Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

From $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Nietzsche: A Beginner's Guide
Nietzsche: A Beginner's Guide
Nietzsche: A Beginner's Guide
Ebook271 pages5 hours

Nietzsche: A Beginner's Guide

Rating: 3.5 out of 5 stars

3.5/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Discover the truth about the much-misunderstood thinker

Often quoted yet highly divisive, Nietzsche remains an enigma long after his death. This clear primer moves deftly through the controversy to examine the philosopher's work in the context of his tumultuous childhood and Christian upbringing. Discussing his infamous declaration that God is dead, his posthumous association with Nazism, and his criticisms of conventional morality, this book is the ideal introduction to the much debated thinker and his extensive legacy.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateDec 1, 2012
ISBN9781780741703
Nietzsche: A Beginner's Guide
Author

Robert Wicks

Robert Wicks is Senior Lecturer in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Auckland, new Zealand. He specialises in Continental European philosophy and philosophical aesthetics, and has published both books and articles in these areas, including 'Nietzsche' (Oneworld 2002).

Read more from Robert Wicks

Related to Nietzsche

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Nietzsche

Rating: 3.6666667 out of 5 stars
3.5/5

3 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Nietzsche - Robert Wicks

    Nietzsche

    A Beginner’s Guide

    ONEWORLD BEGINNER’S GUIDES combine an original, inventive, and engaging approach with expert analysis on subjects ranging from art and history to religion and politics, and everything in between. Innovative and affordable, books in the series are perfect for anyone curious about the way the world works and the big ideas of our time.

    aesthetics

    africa

    anarchism

    aquinas

    art

    artificial intelligence

    the bahai faith

    the beat generation

    biodiversity

    bioterror & biowarfare

    the brain

    british politics

    the buddha

    cancer

    censorship

    christianity

    civil liberties

    classical music

    climate change

    cloning

    cold war

    conservation

    crimes against humanity

    criminal psychology

    critical thinking

    daoism

    democracy

    descartes

    dyslexia

    energy

    engineering

    the enlightenment

    epistemology

    evolution

    evolutionary psychology

    existentialism

    fair trade

    feminism

    forensic science

    french revolution

    genetics

    global terrorism

    hinduism

    history of science

    humanism

    islamic philosophy

    journalism

    judaism

    lacan

    life in the universe

    literary theory

    machiavelli

    mafia & organized crime

    magic

    marx

    medieval philosophy

    middle east

    NATO

    nietzsche

    the northern ireland conflict

    oil

    opera

    the palestine–israeli conflict

    paul

    philosophy of mind

    philosophy of religion

    philosophy of science

    planet earth

    postmodernism

    psychology

    quantum physics

    the qur’an

    racism

    renaissance art

    shakespeare

    the small arms trade

    the torah

    sufism

    volcanoes

    A Oneworld Book

    First Published by Oneworld Publications as

    Nietzsche (Oneworld Philosophers), 2002

    First published in the Beginner’s Guide series 2010

    This ebook edition published in 2012

    Copyright © Robert Wicks 2002

    The right of Robert Wicks to be identified as the Author of this work has been asserted by him in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988

    All rights reserved

    Copyright under Berne Convention

    A CIP record for this title is available from the British Library

    ISBN 978-1-85168-757-2

    ebook ISBN 978-1-78074-170-3

    Cover design by vaguelymemorable.com

    Oneworld Publications

    10 Bloomsbury Street, London, WC1B 3SR England

    Stay up to date with the latest books, special offers, and exclusive content from Oneworld with our monthly newsletter

    Sign up on our website

    www.oneworld-publications.com

    The ideal of the most exuberant, life-filled, world-affirming person, who has not only learned to make peace with and to tolerate, what was and is, but who wants further to have just how it was and is repeated throughout all eternity, insatiably calling out "da capo," not only to himself, but to the entire performance and show.

    Beyond Good and Evil, §56

    Cynicism is the unique form in which unpolished souls can come into contact with what honesty is. And the higher ones should open their ears to every coarse and refined piece of cynicism, and consider it fortunate, when the joker without shame or the scientific satyr speaks out to them.

    Beyond Good and Evil, §26

    I do not want to be a saint; better to be a jester. Perhaps I am a jester.

    Ecce Homo, Why I am an Inevitability, §1

    I am a disciple of the philosopher Dionysus; I’d prefer to be a satyr, rather than a saint.

    Ecce Homo, Preface

    For Catherine, Florence, Elaine and Charles

    Contents

    Preface

    1 The churchyard echoes of Röcken

    2 The worship of wildlife

    3 God’s death

    4 Dissolving the shadows of God

    5 Nietzsche’s seduction of truth

    6 Embracing life versus embracing existence

    7 The contemporary shadows of Nietzsche

    Conclusion: Nietzsche, the jester of metamorphosis

    Glossary

    Notes

    Bibliography

    Index

    Preface

    Some problems are universal. Alexandra David-Néel (1868–1969) – the first European woman to explore the Tibetan capital of Lhasa (in 1924, in disguise) – was once given the same pragmatic advice by an unnamed hermit in the remote Himalayan wilderness as was offered to Nietzsche’s fictional character, Zarathustra, when he expressed his own desire to communicate his mountaintop-inspired thoughts to the general population. The hermit counselled David-Néel to resist publishing her knowledge of the secret oral teachings in Tibetan Buddhist sects, because it probably would be a wasted effort. The teachings could be published surely enough, but they would remain secret nonetheless, for few ears would be in tune with their message. Like Nietzsche’s Thus Spoke Zarathustra – A Book for All and None (1883–85), David-Néel would be writing from the spiritual heights an essentially closed book, and would be offering an invitation to be misunderstood, neglected, and possibly condemned.

    Having decided to brush against the social fiber, both David-Néel – religious scholar, adventurer, person-of-wisdom, and a prime candidate for a Nietzschean superhuman in her own right – and Zarathustra made light of the soberly hermetic advice and proceeded to put their thoughts into writing. Nietzsche’s philosophy, in particular, ended up expressing the frustration of the perennial tension between sociality and individuality, along with the uneasy interdependency between respectable tradition and the irreverent avant-garde. Nietzsche’s external life might have been unassuming, but he often experienced at a spiritual level the solitude of the absolute monarch whose distanced position requires the sacrifice of equal-to-equal friendships and comfortable community.

    And thus was his Zarathustra written 6000 feet beyond people and time, from a perspective that few, if any, of us will ever be able to appreciate abundantly from the inside. Perhaps Friedrich Nietzsche will never be understood as he wished to be understood, for how difficult it is to overcome, or go perspectivally above, almost every ideal type that human culture has set forth to date as a matter of spiritual nourishment and cultural integration – above the ascetic priest, above the great-souled, magnanimous person of classical virtue, above the recognitions bestowed by worldly fame, above the greatest actors, actresses, and musicians, and above most of what we imagine to be the worthy dedications of our lives.

    Perhaps Nietzsche was somewhat mistaken about his having been able to discern future social tendencies and, very possibly, over-zealous in his dedication to set forth the optimal conditions for a reinvigorating, down-to-earth health and flourishing. Such shortcomings would, fortunately, have the effect of rendering his thought more accessible than a more perfect realization of it might have allowed. And yet, despite its limitations, Nietzsche offers us some trying challenges, most of which amount to a dare to define ourselves realistically as complicated, living, now-existing, perishable, and thoroughly embodied creative creatures, as opposed to being a set of purely rational, eternal, and essentially simple souls, which are thought to be spatially, temporally, and only temporarily incarcerated in an alien physicality. Nietzsche longed for release and redemption within this world, not another one; he longed for what he took to be real, rather than imaginary, freedom.

    Some of the themes treated in this survey of Nietzsche’s outlook – his doctrines of eternal recurrence, the will to power, the superhuman, the death of God, perspectivism, his critique of Christian morality, his intellectual relationships to Immanuel Kant and Arthur Schopenhauer, his friendship with Richard Wagner, his influence on contemporary European thought – have been individually treated by numerous Nietzsche scholars in longer, more detailed works. The bibliography will, I hope, direct those whose interest in Nietzsche has been stimulated by this study to enhance and transform their appreciation of his radical ideas. Of special note is the impeccable work of Maudemarie Clark, whose attention to Nietzsche’s theory of knowledge has influentially structured the perspective offered here. I am also indebted to an anonymous reviewer of the manuscript and to my colleague at the University of Auckland, John Bishop, both of whom provided perceptive and constructively detailed criticisms of each chapter. My own approach to Nietzsche tends to reflect an interest in the existential and psychological import of philosophical theories.

    Nietzsche’s multi-layered texts present a formidable task for anyone who intends to outline their general contours. It is hoped that despite the very wide differences in interpretation among scholars, the present work succeeds in portraying the importance of change, expansion, self-criticism, and life-energies within his philosophy. It can be said that Friedrich Nietzsche was the jester of metamorphosis, and that final interpretations of his thought run contrary to the unpredictable, tempting, and sometimes contemptible spirit of the mythic trickster. So this book is best regarded as one entrance into the fiery carnival of Nietzsche’s thought, rather than as an ending, conclusion, or cap.

    I extend further thanks to those teachers, scholars, friends, and students, living and deceased, who have motivated and encouraged my reflections on Nietzsche’s philosophy from an assortment of life’s angles: William H. Hay †, Herbert Garelick, Kathleen Higgins, Jack Kline, Graham Parkes, Roger Peters, Jason Pilkington, Martin Schwab, Ivan Soll, Robert C. Solomon, Stephen Solnick, Paul Warren, Craig Wattam, Kenneth Westphal, Terry Winant, Julian Young, and Mitchell and Jill Zingman.

    I also thank especially those Helens of Troy whose awakening presence in my life helped me appreciate Nietzsche’s immaculate conception of Apollonian women: Gladys Eugenia Bustos-Giraldo, Susan Beth Silverberg, and Lisa Michelle Thompson.

    The translations from the original German texts are my own.

    Auckland, New Zealand

    September 2001

    1

    The churchyard echoes of Röcken

    From Jerusalem to Athens

    If, as a Friedrich Nietzsche aficionado, one makes the honored birthplace pilgrimage to the German town of Röcken, one will be struck by the unassuming plainness of the roadside village. Röcken, located in the pastoral farmlands south of Leipzig, is a town too small for most maps: the village’s more expanded name is Röcken bei Lützen (Röcken near Lützen), and one will inevitably make one’s way first to Lützen. After passing through this moderate-sized community, a small cluster of buildings will soon appear alongside the main road, and if one’s eyes are keen, one will pick out a church building nestling among them. It was in this churchyard that Friedrich Nietzsche played as a boy, and it was in the large house next to the church – the one designated for the pastor and his family – where Nietzsche was born on 15 October 1844. Today, over a century and a half later, it is maintained as a historical site.

    Nietzsche’s childhood was steeped in Lut heranism. His great-grandfather was a Lutheran minister, as were both of his grandfathers, as was his father. Little Nietzsche imagined that he would become a minister as well. One can imagine the youngster peeking through the doorway as his father gave his Sunday sermons, and maybe, as any child in such circumstances might, playing around the pulpit during the quiet countryside afternoons. The intimacy of the humble church and its surroundings is distinctive, and during the off-hours, the child could only have made himself familiar with every inch of the church’s interior, which was situated literally in his family’s backyard. In a real sense, Friedrich Nietzsche began his life in church.

    Although Nietzsche’s childhood appears to have been predominantly happy, it was also unforgettably stamped with death. When Nietzsche was approaching his fifth birthday, his father died from a brain ailment, and within only six months, the life of Nietzsche’s younger brother, Joseph, who was only two years old, was ended by sickness as well. This was a terrible time for Nietzsche, as his own reported nightmares confirm.¹ Throughout his life, death’s shadow followed Nietzsche in the images of his father and little brother.

    With the death of Röcken’s pastor, the Nietzsche family moved to the nearby city of Naumburg, where Friedrich lived with his mother, his sister, his two aunts, and his grandmother, until he entered the prestigious Schulpforta boarding school at the age of fourteen. It is fair to say that Nietzsche’s dramatic loss of significant male figures within his household at an early age, side-by-side with an overdetermination of living female figures, had a formative and lasting influence on his psyche.

    The academic atmosphere at Schulpforta was disciplined and cloisterlike, and in a broad sense, Nietzsche’s environment did not radically change: Schulpforta opened his imagination to the Greek and Latin classics, but he remained in the Christian rural world and continued to be nurtured on Lutheran values – ones which soon became amalgamated with affectionate feelings for his German homeland. During these teenage years, Nietzsche and a few of his friends formed a tiny club which they named Germania, the activities of which included a fateful subscription to a contemporary music periodical.

    Through the club’s subscription to the music journal, the Zeitschrift für Musik, Nietzsche became familiar with the compositions of Richard Wagner (1813–83) – a composer whose works embodied many of the religious and cultural themes that captured the young Nietzsche’s heart, and for whom Nietzsche would develop a tremendous admiration in the years to come. Although he would never compare to Wagner as a composer, Nietzsche was not without considerable musical sensitivity, and by the time he reached his late teens he was writing music that could be played or sung respectably in church. Many of his compositions were stylistically reminiscent of those by Robert Schumann (1810–56), and can easily be mistaken for them by the naïve ear. At this time in his life, Lutheranism, choral and piano music, academic studies, and Germany, all coalesced within Nietzsche’s mind.

    To understand the transformations that occurred in Nietzsche’s life once he entered college, we can reflect for a moment on some of the Christian ideas with which he grew up. One of the first that was impressed upon him – one not unique to Christianity, and which is at least as ancient as the Egyptians and their pyramidic tombs – was the concept of a world beyond the earthly one we inhabit, conceived of as a place to which people’s souls travel after their mundane death. Immediately after his father’s funeral, Nietzsche received a benevolent letter from a Lutheran pastor assuring him that his father, now standing before the throne of the Heavenly Father, continued to look down upon him from the higher world, wishing him well. At a very early age, he was impressed with the concepts of God, death, and the afterlife.

    Another religious idea that entered Nietzsche’s highly reflective mind, and which appears significantly in his later writings, is the persistent question of why a Heavenly Father would allow not only his own father to be taken from him, but also his innocent two-year-old brother. Christians have struggled to find an adequate solution to this problem of evil, and witnessing the death of his younger brother only made the problem more dramatic for Nietzsche. From an early age, he was exposed to questions surrounding the meaning of life, of death, and of the world itself, all set within the atmosphere of accepting the existence of a morally good, all-seeing being called the Heavenly Father who was defined by his own fatherly elders as the object of unconditional love. In sum, Friedrich Nietzsche grew up as a Christian, and his personal life was marked by tragic events which eventually led him to question the Christian outlook and valuation of life, including the idea that the cosmos is, at its core, morally and good-naturedly constituted.

    In 1864, when he entered the University of Bonn as a theology and philology student at the age of nineteen, life changed for Nietzsche. Not only was he situated relatively far from home for the first time, his university studies in philology also took a deep hold upon him. These drew his scholarly interests further away from the study of biblical texts towards that of the Greek and Latin classics – a field into which he been initiated at Schulpforta. Nietzsche was reborn in Bonn, for he loosened the bonds of the church-related world he inherited from his father and his rural upbringing, and soon developed what turned out to be a lifelong affection for Athens and Rome, always set in an uneasy and ambivalent contrast to Hebraic and Arabic Jerusalem. It is well-known that Nietzsche ranted against Christianity at the end of his career, but his attitude towards Middle Eastern culture in general was less cut and dried: while scorning institutionalized Christianity and its roots in Judaism, Nietzsche discerned important virtues in both the Hebrew Scriptures and in Christian asceticism, and he later chose as the figurehead for his own philosophic vision the character of Zarathustra, the Persian prophet of Zoroastrianism. The prophetic Nietzsche derived much of his historical inspiration from the Middle East, despite his condemnation of the highly institutionalized European Christianity that later prevailed closer to his home in Germany.

    Despite the various doctrinal changes that were to characterize his philosophical thought, Nietzsche’s love of music remained rock-solid, and in Bonn he developed his artistic interests, along with his attraction to the classics. Nietzsche studied with a biographer of Mozart, Otto Jahn (1813–69), who was the same age Nietzsche’s father would have been, and who had been academically trained by Karl Lachmann (1793–1851), a well-known philologist of the time. Lachmann specialized in the Roman philosopher Lucretius (98–55 BC), and in the study of textual recension – a genealogical dimension of philology which determines the original authorship of texts by comparing and contrasting secondary and derivative versions. This idea of genealogy would later become central to Nietzsche’s own philosophical style. Nietzsche was also taught by Friedrich Ritschl (1806–76), a specialist in the Roman classics, who was particularly expert on the Roman comic poet Plautus (254–184 BC).² All of these subjects – classics of tragedy and comedy, genealogy, music, philology – remained with Nietzsche for the rest of his scholarly life.

    During his university studies in the mid-1860s, Nietzsche made the momentous encounter, either through the legacy of their books or in person, of two of the most influential figures of his life – the recently deceased Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) and the still living Richard Wagner (1813–83). Both men became his heroes, but sharing the fate of many heroes and idealized father-figures, they were to be replaced by others whom he grew to idealize, ultimately being unseated by the notion of a larger-than-life, super-healthy type of Nietzsche’s own creation. In the end, as we shall see, having become disillusioned with existing examples, Nietzsche became his own teacher, and styled for himself his own ideal in the form of the superhuman, or Übermensch – a super-healthy, super-strong, and yet far from supernatural type. As the years went on, he tended to measure famous individuals against this idealization, offering his applause for Caesar, Napoleon, Goethe, Dostoevski, Thucydides, and the Sophists, while at the same time roasting characters such as Rousseau, Hugo, Sand, Michelet, Zola, Renan, Carlyle, Mill, Eliot, Darwin, and Dante.

    In 1865, when still at the outset of his intellectual odyssey, the twenty-one-year-old Nietzsche came across Arthur Schopenhauer’s The World as Will and Representation, which had originally been published forty-seven years earlier, in 1818. Schopenhauer achieved fame only at the end of his life, however, and his name was a new and fashionable one within academically-legitimated circles when Nietzsche discovered him for himself. Schopenhauer’s philosophy revealed to the still-impressionable Nietzsche a way to interpret the world that, despite having an atheistic twist, shared much of the Christian sentiment with which Nietzsche grew up, as well as the classical Greek philosophy with which he had become enamored. While retaining in substance the traditional Christian moral imperative to resist harming others, Schopenhauer advanced a metaphysical vision that was at odds with Christianity: in the place of an all-powerful, all-knowing, and all-good God at the ruling center of the universe, Schopenhauer substituted a blind, aimless, and fundamentally senseless energetic urge that he could describe as nothing more than the blind force of sheer will.

    Schopenhauer did not explain this will in reference to physical forces. He turned the usual conception inside-out, and explained physical forces in reference to the manifestation of an essentially non-physical will, which he defined as the inner force that metaphysically underlies all things in the cosmos, just as one’s conscious will is the inner force that motivates and animates one’s observable bodily actions.

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1