us, for now, consider Eye and Mind, the final work published in MerleauPonty’s lifetime. This work focuses primarily on science, art and vision, In short,
Merleau-Ponty argues that, while science purports to provide the truth of the world
that art distorts in its creative representation, it is better to see that science offers a
distortion of the world that art presents in a superior manner. At the heart of his
claim is an ontological explanation of art and vision. Science seeks an objective
understanding of nature, which it achieves through operational thinking. However,
Merleau-Ponty shows that art, by focusing on our ontological situation within the
world, calls our attention to our active/passive process of making/discerning our
world. By attending to line, depth, color, the status of the art work and its relation to
the artist, our attention is drawn to a fission of Being.
Thus does Merleau-Ponty use art as the occasion to articulate his ontology. It is
certainly a situated ontology, insofar as he is not pursuing a fundamental ontology
that must be done in order to subsequently move to ancillary tasks like aesthetics,
ethics, or politics. Clearly, the ontology is situated in the aesthetic account. But what
can one say about its political horizon? To answer this question, we can look at
some passages, usually misunderstood as suggesting a pure or fundamental aspect
to Merleau-Ponty’s ontology, which would be consistent with Sartre’s charge that
Merleau-Ponty retracts from the political in pursuit of a pure philosophical reflection. Simply put, such is not the case.
But art, especially painting, draws upon this fabric of brute meaning which operationalism
would prefer to ignore. Art and only art does so in full innocence.47
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Le Visible et l’invisible (Paris: Gallimard, 1964), 237.
I am drawing upon personal conversation with Lefort in 2003. As a kind of commiseration with
someone who has struggled more than anyone with Merleau-Ponty’s notorious handwriting,
I joked with Lefort that I would 1 day write a book about reading the manuscripts that I would title,
Le Lisible et l’ilisible.
47
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, L’Oeil et esprit (Paris: Gallimard, 1964), 13 [Eye and Mind, p. 161].
45
46
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
124
D.H. Davis
447
448
449
450
There are, in the flesh of contingency, a structure of the event and a virtue peculiar to the
scenario. These do not prevent the plurality of interpretations but, in fact, are the deepest
reasons for this plurality. They make the event into a durable theme of historical life and
have a right to philosophical status.53
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
451
452
P
423
ed
422
ct
421
re
420
or
419
nc
418
U
417
ro
of
446
At first glance it appears that Merleau-Ponty is here claiming that painting
provides some immediate access to a pure truth that science has distorted. And,
insofar as his ontology is articulated in terms of art, this seems to lend support to
Sartre’s charge that Merleau-Ponty is committed to a “pure” philosophy. However,
the context of the passage allows for a better reading. Merleau-Ponty is discussing
the manner in which art calls our attention to the “il y a,” to the “there is.” But its
innocence is not a pure vista upon Being. Indeed, that is what science purports to
provide. The innocence of art is precisely an innocence of this innocence, of this
arrogance. Art serves as an interruption of a naïve certainty and introduces meaning
through discord, instability and contingency.
Likewise, Merleau-Ponty has been taken to task for his use of history in this
work, as if it were a pure history that he presupposes. Yet, when we remember how
his reflections upon history were occasioned by the political, we should not be surprised to see that it is inappropriate to attribute this kind of position to MerleauPonty. Levinas, for example, has criticized Merleau-Ponty for his talk of a “primordial
historicity.”48 Four times in Otherwise Than Being, Levinas accuses Merleau-Ponty
of offering a teleological guiding force in this “primordial historicity.” But MerleauPonty never embraced such a monolithic view—one which, in fact, he referred to as
a Hegelian monstrosity, as the “museum” of history.49 For Merleau-Ponty, within
history there must be a “retrograde motion of truth, an incompleteness,” “a lack of
coincidence,” “perpetual” “transcendence,” “divergence”—écart. Historicity is primordial for Merleau-Ponty in the sense that when we pretend to stand outside of the
contingency wherein we are situated, we are pretending to stand outside of history
and effectively denying our historicity. “True history gets its life entirely from us.”50
Far from the pretence of a pure historicity or a fundamental ontology, MerleauPonty writes in a 1958 unpublished note that he is not interested in any notion of
history that does not “differ from itself.”51 There is no ground in the sense of an
idealistic historical telos; there is rather a demand that we attend to “the soil of the
sensible world.”52 However, even if the sensible world has been soiled in MerleauPonty’s ontology, history is no more the guarantor of ignorance than it is the guarantor of truth. Painting has meaning because it is historical:
416
Our historicity is shown in aesthetic terms in Eye and Mind, but it does have its
political horizon. It is just that, in art, to the extent we can avoid, as Merleau-Ponty
Ibid.
Maurice Merleau-Ponty,“le langage indiret et les voix du silence”, in Signes, p. 132. [Signs, p. 82].
50
Ibid., p. 121 [Signs, p. 75].
51
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, unpublished working note, 1958, Box III [old pagination, BnF].
52
Merleau-Ponty, L’Oeil et esprit, p. 12 [Eye and Mind, p. 160].
53
Ibid., pp61–62 [Eye and Mind, p. 179].
48
49
10
The Political Horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology
125
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
said to Sartre, an explicitly political context; we can step back from being “trapped”
in events because of our historicity. Hence, the situation of Merleau-Ponty’s ontology in terms of art is instructive for recognizing its political horizon; and no text
better demonstrates this than the preface to Signs, written in 1960. Here, MerleauPonty writes in explicitly ontological terms about historicity and politics. He writes
that Marxism is today reduced to a “secondary truth.”54 By this, he means that
Marxism cannot take itself for granted as the be-all-and-end-all, the absolute
arbiter of meaning. Instead, it must play the role analogous to that of a scientific
or non-theoretical truth from a previous paradigm: it “keeps its truth,” and is
said to be an “error” not as “the converse of truth” or something that can be objectively refuted, but as a “failed truth.”55 “History never confesses, not even her lost
illusions,” Merleau-Ponty writes. This means that it never “comes clean” with a
pure unadulterated truth. Nonetheless, Merleau-Ponty continues that while “history
never confesses…, neither does she dream of them [her lost illusions] again.”56
For Merleau-Ponty, the transcendence, the divergence, of history, though it precludes any ultimate meaning, provides for the very possibility of meaning. And this
is discussed in ontological terms. Philosophy, because it is situated in the political,
contingent world, “precisely discloses the Being we inhabit.”57 We are situated in
history just as we are situated in language and meaning, according to MerleauPonty. This means that we may speak of historical intentions that exceed our individual intentions, and meanings that resonate beyond individual intentions, just as
we say language speaks to us as well as us speaking in and to language. In an early
draft manuscript version of the preface to Signs, Merleau-Ponty writes that “history
is the house of Being,”—it is “the invisible living in the visible.”58 But if history is
the house of Being, there is no question that we dwell there politically. This is not
an inviolable house, but it offers us shelter for a while. Our situation in Being is
contingent, not pure. Like a painting, our existence “changes, alters, enlightens,
deepens, confirms, exalts, recreates, or creates in advance”59 the existence of others
U
nc
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Signes (Paris: Gallimard, 1960) [p. 9E?] One is reminded of Mao’s
primary and secondary contradictions.
55
Ibid., pp. 20–21. [Signs, p. 10]. Again, one is reminded of what Alain Badiou and Sylvain Lazarus
have called the saturation of the party-state in the cultural revolution. Cf. Badiou’s brilliant analysis in his La Révolution culturelle: la dernière révolution?, Les conférences du Rouge-Gorge,
Paris, 2002. What could account for this remarkable parallel, since the cultural revolution is several years away when Merleau-Ponty wrote these words?
56
Merleau-Ponty, Signes (op. cit.), p. 61 [Signs, p. 35]. And once more, one sees a striking resemblance between Merleau-Ponty’s position here and Badiou’s controversial movement beyond
Maoism—or as I prefer, a movement through the ideal of the party-state in Mao. Is this a hidden
dimension in Merleau-Ponty’s thought—perhaps even hidden from himself? Or is it a manifestation that Badiou was never a Maoist? One could pose the question to Badiou: “Are you now, or
were you ever really, a Maoist?” One could—I wouldn’t!.
57
Ibid., p. 26 [Signs, p. 13].
58
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, unpublished notes BnF, Preface to Signes, vol. IV, p. 19 (back)
(my emphasis).
59
Merleau-Ponty, L’Oeil et L’esprit (op. cit.), pp. 92–93 [Eye and Mind, p. 190].
54
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
126
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
ro
of
488
P
487
ed
486
ct
485
re
484
or
483
nc
482
with whom we live. It is also the source of an “unremitting virtu.”60 The ontological
approach offers a new way of accounting for what Merleau-Ponty, in his 1953 letter,
called “a right to rectification that no serious action ever renounces.”61
Thus, we have established that Merleau-Ponty had the means, the motive, and the
opportunity to construct a contingent, situated ontology. We might, therefore,
acknowledge that, in his own words, Merleau-Ponty is no angel. His ontology is
mired in adversity and in the contingent and is in no manner pure. I think that the
two main reasons Merleau-Ponty has come to be read as if his ontological reflection
were innocent of politics are: (1) Sartre’s influence, and the way he framed the discussion; and (2) the lack of access to notes and manuscripts that contradict the
Sartrean perspective. My goal here was to illustrate that the impurity and contingency of Merleau-Ponty’s situated ontology bespeak its political horizon. By this, I
do not mean to reduce his ontology to the political. Nor do I intend to claim that a
politics is “contained” in the ontology, and can somehow be “extracted.” MerleauPonty is not Descartes, who separated his basis for truth from the world, and is
saddled with the task of connecting the two. Merleau-Ponty finds this to be unacceptable. He has shown that such an unfortunate position would leave philosophy
pure but irrelevant, innocent but impotent; it leaves us in a situation where “The
politics of philosophers is what no one practices. Then is it politics?”62 Obviously
not. But when we attend to the political horizon of Merleau-Ponty’s ontology,
remembering its provenance and situating it within the continuous development of
his thought as a whole, we see that, contrary to Sartre’s claims—and all who have
followed Sartre’s impoverished interpretation—Merleau-Ponty never engaged in a
radical separation of philosophy from the political. The unacceptable breech
between theory and praxis is one which Sartre and others simply project onto
Merleau-Ponty’s work. Merleau-Ponty was no angel; and he recognized history as
anguish. Of this charge, his “guilt” is established63.
U
481
D.H. Davis
Merleau-Ponty, Signes (op. cit.), p. 61 [Signs, p. 35]. His reference to an “unremitting virtu”
surely parallels the “a right of rectification” implicit in any event that he accused Sartre’s position of
abandoning. Cf. p. 13 above. Please also note that Dallery’s translation of l’oeil et esprit misses the
political use of virtu completely. Cf. Eye and Mind, p. 160, for example, where virtu is translated
“meaning and force.”
61
Davis (op. cit.), p. 42.
62
Signes (op. cit.), p. 13 [Signs, p. 5].
63
Versions of this essay were delivered at invited lectures at: McMaster University [Canada],
DePaul University [USA], and Manchester University [UK]. I very much appreciate the questions
and discussion on those occasions. This essay is stronger because of the kind attention it received
there, and from the editors of this volume.
60
Author Query
Chapter No.: 10
0001327768
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please check if section heading levels are set correctly.
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
Query
Chapter 11
1
Derrida’s Specters: Futurity,
Finitude, Forgetting
2
3
Joanna Hodge
4
The triple subtitle to Derrida’s Specters of Marx (1994) invokes the State of the
Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the New International. This paper is intended to
open out a discussion of these, both as distinct elements and as a single structure.
The discussion here relocates the discussion of Marx and his New International
back into the analyses of temporality invoked in the notions of debt and mourning,
of the gift and the transmission of identity across actual deaths in the continuity, the
‘survivre’, the survival or living on, which is constituted in the rituals of mourning.
This paper is thus designed to re-situate Derrida’s analysis of futurity, of an ‘a-venir’,
of the ‘to-come’, as a modification of and challenge to Heidegger’s insistence on the
priority of the future, over past and present. My intention, overall, is a conceptual
one; namely to show how notions of protention, prognosis and programme are
simultaneously brought into view and brought into question by Derrida’s twisting
together of his responses to phenomenology, psychoanalysis and Marxism.
11.1
Specters of Marx
Jacques Derrida, Specters of Marx: The State the Debt, The Work of Mourning and the New
International, 1993, trans. Peggy Kamuf (London and New York: Routledge, 1994).
1
J. Hodge (*)
Manchester Metropolitan University, Manchester, UK
e-mail: J.Hodge@mmu.ac.uk
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_11, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
Derrida’s invocation of the three themes of: the State of the Debt, the Work of
Mourning, and the New International is worthy of more attention than so far has been
given to it.1 My argument here is that they form a continuation of a response to what
on a previous occasion Derrida calls ‘the Jewish-German psyche’, a hybrid structure
[AU1]
5
127
19
20
21
22
128
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
which he highlights in a footnote to his paper “Interpretations at war: Kant, the
German and the Jew” (1988).2 There Derrida proposes readings of texts on nation
and patriotism by, amongst others, Hermann Cohen, who was, like Edmund Husserl,
a passionate patriot in the First World War.3 Hence, one of the themes of my argument here is that Derrida’s proposal of a New International stands in marked contrast
to the nationalisms of these earlier appeals to some connection between intellectual
work and politics, while also, unlike that of Marx, proving resistant to appropriation
by a Bolshevik deviation, in support of a ‘Socialism in One Country.’
The first element of the sub-title, the State of the Debt, relates to my discussion
here of that aspect of Husserl’s legacy which is irreducibly marked by the destiny of
a certain German Jewishness. For the falling out between Husserl and Heidegger
and its reception are hugely over determined by the fate of European Jewry. Both
Husserl and Freud found, to their surprise and increasing discomfort, that they were
taken to be Jews, and not, in Husserl’s case, a Protestant and a patriot, nor, in Freud’s
case, an atheist and a citizen of an ecumenical Vienna.
The second element of the sub-title, the Work of Mourning can be more obviously linked to the legacy of Freud, although Freud’s legacy is itself internally
divided in a way to which Derrida, from 1966 all the way through to ‘Psychoanalysis
searches the states of its soul’ (July 16, 2000), never ceases to draw attention.
And similarly, the third element, the invocation of a New International, obviously implicates Marx and a certain Marxism.4 It is this last element of the title
which receives most attention from Derrida in this text and which most of the subsequent discussion addresses, in a series of colloquia, the proceedings of some of
which have been published.5 However in this paper I proffer futurity, finitude and
forgetting as an alternative framework grounded in temporality as a context for
re-reading Derrida’s text.
In a fine paper, ‘Another Possibility’, Catherine Malabou shows how that openness to a future which cannot be seen coming requires an opening up of both present
23
J. Hodge
See ‘Interpretations at war: Kant, the Jew, the German’ (1988), in Jacques Derrida, Acts of
Religion, trans. and ed. Gil Anidjar (London/New York: Routledge, 2001), 138–139. When Derrida
announces two exemplary Germans for analysis in terms of this German -Jewish psyche, it is a
surprise to find that the names given are not those of Sigmund Freud and Edmund Husserl, but of
Hermann Cohen and Franz Rosenzweig.
3
In the Foreword to Jacques Derrida, Politics of Friendship, 1994, trans. George Collins (London
and New York: Verso, 1999) Derrida sets out the topics of his seminar from 1983 onwards, under
the general heading, Nationality and Philosophical Nationalism (p. vii). A fragment from this
enquiry surfaces in Oxford Literary Review (OLR), vol. 14, nos. 1–2, Oxford 1992, under the title
‘Onto-theology of National–Humanism’, pp. 2–24.
4
Derrida pays special attention to the reception of Marx by Maurice Blanchot and his essay,
“Marx’s Three Voices,” in Blanchot, Of Friendship, 1971, trans. Elizabeth Rottenburg (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 1997) and by Michel Henry, with a long footnote about his work on
Marx (pp. 187–188). It is marked that he does not discuss the analyses of Jean Paul Sartre.
5
See Michael Sprinker, ed. Ghostly demarcations: A Symposium on Jacques Derrida’s Specters of
Marx (London: Verso, 1999).
2
11
Derrida’s Specters: Futurity, Finitude, Forgetting
129
and past, to ‘another possibility’.6 I suggest it also opens up for rethinking the nature
of the connections between future, present and past. The analysis of finitude arrives
in Freud’s psychoanalysis and in Heidegger’s analyses of a being towards death;
and the analysis of forgetting arrives both in the work of psychoanalysis and in that
of Husserl’s analyses of memory. Heidegger’s insistence on a forgetting of the question of the meaning of being is well enough known. But what is usually not noticed
is the role of forgetting in setting out the differences for Husserl between, on the one
hand, protention (which underpins the continuities of intentionality) and, on the
other, the overcoming of the gaps (which emerge both within the memory of individuated consciousness and within the collective memory of traditions; which subsequently require the inscriptions of texts in order to preserve the results of
intellectual discoveries of previous generations). There might be room here for a
counter to the Heideggerian thematic of a forgetting of the meaning of being, in a
Husserlian account of a forgetting of the meaning of forgetting. This can be retrieved
with the assistance of some suggestions made by the third master of suspicion,
alongside Marx and Freud: Friedrich Nietzsche. My argument thus suggests a
perhaps surprising link to be made between (i) Nietzschean genealogies and an
analysis of forgetting and (ii) Husserl’s phenomenology and the analysis of
memory, as retention and as a secondary supplementary structure, compensating
for breaks in attention.
11.2
Debt, Gift and Economy
If ‘debt’ in the first instance signals monetary considerations and the politics of the
World Bank, it is also to be linked back to the notions of the gift and givenness, to
sacrifice as the unreturnable offering, as discussed by Derrida in “Faith and
Knowledge: two sources of ‘religion’ at the limits of pure reason” (1994).7 It links
up to Derrida’s early discussions, in papers published in Writing and Difference
(1967), of Bataille, on restricted and general economies, and of inscription in relation to Freud.8 The financial and economic themes are linked to these notions of an
economy of energy, in the system of drives, as theorised by Freud, and are in turn
linked by Derrida to the discussions of value and of givenness, in the inheritance of
Husserl’s phenomenology. The return of the name of Husserl in this text from 1994
See Catherine Malabou, ‘Another Possibility’, in Research In Phenomenology, vol. 36, Special
Issue on Jacques Derrida (Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2006), 115–129. This focuses on a modification of modality, which is also pursued at length across the various surfaces of Malabou and
Derrida, Counterpath: Travelling with Jacques Derrida, 1999, trans. David Wills (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2004).
7
See ‘Faith and Knowledge: two sources of ‘religion’ at the limits of pure reason,’ 1994, in Acts of
Religion, Gil Anidjar, ed., 40–101.
8
See Jacques Derrida, Writing and Difference, 1967, trans. Alan Bass (Routledge: London and
New York, 1978).
6
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
130
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
becomes less surprising, once it is thought in the context of Derrida’s return to a
reading of Husserl, as guided by his responses to Jean Luc Nancy’s meditations on
Husserl’s account of sense and of the constitution of world.9 For the first part of
Derrida’s discussion of Nancy, ‘Le Toucher’, was published already in 1993 in a
volume of the journal Paragraph: A Journal of Modern Critical Theory.10 The return
of the name of Husserl in this text, haunting Derrida’s writings, takes up the themes
reopened by the publication in France in 1990 of his 1953–1954 dissertation The
Problem of Genesis in Husserl’s philosophy.11
The French reception of Husserl is marked by a split between the responses of
Merleau-Ponty and Sartre, who provide analyses of human beings as given in relations in a world, and the responses, by Cavailles and by Foucault, who critique the
possibility of scientificity in an account of meaning as offered by Husserlian phenomenology. This split between analyses of the human and of scientificity is one
which Husserl’s own writings resist. Derrida is in agreement with Cavailles that
Husserl’s phenomenology cannot provide such a foundational account of scientificity although for the different reasons rehearsed, but not presented, in Of Grammatology
(1967). He is less convinced by the emphasis in the writings of Merleau-Ponty on
making sense of concepts of meaning simply by reference to givenness in the world,
remaining committed to the Husserlian thought that the concept of givenness resists
full presentation in the world. Derrida’s account of the arrival of a meaning for a
political context of activity, as an arrival out of the future, in a mode which cannot
be anticipated, is to be situated in this context of a reception of Husserl. However,
the affirmation of phenomenology in the thought of Sartre and of Merleau-Ponty is
no more helpful as a guide to Husserl’s own thinking than the critiques of Husserl
developed variously by Cavailles and by Foucault. The account of phenomenology
as one of lived experiences of human beings in a world in the absence of Husserl’s
transcendental grounding leaves it open to the charge of radical contingency, and
does not do justice to the scope and ambition of Husserl’s theories.
The detailed investigations of Cavailles, of Canguilhem, and of Foucault render
implausible the thought that there is, in any substantive sense, a phenomenological
foundation for the sciences. For it is simply implausible to suppose that there can be
82
J. Hodge
For Jean Luc Nancy, see The sense of the world, 1993, trans. Jeffrey S Librett (Minneapolis/
London: University of Minnesota Press, 1997). It is safe to presume that Derrida had access to
pre-publication material for this text. See also Jacques Derrida, On touching: Jean Luc Nancy,
2001, trans. Christine Irizarray (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005).
10
See Jacques Derrida, ‘Le Toucher’, Paragraph: A Journal of Modern Critical Theory, vol. 16.2,
On the Work of Jean-Luc Nancy, ed. Peggy Kamuf (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1993),
122–157.
11
Jacques Derrida, The Problem of Genesis in Husserl’s Philosophy, 1990, trans. Marion Hobson
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001). This text refuted the canard that Derrida had
insufficient grasp of Husserl’s texts to be permitted to propose a critical transformation of them, as
he does in Speech and Phenomenon, Introduction to the Problem of the Sign in Husserl’s
Phenomenology, 1967, trans. David Allison, Speech and Phenomena and other essays on Husserl’s
theory of the sign (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1978). It is this text which gives rise
to the identification of genesis as the basic problem of phenomenology.
9
11
Derrida’s Specters: Futurity, Finitude, Forgetting
131
a general theory of foundation for all the sciences, especially granted the immense
variety and internal dynamism of those forms of scientific research in which activity
and progress in the twentieth century has been most marked. What Husserl can be
shown to put forward is an account of meaning without which no claim in relation
to scientific enquiry can be thought to make sense. Only by putting these two parts
of Husserl’s inheritance back together, that of a history of scientificity and that of
the life world as lived (both of which are marked up for attention in The Crisis of the
European Sciences) can sense be made, and the conception itself be motivated, of
meaning arriving as ‘another possibility’ out of the future. Husserlian fulfilled
meaning is to be contrasted to any previous partially intended meaning and is to be
thought as always ‘to-come’. The futurity of fulfilled meaning contrasts with the
thinking of futurity based on a resemblance and continuity between future and past;
for there never has been fulfilled meaning.
The thematics of Husserl on the givenness of phenomena and his enquiries about
meaning and being are linked by Derrida to both Freud and his considerations
concerning systems of psychic energy, and Marx on the differences between a circulation of commodities, as use value, and the economy as exchange value.
Psyche is the classical object of enquiry in Aristotle’s founding text of philosophy
De Anima to which Derrida returns in his longer analyses of the fate of phenomenology in On Touching: Jean Luc Nancy (2001). The conception of an Aristotelian
psyche, as the pure life of the living, the principle of life itself, is rewritten in a different way in the Freudian encounter with the effects of psychic pathologies, where
the expression of the psyche renders the body inert and incapable of activity. This
exchange between pure life and pure passivity is also important for Husserl’s analyses. Husserl’s return to a concept of the lived world, as the only source of meaning,
in his late series of enquiries gathered together under title The Crisis of the European
Sciences (1939), follows up this thought, concerning a concealment of pure life in
the fallen lives of empirically given human beings. The empirical transcendental
doubling traced out by Husserl from 1907 onwards is a doubling of pure life in the
given lives of human beings, which are terminated in the natural deaths to which we
are all destined. Heidegger’s contribution at this point is to think, in the analytic of
Dasein, of human life as the site at which the meaning of being arrives. He marks up
being towards death as marking a limit point, the impossibility of possibility, where
being can no longer arrive. In an early review of volume nine of the Husserliana
edition, Phenomenological Psychology, Derrida registers the absolute importance
for Husserl of a double instantiation of meaning, in its ideal form as transcendentally pure and as given only in its specifically lived modes.12
The Marxian distinction between use value and exchange value has analogues in
the distinction between manifest dream content and that to which it gives access: the
repressed drives and affects generating the pathologies from which their bearers
This is discussed by Len Lawlor, in his path breaking study, Derrida and Husserl: The Basic
Problem of Phenomenology (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2002), and see Jacques
Derrida, “Review of Edmund Husserl: Phaenomenologische Psychologie: Vorlesungen Sommer
Semester 1925 (HUA 9)”, Etudes Philosophiques 18, no. 2 (1963): 203–206.
12
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
132
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
suffer. Each system of masking is disrupted by the arrival of a more adequate mode
of living the contradictory relations which the system of masking covers over. The
systems of psychic energy form, on one level of analysis, a single system, but, on
another, are composed of mutually non-communicating elements, in a manner
duplicated in the account of distinct levels, or modes of psychic activity theorised
by Husserl in his transcendental phenomenology. As psychic activities these levels
are linked, but as systems of meaning of which sense can be made, there are discontinuities from one level to another. These linkages are in evidence as concerns for
Derrida in various places in his writings, and most clearly in the incomplete text
Given Time: 1: Counterfeit Money (1991). The open-endedness of this enquiry
prompts more questions than can be responded to, but it is all the same important to
mark up their role here.
The contrast developed by Freud between a completable work of mourning and
an interminable condition of melancholy also applies to the impasses of intellectual
enquiry. It takes a special kind of investment of energy in a project of enquiry to
bring it to a conclusion, rather than simply to break it off. This then brings into focus
the question of the time horizon for enquiry, for the work of mourning sets out a
determinate time of human living, by contrast to a melancholy which sets out an
indefinite in-between time, of survival without affirmation. The former, the time
structure of mourning, attaches to the status of writings, when there is deemed to be
an author assigning meaning to them; the latter, of melancholy, is the status of writings detached from such an authorial origin. In the absence of such authority widely
divergent interpretations of authoritative texts can arise, with no final adjudication
between them. The polemics, splits and murders committed in the names of Third,
Fourth, and Fifth Internationals bear witness to the fratricidal nature of the differences between the various factions involved, and a full elaboration of this last would
form a lengthy addition to the considerations pursued by Derrida under the title
Politics of Friendship (1994). This text might also be supplemented by a thorough
analysis of Derrida’s uneasy relation to Lacan, through which his responses to Freud
remain channelled from The Post card: From Socrates to Freud and Beyond (1980),
up to the essays in Resistances of Psychoanalysis (1995).
In relation to an account of meaning, then, the sub-title of Specters intimates a
need to think meaning as held in place by a series of differential relations: the difference between incomplete and completed enquiries; the difference between the
temporality of mourning and the temporality of melancholy; and the differences
between amicable and hostile fraternities. The latter then opens on to the most hidden question of all: the inability even for men of good will to dislodge the dissymmetry between invocations of fraternity and invocations of sorority. For all these
names of history so far invoked are names of men, and this aspect of a spectral
haunting of the inheritance of ontology, as supposedly written under the sign of a
gender neutrality, but in fact pursued under that of the silent subordination of
women, is a feature of the legacy of philosophy to which Derrida draws attention in
his Foreword to Politics of Friendship, but which individuals appear powerless to
shift. For while the thinkers invoked: Husserl, Freud, Marx, did not in the first
instance understand themselves to write under the sign of a certain ‘German-Jewish
153
J. Hodge
11
Derrida’s Specters: Futurity, Finitude, Forgetting
133
psyche’ they are clear on a series of differences between the situations of women
and of men. Derrida ruefully remarks in that Foreword:
Democracy has seldom represented itself without the possibility of at least that which
always resembles- if one is willing to nudge the accent of this word- the possibility of a
fraternization. The fratriarchy may include cousins and sisters but, as we will see, including
may also come to mean neutralizing. Including may dictate forgetting, for example, with
‘the best of all intentions’, that the sister will never provide a docile example for the concept
of fraternity. This is why the concept must be rendered docile, and there we have the whole
of political education. What happens when, in taking up the case of sister, the woman is
made a sister? And a sister a case of the brother? This could be one of our most insistent
questions, even if, having done so too often elsewhere, we will here avoid convoking
Antigone… (p. viii-ix).
This is a paradoxical non-invocation which perpetuates a certain silencing of all
the other sisters of history, starting with Ismene. The analysis, however, is arresting:
first, the woman is thought as sister, and then the sister is thought as brother and then
the woman disappears.
The invocation of a certain Freud and a certain Marx is clear enough in this subtitle. It is the third strand, an invocation of the master of phenomenology, in addition
to the now customary intertwining of psychoanalysis and Marxism, which requires
some additional comment. For here, in the place of the classically designated masters of suspicion, Marx, Freud, Nietzsche, the name Husserl arrives in the place of
that of Nietzsche. With this name, there arrives the gesture of affirming a notion of
a philosophical scientificity, assigning a certain priority to the claim of reason, in
answer to the question, of what distinguishes the human. These are the marks distinctive of Husserl’s phenomenology, to which Derrida returns in the essay printed
as a supplement to Rogues: Two Essays on Reason (2003), “The World of the
Enlightenment to Come (Exception, Calculation and Sovereignty)”. The stakes of
alternating the claim of Nietzsche, as the third man in this triptych, with that of
Husserl, is to shift the emphasis in this combined legacy from one of suspicion with
respect to inherited values, to that other feature of the legacy: an affirmation of a
certain Enlightenment disenchantment of nature and of reality, opening them up to
enquiry, and as no longer to be predicated on a certain ‘mystical authority’ as
invoked by Michel de Montaigne. On the other side, this opens out a question to
Husserl’s phenomenology as potentially inheriting a certain version of a critical
genealogy of philosophical concepts, which would begin to do justice to Husserl’s
detailed readings of and appropriations of conceptuality from David Hume and
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz.
Derrida’s attention, in his early readings of Husserl, to Husserl’s account of the
sedimentation and reactivation of philosophical concepts can be linked to a Freudian
attention to the distinction between manifest and hidden dream contents. This
reveals, alongside the Husserlian emphasis on a silent speech of soliloquy, another
layer of inscription in which transcendental intersubjectivity takes on some of the
characteristics of the notion of écriture, as deployed by Derrida (and Barthes before
him). This layer permits a transmission of meaning above and beyond the meaning
intending of empirically given consciousness, as the potentiality of meaning in, say,
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
134
J. Hodge
268
11.3
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
267
the geometrical forms, first entertained for analysis by Euclid and his generation of
geometers. The substitution of the name, ‘Husserl’, for that of Nietzsche has the
advantage of highlighting the extended footnote in Specters (p. 189) on the nonreality of the noematic correlates of noetic acts. It draws attention to a contribution
in Husserl’s phenomenology to a thinking of that which does not appear in an
empirical reality, but to which there is access by means of what Husserl in the sixth
Logical Investigation calls categorial intuition. This, in conjunction with a transcendental logic of wholes and parts, already motivated in the second and third
Investigations, gives rise to an account of meanings and essences, as that which
provide the structuring principles of that which appears immediately.
These principles can be set out, as a result of giving detailed accounts of that which
does appear, and which, in appearing, presents these structuring principles for attention, and for further futural enquiry. These structuring principles then are intimated
but not determinately given in an empirically given, determinate moment, and are
thus of a different ontological order from that which does have a determinate given
temporality. In this footnote to chapter five of Specters, “Apparition of the inapparent, ‘the phenomenological conjuring trick’”, Derrida points out that, of the four
basic components of the analysis of lived experience: content-form (hyle-morphe)
and noesis-noema, three of them: content, form, and noesis (the act of intending) are
all assigned a status of independent, autonomous reality. It is the fourth, the noematic
correlate which, as constituted through inter-subjective, inter-generational negotiations about meaning conditions, permits the arrival of the non-apparent, the
unanticipated, that which is not as yet real, in short, the arrival of futurity as alterity,
and of alterity as futurity. This is the opening in phenomenology, through which
another futurity arrives, and it is thus that politics arrives into phenomenology.
243
Further Remains
Before turning to this more directly it is important to notice that, in the closing
pages of Specters of Marx, Derrida invokes not Husserl, but Heidegger, the treacherous disciple. For at this point, it is more important to Derrida to mark up a connection, already marked in The Post card: from Socrates to Freud and beyond, between
Heidegger on the uncanniness of the call of Dasein to itself, and the uncanniness of
Freud’s analyses of the return of the repressed, in the repetition compulsion. The
temptation to pursue a series of analogies between Heidegger’s relation to Husserl,
Jung’s relation to Freud, and Lenin’s relation to Marx must be resisted, although
such an enquiry, too, would provide an instructive addition to the discussions in
Politics of Friendship, on the politics of discipleship, and to those in ‘Interpretations
at war’ on German-Jewish hybridity. It may be that in each case, psychoanalysis,
communism and phenomenology, with Freud, Marx, and Husserl, the disciple who
was not Jewish was needed to effect permanent entry into the history of European
culture. These issues of how writings come to remain within a transmission of culture would require lengthy discussion. My intent here is rather conceptual: to show
11
Derrida’s Specters: Futurity, Finitude, Forgetting
135
how notions of protention, prognosis and programme are both highlighted and
interrogated by the ways in which Derrida twists together his responses to phenomenology, to psycho-analysis and to Marxism.
The concept of ‘protention’ is formed by Husserl, in his analyses of intentionality,
to denote the futural horizon implied by what currently appears. It can be disrupted
by the arrival of the possibility of intending itself out of a re-configuration of what
there is, which has yet to come into view. ‘Prognosis’ is a medical term inflected by
Freud’s psychoanalytical sessions, while the ‘programme’ for political activism is
the legacy of Marxism. It is the last which has been the more discussed relation to
Derrida’s study, but the invitation is to think all three together. In place of the analyses of memory, which take pride of place in Husserl’s accounts of time and meaning, there arrives a certain emancipatory forgetting. In the place of any claim to
provide a cure for all human ills, in a therapeutic practice marked by success, there
arrives the more modest claim, advanced by Freud, that his analyses can put ordinary human unhappiness in the place of pathological delusion. For through analysis,
human beings come to recognise their finitude, in place of giving way to the delirium of omnipotence. In place of a certain Marxist triumphalism about an end to
oppression, and the beginning of a more fully human history, Derrida opens up a
horizon of futurity in which what will come hangs in the balance between disaster
now and disaster later. This is the shift of register from Husserl’s attempt to affirm a
certain Enlightenment inheritance, thinking a responsibility for each individual in
continuing to assign meaning, to the more modest thought that a thinking of meaning is always only as formally indicated, not, as yet, as fully given. This would be
one way of thinking Husserl’s remark from the 1930s, ‘The dream is over’. The
Husserlian move is then to be redescribed as affirming the destiny of the human, not
as now in our grasp, but as that of seeking to achieve a rational potential, as not yet
realised, and as never to be realised.
In place of this modified Enlightenment view concerning human endeavour, with
a continuing, and in principle unlimited, expansion of the domain of rational inquiry,
Heidegger’s reversion to a pre-Socratic Geek inheritance reveals the workings of
darker forces of violence and uncertainty in the human inheritance. This darkening
of the emancipatory intent can also be seen at work in the relation of Jung to Freud,
and of Lenin to Marx. The originary polemos of the Parmenidean origin returns for
attention, in the danger marked up for attention in the third of Heidegger’s Bremen
lectures, and indeed in Heidegger’s own catastrophic political interventions. While
divided from this by less than a generation, Husserl’s politics reveal a certain impossible nineteenth century optimism, which is put to flight by the cumulative uncovering by, for example, Marx, Engels and V.I. Lenin, of the hidden sources of nineteenth
century wealth and philanthropy: slavery, massacre, ruthless exploitation. Indeed
one might even identify in Husserl a certain migrant naiveté concerning the sources
of European wealth, and a gratitude for being permitted to share in its benefits. This
naiveté is not shared by Derrida. Specters of Marx pursues an analysis of the haunting of a present moment by that which as yet has not happened, but which would
give that present moment meaning, and which, furthermore, if it were to happen,
would break the time series within which that present moment falls. This breaking
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
136
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
open of the time series is thought as necessary for that present moment to present
itself with a claim on meaning. This is the necessary and impossible rupture of time,
as condition for a concept of a fully determinate meaningfulness, which is analysed,
variously, by Marx, Freud and Husserl. As remarked, ‘State of the debt’ does not
simply invoke a financial consideration, but is also closely tied into the reflections
carried out by Derrida shortly before the publication of this text, on the givenness of
death and of time, in both The Gift of Death (1991) and Aporias: dying/awaiting one
another at the limits of truth (1993).
These analyses of givens open up an enquiry into the structure of the given as
differentially thematised, and as constitutive of a certain set of systematic transformations of phenomenological enquiry. The modes of givenness analysed by Husserl,
become the mode of withholding invoked by Heidegger, and are subsequently transformed by Jean Luc Marion and Michel Henry into the donation of a divine intending and the essence of a manifestation of divine unity. This disambiguation of
Husserl’s thought of that which resists presentation in a life world into a donation of
a divine order is no less violent than the violence of Heidegger’s insistence on the
primordial status of the finitude of Dasein. The return of religious commitment, no
longer in objectively constituted structures of onto-theology, but in the mode of
theophany, and in the mode of attestations of faith opens the way to the new politics
of martyrdom, where lives are lost, not in the name of the emancipation of the
oppressed, but in the cause of attesting to the glory of some god of punishment and
reward. This is where a retrieval of Nietzsche’s thinking of the politics of ressentiment and the ascetic ideal is so urgently needed, to provide an analysis of who
benefits when young men are seized by enthusiasm, in response to the preaching of
old men, who speak on behalf of long dead gods. The interleaving in Specters of
Marx of Hamlet’s ghost, Freudian analysis, the figure of Marx, and phenomenological themes reveals how any presumed permanence is disrupted, by the return of a
repressed, in the form of the revenant, which in turn might make room for a genealogy of what is to come: as an enquiry into provenance.
The emphasis on a futurity, the invocations of an ‘a-venir’ in Derrida’s writings
is well enough known. In this paper I have drawn attention to an inter-dependence
of this version of futurity, with the workings through of a certain finitude, in relation
to an intertwining of themes from Freud and from Heidegger, and with the role of
forgetting, to be excavated by intertwining themes from Nietzsche and from Husserl.
That which arrives for good or ill may arrive as much through the permissiveness of
a certain forgetting as through the accumulations of memory. A ‘new international’
can arrive only once the old theorisings and practices of the Marxist and Marxian
Internationals have been put to one side, along with the old nationalisms, which
marked the responses of Cohen and Husserl to the First World War. A ‘work of
mourning’ is to be thought in relation to the contrasting dynamics of terminable and
interminable analysis. The state of the debt, in the narrower sense, conjures up monetary and financial considerations as well as those of the wider economy, alongside
the Freudian notions of a circulation of energy. It also intimates the relation of current research to an inheritance which it seeks both to reactivate and to forget. Derrida
draws attention to a certain forgetting of Marx, even when he is invoked, and it is
329
J. Hodge
11
Derrida’s Specters: Futurity, Finitude, Forgetting
137
possible to see a certain forgetting of Husserl, here, even when he is invoked. These
various interwoven strands of enquiry constitute a complicated series of temporalisations and thematisations of temporality, which cannot be done justice to under the
rubric of a ‘time out of joint’. This ‘time out of joint’ indicates rather a series of
phenomena to be analysed than a determinate result of a completed enquiry.
It is tempting to attempt to align the three figures invoked in the sub-title of this
text, the state of the debt, the work of mourning and the New International to the
three dimensions of a naturalised time, thought in terms of the past, the present and
the future. However, the effect of Derrida’s invocation of the a-venir is to unhinge
conceptions of futurity such that a different sequence of past, present and future may
arrive. ‘Another possibility’, another way of thinking modality, presupposes a much
more radical upheaval of present modes of existing and conceptualising than are so
far canvassed. It is important to show how these three sub-titles are all in the first
instance turned towards a reception of the past, and not towards the future. The
attempt to turn them around can lead to the very foreclosure of the future which
Derrida warns against. The state of the debt can be rethought in terms of a gesture of
an infinite giving of thanks for what has been inherited, but this renders it a question
for religion. It can be thought as an opening of time, between past and present, within
which there can arrive an abstract schema, permitting a re-organisation of concepts
and of thought. This renders it a question for philosophy. It can also be articulated as
a work of mourning, turned around into the mode of an infinite repetition of the death
drive, in the mode of denegation: ‘the possibility that nothing happened’.13 This renders the state of the debt as trauma, blocking all further development. If another kind
of future is to be allowed to arrive, this possibility too has to be transformed into a
mode of thinking what happened otherwise. This is what leads to an opening of time
not between past and present, but between present and future. Thinking Husserlian
futurity through a Nietzschean suspicion of what is inherited opens up Derrida’s
thinking of the a-venir in a way which might release it from its dangerous proximity
to religious sectarianism, in the figure of the messianic.14
See again Catherine Malabou, ‘Another possibility’ p. 127. This is the mode of denegation
described, but not directly invoked in the remarkable analyses provided by Derrida in his contribution to Giovanna Borradori, Philosophy in a Time of Terror, dialogues with Jürgen Habermas and
Jacques Derrida (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2003).
14
These remarks form an extended footnote to my study, Joanna Hodge, Derrida on Time (London/
New York: Routledge, 2007).
13
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
Author Query
Chapter No.: 11
0001327769
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please provide department name in the affiliation for the author
“Joanna Hodge.”
Query
Chapter 12
1
The Political and Ethical Significance
of Waiting: Heidegger and the Legacy
of Thinking*
2
3
4
Felix Ó Murchadha
ro
of
5
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
“All things come to those who wait.” This saying implies an understanding of waiting
which is anything but resigned, quietist and fatalist. Waiting, in such an understanding, is a preparedness for the future, a withdrawal from the busyness of the now and
an acceptance of things as that which comes rather than what is conquered or appropriated. Philosophy, which begins in wonder we are told by Plato and by Aristotle,
must similarly wait; it must perhaps cultivate waiting above all and have patience as
its greatest virtue. Philosophers fail – and in some cases have failed scandalously –
when they lapse in their exercise of that virtue. The legacy of philosophy remains tied
to the patience of waiting, however, and despite his failures Heidegger remains true
to that legacy. It is a legacy which is politically and ethically significant, but is so only
indirectly. Philosophy for Heidegger concerns the possibility of action, but can only
understand that possibility through a withdrawal from ethical and political action, a
withdrawal which is neither ethically nor politically justifiable.
Heidegger’s thought has become a legacy with which we struggle. This struggle
is one with the history of the past century, in particular that of the Nazi regime. This
struggle has been there almost since the beginning of the reception of Heidegger’s
work, but – in the English and French speaking worlds – only became a central issue
since the late 1980s. But such a struggle with the legacy of Heidegger is part of a
wider struggle with the legacy of philosophy. This should not be surprising: unless
with culpable smugness we distort the history of the Nazi period as simply an aberration, then the traces of Heidegger’s response to the political and ethical situation
of his time must in part be related to wider issues of the legacy of philosophy in its
* This essay is a revised version of a contribution I made some years ago to a panel discussion on
Heidegger’s legacy organized by the Canadian Society for Hermeneutics and Postmodern Thought
(now known as the Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy). I would like to thank to Andrea
Rehberg for her comments on this article.
F.Ó. Murchadha (*)
NUI, Galway, Ireland
e-mail: felix.omurchadha@nuigalway.ie
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_12, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
139
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
140
F.Ó. Murchadha
41
I
36
37
38
39
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
P
35
Philosophy, at least since Socrates, has required a withdrawal from the world of
political and ethical engagement.1 This motif of withdrawal arises again and again
in the history of philosophy and for reasons essential to philosophy itself. Philosophy
asks about the ‘taking’ and the ‘granting’ of the ‘taken-for-granted’. It is not concerned with the imperative of a certain politically or ethically constituted act, but
rather with the possibility of such an imperative at all. In the case of any action I take
in response to my political or ethical commitments the context of such action is put
behind me, is taken-for-granted. The actor, Goethe says, is without conscience; but
philosophy is only as listening to the claims of conscience.2 That is the paradox:
to question responsibility, to question the place of the human being in being
(Sein), indeed to question being, all that involves the breaking away from those
commitments, those ties of responsibility, of love and friendship, of duty and service,
through which we are persons, citizens, friends. To ask about the possibility of
politics or the nature of ethics is to open oneself to the contingency of all political
and ethical claims and this makes philosophy apolitical and unethical. It is apolitical
because only by a lack of engagement in the political can philosophy ask what it is
for a being to be or not to be concerned with justice. It is unethical because philosophy is rooted in self-responsibility, which is not the responsibility to act well towards
ed
34
ct
33
re
32
or
31
nc
30
U
29
ro
of
40
relation to politics and ethics. The following cannot hope to do any more than
suggest certain directions of investigation regarding the legacy of Heidegger’s
thought within the legacy of philosophy. The debates regarding Heidegger’s Nazi
engagement are barely mentioned. Instead, I try to situate Heidegger in terms of
the place of philosophy in relation to politics and ethics and the manner in which
phenomenology redefines that place.
This essay is divided into three parts. The first argues that in an important respect
the legacy of philosophy is apolitical and unethical. The second asks about the place
of phenomenology in this legacy and attempts to show how, precisely as apolitical
and unethical, the comportment of waiting is essential to phenomenology. The third
section then goes on to show how Heidegger is true to this essential element of phenomenology and how his thought leads to an encounter between philosophy and
poetry.
28
Cf. Plato, “The Apology,” trans. H. Tredennick in E. Hamilton and H. Cairns, The Collected
Dialogues of Plato (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989) 23b8 “This occupation [testing
the truth of the oracle’s pronouncement on Socrates] has kept me too busy to do much either in
politics or in my own affairs.”
2
This is an insight which we can find already with Socrates and the figure of the daimon and one
which is deepened in Stoicism and given further articulation by Saint Augustine. The place of
conscience for philosophy is, however, first given truly systematic treatment by Heidegger in
sections 54–60 of Being and Time.
1
12
The Political and Ethical Significance of Waiting…
141
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
others and oneself, but rather to question the grounds of all such action.3 To ask such
questions is to open up the contingency of justice and responsibility in a way which
our normal political and ethical commitments cannot justify.4
That is the crucial point here: philosophy is politically and ethically unjustifiable
and it is so because it claims to put ethics and politics into question in such a manner
that is politically and ethically irresponsible. Philosophy is not responsible to society, it is responsible to nothing, to no entity (Seiende). Philosophy is by its very
calling irresponsible politically, ethically, personally. It is so for a reason which
phenomenology first uncovered explicitly: only in breaking the ties of responsibility
can responsibility be allowed to appear as itself.
In other words, philosophy as the pursuit of the taking and granting of the takenfor-granted, is only possible if thought is free to pursue that which gives itself to
thought and has no other responsibility except to that. This may mean that the very
pursuit of philosophy is questionable, but if so only on grounds which are philosophically question-begging.
Of course the philosopher is also a citizen, a lover, a friend, a colleague. What
she thinks influences what she is in these relations and what she is in these relations
influences what she thinks philosophically. But this influence is merely empirical:
why in fact she thinks the way she does is something different to why she thinks,
i.e. which way of thinking gives rise to, that same thought. Only the latter is relevant
philosophically: only in relation to thinking, not to praxis, is a philosophical
position open to question.
At another level, though, at the origins of philosophy the life of the philosopher
was and is relevant. This is captured in the Socratic idea that virtue is knowledge.
Contrary to Aristotle’s critique, this does not amount to an unjustifiable optimism
concerning human continence, but rather is the reverse side of a profound insight,
that knowledge is virtue. In other words, to know the good is to be good, is to
correspond proportionately to the good5: reasoning is proportional correspondence
to the logos and only that which is of the same (koinos) nature can correspond.
The fascination with the human arose essentially not out of some anthropological
It is only on the basis of such responsibility of the philosopher (one which in different ways was
already made thematic by Nietzsche and Husserl) that Heidegger’s account of authenticity in Being
and Time can be understood.
4
It may be objected that throughout the history of philosophy the claim has been made to the political relevance of philosophy. But philosophy is thinking and thinking has no effects, it alone brings
nothing about. To act politically is to attempt to bring things about and such an attempt requires an
understanding of the specific situation in which one finds oneself. If I may quote from Plato’s
seventh letter (325d–326a): “I who had at first been full of eagerness for a public career, as I gazed
upon the whirlpool of public life and saw the incessant movement of shifting currents, at last felt
dizzy, and while I did not cease to consider means of improving this particular situation and indeed
of reforming the whole constitution, yet, in regard to action, I kept waiting for favourable moments”.
The time of action is not the time of philosophy (although I will attempt to show that they are
closer for Heidegger than for Plato).
5
Cf. Plato, “The Republic,” trans. P. Shorey in E. Hamilton and H. Cairns, The Collected Dialogues
of Plato (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989), 508b7–508c1I.
U
3
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
142
F.Ó. Murchadha
97
II
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
The Greek legacy of philosophy is responded to differently in each epoch and
phenomenology is characterized by the radicality of its response. A first clue can be
taken from the slogan ‘zu den Sachen selbst’, ‘back to that which itself matters’.6
That which matters to philosophy is the granting and taking of things, the appearing
of things in their appearing for those to whom they appear. It is the great service of
phenomenology to have renewed this age-old philosophical impulse. It is this which
lies at the core of Husserl’s claim to a presuppositionless science. The way to such
a position for Husserl began and ended with the phenomenon: only there, with the
appearance of things, with their granting, can philosophy begin to reach knowledge
which is absolute – freed, ab-solved, of societal connections. This absolving from
what Husserl termed the natural attitude took the form of a reduction, of a leading
back (re-ducere), to that which came before all relationships, all commitments.
Here quite strongly we can hear the echoes of the first paragraph of Descartes’
Meditations, which themselves however merely echo Socrates’ Apology. The leading back is not a return to some empirical ego, a return which would in effect amount
to a reaffirming of the societal connections he wished to overcome, but rather a
return to the very possibility of the ego. It is there in the transcendental ego that the
taking and the granting of things are seen in their inner unity.
The epoché is a putting out of play of all worldly involvements. This sounds
innocuous enough when discussed epistemologically, but it amounts to a radical
putting out of play of all interested engagements, such that the ego is disinterested
even – indeed especially – with respect to itself. All ongoing political and ethical
relations and their attendant commitments and responsibilities are to be put out of
play: only thus can we move from the natural to the philosophical attitude. It is not
surprising that Husserl throughout his reflections on the epoché and the reduction
questioned the motivation of what he sometimes termed a “conversion” to the philosophical attitude. Finally the only appropriate justification is that of wonder: philosophical wonder points beyond the natural attitude. But what it points towards is
not anything new, not something to be done, but rather the ‘phenomenological
P
99
ed
98
ct
95
re
94
or
93
nc
92
U
91
ro
of
96
navel gazing, but rather with the realisation that the human ultimately had nothing
to which out of necessity it could correspond, but rather that such a correspondence
was a task to be completed. The question how this was to be fulfilled depended on
what that was to which human beings could strive to correspond. Philosophy’s
vocation was to aid this completion. Heidegger in Being and Time with the figure of
Dasein and in later works with that of the ‘mortal’, repeats and at the same time
disrupts that vocation.
90
This translation is of course tendentious, but no more so than “to the things themselves”. In the
end “Sache” is not translatable into English.
6
12
The Political and Ethical Significance of Waiting…
143
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
residuum’ which the epoché reveals, is one in which “we have not lost anything, but
rather gained the total absolute being, which understood correctly contains all
worldly transcendents within it”.7 This gain, however, is won precisely at the cost of
my ethical and political relations as embedded in my natural attitude – in the philosophical attitude they are disclosed as those in which I am only disinterestedly
involved.
If the philosopher must withdraw from societal connections, then the question
arises as to whether he finds himself ‘beyond good and evil’. Is he unconstrained
and free from all convention? Certainly the case of Alcibiades shows how a limited
appreciation of philosophy can suggest just that. Philosophy though is concerned
with thinking, concerned with that which gives itself to thought. Such thinking is
not calculation, but rather the becoming as that which is to be thought. It is first and
foremost a responding to what calls to be thought. To respond it is necessary to wait.
Philosophy from its beginnings knew of the necessity. To quote Heraclitus: “being
(phusis) loves to conceal itself”. (Diels/Kranz, B 123) Only a patient waiting can
bring to sight what conceals itself. Phenomenology is rooted in this insight. ‘Back
to that which itself matters’ is a return from philosophy as argumentation, as the
neutral working out of plausible positions, to that which shows itself as mattering,
as being a matter which matters. The impatience of argument – which we often witness among analytic philosophers – is avoided in favour of a form of intellectual
fitness programme which trains the philosopher to see and hear and feel and even
smell and taste in a new and purified manner. The philosopher needs to correspond
to that which shows itself. This is an exercise in patience and waiting, by which we
can allow the thing to show itself to us.
That which itself matters in perception is an object which shows itself only in
profile. To perceive the object fully, from all aspects, requires time or intersubjectivity: either the assumption of another point of view or of my own future point of view
on the object. For the latter I must wait: that appearance as much with the house as
with the boat coming up the river – to allude to Kant’s examples8 – is an appearance
to come. And this waiting is in fact constitutive of appearance itself. For something
to appear to me it must appear as something and how it appears either fulfils or
disappoints my expectations. Either way I must wait on the thing, on its appearance.
Waiting – and this is a basic phenomenological insight – is at the basis of all experience to the extent to which experience is temporal.
Now, certainly for Husserl phenomenology was governed by the paradigm of
consciousness, in particular perceptual consciousness.. Heidegger, for reasons central to his reworking of phenomenology, breaks with this paradigm. But for him too
waiting lies at the core of philosophy. As he puts it at the end of his Introduction to
Metaphysics,“to be able to question means to be able to wait” (Fragen können heisst
E. Husserl, Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenological Philosophy, Book One, trans. F. Kersten
(The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982), 1950, 113.
8
I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp Smith (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1929),
B 232/A 189 – B256/A 211.
7
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
144
F.Ó. Murchadha
168
warten können).9 Questioning meant for Heidegger being responsive to where we
find ourselves (sich befinden). For him – as indeed for the later Husserl – we find
ourselves in a time of crisis.
169
III
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
ro
of
175
P
174
ed
173
ct
172
Philosophy for Husserl neither stands above the world nor acts within it, but rather
reflects on the world as phenomenon. For Heidegger – as indeed for the later Husserl
– such reflection requires a thinking of the crisis (the danger and the decision) which
faces humankind at this historical time. The response to this crisis animates
Heidegger’s thinking from the 1919 “War Emergency” lectures to his last testament
in the Spiegel interview. If philosophy asks about the possibility of politics and ethics,
it must think historically.
I wish briefly to indicate what the crisis in which we find ourselves is for
Heidegger, then look at what it is to be in a crisis, and finally how in thinking that
crisis Heidegger opens up the possibility of a radically new politics and ethics. In all
of this I wish to stress the element of correspondence (Entsprechung) which
Heidegger never ceases to emphasise.
The crisis in which we live is not immediately evident. Certainly the signs are
there, but what in fact the crisis is remains initially obscure. The crisis revolves
around being, but the obscurity of the crisis is indicated by the fact that we think
being is no longer an issue. ‘There is no crisis’ because the issue has long been
decided. To reveal the crisis Heidegger has to dig beneath the surface, his method
for doing so he calls Destruktion. This method upsets the taken-for-grantedness of
the taken-for-granted, or in Heidegger’s terms the forgetting of the forgetting.
Destruktion is a method of reduction. It leads back to an originating experience.10
This does not mean that it brings us back to a primal stage, but rather to that which
gets covered over when we – we in the legacy of Plato – start to philosophise.11 We
ask about the presence of things to consciousness, but we do not question the presencing itself. The granting of entities remains unthought. Destruktion is not the
wilful destroying of ontology, but the listening to what is unsaid. While Husserlian
phenomenology waited on the appearing of things, it did not allow that appearing as
granting to appear because it made all appearing subject to consciousness. The
problem for Heidegger is not so much the impossibility of the completion of the
re
171
or
170
nc
167
U
166
M. Heidegger, An Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. R. Manheim (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1987), 206 (translation modified).
10
Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. J. Stambaugh (Albany: SUNY Press, 1996), 20; “We understand this task as the destructuring [Destruktion] of the traditional content of ancient ontology …
This destructuring is based upon the original experiences in which the first and subsequently
guiding determinations of being were gained.”
11
Ibid., “its [destructuring’s] critique concerns ‘today’”.
9
12
The Political and Ethical Significance of Waiting…
145
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
reduction,12 as that Husserl did not carry the project far enough. While Husserl
reduced things to their appearance for consciousness, Heidegger attempted to reduce
entities to being.13 To speak of a phenomenological reduction in Heidegger does not
imply that he takes over the reduction as practiced by Husserl, manifestly he does
not.14 For Heidegger Dasein is not to be understood in terms of its sensual kinaesthesia in the manner of Husserl’s account of sensibility, but rather as an entity
(Seiendes) through which being is disclosed. “Dasein is its disclosedness [Dasein
ist seine Erschlossenheit].”15 Phenomena are reduced from the self-evidence of their
appearance, to the how of their appearing.16
On the basis of fundamental moods, Heidegger questions the presence of entities
as phenomena as to the coming to presence of such phenomena. This coming to
presence which Heidegger terms unconcealment, indicates a concealment at the
heart of appearance. This concealment cannot appear as an entity, cannot be made
present (to consciousness), but – and this is Heidegger’s attempt – may be allowed
appear precisely as non-presence. This non-presence is – as Heidegger never tires of
pointing out – addressed whenever we speak of the entity: this is a table, this is a
jug. It comes to appearance not as a thing, rather as the granting of things to presence. Heidegger asks of the givenness of things, their granting. While for Husserl
this question always meant givenness to consciousness (hence the principle of all
principles),17 for Heidegger the question is how being is given. To answer that question it is necessary to wait not simply for the appearance of a thing, but for that
which makes both granting and taking possible. The unconcealment of entities
which Heidegger calls truth (aletheia) is that which makes Dasein possible. But the
emphasis on Dasein obscured the search for that which lies at the root both of taking
and of granting. This could not itself be an entity, because then the question as to its
U
nc
or
12
As Merleau-Ponty suggests, Phenomenology of Perception, trans. C.Smith (New York:
Humanities Press, 1964), viii.
13
Cf. J-L. Marion, “Beings and Phenomenon” and “The Nothing and the Claim” in Reduction and
Givenness (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1998). Far from discounting the need for the
epoché, Heidegger’s own account of the relation of the inauthentic to the authentic can best be
understood precisely as an epoché which however happens to Dasein rather than being an act of
Dasein. So understood the analysis of Angst becomes less (as is sometimes alleged) a psychological and firmly a phenomenological account as can be seen in the following famous passage:
“In Angst the things at hand in the surrounding world sink away, and so do innerworldly beings in
general. …Angst individuates Dasein to its ownmost being-in-the world [and] … discloses
Dasein and being-possible.” (Being and Time, pp. 175f.).
14
Rudolf Bernet, indeed, states that “the difference [between Husserl and Heidegger] concerns
the concept of the phenomenological reduction and the manner of carrying it out.” (Bernet,
“Phenomenological Reduction and the Double Life of the Subject” in T. Kisiel and J. van
Buren, Reading Heidegger from the Start. Essays in his earliest thought (Albany: SUNY Press,
1994), 258).
15
Being and Time, p. 125 (translation modified).
16
“To let that what shows itself be seen from itself, just as it shows itself from itself.” (Being and
Time, p. 30).
17
Cf. Ideas I, p. 52.
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
146
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
ro
of
230
P
229
ed
228
ct
227
re
226
or
225
granting would arise. Rather, this is an event, a happening. This conclusion is
glimpsed at the end of Being and Time in the section on historicity,18 but receives its
explicit statement only in the Contributions to Philosophy (1936–1938).19
The appearance of entities is possible only insofar as the granting of their appearance does not appear. But, for us, all that is what appears as objects. The crisis in
which we find ourselves results hence from the almost total concealing of that granting, such that the human only meets the human.20 But implicit since the Greek
concept of proportional correspondence as task is that alterity is essential to being
human: to be human is only possible in response to a claim which comes from elsewhere. This alterity though does not simply stand outside the human being, that
would mean that the human was already decided. Rather, to be human is to be other,
to be placed in the play of alterity. The crisis is precisely that the possibility of decision (kritein) has been removed. Decision involves the initiation of the new, the
opening up of the future. Decision requires alterity. In Homer we read whenever the
hero comes to a point of decision they are approached by a god or goddess.21 From
the goddess comes the beginning (Anfang), to which they then respond to in starting
a new course of action. The beginning is not in human power because it is a break
with what was, a move beyond all existing grounds (principle of sufficient reason).
In Christianity this was known as kairos. This is a time which cannot be calculated,
only prepared for; the time when an epiphany – the appearance of the wholly other
– calls for response. This appearance is the appearing of appearing, the bringing to
light of light, which both is and is not of the visible. Such alterity comes not from
human beings, is not of human beings, but is only possible for human beings and by
human beings. It calls for response.22
Response begins with an initiation from an other. The one who responds is the
one upon whom a claim is made.. This claim – Anspruch – calls for a response,
indeed a correspondence – Entsprechen. This speaking is not the expression of
opinion or of knowledge, it arises out of a fundamental mood (Grundstimmung)
where we are affected and speechless. Speechless because here is experienced not
the given but the event of givenness itself. It is this which philosophy since its beginnings has attempted to respond to. Speechlessness though seems an unlikely place
from which to approach politics or ethics. Yet while ethics and politics are in the
nc
224
U
223
F.Ó. Murchadha
Being and Time, § 75.
M. Heidegger, Contributions to Philosophy: From Enowning, trans. P. Emad and K. Maly
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999).
20
Heidegger, “The Question Concerning Technology” in The Question Concerning Technology
and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt (New York: Harper & Row, 1977), 27.
21
Homer, Iliad, book 1 (200–260) where Achilles at a decisive moment in his confrontation with
Agamemnon is approached by Athena who initiates a course of action which sets the course of
much of the rest of the Iliad.
22
On the importance of the concept of kairos for an understanding of Heidegger’s project in Being
and Time and beyond see the author’s Zeit des Handelns und Moglichkeit der Verwandlung:
Kairologie und Chronologie bei Heidegger im Jahrzehnt nach “Sein und Zeit” (Wurzburg:
Konigshausen & N., 1999).
18
19
12
The Political and Ethical Significance of Waiting…
147
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
realm of speech, the fluency of speech gliding over the rough edges actually spells
their demise. To answer the claim of being is not to rehearse long learnt words, but
rather the words which emerge from the speechlessness of mood arise out of
response.23 The speaking, which lies at the base of politics and ethics, responds to
the claim and either corresponds to it or does not. The possibility to be human
depends on such speaking, out of which political and ethical being with others
emerges. Such speech attempts at response, its success cannot be known in advance,
because it depends on no past. It is a speaking which allows the possibility of acting
and dwelling.
The place of judgement here becomes particularly problematic and its basis
essentially fragile. Already in Being and Time Heidegger speaks of the choice of
a hero,24 and this theme is continued in the 1930s with the discussion of the demigods in relation to Hölderlin.25 Heidegger’s own choice in 1933 of Hitler as ‘hero’
was a disastrous one. But in making that choice he had already given up the place
of philosophy and mistaken his role as philosopher. That role was not to enter into
the political domain, but to think the very possibility of speech out of speechlessness, a possibility which is essentially a-political, because it comes before any
polis. It is here that Heidegger turns to the poet, in the hope that the poet has an
ear for that which can be brought to language. But this does not amount to a turning away from the political. In his first lecture course on Hölderlin, in 1934,
Heidegger makes clear that the poet, the statesman and the thinker are all three the
creators (die Schaffenden) of the polis.26 All three act outside the polis, but aim to
establish the polis, i.e. the domain in which speech and discourse is possible.27
Each of these three creators acts in the midst of the struggle of revealing and concealing, which in the “Artwork Lectures” Heidegger understood as a struggle
between world and earth and later as a struggle of earth and sky, mortals and gods.
Central to these accounts is the experience of making – poiesis. Poiesis, however,
has been levelled off into mere production: the earth and all upon it, including
human beings, have become mere material, standing reserve. The poetic ear for
alterity has been deafened.
Yet the claim of being is to be heard, precisely as the claim of technology.
Technology is, for Heidegger, not a human doing but rather is how entities are
unhidden, how they are granted in the current epoch. This sounds like fatalism and as
such the death knell of any ethics and any politics. But that which is not a human doing,
and not in human control, is not on that account blind necessity: such a conclusion
would be based on a metaphysical dichotomy of human freedom and natural necessity.
23
See “Postscript to ‘What Is Metaphysics?’” in Pathmarks, ed. W. McNeill (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998), 237.
24
Being and Time, p. 352.
25
M. Heidegger, Hölderlins Hymnen ‘Germanien’ und ‘der Rhein’ Gesamtausgabe vol. 39, ed.
S. Ziegler (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1989).
26
Ibid, p. 51 f.
27
Introduction to Metaphysics, p. 152.
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
148
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
ro
of
298
P
297
ed
296
ct
295
re
294
or
293
Freedom, for Heidegger, is not the realm of politics and ethics in contrast to nature
as necessity. Freedom is rather that which makes politics and ethics possible in the
first place and this possibility is a possibility of ‘nature’ (earth and sky). Freedom is
a gift, a giving of space. It is in this sense that Heidegger can say that freedom is not
a property of human beings, but rather that freedom is letting be of entities.28 It is the
opening in which entities appear. Freedom in the sense of the open is what politics
and ethics require; they are indeed only through letting the open be. Without such
opening, without the future as an aspect of time, action would be impossible.
The open, however, is not except for the closed, the open is the dis-closed. The
possibility of freedom lies in the destining of being (Seinsgeschick), which is the
gift of opening. This gift is contingent, is changeable.29
Such change Heidegger frequently characterises by a small word, jäh, which is
generally translated as sudden or suddenly. The sudden is that which brings past
and future to be in a decisive moment, precisely by differentiating them. This
moment is not to be planned, not to be produced. If it were, it would simply amount
to a continuation of what went before. Production depends on continuity, on the
absence of surprise. The political and the ethical though can only arise through
surprise, or at least a preparedness for surprise. Freedom is not the spontaneous
capacity to control the future, but rather the preparedness for a future which is
other. Such a preparedness opens up the possibility of change and transformation:
it is a preparedness for the granting of a future which can only be taken in the mode
of response. When the claim of technology is recognised, the granting of entities is
disclosed. The taking of those entities is not a separate matter as the very entity
which we are is itself standing reserve, is itself granted through technology. The
taking is obscured because the granting is such that it hides itself as granting by
making the one who takes – the human – into one more material resource. The possibility of corresponding to technology resides in the human capacity to see this
granting as granting. How is that possible? It is possible precisely through the recognition that technology is not a human product. This recognition is the beginning
of a response. Response begins with a recognition of our position as in the accusative case, of being subject to a claim, the claim of being itself which shows itself as
that which matters.
nc
292
U
291
F.Ó. Murchadha
“The Essence of Truth”, in Pathmarks, p. 145 f.
The implications of this are quite far-reaching in terms of Heidegger’s critique of modernity. It is
modernity which understands freedom purely as spontaneity. In such a view destiny as the givenness of a situation can only seem a curb on freedom. But freedom for Heidegger is the setting forth
of a situation in which to act, and that lies not in the power of the individual actors but is a matter
of destiny (moira, fortuna). In this Heidegger’s position only seems strange to moderns. It is
revealing to remember that for the Greeks even Zeus himself was subject to moira. Modernity, by
subjectivising the Judaeo-Christian creator god, has distorted the relation of freedom and necessity. Cf.. Heidegger, “Moira” in Early Greek Thinking, trans. D.F. Krell and F. Capuzzi (New York:
Harper Collins, 1985), 50 ff.; see also W. McNeill, The Glance of the Eye. Heidegger, Aristotle and
the Ends of Theory (New York: SUNY Press, 1999), 143.
28
29
12
The Political and Ethical Significance of Waiting…
149
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
With the exception of some oblique references, this essay has passed over
Heidegger’s Nazi engagement in silence. This engagement for all its sordid and
scandalous nature can in its philosophical significance only be understood with reference to the wider legacy of philosophy. That legacy encountered a radicalisation
with the phenomenological performance of the epoché and reduction which
Heidegger brought to its political and ethical significance. As I have attempted to
show, such a radicalisation does not amount to a ‘holiday’ from such ethical and
political commitments and responsibilities, but a profound reflection upon them.
Such a reflection places philosophy in essential relation to the time of politics and
of ethics, to the historical. As such philosophy can neither be timeless nor engaged,
but rather a thinking of the present kairos, the present decisive moment, in the opening of which ethics and politics are possible. Heidegger’s legacy is to radicalize the
philosophic disengagement from politics and ethics into a timely thinking of the
historical destiny of the present in which, if at all, it is possible to act politically and
ethically. Such thinking is a thinking which is prepared to wait.
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
Chapter 13
1
Othering
2
Robert Bernasconi
3
In this paper I address “othering,” the differentiating that human beings sometimes
employ in relation to each other in an effort to establish a distance between them.
I limit “othering” to the relation with human beings and leave for another time
consideration of a comparable process that can take place in relation to animals, to
imaginary beings, and to things. The form of othering that I am concerned with
here, othering between humans, thus takes shape across a certain sameness which
constitutes a bond between the people being differentiated. Sometimes the very
humanity of the other can be called into question, because the focus on differentiation can be so extreme. But even when this othering takes the form of denying that
another human being is human, as has sometimes been the case in racial thinking,
this still can take place across sameness. As Sartre liked to say, “To treat a man like
a dog, you must first recognize him as a man.” My concern in this paper is to
expose as a gross oversimplification the model whereby one individual distances
himself or herself from an other by objectifying them through a system of classification or through the gaze. One is oneself always implicated in this othering in
complex ways and I will appeal to some of Jean-Paul Sartre’s analysis in his late
works to illustrate this.
What I am here calling “othering” has thus got nothing to do with what
Emmanuel Levinas calls the relation to the Other. Levinas describes the face to
face relation to the Other as a relation with an abstract face.1 Levinas’s Other is not
different from me by virtue of any characteristics that he or she possesses, although
Emmanuel Levinas, “La signification et le sens,” Humanisme de l’autre homme (Montpelier: Fata
Morgana, 1972), 57; trans. Alphonso Lingis, “Meaning and Sense,” in Basic Philosophical
Writings, ed. A. Peperzak, S. Critchley, and R. Bernasconi (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1996), 59.
1
R. Bernasconi (*)
Pennsylvania State University, University Park, PA, USA
e-mail: rlb43@psu.edu.
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_13, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
151
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
152
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
at one time Levinas seems to have wondered if what we now call gender is an
exception.2 It is true that Levinas offers an account of the Other as widow, orphan,
poor person, or stranger, but I believe that it is a mistake to think of these terms as
sociological categories in this context. Levinas’s Other arrives without a place in
society. I am dispossessed in the face of the Other, but without my having to calculate which of us has more. By contrast, my concern here is with how othering operates concretely in society, beyond the artificial abstractions of the usual philosophical
models of a dialectic of recognition, an objectifying gaze, or the radical separation
of absolute alterity. I can leave open the question of whether or not Levinas’s
account can and should be reconciled with mine, because othering as I mean it here
is always determinate.
The usual models for thinking about the categories by which people designate
themselves or others as members of some group or other are far too simple. They
tend to rely on a form of oppositional thinking, as when one thinks in terms of
Catholic and Protestant, Christian and Jew, Black and White, male and female.
Social identities are never formed in isolation but always shaped within a complex
intersecting network that implicates all the other social identities operative at a
given time. To group individuals according to identifiable features such as skin
color, size, gender, length of hair, choice of clothing and so on, usually means that
they do not conform to some norm that we have established for ourselves. But this
does not mean that their otherness constitutes a simple negation, and one should not
forget those other others who are not the others against whom I define myself but
with whom I identify in spite of their otherness. We often associate some group or
other with a certain set of qualities as a way of denying that our group shares these
same characteristics. Nevertheless, to the extent that we associate these characteristics with a group to the point where we identify it with them, then they cease merely
to embody these characteristics: they are these things for us pure and simply.
Suburban Whites often see young Black men as a potential source of danger irrespective of the true circumstances. They see a threat, even where there is none. By
the same token, one group is lazy, another is dishonest or miserly, and so on, in spite
of all evidence to the contrary.
Anxieties are not the only source of othering. There are, for example, also desires.
When I desire something I readily assume that others share the same desire. But in
those cases when I do not admit the existence of this desire in myself, then it is othering. Nor is this limited to desire, but extends to other concerns. I plot so I see plots
everywhere, but I imagine that it is everybody else who plots, whereas I am merely
goal-directed. Furthermore, my outrage at certain things have their source in me. It
seems that among the most vociferous opponents in Congress of President Clinton’s
sexual “indiscretions” as President were some who were themselves adulterers.
25
R. Bernasconi
“The notion of a transcendent alterity – one that opens time – is at first sought starting with an
alterity-content – that is, starting with femininity.” Emmanuel Levinas, “Preface,” in Le temps et
l’autre (Montpelier: Fata Morgana, 1979), 14; trans. Richard Cohen, “Preface,” in Time and the
Other (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1987), 36.
2
13
Othering
153
In stereotyping, someone, whether an individual or a collective does not matter,
sees another or others in terms of some abstract quality or character which has come
to be linked with some other more obvious feature. Presented in this way it might
seem that we are dealing with false inferences, and racism and sexism are sometimes attacked as such. So the question of whether it is rational or right for Whites
to fear a Black man walking toward them on a lonely street after dark is debated in
part with reference to statistics, just as government agencies may target people with
a certain profile as appropriate objects for scrutiny as potential terrorists. Clearly it
is important to know what the statistics say and to allow reason its role, but it is also
important to know how our prejudices operate, so that we can scrutinize them effectively. An analysis that shows the complexity of our othering will remain incomplete if it does not also enrich correspondingly the means we employ to combat its
worst effects when othering becomes prejudicial. For example, there was a time
when one could combat racism by pointing to exceptions to the dominant racial
characterizations. This was persuasive in a time of racial essentialism but with the
advent of statistical racism enshrined since Galton in Quetelet’s bell-curve, occasional exceptions confirm the account as much they refute it. This indeed is why
“the exception proves the rule” no longer means that the exception tests or disproves
the rule.
Stereotyping as a form of othering says almost as much about the perceiver as
about the perceived. It reveals my concerns, very often my anxieties about myself.
The attempt to project elsewhere, to thrust away, what I most dislike about myself
is often central to the process of othering. I characterize the other as superstitious or
spontaneous as part of my ambivalence about my own superstitions or spontaneity.
To be sure, it only strikes us that someone is projecting in this way when the original
observation is so implausible that those who hear it find themselves obliged to seek
an explanation for it in the speaker. It can happen that the projected characteristics
are ultimately positive, but even in such cases the process of stereotyping remains
negative because of the expectations it creates.
When White people labeled certain groups “primitive,” a whole set of assumptions come into play not just about them, but also about the Whites in relation to
them: an alleged White superiority, reasonableness, and rationality, was being posited in contrast with their supposed inferiority, illogicality, and ignorance. A similar logic persisted in the contrast between “the civilized” and “savages” in spite of
the fact that those called “civilized” perpetrated atrocities on those they called savages. Indeed, they could act that way only because these others were characterized
as savage, whereas we who abuse them are not.
Another form of othering is exoticisation. Nothing is inherently exotic. The exotic
is produced by a process which recontextualizes specifically in ways relative to us.3
A culture can similarly be made to appear exotic. To characterize the other as primitive or exotic is in a sense to silence the other; it is to enclose the other in a cocoon
3
Peter Mason, Infelicities. Representations of the Exotic (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Press, 1999), 3.
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
154
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
from which he or she does not and cannot speak to me as an equal.4 Although not
excluded from reason altogether, the other as primitive or exotic is not rational in the
same way or to the same degree as I am. Nevertheless, what is decisive here is that
both the primitive and the exotic are in their otherness also ourselves. In the case of
primitives, they are ourselves in an entirely different guise: they are what we believe
we were and are no longer and can never be again. In primitivisation, we recognize
something of ourselves but at the same time we disown that part of ourselves.
Hence the primitives are not yet like us, although we might think that perhaps they
could become so over time under our direction. In exoticisation, we romanticize what
we disown. The exotic are also ourselves by virtue of the way in which they are not
like us. They are usually a projection of our desires for ourselves.5
For example, some Europeans chose to identify themselves with reason and
so came to identify emotion as African. This was a way of disowning passion
brought about in part by a certain religious culture which highlighted the practice of
self-control. But subsequently these Europeans or their heirs developed a passion
for passion. This resulted in the exoticisation of African art, African music, African
culture and so on – albeit one that did not alter the hierarchy of societies in any
fundamental way – and that in addition tended to understand that culture in simplistic ways.
There are cultures where “the man” comes to understand himself as the embodiment of discursive reason and mastery, and so he thinks of “the woman” as emotional, intuitive and subservient. In such cultures, when the man falls in love, loses
his head, prostrates himself before his beloved, his emotions are paramount as he
awaits the time when the object of his affections accepts his offer of marriage, which
is presented to her as a rational decision: “I have property, an income. I bring you
the promise of security.” And yet acceptance of the offer is supposed to restore the
proper order: the mastery of reason over passion, the mastery of the man over the
woman. Insofar as anything like this actually happens, it happens because each one
is performing a role, acting not as themselves but as they are supposed to act, acting
as other men and women act. This observation leads naturally to a consideration of
Sartre’s contribution to this theme.
I am not thinking so much of Sartre’s account in Being and Nothingness where
the Other threatens me with his or her gaze and takes the initiative away from me,
but Critique of Dialectical Reason, which is unfortunately less well-known. In
Critique of Dialectical Reason Sartre describes how, particularly in cities, people
tend to live their lives as a plurality of isolations. This does not mean that they
are independent individuals. Sartre shows how the isolated individual is a myth, a
false abstraction, a distortion of reality. Each one of us lives our isolation by living
105
R. Bernasconi
There was a time when a society or a people could be both primitive and exotic, but the dominance of certain ideas of economic and social development have made this less likely. Tzvetan
Todorov, On Human Diversity. Nationalism, Racism and Exoticism in French Thought, (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1993), 266.
5
See further, Robert Bernasconi, “Lévy-Bruhl among the Phenomenologists: Exoticisation and the
Logic of the Primitive,” Social Identities 11, no. 3 (May 2005): 229–245.
4
13
Othering
155
in everyone else’s project negatively. Sartre calls this process “seriality” and his
most famous example is the bus queue where we are formally identical insofar as
we share the same aim of getting on the bus, but have a unity that is simply negative
insofar as my place in line cannot be explained simply by reference to me, but must
refer to all the others whose place in line is equally not a function of themselves but
relative to the others. Sartre summarizes this idea by saying that everyone’s fate is
determined “as Other by every Other as Other.”6 That is to say, each person has their
place in line not on their own account but as other than the others, whereas these
others equally depend on everyone else for having the place in line that they have.
Each is not only other than the other but also other than himself.7
Sartre applies this notion of a serial unity in order to explicate social identities.
So, for example, Jews, as members of a minority grouping, submit to a “perpetual
being-outside-themselves-in-the-other” which, when it is embraced with conscious
lucidity, amounts to a responsibility for all other Jews and being at mercy in turn for
what they do insofar as what one Jew does comes to be associated with them all.8
Similarly a colonialist who beats his colonial servant may do so for no better reason
than that this is what a colonialist does in such circumstances.9
These are Sartre’s examples, but it is easy to supplement them with other examples.
Consider a Black family in the United States that buys a house in a predominately
White area. White families may start to put their houses on the market not because
they are at all impacted by the family directly, but because of a conviction that
Others – other White families – might do so, and prices will fall. They act not as
themselves but as other than themselves, that is to say, as White families act. What
makes Sartre’s analysis so rich is that he clarifies that it is a mistake to think of othering
simply as a differentiation relative to me or my group because I can be another to
myself, as in a case like this one where the White family acts as a White family in spite of
itself because the social context makes a certain set of actions rational even though
nobody is willing to own them. Thus even in a situation where there might in fact be no
White family that would refuse to buy a house in a certain neighborhood simply because
a Black family has moved there, so long as that is not known for sure then White families will act as if they were that family. Or to put it otherwise there need be no racists,
one need not even think that there are racists, one need only think that some other
people might think that there are racists for one to believe it rational to act as a racist
would act, at least according to a short-term calculative conception of rationality.
Seriality can also be used to explicate the charged character of politics that arises
from the passivity of receiving political messages through the media as opposed to
being at a meeting where one’s reaction is an integral part of the event.10 Listening
Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason (London: Verso, 1976), 261.
Sartre, Critique, 266.
8
Sartre, Critique, 268.
9
See further, Robert Bernasconi, “Sartre and Levinas: Philosophers Against Racism and
Antisemitism” in Race after Sartre, ed. Jonathan Judaken (Albany: SUNY Press, 2008), 113–127.
10
Sartre, Critique, 270–272.
6
7
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
156
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
to a distant voice on the radio or on television, one is conscious not only of the
impotence that arises from being in no position to respond, but also of the fact that
others are listening and one has no way to reach these others directly, except possibly by a letter to the newspaper, which is simply to answer seriality with seriality. In
any event, one is no longer listening to this voice coming from the Other as oneself,
but listening to it as it might be listened to by Others.11 Furthermore, to apply Sartre’s
analysis to contemporary politics in the United States, this voice often presents
itself as expressing not simply the beliefs of the individual speaker, but the views of
everyone it addresses. It tells them what they are supposed to think already: “The
American people stand for x;” “the American people know y.” A loyal United States
citizen who wants to be a “good American” and who hears this and who does not
share these beliefs is faced with a discrepancy within him- or herself. But that same
person will likely at the same time be concerned about this form of rhetoric which
is designed to make passive listeners go along with it without thinking, because it
tells them what they are supposed already to know. They are being invited by the
speaker no longer to think according to their individual will, their particularity, but
to submit to the general will. This amounts to a manipulation of the series. Sartre
discusses it with relation to the phenomenon whereby once a recording hits the top
ten then its sales tend to multiply: it becomes a recording I must have because the
Other has it and so I listen to it “as an Other, adapting my reactions to those which
I anticipate in Others.”12 Of course, this applies to all aspects of fashion.
At the heart of Sartre’s account of seriality is the impotence of the individual.13
This impotence is perhaps nowhere more clearly experienced today than in the seriality of the secret ballot and the discrepancy that exists between our ideas of what
democracy should be and the reality we exist. When voting took place in public, as,
for example, through much of the nineteenth century or even in trade union student
union meetings in Europe in the 1960s, there was a sense of a collective coming
together to express itself. These collectives were not a collection of individuals
whose views were established mathematically. They came into existence in the process and disappeared as easily. However, voting privately behind a curtain one’s
action has no meaning until later when the count is announced and even then the
results await the interpretation that is put on it by politicians and media before it
actually counts as saying something beyond “I prefer this one to the others.” My
individual reasons for voting one way or another may never be known, but some
will say that this politician was given a mandate by the electorate to do certain
things, whereas others will say it was simply a protest vote. There is no controlling
mechanism to interpret it. Knowing this, the voter now has to second guess the process. Smart politicians manipulate the votes by suggesting ahead of time how their
vote might be interpreted: this vote which happens to be for a representative of a
political party that is for withdrawing the troops is apparently going to tell the
180
R. Bernasconi
Sartre, Critique, 274–275.
Sartre, Critique, 646.
13
Sartre, Critique, 227 and 309.
11
12
13
Othering
157
terrorists they can attack with impunity. In this way my vote is no longer my own.
It has been wrested from me.
That is not to say that I cannot try to take my vote back. So I watch the opinion
polls and if I see one side winning easily or without my help, I strategically shift my
vote to register a protest. I am now voting, not as this individual operating in isolation without any communication, as Rousseau had wanted,14 but in relation to how
I anticipate the others will vote and with an eye to how still other others will interpret the sum of all our votes.
I have argued here that the problem with the conventional understanding of
othering is that the other is thought of as differentiated from me following the simple model of the gaze, as in the early Sartre. This tends to underwrite the individualism of modern society. Particularly in the United States people like to think they
somehow have a right to be seen as they want to be seen, that each individual can
choose his or her own social identity. This is an understandable reaction to unjust
stereotyping, but it seems to be an attempt to replace the violence of imposing a
false identity on someone with an impossible ideal of how society might work,
impossible because it neglects the action of othering. By contrast, the later Sartre
points with unprecedented clarity to structures that radically displace this highly
exaggerated abstract individualism. I hope to have done enough here to suggest that
Sartre’s account in Critique of Dialectical Reason takes us beyond individual projection, because it is rooted in the social conditions that transcend, even as they
implicate, the individual. Othering may be employed as a way of differentiating
oneself from some others, but it does not always accomplish what it sets out to
establish. We must learn to read this process differently in order both to understand
better what lies behind it and to counter it when necessary.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, On the Social Contract, trans. Judith R. Masters (New York: St. Martin’s
Press, 1978), 61.
14
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
Part III
Aesthetic Practice and Critical
Community: Friendship
1
2
3
Chapter 14
1
Otogogy, or Friendship, Teaching
and the Ear of the Other
2
3
Graham Allen
ro
of
14.1
4
Teaching, Friendship, Responsibility
ed
P
Efforts to determine the character of friendship and its entailment from the perspective of
humanity itself would include individual human beings, persons in one-to-one relationships
and in larger relational groups, such as families, local communities, societies, states, societies of nations, etc. The deconstructive perspective would highlight changed and changing
contextual perspectives on issues and hold open to question and challenge all claims regarding universal ideals and principles and the evaluation criteria appropriate to them.1
U
nc
or
re
ct
It would also, I’d like to add, include teaching, a philosophical and historical
understanding of the relationship between friendship and teaching, and a deconstructive analysis of the problematics of that relationship accompanied by the more
“empiricist” approach envisaged by Tony O’Connor in his “O Friend, Where Art
Thou?.” It’s a good question, my friend’s question. It immediately takes me back to
the text which made me first realise quite how inextricably linked teaching and
friendship were for those writers (philosophers, novelists, poets, political theorists)
who emerged from the Age of Reason and found themselves in a post-revolutionary
nineteenth-century. Friendship, by the way, would also include literature and the
relationship between literature and philosophy. There is thus a kind of inevitable
surplus force created by this kind of list, and this paper will attempt to exploit some
part of that force in its focus on teaching and friendship.
The text I have just referred to is Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein, a novel in which
the need for friendship, the call for friendship, and the possibility or impossibility of
Tony O’Connor, “O Friend, Where Art Thou?: Derridean Deconstruction and Friendship” in
Formless: Ways In and Out of Form, ed. Patrick Crowley and Paul Hegarty (Oxford and Bern: Peter
Lang, 2005), 39–51; here: p. 51.
1
G. Allen (*)
School of English, University College Cork, Cork, Ireland
e-mail: g.allen@ucc.ie
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_14, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
161
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
162
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
ro
of
33
P
32
ed
31
ct
30
re
29
or
28
friendship are central concerns. To emphasize this fact, Shelley added a passage, an
echo of lines from Shakespeare’s Richard III, in the 1831 edition of her novel. Walton
and Frankenstein (“the stranger”) are discussing their common desire to find a friend,
and the latter states: “I agree with you … we are unfashioned creatures, but half made
up, if one wiser, better, dearer than ourselves – such a friend ought to be – do not lend
his aid to perfectionate our weak and faulty natures.”2 Without the friend, so
Frankenstein’s logic runs, and so the novel dramatically shows, we are half-creatures,
or to employ the phrase used by her father, William Godwin, abortive men. A friend
is the other who teaches us to become that perfectionized unity we are capable of
becoming, who enables an ontological redoubling memorably articulated in
Montaigne’s text.3 But a friend also acts as a teacher, an instructor beyond or outside
of the malforming structures of power, hierarchy and force normally associated with
the teaching scene. This is, at least, what the Rousseavian account of teaching
attempts to establish in Émile, but in a staged, physically and verbally rhetorical
manner which made Mary Shelley’s father attack Rousseau for perverting the idea of
a friendship based teaching.4 The problem must be surmounted, according to Godwin,
if we are to ever produce that truly rational mode of education which would in its turn
help to establish a truly rational society. The dream of the Enlightenment depends
upon the idea of a coincidence between friendship and teaching.
This is where the work of Derrida can help us as thinkers and teachers. Derrida’s
work allows us to contemplate and even live an approach to ethics and to knowledge
which recognizes the unattainable nature of universalist ideas (concerning justice,
responsibility, hospitality) without giving up on them. Enlightenment ideas of justice,
responsibility and hospitality are, to employ a phrase Derrida often uses in his later
work, impossibly possible, they are ideas which can never be fully and finally established, founded, authorized, and yet they are the ideas we should face towards, that
we cannot do without.5 So, instead of taking sides in a move already compromised
Mary Shelley, Frankenstein; Or, The Modern Prometheus, in The Novels and Selected Works of
Mary Shelley, 8 vols., ed. Nora Crook, vol. 1, p. 187. The Shakespeare reference is to Richard’s
self-image in his first speech, Richard III, I.i. 20–21.
3
“Our souls were yoked together in such unity, and contemplated each other with so ardent affection, and with the same affection revealed each other to each other right down to the entrails, that
not only did I know his mind as well as I knew my own but I would have entrusted myself to him
with greater assurance than to myself.” Montaigne, “On affectionate relationships” in The Complete
Essays, trans. M. A. Screech (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1999), 205 – 219; here: p. 213.
4
“There is an essential disparity between youth and age; and the parent or preceptor is perhaps
always an old man to the pupil …. Rousseau has endeavoured to surmount this difficulty by the
introduction of a fictitious equality. It is unnecessary perhaps to say more of his system upon the
present occasion, than that it is a system of incessant hypocrisy and lying.” Political and
Philosophical Writings of William Godwin, 7 Vols, Gen. ed. Mark Philp (London: William
Pickering, 1993) vol. 5, p. 131.
5
See, for instance, Derrida’s The Gift of Death, trans. David Wills (Chicago/London: The Chicago
University Press, 1996); Of Hospitality, trans. Rachel Bowlby (Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2000); On Cosmopolitabism and Forgiveness, trans. Mark Dooley and Michael Hughes
(London/New York: Routledge, 2002).
2
nc
27
U
26
G. Allen
14
Otogogy, or Friendship, Teaching and the Ear of the Other
163
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
by its assumption that there are clear and stable sides to be taken, we preserve and
defend the Enlightenment by asking questions of it, and we preserve and defend
teaching by asking questions of it; questions which, currently, are illegitimate in an
academic environment in which transparency and calculability are the law.
I have always admired and loved my friend’s, Tony O’Connor’s, teaching, having
seen its results time and time again in the thought and the behaviour of the students
who have received it as a gift. Yet Tony O’Connor, my friend, is leaving the academic
teaching environment at a moment in which the dominant force is a linguistic and an
economic performativity: teaching must be calculable; teaching must be transparent; teaching must be productive; teaching must be responsible; teaching must be
evaluatable, auditable; teaching must be visible, its methods reproducible and shareable. All these demands on teaching might sound reasonable, until we register the
fact that they come to us by way of legalistic demands which implicitly, and increasingly explicitly, put a bar on what my friend and I might call philosophical thinking
on teaching. A techno-bureaucratic statement of the current performative culture
might demand that teaching must be calculable; a philosophical question might be to
ask whether teaching concerns or does not concern Bildung, and if it does whether it
could ever, logically, rationally, anticipate (in advance) its own effects. Technobureaucratic agencies, however, are quite capable of demanding that teaching include
Bildung and be calculable. Philosophy and teaching, at that point, find themselves
eased out of the picture, sidelined as non-economic luxuries, part of the expendable,
side issues of reason and thought, where thought is defined as that mental process
which does not already know, in advance, its own outcome, its own products.
But is it responsible, in this performative environment of transparency, where
everything must be visible, calculable and productive, simply to return to the questions such a transparent ideology conceals? To stock-pile the questions and aporias,
the contradictions and incompatibilities? As if, in the name of a reason to come, one
were building an arsenal of weapons not yet available for use? I would venture to say
that the answer is no, that responsibility, responsible teaching, must involve something more. There are, after all, students in front of us, people whose futures we as
teachers will effect one way or another. I think Tony O’Connor would argue that
responsibility cannot simply be posited in the to-come, and I think Derrida would
and indeed did say the same thing. The link I have been remembering, in the name of
my friend, between teaching and friendship is the marker of this unavoidable responsibility, since friendship (whether or not it is possible in its Enlightenment senses)
would have to be extended towards the students, offered as a gift, without reserve and
without calculation (or at least without the calculable) for teaching to occur.
14.2
Otogogy
Derrida, in “Otobiographies: The Teaching of Nietzsche and the Politics of the Proper
Name,” remarks on having too little time. The rhythm he employs is fast paced, the
pace of a spoken address. Derrida evokes and utilizes a certain freedom—he cites in
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
164
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
ro
of
101
P
100
ed
99
ct
98
re
97
or
96
this context “academic freedom,” he says “I repeat: a-ca-dem-ic free-dom—you can
take it or leave it” (O, p. 4). This freedom is the academic freedom of the philosopher
who could say more, who could fill in the gaps between and within his aphorisms,
who could make the connections between the texts discussed and all the countless
other texts which could connect to those discussed. The academic freedom of the
philosopher who is speaking to the ears of the other and wants those ears to be small
ones, capable of registering differences.
What I want to talk about is otogogy, a neologism of my own making which I do
not intend to expressly define (you will hear it or you will not), and I want to do so
by looking a bit more closely and a bit more slowly than Derrida does at Nietzsche’s
On the Future of our Educational Institutions.6 Derrida’s “Otobiographies” text
concerns the legacy of Nietzsche’s texts and Nietzsche’s name; it concerns how
Nietzsche’s name inherits from the future to which it calls. It is about how autobiography ultimately becomes biography, that is how the text by the author on himself, the text which ventures (puts forth) the author’s name, must ultimately come to
mean what it means because it is read and signed (given meaning) by those who
read it (rather than by the author him-or-herself). The essay is also about how the
worst returns in the future, in place of the future. The essay is about this and about
how Nietzsche already knows it. Nietzsche writes: “I know my fate …. One day my
name will be associated with the memory of something monstrous.” (O, p. 31) Even
though the real monster for Nietzsche is society, the culture machine, the “hypocritical hound” which “whispers in your ear through his educational systems, which are
actually acroustic and acroamatic devices” which make “your ears grow larger”
until you turn into long-eared asses—even though there is a whole critique of the
“culture machine” in Nietzsche’s text(s), it remains the fact, as Derrida states, that
“[t]here is nothing contingent about the fact that the only political regimen to have
effectively brandished his [F.N ‘s] name as a major and official banner was Nazi.”
(O, p. 31) It remains a fact that Nietzsche, at least Derrida’s Nietzsche, knew this,
knew and argued that, to quote Derrida’s reading, “all post-Hegelian texts have this
potential to go in two ways—left or right—including, by implication, his own
texts—there is no guarantee—there is only a destination of the text—to the ear of
the other—the post-Hegelian other.” (O, p. 32) There is no guarantee. No calculability in one’s texts and, by implication, one’s teaching. It can always, potentially, end
up resembling what Derrida calls the “poisoned milk which has …. gotten mixed up
in advance with the worst of our times.” (O, p. 7)
Nietzsche’s 1872 On the Future of our Educational Institutions is full of monsters and full of ears. It is the text in which Hitler saw confirmation of his own ideologies in Nietzsche’s references to a great Führer (someone we—students and
teachers—need, according to Nietzsche). It is a text against the modernizing of
university and secondary school (the German Gymnasium) and in particular the
tendencies of extension (democratization or massification) and diminution (service
to the state). Nietzsche’s text is uncanny and disturbing, if we listen to it closely.
nc
95
U
94
G. Allen
Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Future of Our Educational Institutions, trans. Michael W. Grenke
(South Bend: St. Augustine’s Press, 2004). Hereafter cited as FEI.
6
14
Otogogy, or Friendship, Teaching and the Ear of the Other
165
ro
of
It is a text which seems to speak against our basic political ideas and ideals, and yet
in which we cannot help but see the voice of something that looks like friendship.
I will return to this.
Against the modern trends of extension and diminution, Nietzsche argues for the
“truly German” tendencies of narrowing and concentration. Nietzsche’s argument
involves a wholesale critique of the modern idea of academic freedom: the academic freedom of the teacher and the academic freedom of the student. Academic
freedom concerns our ears and our hands, as well as our mouths, Nietzsche argues.
In the fifth lecture, Nietzsche’s old, grey-haired philosopher (of whom more in a
moment) imagines a hypothetical conversation with a foreigner about the “university only as an educational institution [Bildungsanstalt].” (FEI, p. 106) The foreigner
asks: “how is the student connected with the university with you?” And the old,
grey-haired philosopher states: “through the ear.” Yes, repeats the old, grey-haired
philosopher, “Only through the ear.” He explains:
ed
P
The student listens. When he speaks, when he sees, when he walks, when he is sociable,
when he practices the arts, in short, when he lives, he is independent, i.e. not dependent
on the educational institution. Very frequently the student immediately writes something
as he hears it. These are the moments in which he hangs on the umbilical cord of the
university. He can chose what he wants to hear, he does not need to believe what he hears,
he can close his ears if he does not like to hear. This is the “acroamatic”[7] method of
teaching. (ibid)
re
ct
We could come back to that tantalising word “acroamatic” later, perhaps.
Nietzsche goes on to describe how the teacher, separated from the students by a
“monstrous gap,” speaks whatever he wants to the students. So that the scene of
modern Gymnasium teaching, becomes that of
or
One speaking mouth and very many ears with half as many writing hands—that is the external academic apparatus, that is the educational [culture – bildung] machine of the university
in action. (FEI, pp. 106)
U
nc
This is the “acroamatic” “mouth to ear” scene of modern “academic freedom,”
which ultimately leaves the student able to open or close his ears at will. This is the
vision of education against which the old, grey-haired philosopher speaks. On the
Future of Our Educational Institutions is cast in a fictional, operatic, one might
almost say Wagernian form (Wagner was in the audience for the second lecture).
The text has an introduction and a preface. In the latter Nietzsche dedicates his text
to the few “calm readers,” a “few human beings,” “not swept up in the dizzying
haste of our rolling age,” readers (only a few) who “still have time” to contemplate
“our education” and who have “still not unlearned how to think” while they read;
they “still understand[s] how to read the secret between the lines” (FEI, p. 19).8
7
“Acroama,” “Acroamata”: “1580. from Gk. Anything heard, f. hear. 1. A rhetorical declamation
(as opp. to an argument); 2. Anc. Phil. Oral teaching heard only by the initiated; esoteric as opp. to
exoteric doctrines. Hence: Acroamatic adj. orally communicated; esoteric; secret”. (OED).
8
Of course, as Derrida makes clear, the addresses or lectures were not published in Nietzsche’s
time. Whenever they have subsequently been published they have been so against Nietzsche’s
express prohibition.
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
166
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
ro
of
181
P
180
ed
179
ct
178
re
177
or
176
The plot of this text involves two young students (one of whom is Nietzsche)
who, 5 year’s previously, dedicated their lives to founding a “small union of a few
comrades, with the intention to find for our productive inclinations in art and literature a firm and obligatory organization.” (FEI, p. 23) The two young students have
come back to Rolandseck on the Rhine to celebrate in “a thankful, indeed ceremonious, feeling” this initial founding “inspiration.” In shooting their pistols they disturb
the old, grey-haired philosopher, his dog and a “somewhat younger man” who
accompanies him. The old man is furious, since he says that the shooting of their
pistols represents “a true assassination attempt against philosophy.” (FEI, p. 28) The
old man is, it turns out, waiting for his “old friend,” one of “our first philosophers”
and the young students have disturbed his preparatory thoughts. (FEI, p. 31)
Nietzsche’s student (the student that is “Nietzsche”) realizes that there may indeed
be something to be gained by listening to the old philosopher’s conversation with
his younger companion (FEI, pp. 33–34). This latter is a man who has given up a
teaching career in disgust. Repeating on demand the philosopher’s “cardinal principle” concerning education, “how unbelievably small the number of really educated ones finally is and can be in general” (p. 34), it is the younger companion who
presents a critique of the current educational trends of extension and diminution.
The old philosopher at one point interrupts him in agreement: “The most general
education is just barbarism.” (FEI, p. 38) and, prompted by his companion, begins
a sustained critique of the current Gymnasium system; a critique which rests on the
manner in which German youth have been barbarously emancipated from a strict
education in the German classics. This is a betrayal, he argues, of the most fundamental aspect of education, the “one healthy and natural starting point” of education, which is “the artistic, serious, and rigorous habituation in the use of the mother
tongue.” (FEI, p. 54) The true task of the educator is to bring “the ones little gifted”
into “a holy terror [Schreck] before the language, the gifted ones into a noble
inspiration for the same.” (FEI, p. 45)
The old man insists that the only thing that will bring back to the masses a genuine culture (Bildung) is an educational system which serves to inspire a few heroes
of the mother tongue: “Thus education of the mass cannot be our goal: rather education of the individual, selected human beings equipped for great and lasting works.”
(FEI, p. 66) The current educational institutions, the Gymnasium and the university,
serve the state; whereas educational institutions which genuinely give birth to culture, which form culture, serve the masses and the mother tongue by breeding out of
them men of genius which should be “ripened and nourished in the mother’s lap of
the culture of a people.” (FEI, p. 67). The two young students, enthused by hearing
a philosophy not intended for them, leap up to thank the philosopher, who has completely forgotten their presence. The students, however, insist that the philosopher
stay to speak to them more and wait for the arrival of his philosophical friend.
Finally, they hear the sounds of the philosopher’s friend (one of “our first philosophers”) travelling towards them on the lake. The old man asks the students to fire
their pistols in rhythm to the song emanating from the friend’s boat, but they misfire,
shoot unrhythmically, and it turns out that the friend is arriving with a bunch of
students, friends of the young students who have already so inconvenienced the
nc
175
U
174
G. Allen
14
Otogogy, or Friendship, Teaching and the Ear of the Other
167
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
philosopher. This sends him into a rage and his anger is hardly appeased when the
students and the companion ask the philosopher to now speak about the university,
adding that surely it can be said that the Gymnasium at least fits some young men to
embark on an independent course of study. That they have not been listening carefully enough is obvious here; and it is here that we get the philosopher’s long discourse on the university as a place of ears and mouths and scribbling hands: an
education (culture) machine for the service of the state. The Gymnasium gives no
guidance to the young student, academic freedom turns out to be isolation: “Free!”
the philosopher says, mockingly: “Test this freedom you knowers of human beings!”
(FEI, p. 108) Instead of an education (Bildung – formation, cultural formation) the
young student of the Gymnasium and the University is left bewildered by “the unendurable burden of standing alone.” (FEI, p. 112)
Derrida writes, paraphrasing the argument of this section of the text (which, in
many ways, is the argument of the whole text): “The whole misfortune of today’s
students can be explained by the fact that they have not found a Führer. They remain
führerlos, without a leader.” (O, p. 28) This is the part of the text, in other words, in
which the infamous references to the need for a great Führer occur. I would, however, add that there are two sides to the misfortune, or tragedy, of “today’s students.”
One side is, indeed, being führerlos; but the other side is being isolated, bewildered,
burdened, lost. I say these are two sides, I separate them, since it is where come the
most direct calls for a great Führer, that we also get the most humane, the most
touching, the most affective and pathos-driven, the most teacherly speech from that
cross, irritated, irascible, contrary, apparently flawed, friendless, or at least lingering
(friend-lingering) grey-haired, old philosopher. This is the moment, in other words,
when the constantly erupting anger of the old, grey-haired philosopher displays
what? Sensibility? Parental concern? Fatherly outrage? Maternal care? What would
we call—and how do we hear—this anger for the lost student?
U
nc
or
…. for that time, in which he is apparently the single free man in clerk’s and servants’ reality, he pays for that grandiose illusion of freedom through ever-renewing torments and
doubts. He feels that he cannot lead himself, he cannot help himself: then he dives poor in
hopes into the daily world and into daily work: the most trivial activity envelops him, his
members sink into flabbiness. Suddenly he again rouses himself: he still feels the power, not
waned, that enabled him to hold himself aloft. Pride and noble resolution form [bilden] and
grow in him. It terrifies him to sink so early into the narrow, petty moderation of a speciality,
and now he grasps after supports and pillars in order not to be dragged along in that course.
In vain! These supports give way; for he had made a mistake and held tight to brittle reeds.
In an empty and disconsolate mood he sees his plans go up in smoke: his condition is
abominable and undignified … And thus his helplessness and the lack of a leader toward
culture [Bildung] drives him from one form of existence into another: doubt, upswing, life’s
necessity, hope, despair, everything throws him to and fro, as a sign, that all the stars above
him according to which he could pilot his ship are extinguished. (FEI, pp. 111–112)
I will say— without hiding anything—that I see myself in this picture. That is
me, there, in the picture! Driven this way and that way, with no foundation, with no
steady, guiding principle, method or, dare I say it (me a university lecturer!), Bildung.
A formless thing, elevating my work, only then to see it as nothing, striving after a
voice and a vision, only to plummet into a sea of texts I feel I will never master or
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
168
G. Allen
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
Oh the miserable guilty-innocents …. For they lack something, each of them must have
come up against this. They lack a true educational institution that could give them goals,
masters, methods, models, fellows and from whose interior the powerful and elevating breath
of the true German spirit would stream toward them. Thus they starve in the wilderness; thus
they degenerate into enemies of that spirit which at bottom is intimately related to them; thus
they pile up guilt upon guilt more heavily than any other generation ever has piled up, soiling
the pure, desecrating the holy, pre-canonizing the false and the phoney. In them you may
come to consciousness about the educational power of our universities and lay before yourselves in all seriousness the question: What do you promote in them? (FEI, p. 114)
273
274
275
276
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
P
272
ed
271
What do you promote in them? The old, grey-haired philosopher finishes this
speech by returning to the true “German spirit” which the teacher should promote
in those few who are capable of rising out of the mother tongue and the maternal
womb of the people. But that is monstrous to us. That is the beginning of the monstrosity which Nietzsche somehow knew would attach itself, someday, to his name.
So the question remains for us, at least for me: What do you (I) promote in them?
There was supposed to be a sixth and maybe even a seventh lecture to complete
The Future of Our Educational Institutions, but they never came to be. Nietzsche
never wrote them. Like the philosophical friend, the final lectures did not arrive.
Nietzsche’s text finishes (without being complete) with the imminent arrival of the
philosophical friend, although potentially spoilt by his being in the company of
students. Well, that is going a bit fast. The philosopher moves, in the speech I have
just been focusing on, into a description of the post-Napoleonic youth movement,
the Burschenschaft who learnt “on the slaughtering field” of battle what they
couldn’t learn in today’s educational institutions: “that one needs great leaders, and
that all education begins with obedience.” He goes over, quickly, the history of those
students, who fought in the name of Schiller, who, taken from them too early, “could
have been a leader, a master, an organiser” for those students “and whom … now
missed [him] with such heart-felt rage.” Those students who, in that desire for a
leader, learnt on the battle field, committed the instinctive and “short-sighted,” overly
angry, overly enraged “bloody deed[s], in the murder of Kotzebue.” A deed which
demonstrated their tragic situation: “the doom of those portentous students: they did
not find the leader that they needed.” (FEI, p. 117)
ct
270
re
269
or
268
nc
267
U
266
ro
of
277
even assimilate. I also see my students in that passage. My post-graduate students,
most definitely. But also my best (and what does that mean?) undergraduate students.
The ones that show themselves from within the mass (massified) ranks. And show
themselves, usually, almost invariably, because they are lost, awakened to something they cannot live with and now cannot live without. Those students who show
themselves to me for what? For guidance? For leadership? Me? Students who often
seem to want me to say this is it, say, deconstruction is it, say be a deconstructionist,
or say be a Marxist, or a psychoanalytical literary critic, or this kind of feminist, or
that kind, say be a historicist, or a formalist. Students who seem to want me to guide
them, to lead them, the ones who have somehow (is it through me?) learnt the difference between Erziehung and Bildung. So, imagine my reading, you may well be
able to hear it, it may be entirely lost on you, when the old, grey-haired philosopher
goes on, in his anger, thus:
265
14
Otogogy, or Friendship, Teaching and the Ear of the Other
169
nc
No woman or trace of woman, if I have read correctly – save the mother, that’s understood.
But this is part of the system. The mother is the faceless figure of a figurant, an extra. She
gives rise to all the figures by losing herself in the background of the scene like an anonymous persona. Everything comes back to her, beginning with life; everything addresses and
destines itself to her. She survives on the condition of remaining at bottom. (O, p. 38)
U
[AU1]
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
But there is one more thing, if we are going slowly, or trying to, before the end
and the friend’s imminent (non) arrival. It comes in the way of a similie, a musical
figure of an orchestra—peopled with “shrivelled, good-natured” musicians, not
much too look at really, a rather unpromising, motley crew—until the great conductor beats them into glorious music. That is the end, apart from the fact that we wait
for the friend, one of “our first philosophers.” At the end, having been instructed by
a philosopher that we need a leader, we wait with that philosopher on the arrival of
the friend. In fact, we wait the arrival of friends, since the arriving philosopher is
accompanied by students. Are we waiting for a philosopher who will also be a
leader? Or a friend who will turn out simply to be another philosopher reiterating
the call for a leader? Does the friend’s apparent alliance with the arriving students
suggest that he is in fact an enemy? If he is an enemy rather than a friend to the old
philosopher will he turn out to be a friend to the students? And if so how? Is not the
philosopher, despite his bad temper, a friend to those students who he has awakened
to a desire for a genuine German education and culture? Or is he not, rather, in doing
that, their enemy? What, in the context of teaching, of Erziehung and Bildung, is the
difference between a friend and a leader and an enemy? So many questions, so
many acroamatic questions ringing in our ears.
But that is not the end, not for me anyway. Nor is it the end for Derrida, nor, I
imagine, for my philosopher friend, Tony O’Connor. Derrida ends “Otobiographies”
with a warning. “The temptation is strong for all of us,” he writes, “to recognize
ourselves on the program of this staged scene or in the pieces of this musical score.”
(O, p. 38) Perhaps I was going too fast all along and should have reminded myself
of this temptation earlier. But that is not all. Derrida ends with the other who does
not enter into this scene. Not the friend, but rather woman: “woman, if I have read
correctly,” he says, “never appears at any point along the umbilical cord, either to
study or to teach …. No woman or trace of woman.” He adds: “And I do not make
this remark in order to benefit from that supplement of seduction which today enters
into all courtships or courtrooms. This vulgar procedure is part of what I propose to
call ‘gynegogy.’” Quickly, he adds one more, small paragraph:
And that is it, that is the end. Very quickly, at the very end, woman and the Mother
come in only to be lost to figuration.
Time is one of the reasons it happens: this quickness, this speed, and this “No
woman or trace of woman.” The feminine, the possibility of the feminine, gets lost
because of the quickness of time, because we go so quickly that we lose her, lose
sight of her. The feminine I am here – with Derrida – associating with the surprising
pathos and concern for the student. The rhetoric of transparency and performativity
are so quick that they demand what our students will learn from our teaching before
we have even met those students and before we have begun to teach them. Teaching
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
170
ro
of
361
P
360
ed
359
ct
358
re
357
or
356
must occur so quickly, in other words, that friendship, even if it is rhetorically and
juridically demanded, finds no space to enter the scene of teaching. I am associating
friendship in teaching with the appearance of the feminine. Am I going too fast in
that, my friend? Possibly. But I need some ground upon which to responsibly respond
to my current students, and I need it quick. They get lost so quickly. So I try to go as
slow as I can, in this situation of high velocity. It is something, the need for care,
attention, rigour, and above all reading (which is always slow if it is reading), that my
friend, Tony O’Connor, has taught many, many people to understand and practice.
nc
355
U
354
G. Allen
Author Query
Chapter No.: 14
0001327772
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please check the term “Gynegogy” for correctness.
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
Query
1
Kantian Friendship
2
Gary Banham
3
ro
of
Chapter 15
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
Kant’s culminating work in practical philosophy, the Metaphysics of Morals,
concludes its account of the elements of ethics with a very brief discussion of friendship. The discussion of the elements of ethics forms the largest part of the second
half of the Metaphysics of Morals, the half entitled the Tugendlehre or Doctrine of
Virtue. The main division within the discussion of virtue is between duties to oneself and duties to others and the concluding discussion of friendship is part of the
latter. However the account of duties to others is itself divided between a discussion
of duties of love to other human beings and duties of virtue towards them in the
strict sense. The duties of virtue in the strict sense arise from the respect we owe to
others. Given this division of the discussion of duties to others the fact that the
concluding discussion of friendship is articulated as indicative of an intimate union
of love and respect suggests that this concluding discussion is inserted as a way of
bridging the division between the two areas just demarcated. The cultivation of
friendship would appear then to be a way to overcome the division between these
two kinds of duty. However, whilst this appears a first clue to comprehending
the importance of the concluding discussion of friendship, it also points us to a
couple of questions. The first question could be put in terms of the status of the
reference to love and respect in the division of duties since Kant describes them as
“feelings that accompany the carrying out of these duties” (Ak. 6: 448). This reference to feeling is one that has one clear advantage in Kant’s account which is that it
allows for the contrast between the two types of duty to others in terms of forces as
when Kant suggests an analogy between the relationship of love and respect with
that of attraction and repulsion in the physical world (Ak. 6: 449). However, whilst
the advantage of the reference to feeling is that it makes this comparison intuitively
plausible, the disadvantage concerns the fact that Kant’s general account would
[AU1]
G. Banham (*)
Managing Editor, Kant Studies Online, Manchester Metropolitan University, Manchester, UK
e-mail: garybanham@me.com
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_15, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
171
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
172
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
ro
of
36
P
35
ed
34
ct
33
re
32
or
31
seem at odds with such a reference to feeling and furthermore he subsequently
states that in this context love is not to be understood as a feeling but as the ground
of the maxim of benevolence (Ak. 6: 449).1 Similarly, he moves on to state that
respect is not to be grasped here as a sense of comparative worth, which would be a
mere feeling but rather as the basis of a maxim of “limiting our self-esteem by the
dignity of humanity in another person” (Ak. 6: 449). So once again it is a practical
sense, which is being given to the notion of the “feeling” in question and a pathological sense is being discarded. However, whilst the advantage of this element of
Kant’s account is that it preserves the purity of the moral motivation, it undermines
the analogous reference to forces and creates a problem with seeing the contrast
between the two types of duties as one that is based on them pulling us in different
directions.
This gives us our first set of problems. They can be summarized as follows. Either
Kant is serious in viewing the division between two forms of duty to others as
grounded in some sense on feeling and hence can justify the comparison of the relationship between them with the physical forces of attraction and repulsion or he is
not serious about this reference to feeling and can maintain the purity of moral motivation but not the analogy between the two types of duty to others and physical
forces. Either way part of the account seems to be lost. If we lose the reference to the
comparison with physical forces it is not merely that the reconciling role of friendship appears less necessary it is also that the nature of the division between the two
duties seems not to be one that can be captured in the terms Kant seems to wish.
Before moving on to stating the second sort of problem I want to consider, there
is something that should be mentioned as possibly mitigating the concern with the
general contrast between the two types of duty to others that underlies the concluding account of friendship. This mitigation is grounded on the point that Kant makes
that whilst we can treat the two types of duty to others separately and they can even
exist separately that they are nonetheless basically always united “by the law into
one duty” (Ak. 6: 448). Since this is so then the division between the two types of
duty to others has to do with the relative standing of the reference to one of the
principles in relation to the circumstances of moral judgment. However in some
respects this mitigating comment complicates the problem further since if we regard
the two types of duty to others as essentially two aspects of one and the same law
then does this not weaken further the analogy between the two types of duty to others
and physical forces?
This first set of questions arises from considering the background to the introduction of friendship at the conclusion of the Doctrine of Virtue. Some of these
questions are connected however to the ones arising on turning to the account of
friendship itself. Kant opens this treatment with three determinations of friendship
in his first sentence concerning it: “Friendship (considered in its perfection) is the
union of two persons through equal mutual love and respect.” (Ak. 6: 469) Friendship
is presented in its perfection. Hence the treatment of friendship will be part of Kant’s
nc
30
U
29
G. Banham
1
The maxim of benevolence is equated with practical love and said to result in beneficence.
15
Kantian Friendship
173
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
general perfectionism as indicated in his earlier reference to the “ethical law of
perfection” (Ak. 6: 450), the law to love your neighbour as yourself. However the
oddity of treating friendship in terms of perfection is that the general basis of the
division between duties to oneself and duties to others is that the former are based on
cultivation of one’s own perfection, the latter on the happiness of others (Ak. 6: 385).
If friendship is to be considered in terms of perfection but friendship clearly involves
a relation with others then it would appear that the discussion of friendship will in a
sense cross the divide between duties to oneself and duties to others.
The second determination of friendship in the above citation states that friendship involves the union of two persons. This second determination of friendship is
interesting in two different respects. The relation between two persons friendship
involves is particularly intimate if it involves union as this implies a comparison
with a type of physical conjunction as Kant treated in the Doctrine of Right.2 Not
only is there a reference to union, but Kant also treats the union as one between two
persons. The final element of this determination of friendship is that it involves not
merely love and respect but an equal mutuality of them.
The first point to bring out is that Kant treats the discussion of friendship as
clearly part of the description of duties declaring that human beings have a duty of
friendship although he qualifies this point by stating that friendship is unattainable in
practice and that it is the striving for it which is a duty. Since to strive is to exercise
a willed volition then the duty concerns the summoning of a kind of force within us.
The impossibility of the ideal of friendship being achieved is indicated to be connected to the forces in question which are none other those of love and respect which
we have already been focusing on. Kant here clearly refers to feelings that come from
the different duties and he explicitly again draws the parallel between these feelings
and the physical forces: “For love can be regarded as an attraction and respect as a
repulsion, and if the principle of love bids friends to draw closer, the principle of
respect requires them to stay at a proper distance from each other” (Ak. 6: 470).
Despite the oscillation we noted above between speaking of the distinction between
the duties to others in terms of feelings and speaking of it in terms of maxims the
reference to feelings is of cardinal import for the treatment of friendship. Not only
does this reference emerge here clearly but it also does so once again in connection
with the same analogy between the feelings in question and physical forces that was
mobilised at the beginning of Kant’s treatment of duties to others.
The next point of focus concerns the manner in which the principle of love is
limited by the principle of respect in the striving for friendship. Kant brings out both
a key rule that governs such striving and connects the two involved in this striving
to a wider social network: “This limitation on intimacy, which is expressed in the
rule that even the best of friends should not make themselves too familiar with each
other, contains a maxim that holds not only for the superior in relation to the inferior
but also in reverse.” (Ak. 6: 470). The limitation of love by respect follows the
2
“Sexual union (consummation) is the reciprocal use that one human being makes of the sexual
organs and capacities of another” (Ak. 6: 277).
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
174
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
ro
of
119
P
118
ed
117
ct
116
re
115
or
114
model of a restriction and realization schema as love is restricted precisely with
regard to expression. There is only so much one should say to one’s friend: limitation of what one says is the means by which respect governs love. This first point
concerning limitation of expression is connected however to a recognition that
whilst the friends may themselves be striving for a relation in which each is united
to the other in a bond that involves equality (of love and respect), that this does not
prevent it from being the case that they are in fact not equal to each other in social
standing as one will always be (in some degree) the superior of the other. The importance of this point is that there are relations that require respect of the position of the
other.3 So one of the problems the striving for friendship has to deal with is precisely
the unequal standing of the two involved in the striving with regard to social networks that exist over and beyond that of their attempted union.
The general social inequality that marks the relation between the two involved in
striving for friendship affects the degree to which these two can be candid with each
other. The limitation of love by respect is one that we have found concerns this ability for candid expression. If friendship was approached as resting on feelings says
Kant it would never be safe from interruption so he re-determines his notion of
perfect friendship as moral friendship and describes it now in terms of the exchange
between the two of secrets: “Moral friendship….is the complete confidence of two
persons in revealing their secret judgments and feelings to each other, as far as such
disclosures are consistent with mutual respect” (Ak. 6: 471).
Whilst the relation in question is demarcated from feeling it is also intricately
connected to it since the secrets the friends will wish to reveal to each other concern
not only judgments but feelings also. The risks are considerable in such exchanges
since secret judgments will include views on such sensitive matters as religion and
politics which may be imprudently disclosed but also because in speaking of feelings candidly faults may be openly stated which others can take advantage of. So in
tying friendship in to a consideration of society Kant brings out the publicity that we
often wish for judgments and feelings runs into a barrier of fear concerning how
others will use and abuse our declarations.
So our second set of questions can now be stated as arising directly from the
treatment of friendship itself rather than from the division of duties towards others
that precedes it. Firstly, the fact that friendship involves an ideal brings in an element of perfectionism to duties to others that is otherwise contained within the
treatment of duties to oneself alone. This suggests a kind of crossing of this divide,
a crossing that possibly has something to do with the point that there is a striving in
friendship for union with the other so that they are treated as like oneself in some
sense. During the course of discussion of the striving for this union with the other
Kant both insists on the role of feeling—stressing as central to understanding it the
need to harmonize the feelings of respect and love in a manner analogous to that of
physical forces—and he constantly marginalizes the place of feeling in the treatment of friendship, regarding friendships based on feeling as unsafe. Finally the
nc
113
U
112
G. Banham
3
See also Stephen Darwall, “Two Kinds of Respect,” Ethics 88 (1977): 36–49.
15
Kantian Friendship
175
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
striving for friendship with the other involves a desire for communication up to and
including mutual exchange of secretly held feelings and judgments and yet is also
circumscribed by a clear need for limitation on intimacy. Just as the general treatment of duties to others pointed to what appeared to be a need for a decision between
two options neither of which would allow for the breadth of discussion Kant
appeared to wish so also the direct treatment of friendship itself seems to require a
similar set of choices whilst also preventing either pole being chosen.
In order to begin tackling these problems we need to isolate the central elements
of them. In fact, it is the same apparent tension that underlies both the division of
duties to others and the specific treatment of friendship. This is that there appears to
be a reference to feeling that is both required and yet unsustainable within the terms
of the account given. Additionally to this we note also however that the specificity of
friendship carries with it the feature that it appears to complicate the question of the
range of Kant’s perfectionism and that there is an apparent aporia in Kant’s view of
the place of communication of secrets in his model of striving for friendship. These
three points: the problem about the role and status of feeling, the range of Kant’s
perfectionism and the point of reference to a communication that is also strictly limited point to all the problems enumerated as concerning the scope of something in
Kant’s treatment. Questions of scope are modal questions for Kant and are thus connected to the possibility of friendship, a possibility which Kant declares on, when he
states that moral friendship is not merely an ideal but “actually exists here and there
in its perfection” (Ak. 6: 472). Since this is so then the scope of feeling, perfectionism and allowable communicability must be such that we are capable of them.
If we begin with the question of the role and status of feeling in Kant’s general
moral psychology it is so that we can start to clarify the reference to feeling we have
noted both in his discussion of the division of duties to others and specifically in the
treatment of friendship. As early as the Groundwork Kant treated of respect and
indeed did so within the first section of this work. Kant here responds to the accusation that reference to respect is no more than seeking refuge in obscure feelings by
stating that whilst respect is a feeling it is “not one received by means of influence”
but is rather self-wrought by means of a rational concept and hence different from the
type of feeling that can be understood as a product of inclination. Kant then adds:
U
What I cognize immediately as a law for me I cognize with respect, which signifies merely
consciousness of the subordination of my will to a law without the modification of other
influences on my sense. Immediate determination of the will by means of the law and consciousness of this is called respect, so that this is regarded as the effect of the law on the
subject, and not as the cause of the law. Respect is properly the representation of a worth that
infringes upon my self-love. Hence there is something that is regarded as an object neither of
inclination nor of fear, though it has something analogous to both. (Ak. 4: 401n)
There are a number of interesting elements involved in this account of respect.
Since the feeling of respect is distinguished from the inclinations and from fear by
means of its relation to reason the arrival at the feeling of respect has something to
do with a self-limitation. Consciousness of the law is effectively equivalent to a
feeling of respect for it and this respect for it causes a restriction of self-love indicating a possible basis for Kant’s subsequent view of friendship as concerning
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
176
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
ro
of
206
P
205
ed
204
ct
203
re
202
or
201
more than one. The thing that is an object for our feeling but not for inclination or
fear nonetheless can be analogically compared with these latter just as we note that
Kant later analogically compares respect to the physical force of repulsion. The
following through of the analogy with inclination and fear is by means of the feeling of subordination which compromises self-love. The analogy with inclination by
contrast is based on the fact that the subordination of us to the law is something that
we ourselves bring about. Another person can be invoked however as an example of
the law (Ak. 4: 401n).
The importance of the other being an example of the law is returned to in the
Critique of Practical Reason where this example is used to demonstrate the practicability of submission to the law. Once again Kant makes the point here that respect
is a feeling quite distinct from anything pathological and to mark the difference
he speaks here of “moral feeling” (Ak. 5: 76), an expression that recurs in the
Metaphysics of Morals where it is defined in the following way: “a susceptibility on
the part of free choice to be moved by pure practical reason (and its law)…this is
what we call moral feeling” (Ak. 6: 400). However whilst these determinations go
someway to addressing the question as to why there is a discussion of feeling in the
treatment of duties to others they also primarily suggest that the reference to the
other is one in which the other stands in for the law. However whilst there is something to this way of putting the matter we need to amend it slightly in view of our
comprehension of what the moral law is really concerned with. In the Groundwork
Kant lays out the basis for a contrast that is repeated on a number of subsequent
occasions in his later ethical writings. This is the contrast between conditional and
unconditional worth. Objects of inclination have only conditional worth as they first
require that there are needs that they are grasped as meeting. This is the ground of
Kant’s notorious remark to the effect that any rational being would wish to be without inclinations (Ak. 4: 428) but whilst this remark may in some respects be problematic the key point underlying it here concerns the limited value of objects that we
wish to acquire.4 Discussion of beings that arise from nature but are without reason
falls under the heading of things and such beings effectively are related to as candidates for hypothetical imperatives. By contrast the relation to a person is quite different: “because their nature already marks them out as an end in itself, that is, as
something that may not be used merely as a means, and hence so far limits all choice
(and is an object of respect)” (Ak. 4: 428).
On the basis of this treatment Kant arrives at the so-called Formula of Humanity
(Ak. 4: 429) the formula of treating humanity in others and oneself as never merely
a means but also always as an end in itself. This reference to ends is repeated in the
supreme principle of the doctrine of virtue: “act in accordance with a maxim of
ends that it can be a universal principle for everyone to have” (Ak. 6: 395). These
nc
200
U
199
G. Banham
4
See Marcia Baron, Kantian Ethics (Almost) Without Apology (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,
1995) passim. My point, however, is somewhat surprisingly missing from Baron’s extended and
fascinating analysis, namely, that it is in the context of establishing the essential relativity of all
objects of acquisition that Kant makes this remark about inclination. This is important in terms of
his point that what has an end-in-itself is beyond all market price.
15
Kantian Friendship
177
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
two formulas are importantly related as including such a key reference to ends
although the formula from the Groundwork is one that treats an end as something
self-subsistent, “something the existence of which in itself has absolute worth”
(Ak. 4: 428), as given in other words, not as an aim to be achieved. This selfsubsistent end is, as it were, that which we have to have regard for. It limits the
permissible ends that can be adopted as the basis of maxims whether those ends be
thought of as involving aim-oriented action or as concerning the preservation and
promotion of the self-subsistent end-in-itself. That there is a difference between
these two senses of “end” is the point of David Velleman’s comment: “Self-existent
ends are the objects of motivating attitudes that regard and value them as they
already are; other ends are the objects of attitudes that value them as possibilities
to be brought about”.5 The key point here is that the person is valued in a way distinct from an end thought of as an aim despite the fact that our relations with persons include actions in which we work with them to achieve aims. Were it
permissible to relate to persons simply in terms of aims there would be no inherent
problem in slavery. So the distinction between the two forms of end is essential to
the understanding of the formula of humanity.
What is key from what we have uncovered in our treatment here of the formula
of humanity is the understanding that whilst the other can serve as an example of the
law, the basis of them so serving is not merely that they can act in ways that humble
my self-love. It is also that the law is revealed in the formula of humanity as centred
on respect for persons. Persons are thus that the value of which the law enjoins us to
care for. Having established this much I now wish to turn to how Kant builds on this
point in the Groundwork in order to establish the basis of his analogical comparison
between moral motivations in the discussion of duties to others and physical forces.
Uncovering the basis of this comparison should subsequently aid us in describing
ways of understanding the relation between the two forms of duty to others and how
they are combined in friendship.
In the subsequent development of the discussion in the Groundwork Kant makes
a reflexive turn in his consideration of the formula of humanity. It is not merely with
regard to others after all that the formula applies as it is what will be related in the
Doctrine of Virtue as the basis of duties to oneself. This is made clear in the
Groundwork when Kant states that: “to say that in the use of means to any end I am
to limit my maxim to the condition of its universal validity as a law for every subject
is tantamount to saying that the subject of ends, that is, the rational being itself, must
be made the basis of all maxims of actions” and from this “it follows incontestably
that every rational being, as an end in itself, must be able to regard himself as also
giving universal laws with respect to any law whatsoever to which he may be subject” (Ak. 4: 438). Hence the law is founded in what Kant terms autonomy but the
key point about this foundation is that we are each united with all other rational
beings in the capacity of such law-giving and that the possible communion with others
that it provides is what can be envisaged as the kingdom of ends which is analogous
5
J. David Velleman, “Love as A Moral Emotion,” Ethics 109, no. 2 (1999): 357–358.
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
178
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
ro
of
287
P
286
ed
285
ct
284
re
283
or
282
to the kingdom of nature (Ak. 4: 438). The analogy is founded on the way of thinking the law. Whilst with nature we deal with law in general in relation to sensuous
determination, with the moral law we have a “schema of the law itself” (Ak. 5: 69)
whereby the law of nature is made “the type of a law of freedom” (Ak. 5: 70).6
The use of this practical form of schematism is at work in the comparison of the
relationship between the division of the duties to others and the operation of physical forces. Just as the fundamental move between attraction and repulsion is determinative for physical phenomena so, it is suggested, the oscillation between the
attraction to others manifested in a practical orientation of love and a practical repulsion of respect is at work in the intelligible moral world. How does the contrast
work with the moral-practical (non-pathological) feelings and the maxims that are
founded on them? We have noted in our treatment of respect to date that the operation of it is in terms of self-limitation by reference to the recognition of the worth of
the other. If duties of respect are connected to this feeling of self-limitation the
maxim that accompanies such a feeling is described by Kant in accordance with the
feeling, that is, it is a maxim of self-limitation that is primarily at work in the duties
in question. This is the reason why Kant describes the duties of respect as negative
in character as in performing them we merely do what is owed to others in their
capacity as fellows in the kingdom of ends which is to give respect to their humanity. The key to such an approach is not to exalt oneself above others in a moral sense
and this indicates a moral egalitarianism. Others are not, insists Kant, put under
obligation to me when I carry out duties of respect to them as I am here safeguarding the moral world by treating persons as they should be treated, as ends that are
self-subsistent. These duties are described in broadly negative ways as it is acting in
ways that are opposed to respect that is covered by the duties of respect rather than
direct commands to act in ways that manifest respect in some positive sense (with
the examples given including arrogance, defamation and ridicule).
By contrast the duties of love are determined as duties that do put others under
obligation to me, and the cardinal example here, is the cultivation of the feeling of
benevolence that will produce actions in accordance with the maxim of beneficence.
The standard problem with placing value on benevolence however (which is typically the key virtue for utilitarians) is that it would appear to express an impersonal
wish for the good of others that is precisely at odds with loyalties to specific others
such as loved ones and friends. However Kant precisely denies this impersonal valuation of benevolence stating that it arises from thinking of benevolence in terms of
wishes rather than in terms of maxims. Whilst one may wish everyone well this is
not how action in accordance with ends can be structured. Rather: “in acting I can,
without violating the universality of my maxim, vary the degree greatly in accordance with the different objects of my love (one of whom concerns me more closely
than another)” (Ak. 6: 452).
nc
281
U
280
G. Banham
6
The most extensive use of this notion is in Religion within the Limits where the notion of a “schematism of analogy” is explicitly set forward, a notion which I argue elsewhere is determinative for
this work’s decisive stages of argument. See G. Banham, Kant’s Practical Philosophy: From
Critique to Doctrine (London/New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003), Chap. 5.
15
Kantian Friendship
179
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
The partiality that is at work in the maxim of benevolence is intrinsic to it since
there is a physical limitation on the actions that can be performed. However the
limitation is not only physical. If we return now to the example of friendship we do
so with the understanding that what Kant is picturing in this relation is an engagement between two moral equals who embrace each other as such and wish to be
engaged with as such. The problem that emerges within their relationship indicates
the basis of the partiality that is at work in pursuing it. The friend is one to whom
I reveal myself: this is the nature of the love I express in coming close to him. But
in revealing myself to my friend I also request the discretion of the friend in terms
of the way they subsequently treat my public image. Just as we noted that the duties
of respect concerned essentially the standing and reputation of others (arrogance,
defamation and ridicule) so the response of the friend to me is manifested most
clearly in how they care for my standing and reputation. If they repeat my disclosures of secret judgments and feelings as matter for further diffusion they open me to
the possible censure and contempt of others. Hence the relationship of candid
disclosure that Kant treats as being that of friendship is one in which the force of my
attraction to the other is expressed in my treating them as worthy of my confidence
and trust. This confidence and trust however is not only something that the friend is
under an obligation to respect: they are also mutually bound to me in an equivalence
of disclosure.
So the mutual respect that is envisaged by Kant in friendship is concentrated on
the relationship we have to the other of, as he puts it, “the ethical law of perfection”
(Ak. 6: 450). The scope of this perfectionism is one in which my love for the friend
is a love that is akin to that I must cultivate for my own rational nature. This parallel between the rational nature of myself and that of the other is the ground for the
apparent crossing of the duties to oneself and duties to others involved in friendship. Whilst my duty to myself is to make myself morally perfect, my fundamental
duty to others is to concern myself with their happiness inasmuch as they are worthy
of happiness. But to form a bond of friendship is to engage with the other in a way
that requires attention to their moral standing in a sense that is equivalent to the
interest I have in my own. This, and not merely the mutual bond of respect, is the
ground of Kant’s picture of friendship. Were the bond merely one of respect then
the disclosure of secret judgments and feelings would be bound by a self-limitation
in each of the friend’s case that would apply primarily to their own self-expression.
However the relation with the friend is more intimate than this as friendship in
Kant’s moral sense includes duties of love such as the benevolent duty to make
clear to the other their failings (Ak. 6: 470). This element of the love for the other
is the other delicate element of friendship. Such critical response to the friend is a
permission embodied in the friendship but is one that has to be approached as
selectively permitted and as always carefully limited by the respect for the other
that the friendship also has to manifest.
The treatment of friendship hence is indeed integrally linked to the division of
duties to others between duties of respect and duties of love. The division of duties
to others is based primarily on the type of attitude our action is manifesting towards
the other and how this attitude constitutes a kind of relation to them. In the case of
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
180
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
ro
of
372
P
371
ed
370
ct
369
re
368
or
367
nc
366
duties of respect we are offering only that which is due.7 With duties of love we are
offering rather more than this and it is precisely because we are that there is partiality at work in the exercise of duties of love. Without such partiality the attitude
expressed towards others of practical love would not be able to be made manifest
but this limitation is not merely physical but also moral as without limitation of
practical love the delicacy required in specific relations would be necessary in all
and this would provoke constant moral dangers. The reference to physical forces in
the picture of friendship is a specification of the general procedure of Kant’s “schema
of the law itself” and helps to make clearer the kinds of maxim at work in friendship. The maxim is the manner in which the attitude expressed by the feeling has to
made operative. Finally, the mitigation of the contrast between the two types of duty
to others that is offered by the reference to them having been artificially isolated
when in fact they are part of one duty is clarified by the location of them both as
ways of recognising autonomy. Kantian friendship is hence a picture of the kingdom of ends in relations of partiality that, in their very partiality, render more visible
the publicity required for moral relations to thrive.8
U
365
G. Banham
When Kant states that one’s neighbour may be little worthy of respect he is, as suggested above,
indicating a more specific sense of respect than is at work in the formal treatment of duties of
respect. It would be the work of another piece to see the extent to which the recognition of this
additional determination of respect relates to Kant’s standard sense but the suggestion that someone can be seen as not meriting respect is evidently connected to the attitudes they express to
ourselves and others in such actions as arrogance.
8
For a more political treatment of some of these themes that involves a discussion of the value
placed on publicity in Kant’s treatment of right see G. Banham, “Publicity and Provisional Right,”
Politics and Ethics Review 3, no. 1 (2007): 73–89.
7
Author Query
Chapter No.: 15
0001327773
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please provide department name in the affiliation for the author
“Gary Banham.”
U
nc
or
re
ct
ed
P
ro
of
Query
Chapter 16
1
Just Friends: The Ethics of (Postmodern)
Relationships
2
3
Hugh J. Silverman
4
5
‘O my friends, there is no friend.’
If there is ‘no friend’, then how could I call you my friends,
my friends?
By what right/law?
6
7
8
9
…for my friend Tony O’Connor…*
ǼJacques Derrida, Politics of Friendship1
“Is it true that the common ground includes me and not you?”
11
—Lou Reed, New York, 1989 (CD Album, Sire/London/Rhino)
2
Just Friends… Is it possible to be just friends? To be friends requires a certain
understanding of friendship and that one stands on common ground. How can two
people decide to be just friends or the one to ask of the other to be “just friends” if
there is no notion of friendship in the first place? In this essay I discuss how friendship need not be some transcendental concept, some condition for the possibility of
knowledge about friends. I do this by asking what it means to be just friends; to be
*
With deepest respect and friendship, I dedicate this essay to Tony O’Conner whom I first met at
a Workshop on Continental Philosophy, organized by David Wood, at the University of Warwick
(UK) in 1978, and who later spent his sabbatical semester in residence at Stony Brook University
in 1980. Tony has heard two earlier versions for this essay, once at the International Philosophical
Seminar, held in the South Tyrol (Italy), and the second time as an invited lecture for the Philosophy
Department at the University of Cork (Ireland).
1
Jacques Derrida, Politique de l’amitié (Paris: Galilée, 1994), 17. The Politics of Friendship, trans.
George Collins (London/New York: Verso, 1997), 1. Henceforth cited as PF for the English
translation.
2
Lou Reed, “Good Evening Mr Waldheim,” in New York (CD Album, Sire:London/Rhino, 1989).
[AU1]
H.J. Silverman (*)
International Association for Philosophy and Literature, Freiburg, Germany
e-mail: hsilverman@ms.cc.sunysb.edu
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_16, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
10
181
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
182
H.J. Silverman
29
only friends, and to be friends whose relationship is a just one. For friendship is a
responsibility that cannot be denied or affirmed. It is quite simply just there entre
nous (“between us”) – a matter of justice.
Friendships happen because of relationships, and relationships are constituted by
persons who effect friendships – nothing more and nothing less. Friendship arises
because of a relationship and relationships are always already in contexts. The social
and political context is the place in which friendships happen. And just friendships
mark out the spaces in which to be only friends is the only way to be friends; friends
in which the differences between persons in friendship are matters of justice. These
differences, like justice itself, are indeconstructible. They happen. They cannot not
be true, and they cannot not be just – just friendships…
30
16.1
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
Justice Without Friendship
Can there be justice without friendship? And what justice, or virtue is there in being
just friends?
In Plato’s Republic, the topic at hand is Justice (dikaiosyne). To be concerned
with justice is to be around (peri) justice (dikaiosyne). But around justice, there is
injustice, the absence of justice. To be “in” justice is not to be “around” justice but
rather in the place where justice is located. For Plato, in Socrates’ account, the ideal
state will be a just state, not just a state, but an ideal, just state. Justice, according to
the account, is the performance of one’s natural function. And if everyone in the
ideal, just state, performs her natural function, then the whole state will be just and
everyone in it will be just. But if everyone in the ideal state is just then would there
be any virtue in being just friends in the just state?
The irony of Plato’s account is that in the first book, the second account offered
(following the one offered by the host Cephalus) – is that of his son Polymarchus.
Polymarchus claims that “justice is paying back one’s friends and harming one’s
enemies.” This version is in response to Socrates’ criticism of his first account in
which he claims that justice is “giving each person his due.”
The problem with this account is that receiving one’s due is not available to
everyone in a society and hence injustice would prevail. After all, paying back one’s
friends and harming one’s enemies” is a straight-forward reward/punishment system,
(not unlike behaviourist models as in B.F. Skinner’s Walden Two.)
What does it mean to “help one’s friends and harm one’s enemies?” Does one
always know who one’s friends are? Such a system of exchange (or potlatch, as
Lévi-Strauss would describe it) presumes knowledge of who are one’s friends and
who are one’s enemies. Otherwise the reward/punish model would quickly go awry.
If I know who my friends are, I can exclude my enemies. But such a model assumes
a subject whose authority can bring advantage to those who belong to the circle of
friends. If granting benefits to my friends has value, it is to me that the value accrues
– my friends are supported, my enemies not.
19
[AU2]
16
Just Friends: The Ethics of (Postmodern) Relationships
183
Helping friends, then, is not just—like being a “good Samaritan.”Seeking
advantage—“justice” as defined here—promotes a condition of including some and
excluding others. It presumes that there are already friends and enemies and I just
need to decide which are which. Then I will know who to help and who to harm.
Polymarchus’ revised view is one that presumes a friendship model, and correspondingly an account of friendship in which justice will be meted out to help my
friends and execute harm to my enemies. Perhaps, then, justice is the meting out
itself, the division and separation between two categories of help and harm–both of
which are related to, or constituted by, a single subject, and both establish their
identity by their corresponding affirmation of that single subject.
Socrates shows that such a model is hardly adequate. How can justice depend
upon this kind of discriminatory inclusion or exclusion? Would there be any common ground in claiming that some are friends and the others are enemies? Could
Lou Reed’s ironic song (to the Austrian Kurt Waldheim) be true: that the common
ground includes me and not you? Would not such a model of justice produce bias,
bigotry, indeed injustice?
But then Socrates goes on to give his own account of justice—justice that constitutes the ideal state. Such justice—along with wisdom, even courage and moderation—will establish harmony, unity, cooperation, the full and complete distribution
of functions, duties, goods, benefits, advantages, and values. Doing one’s own thing
takes place within the broader social context. Relationships will be established
according to function and social value. There would be no place for, no need for, no
justifications for—friendships or the absence thereof. Friendships would simply not
play a role in the Platonic ideal state. They would be irrelevant since knowledge of
the good, knowledge of justice would be distributed in practice to all members of
the state, no one would be denied, no one would be favoured, no one would need to
be a friend or foe of anyone. And if they were, it would be irrelevant to the smooth
determination of the just state. Functions rather than relationships would be determinative. Polymarchus’ account—whereby one could help one’s friends and harm
one’s enemies—would be entirely irrelevant.
Citing Derrida, citing Montaigne, citing Aristotle: “o my friends, there are no
friends.” What this could mean, quite simply, is that in Plato’s just polis it would
make no difference whether two or more people are good friends, bad friends, even
just friends, since friends would be irrelevant. So it should be quite a simple act of
affirmation, for someone in Plato’s ideal state, to address someone else in the ideal
state since friends and friendships are irrelevant anyway. The ideal state will be just,
but friendship will have no function at all.
If one reads Derrida’s account of Montaigne’s repetition of Aristotle, the
Platonic view would be open for challenge. After all, Aristotle is very much concerned with both friendship and justice. He thinks that both are needed together.
Derrida writes:
There are, then, three kinds of friendship, respectively founded, as we recall, on (1) virtue
(this is primary friendship); usefulness (for example, political friendship); and (3) pleasure.
Now each species divides up into two: according to equality or according to difference
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
184
(Aristotle says: according to superiority). In this move, justice too will divide into two,
following numerical or proportional equality. Communities will organize this sharing out
sometimes in terms of equality, sometimes in terms of the other.3
103
104
105
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
If friendship (the first type) is a virtue—and we know that for Aristotle, there are
many more virtues than were ever dreamed of in Plato’s philosophy, then friendship
would become a value for its own sake. Such friendship would simply be there as
part of the political arena. All good relationships would be based on friendship—but
would some be excluded and others included? The second type—based on utility
would have a clear function; to realize something like what Polymarchus was suggesting, namely to use one’s friendships for personal or political gain. Maintaining
the right friendships will bring the right (political and personal) advantages. But the
third would be something other than eudaimonia—the happiness achieved by those
in a just state (such as Plato’s) or the happiness achieved if one does what a virtuous
person would do (as in Aristotle’s view). The third has to do with pleasure—the
pleasure of being just, of enjoying the relationship, but once again, where the pleasure belongs to one person or another.
But Derrida notes, following Aristotle, that there is a division between the three
types of friendship. On the one hand, there is “equality,” and on the other hand, there
is “difference.” Equality among friends—not a bad idea when both or all are just
friends. But although Aristotle argues for equality in friendship, this account does
not, it seems, include relations with and among women, slaves, and non-citizens
(barbarians). So the common ground for friendship in Aristotle includes and
excludes—those excluded are not part of the equality. They come under another
model—a model of ruler/ruled, husband/wife, master/slave, parent/child—all hierarchical and hardly equal. In these cases, the possibility pf is not even available, not
a chance. So the only opportunity for being friends is in the case of male citizens of
the polis. Male citizens, however, can be friends only if they are equal, i.e. only if
each citizen has an equality with the others. But is this model, as with Plato, an ideal
condition? Presumably not as such since friends are equal only if there is also justice, and equality is one of the versions of justice. Justice for Aristotle can also be
distributive and corrective. The distribution of goods is quite other than equality, for
goods can be distributed unequally and still be just. Justice as correction is designed
to make both sides equal again—if one person suffers a loss, the other must pay.
Aristotle’s hope is that it will not be an endless generational retribution as in the
House of Atreus (and the plight of Orestes). Even Aeschylus saw a way to bring an
end to the repeated correction of one crime for another. In the Oresteia, he offered a
trial in which 12 jurors would judge whether Orestes could be set free or whether he
must pay for the murder of his mother Clytemnestra and her lover Aegisthus who
had murdered his father and his “war prize” (Cassandra, daughter of the Trojan king
Priam) in retaliation for his father’s murder of his brother’s children, and so on. The
trial would bring justice to Argos. But none of the participants were friends at all.
They were each performing their functions, carrying out their respective duties,
106
H.J. Silverman
3
Derrida, The Politics of Friendship, p. 203.
16
Just Friends: The Ethics of (Postmodern) Relationships
185
following the codes. They were not even just friends. While in Aristotle, there is
indeed a chance that if there is already equality, there could be friendship.
As Derrida points out, the other condition of friendship—of each of the
Aristotelian types—would occur because of difference. But difference here means
“superiority,” that is, the advantage of one over the other because of position,
authority, or some other condition that distinguishes the one from the other.
Similarly justice divides into (1) numerical equality and (2) legal proportionality.
1. numerical equality means that everyone of one sort will be able to be counted as
equals;
2. legal proportionality means distributing the advantages across those who legally
have access to the goods that are available.
But how do these two formulations relate to one another, that is, what is the connection between friendship and justice? If both appeal to equality, then it should be
possible to have friends who are just. But the problem is that equality does not imply
friendship and friendship does not necessarily imply equality. If justice includes
numerical equality, then it should be possible to count up the gains on each side. The
Hebrew lex talionis calls for numerical equality–an eye for an eye. Justice based on
numerical equality requires “restitution”4 in the amount of the loss. Similarly legal
proportionality means that if your house is adjacent to the beach and your neighbour’s house is adjacent to the beach, then both should have proportional access.
But can such a corrective rectification of an imbalance apply to friends as well?
Indeed, how do I “measure” your friendship? Do I count it by how often you
greet me, how late you arrive at my conference paper, or how early you leave, how
willing you are to talk philosophy with me, how good your paper is, etc.? If I stay
for the full conference, can I expect that you will too? Could I assume that you will
devote a proportional amount of energy into the discussion and debate? Clearly
friendship cannot be measured in these kinds of terms. The saying goes: “How
much do you love me? Let me count the ways.” This was King Lear’s mistake: he
judged his daughters’ love by how much they professed their love. What about
Derrida’s friendship with Paul de Man? Must Derrida pay a corresponding price for
each political errancy in de Man’s youth? I think not…
If one applies the Aristotelian model of equality as numerical correction or
legal proportionality, then justice will be of a very different order than friendship. Friendship will not be able to be counted in this way—even if it might be
counted on.
Friendship remains, then, entirely other than justice in the Aristotelian model.
Friendship may be a virtue unto itself and therefore not in any way measurable. If
so, can it have anything to do with justice, which is no longer, as in Plato, a virtue,
but rather an operation of equality and proportion? If friendship is based on utility,
then a calculus may apply, but such friendship is indeed a calculated friendship and
See Jacques Derrida, “Restitutions of the Truth in Shoe Size,” in The Truth in Painting, trans.
Geoffrey Bennington and Ian McLeod (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1987).
4
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
186
H.J. Silverman
189
of dubious status. Friendship according to pleasure, the pleasure it brings to be in
friendship with another person surely has nothing to do with the measurement and
amount of the friendship. Such pleasures—of dialogue, of companionship, of comraderie, of spending time together—are doubtless of another order than the equity
of justice.
190
16.2
186
187
188
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
Friendship Without Justice
Although there may still have been a “perhaps” inscribed between Aristotelian
friendship and Aristotelian justice, let us consider now friendship where justice
plays no role at all. Shakespeare’s Othello depended upon his friend and advisor
Iago in whom he puts unswerving trust. But Iago was unjust, devious and un-loyal.
Iago placed the doubt–not just a “perhaps” but a gnawing conviction–that Desdemona
had been unfaithful. Tortured by his doubts, Othello, anguished by his suspicions,
contorted by the trust he placed in his friend Iago, snuffed out his wife’s life with a
pillow while she slept. “O my friends, there are no friends” – for if one’s friends are
like Iago, how can one trust anyone.
Montaigne’s presumed citation of Aristotle: “O my friends, there are no friends”
could have been exclaimed by Othello years later as advice to others – his associates
whom he calls “friends”—how foul a deed Iago exerted upon him by introducing
more and more distrust into his fragile psychology. The exclamation would be one of
despair that one’s friends cannot be trusted—that there are “no friends” whom one
can trust, that effectively there are no friends any more. And Shakespeare is replete
with such instances. Julius Caesar should never have trusted Cassius and Brutus.
“Et tu Brute” was his final cry of despair as his friend Brutus and Cassius stabbed
him repeatedly. King Lear trusted his two deceitful daughters and did not believe in
his only loving daughter Cordelia. Furthermore, Mark Antony (in Shakespeare’s
Antony and Cleopatra) when calling upon his countrymen to hear his public appeal
begins with “Friends, Romans, Countrymen, lend me your ears…” to persuade them
with his rhetoric, not with the truth or with anything genuine or just.
In retrospect, Othello would hardly have considered the advice he received from
Iago to be just; Julius Caesar would hardly want his “friends” to constitute the basis
for justice in the Roman Empire; and Lear would hardly consider his two daughters’
deceit to be just. These kinds of friendships would not have anything to do with
being just.
No wonder Montaigne’s remembrances of his departed friend La Boétie was not
based on justice but a very deep, personal relationship—one that stood outside the
frame of justice. Montaigne’s loss was profound and sincere. His dead friend left a
profound impact, but not on any claim to a just state. Rather the relationship was
genuine and devoted—Montaigne’s essay “Of Friendship” was an attempt to remember his friend, to give him the status he was due, but not in any way to appeal to
justice. “O my friends, there are no friends” for friends come and go, one cannot
count on their eternity, one cannot count on their continued presence, one cannot
185
16
Just Friends: The Ethics of (Postmodern) Relationships
187
count on their undying fraternity. At best, one can realize that “to philosophize is to
learn to die”—a lesson Montaigne offers from his reading of Seneca and the stoics.
Read in another way, La Boetie would have been a “true” friend. Derrida writes:
“Favorinus in the second book of his Memorabilia mentions as one of his habitual
sayings that ‘He who has friends can have no (true) friend.’”5 If one has lots of
friends, and hence the question of the number of friends one can/should have, could
any one of them be a “true” friend. One can have many official friends, but few if
any “true” friends. So the uniqueness and singularity of the “true” friend is indeed
memorable and remarkable. But such a true friend can be quite personal and need
not depend on any particular social formation.
16.3
16.3.1
The Justice of Friendships
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
Modern Friends – With Justice and Liberty
for All (vielleicht/peut-être/maybe)
The Enlightenment, and even the French Revolution, bring justice and friendship
into concert; but in a markedly modern fashion. Friends will be friends because they
can reason together, and if they can reason together, they can even constitute a just
state—one designed according to a contract in which friendship will not only be
welcomed but encouraged. Once a sensus communis is established, a sensus fraternitatis is also constituted No longer must friendship be understood as an individual,
personal, irrelevant pleasure, need, or utility. Friendship can become the backbone
of the social contract.
“O my friends, there are no friends” need not be simply an apostrophe, an expression of exasperation and joy at the same time – as when Rimbaud writes: “O saisons,
ô chateaux, quel âme est sans defaut?” O my friends, can be more than a “vocative”
form. It can also be a dative form (as Derrida points out). “O my friends” can be a
decisive address to (dative) specific people, not many please, but perhaps more than
one might think. “O my friends”—imagining an address to members of a contractarian state—“there are no friends” would mean that there are none outside of the social
contract. After all, Rousseau described, in the Second Discourse On the Origins of
Inequality among Mankind, how some “noble savage”—one without friends or interlocutors—would have to submit someday to a society which seeks to overcome social
corruption by forming together (as impersonal friends and comrades) and constituting
a viable society according to the general will. “O my friends, there are no (particular)
friends”—just friends in a contractarian enlightenment democratic society.
If in a contractarian enlightenment democratic society, there are no particular
friends, the question remains as ti whether there are any “true” (veritable) friends as
5
226
Derrida, The Politics of Friendship, p. 207; parentheses added.
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
188
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
was, presumably, La Boétie for Montaigne—a dead friend who is remembered
fondly. Enlightenment friends are supported by a social organization that makes
friendship possible. Without the democratic practice, there would be no friendship
possible. “O my friends, there are no friends.” Once the enlightenment society based
on rationality—Hobbesian, Lockean, Humean, and particularly Kantian—takes
hold, attachments and relationships will take a very different shape. Charles Fourier,
for instance, could argue for a utopian society in which personal affections will be
organized into phalanges—where people of different character and characteristics
are organised according to those criteria. If they are to be friends, their friendships
will have to be based on compatibility—not identity or similarity. So if such a utopian society could be just, then the passionate attractions could also be called friendships. But here, oddly, none would be excluded. There would be no strangers in a
society based on passionate attraction.
This search for a just society, one in which friendships could also be possible,
produced the French Revolution when aristocracy and hierarchy came under the
guillotine. Equality, Liberty, Fraternity would be the motto–printed on each and
every coin–until erased by the Euro. Fraternity—male bonding at the social level—
should make friendships possible, and the link with equality and liberty would be
definitive. To be in friendship—as fraternity (and Derrida devotes considerable
attention to this development)—would no longer be separated from equality (equal
rights in any case) and liberty (the freedom from dominance and subjugation).
Friendships could arise freely, equally, and in fraternal concert. The declaration of
equality, liberty, and fraternity is not the same as its achievement. Declaration is not
an address. “There shall be equality, liberty, fraternity” does not mean that all persons can actualize relations on such grounds. The declaration of independence
forms a right and law according to which it should be possible for all sorts of friendships to arise—freely. But these rights establish the conditions for the possibility of
friendships. They do not mean that there are in fact any. For there to be such friendships, one needs to address another as a friend and to enact the relation to (and with
the other as) a friend. That this may be possible is only the first step.
Once possible, the romantic appeal to individuality, personal affect, proximity to
nature, the one-on-one relation of friendship can thrive. But the romantic appeal to
friendship is only possible once the French Revolution has taken place, once the
Declaration of Independence has been affirmed. “Elective Affinities” are relationships of love and friendship (philia, amour/amitié), but they require a context in
which the justice of those relationships–affirmed and confirmed by law (droit)—can
be realized. By what right (droit) can we have relationships? What affirms these
relationships, what prohibits or limits them? This is Derrida’s question to the postrevolutionary and romantic Weltanschauung.
The justice of modern friendships will depend upon a political law/right (droit)
which authorizes the personal and the interpersonal. But this same kind of authorization can produce dystopian models as well. Zamiatin’s We, Huxley’s Brave New
World, Orwell’s 1984 – all worlds in which affinities are authorized and limited by
law, by social formation, by a determinate conception of the political. They produce
equality, but exclude and delimit possible relationships by circumscribing certain
262
H.J. Silverman
16
Just Friends: The Ethics of (Postmodern) Relationships
189
freedoms and interactions: O my friends, there can be no friends in a society like
this. O my friends, there can be no friends in a society without justice. O my friends,
there can be no friends until justice and friendship happen in the same place…
maybe (peut-être, veilleicht).
16.3.2
The Justice of Postmodern Friendships
“Is it true that the common ground includes me and not you?” Lou Reed, “Good
Evening Mr Waldheim” New York (1989). The irony of the question suggests that
the common ground is illusory, a phantom of a modern theory of tolerance in which
there is no common ground other than the one constituted from one position or the
other. I choose to tolerate you—as long as I can tolerate you. You can hardly be my
friend if I have to tolerate you. I can hardly be your friend if you have to tolerate me.
Yes, you may come as a stranger and leave as a friend6—you may be drawn into a
world of eros, proximity, affinity, but this does not mean that we are friends for more
than an hour or two. But this is not friendship. It is not a common ground. It is utility,
or pleasure, bought and sold out of utility.
Utility will hardly make a relationship of friendship what it should be. The
romantic achievement would be lost, the revolutionary gains would have failed, the
liberties that overcome exclusion would be erased. And tolerance is a model of
inclusion by way of exclusion. Tolerance retains alterity, strangeness, and hierarchy.
I cannot be a friend of someone whom I have to tolerate. O my friends, there are no
friends if I have to tolerate you.
Tolerance can be legitimated by law. Equality can be the basis for tolerating
someone (else). If we are equal by law, then I am obligated to tolerate you. If I don’t
tolerate you, then I can be held accountable (by law). But tolerance can hardly be
the basis for a friendship–even if friendship requires some form of equal status. Can
a governor be friends with a garbage collector or a teacher with a student? Or if the
unequal status is of one order, the demand for equality would have to be on another
level–common interests, common concerns, common love. Common-al-ity (community) can overcome differences of status. But commonality does not belong to
one or the other in the friendship relation. Commonality belongs to the community
in which the friendship arises. But Derrida cites Bataille when speaking of a “community in which there is no community”7—a condition of what Blanchot calls the
“inavowable community” and Jean-Luc Nancy calls “an inoperative community”
(une communauté desoeuvrée).
These are each “communities” that do not function as communities, as something held in common. In these “communities,” the common ground is effaced in
“Du kommst als Fremder und gehst als Freund.” (Bilibi Bar, Seegasse, 1090 Wien) This place of
“encounter” no longer exists. But the sign outside stating “You come as a stranger, and you leave
as a friend,” suggests the “erotic friendship” indicated here.
7
Derrida, The Politics of Friendship, p. 48, note 15.
6
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
190
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
favor of a community in which there is no community; a network of relationships
and friendships in which there is nothing in common.
But what is a friendship in which there is nothing in common? It is a fabric of
differences. We are friends because we are different. If there were no differences,
there could not be any friendship. But these differences do not arise as an articulation
of myself in relation to another, nor from another back to myself in order to affirm
the other. These differences arise between us. O my friends, there are no friends (who
constitute themselves as friends). I can address my friends, I can call out “aux amis!”
but I do not constitute the other as a friend when I do so. The reciprocity of friendship
requires that I receive the other and they receive me. But this does not make for
friendship since friendship happens between us, between friends and is not shared
with any one else. To be shared (partager, as we learn from Nancy) means to be both
brought together and separated. What is between friends is the friendship that does
not belong to either of us. We share a friendship and yet the friendship is not anything
other than the relation we have between us, namely, the differences between us. And
yet, we live the differences and sometimes they constitute friendship.
Brecht’s Threepenny Opera is a modern (capitalist, bourgeois) community in
which there are no friends. All relations, Mack the Knife (Mack Heath, leader of the
thieves, bank robbers, gangsters), Peacham (leader of the beggars who dress up in
order to lure good Samaritans into giving them money), the women of the brothel,
the police captain and his corrupt daughter Polly (who seems to have fallen in love
with Mack Heath), indeed all the characters in the play are engaged in relations of
utility. Maybe there is a love relation–but it is one-sided–Mack Heath is just as
happy with his whores as he is accepting Polly’s somewhat exaggerated love for
him. So even that relation is one of utility. All the figures are engaged in acts of
injustice; all relationships are unfriendly–in any sense of virtue. The pleasures are
passing and just for momentary pleasure and gain. These modern relations are based
on injustice, deceit, conflict. The absence of the enlightenment ideals is precisely
what keeps the relations alive. They are all transgressive, disingenuous and conflictual. Each person is essentially solitary, isolated, and narcissistic. In this sense, they
are all equal, but this does not make them friends; or just–not even just friends. As
modern relations–one subject constitutes the other, one position or identity seeks
the advantage of the other, one self takes the other as an object. And yet, read in a
postmodern way, there are differences. Reading the relations as relations of difference reconstructs the set of relations in the play–opens the possibility (perhaps) of
thinking relations otherwise, of thinking the relations postmodernly.
In Jim Jarmusch’s film Ghost Dog, the question of the justice of friendship is
engaged in a different way. Ghost Dog (played by Forrest Whitaker), as he is called,
owes his life to the one who saved him from being beaten and possibly shot. Ghost
Dog follows the “Code of the Samurai.” He is a “hit man.” He carries out his function with skill, precision, and expertise. Ghost Dog lives alone—on the rooftop of a
New York apartment house. No one knows who he is—he is a ghost, even to those
who call upon his services. He has no personal acquaintances, no collaborators, no
friends. He carries out his function independently. He steals cars, listens to his
music, carries out the executions.
343
H.J. Silverman
16
Just Friends: The Ethics of (Postmodern) Relationships
191
And yet he remains invisible. But one job goes wrong, the daughter of one of the
bosses, who is having an affair with another gang member, is present when one of
the executions takes place. She is herself like a ghost, but she comes back to haunt
him in the end. His execution is then called for. According to the Mafia code, he
knows that he must go down—and (according to the Code of the Samurai) at the
hand of the “master” who saved his life.
Ghost Dog has no friends—except for the Haitian Ice Cream Man at the edge of
the park and the little girl who befriends him as well. But the Ice Cream man speaks
only French—Creole—and yet they understand each other across the different languages. Just as Derrida is concerned (in Force of Law)8 that he must address the
lawyers at Cardoza Law School in their language (English), the question of address
becomes crucial in Ghost Dog’s relations with the Ice Cream Man. The one speaks
French, the other English—and yet they understand each other perfectly. Something
happens in the friendship relation, based on difference, and yet out of that difference
communication. Ghost Dog knows that he must die. He leaves his possessions with
the Ice Cream Man and then allows himself to be shot down by the man to whom he
owes his life. For all they had in common was the compact—one in which Ghost
Dog followed the Code of the Samurai and the other followed the Code of the
Mafia. These two codes intersected for a time—in part by virtue of utility, in part by
an order other than that of the one or the other—the double codes. The juxtaposition
of codes is the marking off of differences—differences that intersect but that do not
require tolerance, that do not require utility, that do not even require pleasure.
And what of the little girl in the park? Ghost Dog befriends her. Other than the Ice
Cream Man, she is the only one who comes to like him, to be his friend. Is this an
equal relation? Surely not. She is a little girl; he a hired killer. But she reads his book–
the code of the Samurai–and she has a way to understand him. Out of this relation of
understanding–she for him, him for her– the friendship happens in between. And
there is much that they keep between friends (entre eux). Between friends–that is the
justice of relation–not anything either can take away with them . Justice gives them
the relation and the relation gives its own justice. Ghost Dog and the little girl are just
friends–friends whose relation is such that neither can take anything away with him
or herself. All that remains is the justice of their relation–the giusto, the exactitude,
the precision, the justness of their relationship of difference.
Derrida writes:
When will we be ready for an experience of freedom and equality that is capable of respectfully experiencing that friendship, which would at last be just, just beyond the law, and
measured up against its measurelessness?9
The relation of Ghost Dog to the little girl, as with his relation with the Haitian
Ice Cream Man, are just that, relations of friendship that are slightly beyond the
Jacques Derrida, “Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority,’” in Deconstruction
and the Possibility of Justice, ed. Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson
(London: Routledge, 1992).
9
Ibid., p. 306.
8
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
192
H.J. Silverman
430
law–beyond the law in that they cannot be measured in their measurelessness. The
friendships happen in between persons–not from one or the other. The differences
are measured in their measurelessness. Their justness is the between. Derrida writes
further:
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
Justice in itself, if such a thing exists, outside or beyond law, is not deconstructible. No
more than deconstruction itself, if such a thing exists. Deconstruction is justice. It is perhaps because law (droit) (which I will consistently try to distinguish from justice) is constructible, in a sense that goes beyond the opposition between convention and nature, it is
perhaps insofar as it goes beyond this opposition that it is constructible and so deconstructible and, what’s more, construction that, fundamentally, always proceeds to questions
of droit and to the subject of droit.10
427
428
429
445
The law of the relation between Ghost Dog and the little girl is established by
reading, meeting in the park, sharing the codes. But the justice of their relation
cannot be anything other than the between of that relation. What do they have
between them? Understanding, truth, differences. But none of these are anything
more than the un(in)deconstructible differences between them–the justice of the
friendship relation.
Hence, according to Derrida–already in an autobiographical mode (thinking of
his relation to Paul de Man)11:
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
…the friendship of a justice that transcends right [le droit], the law [la loi] of friendship
above laws – is this acceptable? Acceptable in the name of what, precisely? In the name of
politics? Ethics? Law? Or in the name of a sacred friendship which would no longer answer
to any other agency than itself? The gravity of these questions finds its examples – endless
ones – every time a faithful friend wonders whether he or she should judge, condemn, forgive what he decides is a political fault of his or her friend: a political moment of madness,
error, breakdown, crime, whatever their context, consequence, or duration.12
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
Is the little girl responsible for the assassinations that Ghost Dog carried out?
Surely not. And yet, they can be friends. They can have something–that is nothing–between them. Derrida is not responsible for the acts and writings that Paul
de Man put into print in his youth,. Derrida is not responsible for Martin
Heidegger’s outrageous political attitudes. But if responsibility does not depend
on one or the other, if responsibility happens between them, then they will be
responsible for what happens between them (entre eux), and not for what happens
before they ever met.
The responsibility of friendship is not something that belongs to one friend or the
other. “O my friends, there are no friends” who are not responsible for what happens between them. They may be just friends, but the justice of their friendship
means that the differences between them mark (precisely and only–juste) what
Derrida, “Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority,’” p. 14f.
See Jacques Derrida, Memoires for Paul de Man, 2nd ed., trans. Cecile Lindsay, Jonathan Culler,
Eduardo Cadava, and Peggy Kamuf (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986).
12
Derrida, The Politics of Friendship, p. 183.
10
11
16
Just Friends: The Ethics of (Postmodern) Relationships
193
happens between them. What they have in common is what they are both responsible
for. And that responsibility cannot be denied nor affirmed. It is quite simply and
justly just there. It is a matter of justice. Any further clarification is the “democracy
à venir, to come”—the community of democratic persons who have nothing in
common. “O my (democratic) friends,” Derrida writes. And yet he addresses none
of them–only the fabric of (postmodern) differences between them… these just
friends…of the here and now in the name of a democracy (of the future) ‘à venir’
(to come).“Is it true there is no common ground between me and you?” But perhaps
there is friendship entre nous, between us…
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
Author Queries
Chapter No.: 16
0001327774
Details Required
Author’s Response
AU1
Please check affiliation for the author “Hugh J. Silverman” for
correctness.
AU2
Please provide the opening quote in the sentence starting
“After all, paying {”
Queries
Chapter 17
1
The Art of Friendship
2
William S. Hamrick
3
It is an honor to take part in this celebration of Tony O’Connor’s career and
philosophical accomplishments, which I have observed at first hand across many
years together in the British Society for Phenomenology. I wish to do this here by
analyzing his delightful and challenging essay, “O Friend, Where Art Thou?: Derridean
Deconstruction and Friendship.”1 In Part I, I will show how the essay reflects critically
on Jacques Derrida’s book, Politics of Friendship,2 the first chapter of which begins
with the strange and provocative quotation from Montaigne of a remark attributed
to Aristotle, “O my friends, there is no friend” (PF 1). I will also offer some criticisms of the analysis of Aristotle. Then, in the second part of the essay, I will take up
Tony O’Connor’s invitation to “a more empirical approach” (TOC 49) to supplement Derrida’s deconstructive remarks about definitions of friendship.
I
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
The salient points of Derrida’s text, as O’Connor succinctly and clearly explicates
them, are as follows. He begins with the claim of Derrida’s earlier work,
Of Grammatology,3 that “texts, or text analogues, do not have fixed essences”
(TOC 39)—a claim reflected in Jean-Paul Sartre’s contention in What is Literature?
The essay appears in Patrick Crowley and Paul Hegarty, eds. Formless: Ways In and Out of Form
(Oxford, Bern, et al.: Peter Lang, 2005), 39–51 (hereafter referred to as “TOC).”
2
Jacques Derrida, Politics of Friendship (New York/London: Verso, 1997) (hereafter referred to
as “PF”).
3
Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, trans. G. Spivak (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University
Press, 1976).
1
W.S. Hamrick (*)
Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, IL, USA
e-mail: whamrick@sbcglobal.net
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7_17, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
4
195
16
17
18
19
196
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
that “the literary work is an open-ended construction by both author and reader” and
Roland Barthes’ arguments for “intertextuality” in S/Z (Ibid.).4 By extension, for
Derrida, friendship has no fixed essence. More specifically, he is concerned to
undermine “canonical,” “logocentric,” universal definitions of friendship by displaying their “limitations, untested presuppositions and paradoxes” as well as “to
use paradox and the limited character of evidence to indicate something positive,
but not absolutely essential, about friendship” (TOC 41).
As regards the deconstructive critique, Derrida’s Politics of Friendship offers us
a series of analyses of major accounts of friendship from ancient to modern times,
all of which, on his view, rest on paradox, question-begging, and display substantial
lack of supporting evidence. It is especially with regard to the latter that the analogy
with textual indetermination takes shape, for Derrida holds that traditional (“canonical”) definitions of friendship are never supported by complete, objective evidence.
The reason is that they make up “part of a series of interpretive networks through
which friendship is both described and constituted” (TOC 43).
This can be seen clearly, for Derrida, in Cicero’s distinction between friendships among “ordinary folk, or of ordinary people (de vulgari aut de mediocri)”
and “true and perfect friendship (de vera et perfecta)” (PF 3). On Cicero’s view,
these “great and rare friendships…. take on the value of exemplary heritage;” they
resonate with “light, brilliance and glory” (Ibid.). However, for Derrida, there is no
“independent justification” for this “valorization of friendship as exemplary”
because it underestimates the significance of the context and the “underdetermination of evidence, in the constitution of values and theories” (TOC 43). When these
factors are taken into account, we can see, for Derrida, that Cicero’s “true and perfect friendship” is a “narcissistic projection of the ideal image,” the image of oneself” (PF 4), in the friend. This projected exemplar is the “ideal double … the same
as self but improved” (PF 4).
The ecstatic future hope offered to the friend as one’s exemplar, in the sense of
what can be copied, is the future, immortal preservation of the image in the friend.
Long before Maurice Merleau-Ponty described the reversibility of flesh and the
narcissism of all vision,5 Cicero’s view of the true friend was that, “since we watch
him looking at us, thus watching ourselves, because we see him keeping our image
in his eyes—in truth in ours—survival is then hoped for, illuminated in advanced, if
not assured, for this Narcissus who dreams of immortality” (PF 4). Yet, Cicero’s
concept of friendship rests on a distinction between the same and the other, and even
though concerned action for the sake of the other would reasonably be thought to be
a hallmark of friendship, Cicero privileges the same, the projection and attempted
realization of one’s own (improved) image (Ibid.).
20
W.S. Hamrick
Jean-Paul Sartre, What is Literature?, trans. B. Frechtman (London: Methuen, 1978) and Roland
Barthes, S/Z, trans. R. Miller (New York: The Noonday Press, 1974).
5
In Merleau-Ponty’s later ontology, body and world “form a couple, a couple more real than either
of them. Thus since the seer is caught up in what he sees it is still himself he sees: there is a fundamental narcissism of all vision.” The Visible and the Invisible, Followed by Working Notes, trans.
Alphonso Lingis (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970), 139.
4
17 The Art of Friendship
197
Derrida’s analysis of Cicero serves as an introduction to the much more
substantial analysis of Aristotle’s discussion of the “essential and unchanging
characteristics” of friendship that prepare the ground for the emergence of “the
Canonical View of Friendship” (TOC 44). The principal and well known themes
of Aristotle’s analysis make their appearance here: the three kinds of friendship
(the primary one rooted in virtue and its derivative versions based on utility and
pleasure), the recognition that the Greek conception of friendship (philia) is much
wider than what the English word designates (“civic friendship functions in a mode
of unanimity so as to ‘hold states together’” (Ibid.), and that friendship is both
founded in and the expression of self-love (“Being a good person, therefore,
primarily involves loving oneself, where noble actions are performed which will
be of benefit to others” (Ibid., 45).
As a result, for Derrida, Aristotle’s view of friendship, just as the later Ciceronian
version, rests on the distinction between the same and the other and privileges the
former. The friend is “another myself” (Nicomachean Ethics, IX, 1166 a326; see
also PF 276), and reciprocity with the other gets reduced to self-interest. Given
Aristotle’s view that one should love in a certain way rather than in others, and that
loving is more important than being loved (Nic. Ethics, Book VIII, 1159 a27),
Derrida considers that Aristotle’s view “has led to the emergence of the subjectobject division in the subsequent history of Western philosophy which, in turn, gives
rise to the canonical view of friendship” (TOC 45) that gives prominence to “the
subjective side of the relationship of self and other” (Ibid.).
This stress on knowledge behind the formation of bonds of friendship creates for
Derrida an unacknowledged paradox for Aristotle and the subsequent canonical
view of friendship. It appears to prevent loving when one does not know it, although
the other can love me without my knowing it. This a-symmetry creates the unrecognized effect that “reciprocity has only a secondary status in the determination of
friendship” (TOC 46). However, reciprocity can be said to be valuable in itself
because of the mutual obligations and benefits it confers on friends, in the widest
sense possible. Yet, the author states, “Derrida might argue plausibly, however, that
this picture of friendship is too narrow and one-sided, insofar as friendship, especially on the Aristotelian model, cannot be determined without a role for selfishness” (Ibid., 47).
Difficulties in the notion of reciprocity lead O’Connor to take up the difficult
subject of the meaning of fraternity. Before following him that far, however, some
corrective observations about Aristotle are plainly called for. First, as Sir David
Ross observes, although there is very little trace of altruism in Aristotle’s account of
friendship, the fact that loving is more important than being loved can be construed
as doing justice to “the altruistic element.”7 For instance, Aristotle tells us, a mother
sometimes “gives her child away to be brought up, and loves him as long as she
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis/London: Hackett Publishing
Company, 1985) (referred to hereafter as “Nic. Ethics”).
7
Sir David Ross, Aristotle (London: Methuen, 1966 [1923]), 230.
6
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
198
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
knows about him; but she does not seek the child’s love, if she cannot both [love and
be loved]. She would seem to be satisfied if she sees the child doing well, and she
loves the child even if ignorance prevents him from according to her what befits a
mother” (Nic. Ethics, Book VIII, 1159 a30–33).
We would not normally construe this relationship to be one of friendship, but we
need to bear in mind that Aristotle uses philia to refer to “any mutual attraction
between two human beings.”8 This is but a single example, for Aristotle, of the
moral general altruistic point that, towards a friend, “you must wish goods for
his own sake” (Ibid., 1155 b31). Moreover, the philosopher adds immediately,
reciprocity, so far from being secondary in friendship, is a necessary condition
of its existence in the first place. Without reciprocity, “you would be said to have
[only] goodwill for the other. For friendship is said to be reciprocated goodwill”
(Ibid., 1155 b33).
A second modification consists of inserting into O’Connor’s discussion Aristotle’s
distinction between good and bad self-love. The former’s characterization of selflove as “selfishness” applies only to bad self-love, that is, greed for “money, honours and bodily pleasures” (Nic. Ethics, Book IX, 1168 b17). These desires exploit
the non-rational part of the soul, whereas good self-love is an honest appreciation
(in both senses) of one’s virtue and dedication to the interest of friends (narrowly
conceived) and fellow citizens. As Ross indicates, the virtuous person can spend
money for the sake of others, but “he gets the better of the bargain: they get only
money, but he gets ‘the noble,’ the satisfaction of doing what is right. And even if he
dies for others, he gains more than he loses.”9
Finally, something should be said about Derrida’s claim that Aristotle’s stress on
the primacy of self-interest and loving as opposed to being loved “has led to the
emergence of the subject-object division in the subsequent history of Western
philosophy” (TOC 45), which has in turn formed the canonical definition of friendship that emphasizes “the subjective side of the relationship of self and other.”
The phrase, “has led to,” is highly vague, and the precision required to defend
the alleged causal connection almost impossible to obtain. A putative cause so far
removed from its alleged effect and blended with so many other historical antecedents
of modern philosophy would be nearly impossible to trace. Moreover, even if we
adopt hypothetically the language of modern philosophy and think in terms of
consciousness and its objects, the previous paragraph shows that it still would not
be quite right to think of Aristotle privileging the “subjective” side of friendship.
Reciprocity is essential to the definition of friendship and the good sense of self-love
focuses on the effects of one’s actions on others.
With these adjustments in mind, let us then continue to follow O’Connor’s
analysis of the theme of fraternity. Spurred by Blanchot’s comment that the evils of
Nazism made “us” recognize that the Jews were “our brothers,” Derrida questions
what fraternity might mean in this case. The meanings of “brothers,” “our,” and
98
W.S. Hamrick
8
9
Ibid.
Ibid., p. 232. Aristotle’s text on which Ross draws here is Nic. Ethics, Book IX, 1168 a28–1169 b2.
17 The Art of Friendship
199
“we” become problematic in such a context. “What can the name ‘brother’ or the
call to fraternity still mean,” he asks us, “when one or the other arises in the speech
of friendship which, like that of Blanchot … has so radically delivered itself from
the hold of all determined communities” (PF 304)? O’Connor is quite right to note
that the stakes here for Derrida are how to formulate our responsibility to and for
others without “any express commitment, or prior to any assumption of responsibility in the name of autonomy” (TOC 47). In the absence of any defensible universal
definition of friendship, how can deconstruction articulate “some implications for
the theory and practice of friendship of the tensions arising from the competition
between the claims of reciprocity and self-interest in the canonical tradition”
(Ibid.)?10 Indeed, does it make sense to speak of “friendship in the literal sense?
Does this question still make sense, precisely” (PF 240)?
Derrida’s Politics of Friendship offers us designedly open, challenging questions
about friendship that are provisional and seek to interrupt “a variety of canonical
readings and their universalist presuppositions” (TOC 49). At the same time, the
deconstructive enterprise, as O’Connor quite correctly observes, is confined more
nearly to “speculative rather than empirical and distributive questions in philosophy” (Ibid.). Consequently, he points out, a “more empirical approach to friendship” could provide a useful “supplement” (Ibid.) to Derridean deconstruction. Such
an empirical investigation would avoid universalist definitions, and remain sensitive
to “contextual, or cultural, influences on interpretation” as well as to the fact that
“evidence is always underdetermined” (Ibid.). If Derrida were to object to the necessary presence or implication of some universal assumptions in such an empirical
inquiry, O’Connor replies that the risks are no greater or less necessary than those
entailed in deconstructive critique itself. Nevertheless, the risks here do reinforce
the requirement of sticking to contextual, particular descriptions. These contexts are
“bounded” by “language, history, culture, institutions, and practices” (TOC 50).
Once these contexts are acknowledged and observed, O’Connor argues, certain
explicit and implicit questions present themselves for analysis. In the last two
pages of his essay, he only raises these questions as a way of pointing toward future
investigations. They are suggestions—hints, really—of the directions that his
future thinking might take. For that reason, they remain not fully formed; they
are underdeveloped, like photographs just emerging from developing liquid.
Nevertheless, these questions are of vital importance, so I will list them here only a
bit more briefly than the author himself poses them.
10
It is in the context of asking this question that O’Connor writes, as noted earlier, “friendship,
especially on the Aristotelian model, cannot be determined without a role for selfishness” (TOC 47).
We have already seen that, with regard to what Aristotle calls “good self-love,” there is no tension
between reciprocity and self-interest. Also, the discussion of the relationship between reciprocity
and self-interest has a long history. It is as least as old as Plato, and its modern history begins with
Machiavelli and Hobbes. I wish that the author had ventured an opinion as to what Derrida
might have made of this history and also of the fact that even Hobbes, as well as all other psychological egoists, would see no “tension” between reciprocity and self-interest because they are in
fact identical. Cannot psychological egoists be friends, at least in Aristotle’s senses of utility and
pleasure, and if not, why not?.
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
200
W.S. Hamrick
201
II
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
200
The first question is whether “Derrida’s anti-Aristotelian point about the need to
deconstruct a view of friendship, as linked to both kinship and the primacy of selfinterest, could be seen to have pragmatic value” (TOC 50). This “pragmatic value”
is cashed in terms of whether historical evidence provides a warrant for the usual
belief that “we have special duties toward, and responsibilities in respect of, kin, but
not to outsiders or strangers” (Ibid.). Anyone who has not slept throughout an entire
introductory course in anthropology knows about the changing nature of families
across the centuries and the correspondingly changing ways that they adopt, conserve, and adapt their values. They also know that the lines separating oppositional
insiders and outsiders are drawn differently. The same question also arises within
families in the changing treatment of spouses and children along gender lines and
whether, by implication, if “traditional marriage is fundamentally exploitative of the
female partner,” this exploitative framework eliminates “the possibility that heterosexual marriage partners, or even males and females generally, could ever become
equal friends” (Ibid., 51).
To come to grips with such questions, O’Connor brings us back to “the Aristotelian
attempt to account for friendship in terms of reciprocity, this time around the principle of mutual assistance” (TOC 51). This principle takes for granted the traditional
view of special duties towards insiders as opposed to outsiders, this time phrased
slightly differently: “that mutual assistance is due primarily to members, friends,
and to those who cooperate as part of some personal and social arrangement” (Ibid.,
emphasis mine). However, as the author immediately adds, even this principle is not
complete or self-sufficient, for no sooner is stated than it immediately invokes “the
wider question of what is due to persons generally” (Ibid.). These questions taken
together point directly to two crucial problems currently roiling the social, political,
legal, and moral waters throughout the world: immigration and the use of natural
resources and its impact on global warming.
174
Such are, in rapid summary, the principal themes of Tony O’Connor’s stimulating
essay. To adapt a well known expression, the “covers” of this article are too close
together. The last two pages, especially, provoke and authorize us to go further,
both in terms of questioning what has been said and then responding to the implicit
challenge to provide “a more empirical approach to friendship.” Here I would like
to do both.
In terms of critical questioning, I would first like to recur to “Derrida’s antiAristotelian point about the need to deconstruct a view of friendship, as linked to
both kinship and the primacy of self-interest.” Some discussion on the connection,
for Derrida, between the “primacy of self-interest” that he finds in Aristotle and the
latter’s view that the friend is “another myself”—the same, not the truly other—
would have been valuable. For, as we have already seen, there is for Aristotle an
altruistic element in self-love. Furthermore, Aristotle’s sense of good self-love, so
17 The Art of Friendship
201
far from being inconsistent with friendship, is essential to it. This claim falls far
short of a universalist definition, for it states only a necessary condition. And it is
plain that it is a necessary condition because it amounts to a basic self-respect, an
acknowledgement of having some goodness to offer the other, in the absence of
which relationships fail. This is old news to marriage counselors and therapists,
among others, and anyone can perceive its truth in cases in which one or more parties in a relationship of emerging friendship have nothing to offer the other(s). They
are emotionally needy and dependent: as an acquaintance once phrased it, they
“come on all needy and suck you dry.”
Finally, self-interest and conceiving the friend as “the same” are not identical.
On some views of self-interest, the two concepts may converge, but they need not,
and a “more empirical approach to friendship” would show that their relationship is
contingent. For example, Alfred North Whitehead expresses this non-identity when
he writes, “When man ceases to wander, he will cease to ascend in the scale of
being…. A diversification among human communities is essential for the provision
of the incentive and material for the Odyssey of the human spirit. Other nations of
different habits are not enemies: they are godsends.”11
A second critical remark concerns the justification for the traditional belief that
“we have special duties toward, and responsibilities in respect of, in, but not to outsiders or strangers.” It would have been instructive had the author evaluated, however briefly, some of the traditional rationales that have accompanied those traditional
beliefs and that still inform corresponding legal concepts. I am thinking of special
responsibilities created by unequal power relations, as in the case of young children,
who are involuntarily dependent upon their parents for their survival, and the duty
of society at large to care for its most vulnerable members: children, the aged, and
the indigent. One could also take into account reciprocal obligations as a way of
fleshing out the “principle of mutual assistance,” as in the case of adult children’s
obligations to care for aging and infirm parents.
Accepting the author’s invitation to provide “a more empirical approach to
friendship,” I would now like to adapt certain ideas from my recent work on kindness,12 but in a very compressed summary. More than half of the book consists of a
descriptive phenomenology of kindness as found in acts and omissions to act, persons, social atmospheres, technology, institutions, and communities. In Part II, these
phenomenological evidences are exposed to hermeneutical questioning in a variety
of contexts, and as guided by Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud, whom Paul Ricoeur
terms the three “masters of suspicion.”13 Finally, the last chapter, “Critical Kindness:
Toward an Aesthetic Humanism,” discusses and defends a residuum of kindness can
11
Alfred North Whitehead, Science and the Modern World (New York: The Free Press, 1967
[1925]), 207.
12
Kindness and the Good Society, Connections of the Heart (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 2002).
13
Paul Ricoeur, Freud and Philosophy, trans. Denis Savage (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1970), 80. See the extended discussion, pp. 80–86.
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
202
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
be rescued from that hermeneutical questioning. This chapter focuses on necessary
conditions of and concrete strategies for bringing genuine kindness into being.
Accordingly, much of this chapter focuses on the type of decision making
required for such a task. I argued that it is analogous to the way that artists solve
problems by unifying disparate elements into the form that is most meaningful considering the conditions imposed on their creativity by limited materials, time, and
resources. Such decision making is also central to establishing and maintaining
friendships. It is likewise integrative by conjugating trust with suspicion, or at least
caution, and by requiring informed judgments about how to bring into being the
greatest possible good of the friend (analogous to the artist’s richest possible creation from the materials before her). In so doing, the will embodied in such decision
making becomes poetic—that is, “the power of unification unfurled by the configuring act constituting poeisis itself.”14
This integrative quality that is central to acts of kindness also applies to friendships because, analogous to the artistic creation, it likewise unifies external events in
the course of social life as well as brings about an internal unity that presents itself to
us as personal integrity. This integrity, or wholeness (from the Latin, integer), is also
closely linked to what Gabriel Marcel terms “disponibilité,” our active disposition to
be at the service of the other, and which constitutes the origin of the self’s “activity
and creativeness.”15 Central also to the experience of friendship is Marcel’s observation that we have a sense of “admiration” for those who are actively ready to be of
service to others. In fact, “admiration” is itself “a form of readiness.”16
Aesthetic experience, from the perspective of both artist and spectator, has other
features that illumine relations of friendship. Such experience can, as Monroe
Beardsley points out, encourage the development of discrimination and refined perception, as well as an internal unity that emerges from the way that through the
aesthetic object we are “taken in hand,” as it were, and then “feel a remarkable kind
of clarification.”17 This clarification goes hand in hand with refined perception in
that it gives us what Marcel called having an “ear” for experience. In aesthetic
experience as in friendship, the word “ear” designates something subtle, “a certain
faculty for appreciating relationships.”18 Lacking this feeling of attunement to the
252
W.S. Hamrick
14
Paul Ricoeur, Oneself as Another, trans. Kathleen Blamey (Chicago/London: University of
Chicago Press), 142. Ricoeur often spoke of the unwritten third volume of The Philosophy of the
Will as a “poetics of the will.” The poetics of the will best suited for the realization of acts of kindness is not necessarily what Ricoeur had in mind, but it is consistent with all of his discussions of
willing.
15
Gabriel Marcel, “On the Ontological Mystery,” in The Philosophy of Existentialism, trans. Manya
Harari (New York: The Citadel Press, 1964), 43.
16
Marcel, “Reply to Otto Friedrich Bollnow,” trans. Susan Gruenheck, in The Philosophy of
Gabriel Marcel, ed. Paul Schillp and Lewis Hahn (LaSalle: Open Court Press, 1984), 202.
17
Monroe C. Beardsley, Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism (New York: Harcourt,
Brace, and World), 574.
18
Gabriel Marcel, Tragic Wisdom and Beyond, trans. Stephen Jolin and Peter McCormick
(Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973), 6.
17 The Art of Friendship
203
desires and needs of others would make it very difficult to appreciate the good of a
friend. Therefore, Beardsley concludes that the sensitivity and perceptiveness that
can be gained from aesthetic experience “would have a wide bearing upon all other
aspects of our lives—our emotional relations with other people, for example.”19 It
certainly has a bearing on one’s ability to create and maintain friendships, particularly by way of resisting tendencies to construe the other as “the same.” Also, as
Merleau-Ponty’s analyses of the esthesiology of the body have shown, the feeling
attunement to the other’s needs and desires is already schematized in the flesh.
The Ineinander of intercorporeity grounds social relationships such as friendship,
narrowly or widely construed.
Beardsley also shows how other aspects of aesthetic experience effectively argue
against the logic of “the same.” Such experience can foster the growth of the imagination such that we can learn to see the aesthetic object from another person’s point
of view, that of the artist and/or other spectators, and even when we find that perspective alien and off-putting. This is an attitude, he proposes, that “fosters mutual
sympathy and understanding.”20 It is also an attitude that is crucial to the way that
lines are drawn between insiders and outsiders, to the types of experiences that
Whitehead values, and as Tony O’Connor has pointed out, raises the question of
what we owe to people generally. In addition, it is an attitude that speaks to Max
Scheler’s desire to make phenomenology the “guardian of dialogue.”21
The approach to the other that Beardsley advocates is also one that, in friendship as in the art world, consists of a unity of activity and receptivity, and both are
essential to resisting the logic of “the same” in friendship. The artist’s activity is
one of creative expression. As Mikel Dufrenne notes, “Expression is the revelation of the self, simply because it causes us to actually be what is expressed.”22 He
is perhaps thinking here of Gaston Bachelard’s comment about the “awakening of
poetic creation … in the soul of the reader.” The poem expresses us by making
us what it expresses, and a becoming of our being. Here expression creates
being.”23
This might well sound like the logic of “the same,” and it would be if we
attempted to inscribe our values in the lives of our friends as an artist expresses his
or her vision on the canvas, in the marble, dance, or musical composition. However,
with friendship, although there is an expression of self and values, it is of a very
Beardsley, p. 574.
Ibid., p. 575.
21
On this subject, see Michael D. Barber’s excellent book, Guardian of Dialogue, Max Scheler’s
Phenomenology, Sociology of Knowledge, and Philosophy of Love (Lewisburg: Bucknell University
Press, 1993). See particularly Chap. 4, “The Fundaments of Dialogue: Scheler’s Theory of
Intersubjectivity.”
22
Mikel Dufrenne, The Phenomenology of Aesthetic Experience, trans. Edward Casey, Albert A.
Anderson, Willis Domingo, and Leon Jacobson (Evanston: Northwestern University Press,
1973), 380.
23
Gaston Bachelard, The Poetics of Space, trans. Maria Jolas, Foreword by Etienne Gilson (Boston:
Beacon Press, 1958), xix.
19
20
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
204
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
particular kind. The content of the expression consists of our willingness to assist
our friends in whatever ways possible and only that. Thus we express an appropriate absence from their lives. This discretion is also a necessary condition of friendship, and consists in the expression of our integrity, that in intervening in our
friends’ lives, we do not take up residence in them or in any other fashion attempt
to colonize them.
The expression of friendship in and through intervening in our friends’ lives
respectfully also has the effect of aestheticizing the environment. In Dufrenne’s
phrasing, “There is a nimbus of joy around the joyous man. We say of another that
he exudes boredom. The effect is such that ordinary objects can change their appearance through the mere presence of someone.”24 Just so, there is a nimbus of friendliness around friends, a concrete sign of the mutual investment of trust and help that
instantiates Tony O’Connor’s principle of mutual assistance.”
In relationships of friendship, this activity that I have been sketching is indissoluble from the receptivity through which I open myself to the other to be taught
by him or her, just as the spectator opens himself or herself to an artwork.
Correlatively, artworks as well as friends, as just described, manifest themselves as
worthy of respect. They present themselves as having a certain dignity or integrity
such that they impress on us a claim to adapt to them rather than vice-versa. Thus,
what Dufrenne’s description of the artwork applies equally to the friend: “I submit
myself to the work instead of submitting it to my jurisdiction, and I allow the work
to deposit the meaning within me.”25 It follows also that when I ignore this instructive receptivity and instead enforce my own ideological filters on an artwork or a
friend, I misperceive and distort the referent by making it or him or her submit to the
logic of “the same.” By making it, or him or her, “another me” tout court, I find only
myself and can never learn from it or him or her.
There is no better illustration of such an imposition of “the same” than Jean-Paul
Sartre’s elegantly sarcastic portrait of Monsieur Achille and his friends in La Nausée.
In their café wisdom, “they baptized their little obstinacies and some proverbs in the
name of experience, and they turned themselves into automatic vending machines:
two sous in the slot to the left and voilà anecdotes wrapped in silver paper; two sous
in the slot to the right and one gets invaluable pieces of advice that stick to your
teeth like soft caramels.”26
By contrast with this type of oppressive experience, aesthetic objects, just as
true friends, present the opportunity of a depth of experience. That depth is measured in light of what we discern in, rather than enforce on, the aesthetic object or
the friend. However, because the receptivity involved in such cases is only the
inverse of a corresponding activity, it is just as true that we will not reach this depth
unless we acquire the requisite sensitivity that flows from making the effort to
commit ourselves to the aesthetic object or friend. Therefore, for the friend as for
the artwork, “The more I lay myself open to the work, the more sensitive will I be
316
W.S. Hamrick
Dufrenne, p. 177.
Ibid., p. 393.
26
Jean-Paul Sartre, Nausea, trans. Robert Baldick (New York: Penguin Books, 1965), 100.
24
25
17 The Art of Friendship
205
to its effects…. Aesthetic feeling has depth not only because it unifies us but also
because it opens us up.”27
For example, “A man knows tenderness in a Mozart andante—that singular
nuance of tenderness smiling through tears, that delicate joy which has undergone
untold tribulations without becoming lost in them—because his depths have been
offered substantial nourishment.”28 The same “substantial nourishment” and required
effort to reach it also obtain in the narrow circle of very good friends, as opposed to
the much wider sense of Aristotelian philia or, say, George Herbert Mead’s notion
of “the generalized other.”29
Finally, it is worth observing of the necessary effort involved that such friendships are not easy to establish and maintain. This is because, among other things,
there are powerful cultural influences that reduce and deform the depth of feelings
required into superficial, transient gratifications. For example, we are mobile and
often change residences. We live at a frenzied pace, and it is not only food that must
be fast. We believe in and demand instant solutions (just add water). We have an
insatiable craving for non-stop talking, from talk radio to blogs, but little time or
patience for thinking. Web sites such as Face Book offer the possibility of being
“friends” with a page owner. Marcel was not wrong when he wrote that the joy of
existence has been degraded to satisfactions,30 and this was written long before
ubiquitous personal computers and mobile phones thoroughly mediated intercorporeal relationships with e-mail, chat groups, and text messaging.
But now I can sense the ghost of Derrida smiling (or scowling) over my shoulder.
For, the question of fraternity returns in the form of asking, Who is this “we?” The
answer is, the object of an empirical generalization from my own culture. Tony
O’Connor is certainly correct to stress the necessity of taking historical and cultural
conditions into account in an empirical investigation of the reality of friendships,
and from small French villages to those of indigenous peoples in Guatemala, I have
witnessed flourishing friendships in substantially different conditions. O’Connor
has invited us to follow his “more empirical approach to friendship,” to which I have
attempted to respond here, and I wish to conclude by issuing a reverse invitation. I
hope that, reflecting on his own culture and historical conditions and beyond, he
pursues that empirical approach in the light of the aspects of an aesthetic humanism
briefly sketched here. He thinks clearly and deeply about important philosophical
questions, from the published results of which we have all benefited over the years,
and of which I look forward to a happy continuation throughout his well earned
retirement. To him, I dare say, “O friend, thank you for being a friend.”
Dufrenne, p. 405.
Ibid.
29
The “generalized other” represents “the attitude of the whole community. George Herbert Mead,
Mind, Self, and Society (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1934), 154. This “other” is not
necessarily a specific person. As Alfred Schutz notes, “the generalized other” “may take the structure of an individual, a type, a collectivity, [or] an anonymous audience or public.” Collected
Papers, Vol. I, The Problem of Social Reality, Edited with an Introduction Maurice Natanson, with
a Preface by H. L. Van Breda (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1962), 189.
30
Marcel, “Reply to Otto Friedrich Bollnow,” in Schillp and Hahn, p. 202.
27
28
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
Tony O’Connor Biography
1
This collection of essays was commissioned to honour the philosopher Tony O’Connor
on the occasion of his 65th birthday and ensuing retirement from Unversity College
Cork, Ireland.
Dr. Tony O’Connor received his Ph.D. from the National University of Ireland in
1975 and taught at the Philosophy Department, University College Cork for almost
30 years where, at the end, he was also Head of Department. Throughout his career he
was tireless in generating and being involved in philosophical discussion and debate.
He was President of the British Society for Phenomenology until 2004 and is now
Vice President. He also was Chairman (1996–1999) and Secretary (1992–1995) of
the National Committee for Philosophy, Royal Irish Academy. Other memberships
include the Society for European Philosophy, where he is on the Executive Committee,
the International Association for Philosophy and Literature, the Irish Philosophical
Society, the Irish Phenomenological Circle, and the Philadelphia Association,
London, of which he is an Associate Member. He is a member of the Editorial
Advisory Board of the book series Continental Philosophy, Routledge, New York
and London. He has published on art, friendship, politics and on hermeneutics and
continental philosophy more generally.
The contributions gathered in this volume are united in their attempt to respond
appropriately and with care according to the expertise of their authors to Tony O’Connor
as a philosopher, educator and person in different ways: by interpreting O’Connor’s
work, by thinking through issues which he has addressed in his work, by offering their
own work for discussion and by addressing Tony O’Connor personally.
Email Addresses (In Alphabetical Order)
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
Graham Allen: g.allen@ucc.ie
Gary Banham: garybanham@me.com
Robert Bernasconi: rbernscn@memphis.edu
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
2
25
26
27
207
208
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
Douglas Burnham: H.D.Burnham@staffs.ac.uk
Edward S. Casey: escasey3@aol.com
Nicholas Davey: j.r.n.davey@dundee.ac.uk
Duane Davis: ddavis@unca.edu
Francis Halsall: halsallf@ncad.ie
William Hamrick: whamrick@sbcglobal.net
Joanna Hodge: J.Hodge@mmu.ac.uk
Julia Jansen: j.jansen@ucc.ie
David Farrell Krell: davidfkrell@gmail.com
Alphonso Lingis: allingis@hotmail.com
John Mullarkey: J.Mullarkey@kingston.ac.uk
Felix ó Murchadha: felix.omurchadha@nuigalway.ie
Sinéad Murphy: sinead.murphy@newcastle.ac.uk
Hugh Silverman: hsilverman@ms.cc.sunysb.edu
Talia Welsh: tl_welsh@yahoo.com
James Williams: j.r.williams@dundee.ac.uk
28
Tony O’Connor Biography
Index
A
Action, 7, 50, 57, 65, 68–70, 109, 119, 120,
126, 139–141, 146, 148, 156, 157, 165,
177–179, 196
Adorno, T.W., 30, 101
Aesthetics
idea(s), 28, 30, 33–35
judgment, 3
theory, 23, 24, 31, 35, 108
Alienation, 14, 15, 21, 22, 31, 67
Anthropology, anthropological, 43, 86, 87,
141, 200
Antonioni, M., 70
Arcadia, 24, 25, 34, 35
Aristotle, 14, 53, 131, 139, 141,
148, 183–186, 195,
197–200
Art, 1, 13, 23, 38, 49–61, 74, 90, 101, 123,
154, 161, 195–205,
Artistic practice, 15
Attitude
phenomenological, 142
philosophical, 120, 143
B
Bachelard, G., 203
Bataille, G., 86, 129, 189
Beardsley, M., 202, 203
Being, 31, 52, 75, 109, 112, 113, 115,
116, 123–125, 140–142, 145–147,
154, 197
Benjamin, W., 76, 77, 80
Bordwell, D., 63–71
Brecht, B., 65, 190
C
Cavell, S., 67
Childhood/Children/Child, 21, 37–48, 83, 85,
90, 100, 112, 184, 197, 198, 200, 201
Cicero, 196, 197
Cinema, 6, 63–72
Coleridge, 15
Communication, 45, 66, 73, 99–106, 109, 157,
175, 191
Community, 2, 4, 6, 7, 46, 92, 99–110, 189,
190, 193, 205
Conscience, 100, 140
Consciousness
embodied, 3, 114
historical, 3, 86
Constancy, 45, 46
Creation, 14–22, 42, 49, 50, 58, 67, 106,
202, 203
Creativity, 3, 15–17, 44, 94, 121, 202
Curtiz, M., 71
D
Dasein, 131, 134, 136, 142, 145
Death, 1, 15, 22, 25, 29, 59, 77, 78, 82, 89,
112, 116, 129, 131, 136, 137, 147, 162
Debt, 102, 127–134, 136, 137
de Kooning, 49, 50
Deleuze, G., 52, 55, 99–110
Derrida, J., 9, 28, 127–137, 162–165, 167,
169, 181, 183–185, 187–189, 191–193,
195–200, 205
Destruktion, 144
Dialectic, 15, 21, 22, 54, 115, 116,
121–123, 152
F. Halsall et al. (eds.), Critical Communities and Aesthetic Practices: Dialogues with
Tony O’Connor on Society, Art, and Friendship, Contributions To Phenomenology 64,
DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1509-7, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
209
210
Disinterestedness, 23, 31–33
Donation, 99–110, 136
Drawing, 37–48, 50, 54, 59, 78, 123
Drives, 35, 37, 38, 129, 131, 167
Duty(ies), 91, 109, 140, 171–180, 183, 184,
200, 201
E
Earthwork(s), 49–51, 56–60
Economy, 27, 28, 35, 94, 129, 131, 136
Edge, 3, 5, 49–61, 80, 81, 191
Education, 5, 38, 70, 87, 133, 162,
165–169
Empiricism, 113
Epoché, 114, 142, 143, 145, 149
Equality, 100, 162, 174, 183–185, 188,
190, 191
Essence(s), 21, 38, 58, 100, 102, 113–115,
119, 134, 136, 148, 195, 196
Existence, 2, 17, 19, 22, 26, 31, 32, 47,
112–115, 125, 152, 156, 167, 177,
198, 205
Experience, 3, 6–8, 14, 20, 23, 24, 26, 27,
29–33, 35, 37–43, 45–47, 56, 58, 75,
86–88, 91, 93, 99, 101, 113, 114, 134,
143, 144, 147, 191, 202–204
F
Film, 63–72
Finlay, I.H., 24–26, 32
Forgetting, 9, 122, 127–137, 144
Foucault, M., 4, 5, 47, 111, 130
Frame(s), 3, 49–51, 57, 59, 60, 68, 119,
121, 186
Frankenthaler, H., 38
Freedom, 21, 39, 44, 55, 84, 116, 118, 121,
147, 148, 163–165 167, 178, 188, 191
Freud, F., 38, 93, 128, 129, 131–136, 201
Friendship, friend
Kantian, 171–180
moral, 172, 174, 175, 198
politics of, 4, 128, 132, 134, 181, 184, 187,
189, 192, 195, 196, 199
postmodern, 8, 9, 181–193
Futurity, 127–137
G
Gadamer, H.-G., 5–8, 14, 15, 22–24, 26, 27,
30, 31, 34
Genius, 14–17, 20–22, 59, 76, 81, 166
Gestalt Theory, Gestalt Psychology, 45, 46, 121
Index
Gift, 78, 100, 103, 110, 127, 129–134, 136,
148, 162, 163
Godard, J.-L., 65–68, 71
H
Hegel, 38, 68, 112, 122
Heidegger, M., 21, 23, 24, 54, 56, 57, 59, 60,
75–77, 79, 80, 101, 109, 112, 122, 128,
134, 136, 139–149
Hermeneutics, hermeneutical, 2–8, 13–35,
85–95, 139, 201, 202, 207
History, historical, historicity
effective, 4, 5, 14, 22
Hitchcock, A., 64, 70
Hölderlin, M., 73–84, 147
Hopkins, H., 49
Hopper, E., 51–53
Horizon(s),
fusion(s) of horizons, 14, 21, 22
Husserl, E., 37, 38, 47, 112, 122, 128–137,
141–145
I
Idealism, 20, 113, 114, 116, 122
Intentionality
embodied, 114
Interpretation, 3, 6, 14–17, 22, 26, 28–34, 42,
43, 46, 47, 86, 87, 108, 126, 156, 199
Intersubjectivity, 133, 143, 203
J
Jarmusch, J., 190
Jew, J., 7, 128, 152, 155
Justice, 8, 104, 109, 130, 133, 137, 140, 141,
162, 182–193, 197
K
Kairos, 146, 149
Kant, I., 4, 5, 7, 9, 14, 15, 20–35, 61, 101, 103,
128, 143, 171–180
Kubrick, S., 64
L
Lacan, 82, 132
Language, 17, 24, 27–29, 33, 35, 40, 45, 54,
76–78, 80–82, 84, 89, 93, 106–108,
125, 147, 166, 191, 198, 199
Leibniz, G.W., 37, 133
Levinas, E., 124, 151, 152, 155
Index
Literature, 5, 112, 161, 166, 181, 195,
196, 207
Lyotard, J.-F., 99–110
M
Marin, 49
Meaning, 3, 13–17, 22, 24, 26–29, 31–35, 37,
39, 42–46, 66, 75, 77, 78, 86–88, 91,
93, 95, 99–104, 106–109, 119,
123–126, 129–136, 151, 156, 164, 197,
198, 202, 204
Merleau-Ponty, M., 6, 7, 37–48, 53, 60, 74,
84, 111–126, 130, 145, 196, 203
Mondrian, 50
Montaigne, M., 133, 162, 183, 186–188, 195
Morgenstern, S., 42
Mourning, 82, 127, 128, 132, 136, 137
N
“New International,” 127, 128, 136, 137
Nietzsche, F., 3, 15, 22, 26, 32, 38, 71, 76, 77,
93, 94, 108, 129, 133, 134, 136, 137,
141, 163–166, 168, 201
O
Obligation, 91–93, 102–106, 178, 179, 197,
201
Ontology, historical, 14, 22, 121, 124
Othering, 7, 151–157
Other, the, 151, 152, 154, 156, 161–170
Otogogy, 161–170
P
Painting(s), 41, 49–54, 60, 106, 108
Perception, perceptual, 7, 37, 38, 40–47, 53,
55, 65, 101, 113, 114, 119–121, 143,
145, 202
Performance, collective, 3, 85–88, 94
Phenomenology, phenomenological, 2, 37–40,
47, 48, 111–115, 119–122, 127,
129–136, 140–145, 149, 151, 195, 201,
203, 207
Picasso, 42, 43, 52, 54, 59, 74, 78
Plato, 5, 6, 14, 122, 139–141, 144, 182–185,
199
Poetry, 24, 54, 60, 78–82, 140
Polanski, R., 70
Politics, political, 2, 4, 6, 26, 67, 85, 88, 91,
94, 102, 104, 105, 109–126, 128–130,
132–136, 139–149, 155, 156, 161–165,
211
174, 180–185, 187–189, 192, 195, 196,
199, 200, 207
Pollock, J., 49, 50, 59
Poussin, N., 24, 25
Pre-conceptual, 24
Psychoanalysis, psychoanalytic, 38, 41, 42,
47, 127–129, 132–135, 168
R
Rancière, J., 70
Reason, instrumental, 99–110
Receptivity, 203, 204
Reciprocity, 190, 197–200
Reduction, 47, 114–116, 142, 144,
145, 149
Reflection, 4, 6, 13–22, 25, 29, 38, 39,
49–61, 63–72, 113–117, 119,
120, 123, 124, 126, 136, 142,
144, 149
Refraction, 63–72
Representation(s), 28, 31, 40–42, 44, 45, 52,
54–56, 72, 87, 93, 101–105, 107, 119,
123, 153, 175
Resnais, A., 67
Respect, 13, 17, 18, 20, 24, 26, 28, 44, 78, 79,
107, 117, 119, 133, 140, 142, 171–181,
200, 201, 204
Response, 8, 77, 82, 103, 106, 108, 114,
116–118, 127, 136, 139, 140, 142, 144,
146–148, 179, 182
Responsibility, 6, 8, 9, 91, 105, 118, 135,
140, 141, 155, 161–163, 182, 192,
193, 199
Ricoeur, P., 14, 26, 201, 202
Ritual(s), 3, 59, 85–88, 91, 113, 127
Romanticism, 17, 20–22
Rothko, 49
Rousseau, J.-J., 86, 157, 162, 187
S
Sartre, J.-P., 7, 111, 112, 114–120,
122–126, 128, 130, 151, 154–157,
195, 196, 204
Schelling, F.W.J., 15, 21, 80, 122
Schleiermacher, 24
Schopenhauer, 15
Schrader, P., 70
Scorcese, M., 69
Sculpture(s), 30, 49, 57
Seriality, 7, 155, 156
Seurat, 49
Shelley, M., 22, 161, 162
212
Smithson, R., 50, 51, 56–60
Splendour, 3
Symbols, cultural, 3, 86, 93
T
Teaching, 5, 74, 114, 161–170
Thinking, 2, 7, 16, 22, 25, 27, 32, 42, 59, 65,
76, 90, 123, 129–131, 134–137,
139–149, 151, 152, 154, 156, 163, 178,
190, 192, 199, 201, 203, 205, 207
Thompson, K., 65, 66
Tradition, 6–9, 14, 24, 37–41, 44, 45, 64, 89,
92, 113, 114, 129, 144, 196, 199–201
Translation, 16, 26, 53, 73–84, 109, 111, 112,
126, 142, 144, 145, 181
Index
U
Unconscious, the, 37–39, 81
V
van Sant, G., 64
Vinterbert, T., 69
Violence, 26, 34, 85–95, 135, 136, 157
W
Waiting, 7, 8, 19, 80, 84, 136, 139–149,
166, 169
Whitman, W., 50
Withdrawal, 18, 19, 109–110, 119, 139, 140
Wittgenstein, 29, 33, 57