Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry
4/5
()
About this ebook
Michael Ignatieff draws on his extensive experience as a writer and commentator on world affairs to present a penetrating account of the successes, failures, and prospects of the human rights revolution. Since the United Nations adopted the Universal Declaration of Human Rights in 1948, this revolution has brought the world moral progress and broken the nation-state's monopoly on the conduct of international affairs. But it has also faced challenges. Ignatieff argues that human rights activists have rightly drawn criticism from Asia, the Islamic world, and within the West itself for being overambitious and unwilling to accept limits. It is now time, he writes, for activists to embrace a more modest agenda and to reestablish the balance between the rights of states and the rights of citizens.
Ignatieff begins by examining the politics of human rights, assessing when it is appropriate to use the fact of human rights abuse to justify intervention in other countries. He then explores the ideas that underpin human rights, warning that human rights must not become an idolatry. In the spirit of Isaiah Berlin, he argues that human rights can command universal assent only if they are designed to protect and enhance the capacity of individuals to lead the lives they wish. By embracing this approach and recognizing that state sovereignty is the best guarantee against chaos, Ignatieff concludes, Western nations will have a better chance of extending the real progress of the past fifty years. Throughout, Ignatieff balances idealism with a sure sense of practical reality earned from his years of travel in zones of war and political turmoil around the globe.
Based on the Tanner Lectures that Ignatieff delivered at Princeton University's Center for Human Values in 2000, the book includes two chapters by Ignatieff, an introduction by Amy Gutmann, comments by four leading scholars--K. Anthony Appiah, David A. Hollinger, Thomas W. Laqueur, and Diane F. Orentlicher--and a response by Ignatieff.
Michael Ignatieff
Michael Ignatieff is a writer, historian and former politician. He has taught at Cambridge, Oxford, the University of Toronto and Harvard and is currently university professor at Central European University in Vienna. His books, which have been translated into twelve languages, include Blood and Belonging, Isaiah Berlin: a life, The Needs of Strangers, The Russian Album and The Ordinary Virtues.
Read more from Michael Ignatieff
On Consolation: Finding Solace in Dark Times Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Needs of Strangers Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Hedgehog and the Fox: An Essay on Tolstoy's View of History - Second Edition Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Blood and Belonging: Journeys into the New Nationalism Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Russian Album Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Charlie Johnson in the Flames Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Ordinary Virtues: Moral Order in a Divided World Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Lesser Evil: Political Ethics in an Age of Terror Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5
Related to Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry
Titles in the series (18)
Work and Welfare Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Democracy, Culture and the Voice of Poetry Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Meaning in Life and Why It Matters Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Striking First: Preemption and Prevention in International Conflict Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsTruth v. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Multiculturalism: Expanded Paperback Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Foragers, Farmers, and Fossil Fuels: How Human Values Evolve Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Limits of Constitutional Democracy Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Private Government: How Employers Rule Our Lives (and Why We Don't Talk about It) Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Lives of Animals Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Freedom of Association Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5A Different Kind of Animal: How Culture Transformed Our Species Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Primates and Philosophers: How Morality Evolved Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Why Trust Science? Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law - New Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The President Who Would Not Be King: Executive Power under the Constitution Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Nature of Space and Time Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Related ebooks
American Exceptionalism and Human Rights Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsInternational Human Rights: Universalism Versus Relativism Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHuman Rights at Risk: Global Governance, American Power, and the Future of Dignity Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Human Rights Culture: A Study in History and Context Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsDemocratic Legitimacy: Impartiality, Reflexivity, Proximity Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Endtimes of Human Rights Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Democracy: A Beginner's Guide Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe History of Human Rights: From Ancient Times to the Globalization Era Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Reinventing Human Rights Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsUniversal Human Rights in Theory and Practice Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Speech Matters: Getting Free Speech Right Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsDemocracy and Its Crisis Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Seeing the Myth in Human Rights Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsNot Enough: Human Rights in an Unequal World Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Politics of Law and Order: Street Crime and Public Policy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMaking Human Rights a Reality Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsUniversal Human Rights and Extraterritorial Obligations Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsEmergency Politics: Paradox, Law, Democracy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Mandate of Dignity: Ronald Dworkin, Revolutionary Constitutionalism, and the Claims of Justice Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAn introduction to the European Convention on Human Rights Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSetting the People Free: The Story of Democracy, Second Edition Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPopular Democracy: The Paradox of Participation Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsConservatism: The Fight for a Tradition Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Why Deliberative Democracy? Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Representative Democracy: Principles and Genealogy Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The State and the Rule of Law Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA Democratic Conception of Privacy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Human Rights Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA Pure Theory of Democracy Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5A Preface to Economic Democracy Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5
Philosophy For You
The Boy, the Mole, the Fox and the Horse Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Dictionary of Obscure Sorrows Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Source: The Secrets of the Universe, the Science of the Brain Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Four Loves Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of War Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Sun Tzu's The Art of War: Bilingual Edition Complete Chinese and English Text Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Be Here Now Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Art of Loving Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Experiencing God (2021 Edition): Knowing and Doing the Will of God Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Meditations: Complete and Unabridged Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Republic by Plato Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/512 Rules for Life: An Antidote to Chaos Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5THE EMERALD TABLETS OF THOTH THE ATLANTEAN Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Courage to Be Happy: Discover the Power of Positive Psychology and Choose Happiness Every Day Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Little Book of Hygge: Danish Secrets to Happy Living Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sapiens: A Brief History of Humankind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Beyond Good and Evil Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato and a Platypus Walk Into a Bar...: Understanding Philosophy Through Jokes Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Beyond Good and Evil Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato's Republic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Laws of Connection: The Scientific Secrets of Building a Strong Social Network Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Egyptian Book of the Dead: The Complete Papyrus of Ani Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Denial of Death Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Tao Te Ching: A New English Version Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Inward Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5My Big TOE - Awakening H: Book 1 of a Trilogy Unifying Philosophy, Physics, and Metaphysics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Reviews for Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry
13 ratings1 review
- Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Extremely powerful book; I regret that I waited so long to get around to reading it. Ignatieff argues that the purpose of human rights, drawing from its roots in natural law, is to protect human agency. This leads to the conclusion that they will primarily protect negative freedoms, or freedoms "from", rather than freedoms or rights "to."
He further disagrees with the idea of rights as trumps, instead suggesting that they are starting points for negotiations. We may be forced to accept, as Rawls said, that liberal democracies are not the only form of acceptable human society. He illustrates the point that groups should have the right to define for themselves what kind of life they have through the example of FGM. So long as people have right to leave, there can be little cause for outside objection.
Book preview
Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry - Michael Ignatieff
INDEX
Introduction
AMY GUTMANN
NO ONE shall be subject to cruel, inhuman, or degrading treatment or punishment.
This statement of Article 7 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights is part of what Michael Ignatieff aptly calls the juridical revolution
in human rights since 1945. Other critical international documents of the revolution include the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and the Geneva Conventions of 1948, the revision of the Geneva Conventions of 1949, and the international convention on asylum of 1951.
Covenants without swords are but words, Thomas Hobbes famously wrote. What kind of revolution is marked by so many words that lack the backing of swords? The International Covenant, unlike the original Universal Declaration, is a legally binding treaty among nations. A Human Rights Committee has the authority to adjudicate violations that are brought before it. The legally binding nature of this and other human rights treaties is another indication of the rights revolution. To say that human rights are legally binding, however, is not to say that there is an authoritative agent with the power to hold sovereign states to the law. For this and many other reasons, the human rights revolution is far from complete, and its capacity to come closer to realizing its aims is widely questioned, especially outside of now highly organized communities of human rights activists. Moreover, what would count as a successful completion of the human rights revolution is by no means clear, or clearly established in either the theory or the practice of human rights in the international arena.
We therefore begin this book with the most basic set of questions concerning the political morality of human rights. What is the purpose of human rights? What should their content be? When do violations of human rights warrant intervention across national boundaries? Is there a single moral foundation for human rights that spans many cultures, or are there many culturally specific moral foundations, or none? In what sense, if any, are human rights universal? These are among the hard and critical questions raised by the human rights revolution, and addressed by Michael Ignatieff's two essays in this volume and the commentaries by Anthony Appiah, David Hollinger, Thomas Laqueur, and Diane Orentlicher to which Ignatieff responds. The essays and commentaries were first presented as the 1999–2000 Tanner Lectures on Human Values at Princeton University under the auspices of Princeton's University Center for Human Values.
If we begin with the most basic question—What is the purpose of human rights?—we will immediately see how hard it is to arrive at a meeting of minds on a single answer. Harder to see, apparently, is how unnecessary it is to insist on a single answer. Human rights can serve multiple purposes, and those purposes can be expressed in many ways, not only across different societies and cultures, but even within them. No major culture is univocal in its answer to this question. That there can be many good answers to a single question as practically important as the purpose of human rights should not prevent us from offering our own best answer, especially if that answer is one that speaks to many people, as does Ignatieff's understanding of human rights.
The purpose of human rights, Ignatieff argues, is to protect human agency and therefore to protect human agents against abuse and oppression. Human rights protect the core of negative freedom, freedom from abuse, oppression, and cruelty. This is a starting point for some complex thinking about what the purpose and content of the evolving international human rights regime should be. But even the starting point is more complex—and contestable—than first appearances might suggest. Protecting human agencies, and protecting human agents against abuse and oppression, cannot be identified simply (or solely) with negative liberty, freedom from interference. Nor is the core of human rights constituted only by negative freedoms. The right to subsistence is as necessary for human agency as a right against torture. A right to subsistence is not a negative freedom, as the right against cruel and unusual punishment is. Starving people have no more agency than people subject to cruel and unusual punishment. Including subsistence rights in the human rights regime was also an important part of reaching an international agreement on the nature of human rights.
If an important purpose of human rights is to protect human agency, and the rights that protect human agency are not exclusively negative liberties, it is still the case, as Ignatieff argues, that a human rights regime does not claim—or realistically aspire—to be morally comprehensive. The enforcement of human rights in the international arena does not guarantee that anyone whose rights are effectively protected will live a wonderful life. Or even a (morally or nonmorally) good life. When human rights are honored and enforced, they are effective instruments to protect individuals from abuse, cruelty, oppression, degradation, and the like. This purpose of human rights—which Ignatieff calls pragmatic, which is not to deny that it is moral in its core purpose of protecting human agency (just as pragmatism is a moral and political philosophy)—can provide a guide to the content of a human rights regime. Human rights institutions and agencies—both governmental and nongovernmental—should not try to proliferate human rights beyond what is necessary to protect persons as purposive agents, or to realize a similarly basic purpose of human rights (such as the dignity of persons, a purpose that Ignatieff rejects and to which I shall return). Proliferation of human rights to include rights that are not clearly necessary to protect the basic agency or needs or dignity of persons cheapens the purpose of human rights and correspondingly weakens the resolve of potential enforcers.
Proliferation of human rights also makes it far more difficult to achieve the broad intercultural assent to rights that an international human rights regime requires to be effective. If human rights are pragmatic political instruments, then human rights regimes should aspire to be effective before they aspire to be more comprehensive in their pronouncements. Human rights should not be conceived as guarantors of social justice, or substitutes for comprehensive conceptions of a good life. Protections against cruel, inhuman, and degrading treatment—all of which are compatible with multiple expressions of the purpose of human rights—are widely viewed as the core of a human rights regime. If protections against cruelty and degradation—freedom from harm and freedom to live a decent life—are not human rights, then one might say that nothing is. And some people, of course, do say that nothing is a human right, but that does not mean that they are right, or even reasonable in claiming that there are no human rights. To believe in human rights does not entail believing that they exist independently of human purpose. Human rights are important instruments for protecting human beings against cruelty, oppression, and degradation. That's all we need to believe to defend human rights. Many people believe far more about human rights, for example, that there is a divine or natural source of human rights. The human purpose of defending human rights, however, may not differ dramatically, even if the imputed sources do.
But must a human rights regime be restricted (or restrict itself) to protections of negative freedoms alone to be effective, to gain international assent and enforcement, as Ignatieff sometimes suggests? I am doubtful in light of the arguments (including many made by Ignatieff himself), the evidence of the origins of the Universal Declaration, and the apparent need to include rights to subsistence (which are not negative freedoms) to gain international assent to most human rights documents in the global arena. Although rights to subsistence and to basic political freedoms (due process, habeas corpus) are not negative liberties, they too are a necessary part of what it means to treat people as purposive agents, and to protect them against degrading treatment, of which dire poverty is certainly one form. A human rights regime still needs to avoid overextending itself beyond what are reasonable aspirations. But it also needs to avoid a minimalism so sparing that its enforcement would leave the most vulnerable people without what is (minimally) necessary to protect their ability to live a minimally decent life by any reasonable standards. Starving people are denied their human agency. They are also being denied their dignity, and they are being degraded. They are not being treated as agents with a human life to lead. There are many other ways to describe the gross injustice inflicted upon starving people in today's world, where there are ways both to prevent starvation and to address it when it occurs. What counts as minimal human rights is bound to be contentious, and broad assent is essential for effective enforcement. But there is good reason to think that an effective human rights regime needs to safeguard subsistence rights as well as a set of negative liberties.
Another reason to wonder whether we should hold human rights regimes to only the most minimalist standards is that problems of agreement, interpretation, and enforcement inhere even in the most minimalist formulations of human rights. Minimal
is not necessarily synonymous with maximally consensual
or easiest to enforce.
It may be easier to enlist agreement on a set of human rights that combine protections of negative freedoms with subsistence, and maybe even other welfare rights, than it is to insist on restricting a human rights regime to negative liberties alone. Ignatieff makes no such insistence, but he often argues or alludes to the idea that human agency supports only negative liberty. I have argued that human agency itself supports more than negative liberty. But my argument is only one of several that could be cited in defense of subsistence rights (and perhaps also more rights) as part of a human rights regime that is neither minimalist nor maximalist.
Despite the attraction of minimalism, it must be said that what counts as a minimal set of human rights is by no means either obvious or agreed upon by even good-willed people. Even the means of protecting people against cruel, inhuman, or degrading…punishment
is open to reasonable disagreement. When the Taliban stone women to death for adultery, this is about as clear a violation of a human right against cruel, inhuman, and degrading treatment as any. But does the United States violate a human right that belongs in the minimal set when its judicial system sentences people to death? Does capital punishment as practiced today in the United States constitute a human rights violation under Article 7? To answer in the affirmative, one need not think that capital punishment is equivalent to the worst atrocities committed by the Taliban. To answer in the negative, one need not approve of capital punishment or even be anything less than an ardent opponent of the practice. This example illustrates the problem of determining how to characterize even a minimal set of human rights. If capital punishment violates a minimal set of human rights, then it cannot be said that the minimal set is uncontroversial, or that it lends itself to effective international enforcement. The U.S. government is famous—or infamous, depending on one's perspective—for not acknowledging the legitimacy of human rights enforcement against its own authority on grounds that its authority is rooted in the consent of the governed
to constitutional democratic sovereignty. The example of capital punishment reveals that the sovereignty of a constitutional democratic regime is no guarantee against tyranny of the majority or minority. (Majorities often do not rule in democracies.) It also remains an open question as to whether more than minimal human rights—an avidly moderate regime of human rights—would fare better or worse by way of international agreement and enforcement.
An equally serious problem for human rights in the international arena—illustrated by the self-exemption of many societies from all or part of the human rights regime—is nationalism. Nationalism is often asserted as a human rights claim on behalf of a self-determining people.
Ignatieff perceptively argues that nationalism is a double-edged sword. Universalized as a human right, nationalism is conceived as the right of collective self-determination. This raises the question of whether collective self-determination is part of the minimal set of human rights because it is intrinsically valuable (for a self-determining people
) or because it is an instrument, a means (as human rights should be) for protecting individuals who share a society together against the worst cruelties that politically organized societies can inflict on individuals. The idea that secure states can better guarantee rights than any available alternative is an instrumental defense of collective self-determination, but not a defense of nationalism per se. To defend collective self-determination as a right that is instrumental to protecting individuals against cruelty, one need not believe that every people
has a right to its own self-determining society, which would permit it to exercise sovereignty over its members.
When a right to collective self-determination is identified with a defense of nationalism, understood as the self-determination of a people, the right loses its clear connection to protection of human agency against cruelty, oppression, and degradation. This is because, as Ignatieff recognizes, nationalism solves the human rights problems of the victorious national groups while producing new victim groups, whose human rights situation is made worse.
Collective self-determination needs to be distinguished from nationalism for it to qualify as a means of protecting all persons against the worst forms of cruelty and oppression. There is no right to victimize individuals in the name of being a people or nation. Nationalism is the response to one human rights problem and the creation of another because nations assume the authority to victimize individuals under the guise of their right to self-determination.
A human rights regime therefore cannot consistently defend nationalism—or the absolute sovereignty of a people—as what the human right of collective self-determination entails. Collective self-determination as a human right does not carry with it the authority to oppress minorities. Collective self-determination is a human right exercised in groups, which is conditional—as are all such group rights—on the group's respecting the other rights of individuals. Whenever collective self-determination is confused with national sovereignty in an unqualified sense, it increases the risk of other rights violations; indeed, it sometimes supports other rights violations. Human rights violations cannot be justified—or even condoned or excused—in the name of nationalism; human rights violations render nationalistic states subject to criticism, sanction, and, as a final resort, intervention.
Determining that a nation-state has violated basic human rights, however, does not tell us whether and what kind of criticism, sanction, or intervention is likely to succeed in improving the situation of oppressed individuals, which is, of course, the purpose of human rights as political instruments.
The most controversial—and sometimes the only potentially effective—response to persistent human rights violations by states is intervention. Under what conditions, Ignatieff therefore asks, is intervention justified to reverse human rights abuses within states? Like nationalism, intervention is a double-edged sword. It must be used sparingly lest it become an unintended excuse for human rights violations on the part of intervening states. Yet it must be used when it can be effective to stop (or at least significantly reduce) systematic and pervasive human rights abuses. This standard is far harder to apply than it is to articulate, and it is controversial in both theory and application. Human rights may be universal, but support for coercive enforcement of their norms will never be universal.
If this is realism, it is no recipe for isolationism. The failure to intervene in Rwanda, for example, where many lives could have been saved, was far from inevitable or justifiable. Such failures have undermined the credibility of human rights values in zones of danger around the world.
Arguments about when states should intervene to vindicate human rights are controversial for the obvious reason that so much is at stake in any decision about intervention. But