HUMAN RIGHTS IN CHINA: THE CASE OF WEI JINGSHENG By Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Arts (Asian Studies) with Honours. I thank both my supervisors, Dr Colin Jeffcott and Dr Pierre Ryckmans for their assistance throughout the year.
HUMAN RIGHTS IN CHINA: THE CASE OF WEI JINGSHENG By Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Arts (Asian Studies) with Honours. I thank both my supervisors, Dr Colin Jeffcott and Dr Pierre Ryckmans for their assistance throughout the year.
HUMAN RIGHTS IN CHINA: THE CASE OF WEI JINGSHENG By Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Arts (Asian Studies) with Honours. I thank both my supervisors, Dr Colin Jeffcott and Dr Pierre Ryckmans for their assistance throughout the year.
HUMAN RIGHTS IN CHINA: THE CASE OF WEI JINGSHENG By Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Arts (Asian Studies) with Honours. I thank both my supervisors, Dr Colin Jeffcott and Dr Pierre Ryckmans for their assistance throughout the year.
Copyright:
Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 301
i
HUMAN RIGHTS IN CHINA:
THE CASE OF WEI JINGSHENG
By
K.M. Rudd
Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Arts (Asian Studies) with Honours - taken jointly in the Departments of Chinese and East Asian History and Civilizations.
Australian National University 1980
ii
To my mother.
iii
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I thank both my supervisors, Dr Colin Jeffcott and
Dr Pierre Ryckmans for their assistance throughout the
year. I also thank the other members of the Department
of Chinese who have always been willing to help me when
I have encountered difficulties in my translations.
Mrs Elizabeth McNaughton has, with great patience, typed
this thesis. Dr Wong Yin-wai has written the Chinese
characters, including the frontpiece. I am grateful to
'" "
both these people. Finally, I thank Therese for her
invaluable personal support.
iv
TABLE OF CONTENTS
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
INTRODUCTION
PART A
CHAPTER ONE
HUMAN RIGHTS: AN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE
CHAPTER TWO
THE HUMAN RIGHTS MOVEMENT 1978-79
CHAPTER THREE
WEI JINGSHENG ON HUMAN RIGHTS
CHAPTER FOUR
THE OFFICIAL RESPONSE
CONCLUSION
PART B
A COMPLETE TRANSLATION OF THE TRIAL OF WEI JINGSHENG
APPENDIX
A LIST OF BEIJING'S UNOFFICIAL JOURNALS BETWEEN DECEMBER 1978 AND MAY 1979
NOTES
BIBLIOGRAPHY
GLOSSARY
iii
vi
1
44
81
110
142
151
235
238
260
283
v
'Let the people speak out. The heavens will
not fall'.
(People's Daily 3 January 1979)
'There are no such things as rights without
duties or duties without rights ... We must
have freedom of speech but this does not
mean we need not listen to reason'.
(Guangming Daily 20 March 1979)
'Our bill of indictment makes the point very
clearly that you will not be punished because
of your theoretical enquiries or because you
do not believe in Harxism. It is your
counter-revolutionary activities that we are
punishing. You yourself can see this point.
The Constitution prescribes certain things.
It prescribes freedom of belief. You can
disbelieve Marxism-Leninism-Mao Zedong
thought. You can also believe it. But you
are definitely not permitted to oppose it. To
oppose it would be to violate the Constitution
and if you violate the Constitution, you must
be punished. On this point our position is
clear.
(The Public Prosecutor addressing Wei Jingsheng in Wei's trial on 16 October 1979)
vi
INTRODUCTION
In his inauguration as the thirty-ninth President of
the United States of America, James Earle Carter stated:
Because we are free we can never be indifferent
to the fate of freedom elsewhere. Our moral sense dictates a clare-cut preference for those societies which share with us an a£iding respect for individual human rights.
Since that time, the terms 'human rights' and 'violation of
human rights' have become increasingly commonplace in the
vocabulary used in the conduct of international relations.
However, there is much ambiguity as to what these terms mean.
Both the U.S.S.R. and the U.S.A. are signatories to the
1975 Helsinki Accords on Human Rights. But when Pravda writes
that the Soviet government is 'guaranteeing the Soviet people's
human rights' and when the U.S. State Department decries the
treatment of Andrei Sakharov as a 'gross violation of his
human rights', there are fundamentally different notions
involved. It is therefore necessary to define what we mean
when we use the term 'human rights'.
The notion of 'human rights' has its modern origins in
the philosophical writings of the Enlightenment. The
philosophers of that time had revived a notion which had been
originally formulated by the Stoics of the third century B.C.
With the decline of the city-state, the Stoics began to
emphasize 'man the individual' as opposed to 'man the fraction
of the polity' - a concept that had been expounded by Plato
. 1 . 2
two centurles ear ler.
The Stoics also conceived of a law
validated by the natural order which determined right from
wrong. This 'natural law' was universal in its application
and eternal in its authority. The Stoics conceived that this
vii
natural law dictated that all men were equals and that
therefore equality was man's 'natural right'. Because man's
natural rights were derived from natural law, they too were seen both as universal and eternal.3
Two thousand years later, John Locke revived these
concepts of natural law and natural rights. In His Second
Treatise on Government he argued that by virtue of natural
law, the individual possessed rights of 'life, liberty and
estate'. He argued that government existed for the purpose
of preserving these rights of the individual. He also argued
that a government should be assessed on the basis of the
degree to which it enhanced the individual's opportunity to realize these rights.4
These ideas found expression in the Bill of Rights of
1688 which required the monarch to 'preserve them (the
people) from the violation of their rights •.. and from other attempts upon their religious rights and liberties,.5 England
became the symbol of liberalism for the philosophers of the
Old and New Worlds. In the American colonies, the Virginia
Bill of Rights of 1776, the Declaration of Independence of
1776 and United States Constitution of 1789 all asserted the
rights of the individual over the rights of the state. In
France, the Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen
of 1789 stated explicitly that:
The purpose of all civil associations is the preservation of the natural and imprescriptable rights of man. These rights are liberty, - prosperity and resistance to oppression.6
Such were the models for the constitutions of Europe which
were drafted during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries -
constitutions which enshrined the primacy of the individual.
viii
This constitutional recognition of the natural rights
of the individual was challenged by such philosophers as
Hume, Burke, Bentham, Austin and Hegel. They argued that
rights were the property of the collective rather than the
individual and that these collective rights were not validated
by natural law. These ideas are reflected in such documents
as the German Declaration of Rights of 1848 which referred,
not to the rights of man (the individual), but to the rights 7
of the German people. These ideas are also reflected in the
reasoning of one Karl Marx.
Therefore, by the twentieth century, there existed two
diametrically opposed notions of rights: one which emphasized
the rights of the individual and one which emphasized the
preeminence of the rights of the collective. This fundamental
difference was symbolized in 1948 when the Soviet bloc refused
to ratify the Universal Declaration of Rights which proclaimed
twenty-nine 'equal and inalienable rights of all members of
the human family'. However, when we in the West use the term
'human rights' today, I maintain that we are essentially
drawing upon the Lockeian principles of rights which are
inalienable, rights of life, liberty and property, and rights
which are preeminent over any duty which the individual owes
the collective.
Given that this is our understanding of human rights,
in this account I propose to examine various Chinese notions
of human rights. First, I will examine the evolving notion
of rights through the imperial, republican and communist
periods; second, I will examine the notions of rights
expounded by Wei Jingsheng during the wallposter movement
ix
in Beijing between November 1978 and March 1979; third,
I will examine the Party's response to that movement.
There are a number of limitations involved in
undertaking an analysis of this kind. Our knowledge of
the wallposter movement is primarily dependent upon a
number of foreign journalists stationed in Beijing at the
time. While they were undoubtedly dedicated to their
profession, their coverage of the movement was incomplete
by virtue of insurmountable physical limitations: there
were literally thousands of posters appearing at a number
of different locations in the capital. Therefore-their
coverage was, of necessity, selective. The limitations which
this imposes are made more acute by the fact that not all of
these journalists' dispatches found their way into print,
and of those that did, there is the possibility that they
were edited. Given these difficulties, I have nonetheless
collated a cross-section of reports appearing in the press
in Hong Kong, the united Kingdom and the United States over
a six-month period, in an attempt to systematically analyse
the development of the wallposter movement.
Another set of limitations concerns the unofficial
pUblications which appeared during the movement. I have
had access to a combination of originals, photocopies,
reproductions and translations. There is always the
possibility that some of these documents have been
consciously or unconsciously edited in the process of
t .. 8 ransmlSSlon.
There is also the possibility of forgery.
And in the final analysis, there is no reliable method of
substantiating the authenticity of these documents. As
for Wei's journal, I have access to photocopies of each
x
of its editions, reprints in various Hong Kong Magazines accounting for about three-quarters of its total contents and various translations which account for about the
same proportion. Although I have found the photocopies of the original at times indecipherable, they have been useful in clarifying any inconsistencies arising from a comparison of the reprints and the translations. As for journals other than Wei's, I have not had sufficiently complete collections in original, reprint and translation form to undertake the same kind of comparison. For these journals, I have essentially relied upon the available translations.
A final limitation is one which is not unique to this account. Given that we have no access to Chinese government documents, a great deal of speculation must be made as to the nature of internal political developments on the basis of articles appearing in the official press. For this account the problem is more acute because of the contemporaneous nature of the topic. As will become evident, conjecture plays a prominent part in my analysis
of the regime's response to the movement.
Given all of these limitations, what follows is, I believe, a comprehensive treatment of the three themes
which have been outlined above - drawing upon the unofficial press, the official press and at times the left wing press in Hong Kong. I am aware that a number of works are about to appear on the subject of the wallposter movement.8 I have not referred to any of them. This analysis is original.
CHAPTER ONE
RIGHTS: AN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE
2
Wei Jingsheng did not introduce the concept of the
inalienable rights of the individual to China. The general
concept of rights had been introduced over a century before
by W.A.P. Martin in his translation of Wheaton's Elements of International Law in 1864.1 However, the fact remains
that the concept was introduced. It was not indigenous.
There was no classical Chinese term or terms which Martin
could draw upon to accurately translate the concept of
-!:~ 1 1
'rights'. His selection of quanli ( 1~1t. f ) seems
arbitrary. Quan is usually translated as 'power' and Ii
as
'profit,.2
There is no obvious connection between the
Western understanding of 'rights' and a combination of these
concepts of 'power' and 'profit'. Nor is there any
connection between 'rights' and either of these concepts
individually: 'rights' cannot be equated with 'power', nor can it be equated with 'profit,.3 The inability of the
classical lexicon to express this new notion of 'rights'
was itself a reflection of a fundamental difference between
the Chinese and the Western concepts of the relationship
between the individual and the collective. The concept
introduced by Martin presupposed the primacy of the
individual whereas for two thousand years, Confucian China
had taught not the primacy of the individual but the
primacy of that individual's responsibility to society.
nWERIAL CHINA
Confucianism became the institutional orthodoxy of the
Chinese Empire during the Han dynasty. It remained the
principal strain in Chinese political thinking for over
two thousand years. Confucianism contained no notion of
3
the rights of the individual. Rather, it prescribed the
duties to be performed by one individual to another - or
more accurately, by one class of individuals to another
class. These classes were arranged in a hierarchy.
At the apex of the hierarchy was the ruler: 'the north
pole star, which keeps its place while all other stars turn to it,.4 His relationship with his subjects was defined in
terms of reciprocal duties:
'The
ruler should employ his Ii (~t) and the subj ect ( ~. ) ,.5 Li may be
subject according to the rules of
should serve his ruler with zhong
rendered as 'propriety' and zhong as 'loyalty'. In
Confucian rhetoric, there was a clear distinction between
loyalty and obedience. Zhong did not imply unconditional
obedience to the ruler. Rather, it implied 'action in the ruler's interests' 6 - the nu Le r's moral interests. As to
who decided what was in the rulers moral interest, that,
technically at least, was the prerogativaofthe individual.
The reciprocal duty of Ii is a much wider concept. Li
implies refinement through the practice of ritual and
ceremony. Li also implies regulation - a ruler's
regulation of society for the satisfaction of his subjects
d. 7
eSlres.
A ruler employing his subjects according to the
rules of Ii seems to have both these ceremonial and
regulatory connotations. When zhong and Ii are being
correctly performed, the subject is truly a subject and the
ruler is truly a ruler. Then, says Confucius, 'there is government' - zheng ("if:.t).
Wang Gungwuhasargued that the reciprocity of the
relationship between ruler and subject carries with it an
implicit notion of rights: the 'right' of the ruler was his
4
subject's loyalty and the 'right' of the subject was to be
treated with propriety by his ruler. Wang further argues
that there is a conditionality about these rights: A ruler
cannot expect loyalty unless propriety is evident in his
dealings with his subjects. This argument is supported by
Confucius' statement that 'when rulers have to observe the
rules of propriety, the people respond readily to calls on them for service,.9 However, while zhong may be accepted
as the indisputable right of the ruler, it seems more
tenuous to claim that li is worthy of the assignation 'right'.
Li may well regulate how a subject is treated by his ruler
but it does not challenge the more fundamental principle of
the ultimate political primacy of the ruler. In fact, li
presupposes that primacy. Li serves as little more than a
moral deterrent against the excesses of monarchy - a monarchy which it does not set out to challenge.1Q
Even if this notion of implicit rights is accepted, it
seems to have had little actual effect in restraining the
dictatorial tendencies of successive Chinese emperors. There
was never any doubt as to which of these rights-cum-duties
was the most important. Loyalty was always pre-eminent. In
time, the actual distinction between loyalty and obedience
became less pronounced. By the Song, a Classic of Loyalty
(Zhong jing) had been written which asserted that 'even if
the ruler does not act like a ruler, the subject may not but
b l' k b i 11
act ut 1 e a su Ject .
Any notion of conditionality had
been lost. Loyalty was now an absolute duty and failure to
be loyal was subject to punishment according to the 'Five
, h I ( i ncr ) 12
PunlS ments WU xlng .
Loyalty, in effect, increasingly
5
implied an unconditional obedience to the dictates of the
ruler. Such unconditional obedience is absolutely anti-
thetical to any notion of the rights of the individual.
However, Confucian despotism was mitigated by a number
of other factors. One such factor was the so called 'right
to revolt'. Mencius was asked:
'Is it permitted fora subject to kill a ruler?' He replied: 'One who violates benevolence is a thief and one who violates righteousness is a tyrant. A thief or a tyrant is called a common scoundrel. I have heard that a common scoundrel Zhou13 was killed. I have never heard of anybody killing a ruler,.14
A ruler was only a ruler so long as he behaved like a ruler -
that is through ruling according to the principles of
righteousness and benevolence. When he failed to do so, he
could not longer be considered as a ruler. Under those
circumstances, he was said to have lost Heaven's mandate to
rule. As to how he could be aware of Heaven's attitude
towards him, Mencius went on to say that 'Heaven sees as my people see, Heaven hears as my people hear,.15 Political
stability was a sign of Heaven's approval whereas popular
rebellions were signs of an impending withdrawal of heaven's
mandate. However, the peoples' 'right to rebel' was contingent
upon how accurately they had perceived the ruler's moral
decline. And their accuracy of perception was either
vindicated or invalidated by the eventual success or failure
of their rebellion.
Therefore, in terms of concrete political realities, this
celebrated 'right to rebel' seems little more than a case of
successful treason being treason no longer. Like the ruler's
exortation to proper b e'hav i.ouz , the 'right to rebel' was
primarily a moral constraint on monarchical despotism. At
6
no time was this moral constraint translated into effective
constitutional safeguards. That is to say, the 'right to
rebel' carried with it no notion of popular sovereignty
through the exercise of popular rights.
A second factor mitigating imperial despotism was
ministerial dissent. Confucius said that:
What is called a great minister is one who serves his prince according to what is right and when he finds he cannot do so, retires.16
Here, dao (ill) has been translated as 'right'. Dao suggests an unwavering principle to which all things should aspire.
The minister's commitment to this principle was to take
precedence over his loyalty to the ruler. Confucius went on
to ask whether 'there can be loyalty (zhong) which does not lead to admonishment of its object,17 - its object being the
ruler.
If the minister's admonitions went unheeded, he was
expected to resignr
The Minister Tsze-wan thrice took office and manifested no joy in his countenance. Thrice he retired .•.. He was loyal (zhong) '.18
Confucius, therefore, explicitly states that remonstration
and resignation are legitimate forms of dissent - dissent
which falls within the wider context of ministerial loyalty.
The minister determined the moral nature of a given
situation and the minister alone determined the appropriate
moral response: either approval or censure.
In this sense,
he was a morally autonomous man.
The most famous example of collective ministerial dissent
is that of the Donglin Academy during the last decades of the Ming dynasty.19 The academy was a group of active and
retired ministers who shared a common zeal for the moral
7
reform of government. Between 1620-3, their zeal became
particularly directed against the eunuch dictator Wei
Zhongxian who had become the power behind the throne of
the Emperor Xi Zong. To the academy, Wei epitomized moral
evil and evil had to be eliminated so that good could
prevail. Their programme was simply one of 'throwing the
rascals out' so that men of moral integrity could return to
government. Their's was a moral crusade rather than a
campaign for institutional reform. It failed because moral
protest lacked institutional protection and they themselves
did not seek to introduce measures to provide such safeguards.
It also failed because the academy was accused of forming
a faction (dang).
In the Confucian tradition, political
partisanship of any description was invariably equated with
sedition. As the Analects (Lunyu) recorded: 'The superior
man is dignified but does not wrangle. He is
not partisan'.
(qun er bu dang)
sociable but
rif ) .21
\~~~
Partisanship, irrespective of intent, was dang and dang by
definition was evil. This unequivocably perjorative
connotation of dang served as an effective counter-measure
against the emergence of any notion of a loyal opposition.
The ultimate demise of the Donglin
Academy served notice
that moral opposition without institutional protection could
never be an effective check on the growth of imperial
despotism. Morally autonomous men were of little avail in
the world of 'realpolitik'.
There was, therefore, no explicit notion of the rights of
the individual in dynastic Confucianism. Of course there
were other philosophical traditions in imperial China. The
8
Daoist's (Dao jia) pietistic retreat into himself was
perhaps a type of individual liberty. But it was more an
escape from the prevailing order rather than a challenge to
that order. The Buddhists
(Fo jia) challenged that order
and suffered three great persecutions as a result. Legalists
(Fa jia) were perhaps more ardent advocates of the pre-
eminence of the state over the individual than were the
Confucians themselves.
But Confucianism remained unassailed as an imperial
orthodoxy. The social hierarchy which Confucianism prescribed
was itself antithetical to any notion of equality. Within
that hierarchy, unequal persons were linked by unequal duties.
Both inside and outside of government, loyalty invariably
meant obedience - an obedience vaguely tempered by a number
of moral constraints. The absence of any effective legal
protection of the individual against the arbitrary abuse of
power by the state lends credence to Wittfogel's interpretation of Imperial China as an archetypal oriental despotism.22
REPUBLICANISM - PRE 1911
Following humiliating defeats in the 'Opium Wars' of
1839-42 and 1856-60, China embarked upon a campaign of
military and industrial self strengthening. Feng Guifen, a
prime-mover in this se.lf strengthening movement (ziqiang
yundong), had clearly stated its raison d'etre in 1861:
Why are the western nations small and yet strong? Why are we large and yet weak? We must search for means to become their equal ... we should use the instruments of the barbarians, but not adopt the ways of the barbarians. We should use them so that we can repel them.23
That this selective westernization failed in the
realization of its objectives was brought horne by the
9
humiliating terms imposed on China by the Japanese with the
Treaty of Shimonoseki in 1895. Chinese intellectuals then
turned their attention to a more fundamental reform: that
of their institutions and their ideology. They reasoned
that the institutions and ideology of the west were at the
very heart of western wealth and power. For China 'to
become their equal' would require an assimilation of these
things. Therefore, this generation of Chinese reformers
came to address themselves to notions of liberalism,
parliamentary democracy and more fundamentally, the rights
of the individual. These were not ends in themselves. They
were means toward an end. And that end wa s national power.
The reformers' understanding of rights was influenced
both by their own classical tradition and the example of
Meiji Japan which by the 1890's was hardly a model of
classical western liberalism. An excerpt from a Hunanese
reformist paper in 1897 shows something of the reformer's
preoccupation with the duties of a citizen rather than his
rights:
What would it be like to establish a national assembly (guo hui) ... the national assembly represents the people's public duty (gong yi). But it is representative of popular rights (min quan) ... It (the national assembly) precisely means popular rights. Besides, popular rights is popular duty ... If the people lack rights they cannot devote themselves to public duty.
If they do manage their own undertakings, then the sovereign's authority will reach its utmost ... , the people will avoid becoming slaves of another race.
In this way there can be no severing of the connection between the ruler's sovereignty and popular sovereignty. 24
Rights are validated by their equation with duty. And rights
are valid insofar as they enhance the state's power and
protect the state from foreign sUbjugation. To be sure,
10
parliament is to be concerned both w i, th public duty and
popular rights but the latter are not seen as an absolute
value. A commitment to rights for their own intrinsic sake
is a necessary characteristic of classical Western
liberalism.
Kang Youwei conceived of China passing through three
great ages: the 'Age of Disorder', the 'Age of Order' and
the 'Age of Great Peace' respectively characterized by
absolute monarchy, constitutional monarchy and republicanism.
One age inevitably evolved into the next. 'The present time',
he said, 'is the Age of Order. It is therefore necessary ... to
discuss publicly the matter of constitutional government.
If the laws are not reformed, great disorder will result,.25
Kang's constitutional monarchy was to have representative
institutions whose members would be elected by the people.
But these reforms were seen in terms of their ability to
I' h t ' 26. th f f h . . f
unlte t e grea mass ln e ace 0 t e eXlgencles 0
the time. They were also seen in terms of realizing the
'Great Peace' which Kang saw as a completely collectivist
utopia. Kang's holistic concerns in both short and long
terms denied any fundamental commitment to the intrinsic
value of the individual. As he stated himself: 'when
individual rights and priveleges are extended, the power of the state will necessarily be weakened,.27 The rights
he was primarily concerned with were China's sovereign
rights - much needed in the light of territorial
encroachment by the imperialist powers.
Like Kang Youwei, Yan Fu was primarily concerned with
individual rights insofar as they enhanced the 'wealth
11
and power' of the state. This is reflected in his translation of J.S. r.iill's On Liberty. His cumbrous translation of the title as The Boundaries of the Rights of Society and of the Individual is itself reflective of
his cautious treatment of the subject.28 Yan's understanding of liberty was coloured by his predilection for Spencerian
and Darwinian philosophy. Yan stated that 'it is only when the people are granted liberty that natural selection can be applied and that a good society can ultimately be achieved. ,29 Again, the collectivist objective is apparent. Mill himself was not oblivious to social concerns. In his chapter on
'Liberty of Thought and Discussion', he spoke of 'the greatest good for the greatest number'. But Mill's concern for the interests of society was readily interpreted by Yan in terms of the interests of the state. Even Mill's
chapter on the 'Liberty of Individuality' which spoke of the individual's 'strength of impulse', 'energy' and 'powers' lent itself to an interpretation which saw individual energy as the dynamic of a powerful state. Conspicuously, Mill's emphasis on individual spontaneity and eccentricity were ignored in Yan's commentary. In fact, in his preface to the 1903 edition, he was as much against those 'who think of liberty in terms of unbridled license and recklessness' as against those who saw it as
a doctrine 'of raging floods and ferocious beasts,.29 For Yan Fu, the individual was to contribute to the state, and 'liberty' was the best way of facilitating this.
Both Kang and Yan had advocated constitutional monarchy as the means by which to revitalize the Chinese state.
12
However, Kang's disciples, Tan Sitong and Liang Qichao,
advocated a republic. Yet even their republic in which the
people would enjoy equal political rights expressed in
representative assemblies by no means embodied a commit~ent
to the rights of the individual.
Tan maintained that originally, all men had been equal.
For practical purposes, they selected a prince while
retaining the rights to dismiss him. At all times, prince
and people were equals. According to Tan, it was Xun Zi who
distorted this tradition in order to allow the prince
'supreme and unlimited powers'. The resultant inequalities
had then been institutionalized in the three bonds - the
most abused of these being the loyalty between prince and
minister. Tan stated that 'loyalty signifies mutuality' and
asked 'why was it that only ministers and subjects live up
to it'. Instead, all political relationships should be based
on the relationship between friends - founded on 'equality, liberty and mutual feelings. ,30 Tan specifically attacked
the hierarchical nature of Confucian China which was itself
inimical to any notion of equal rights. However, he did not
go on to elaborate on the nature of those rights nor on the
part they would play in the development of the state.
It was Liang Qichao who provided the most definitive
analysis of what the early reformers understood by the
concept of rights. Others tended to presuppose the concept
and then proceeded to describe its importance in terms of
its relationship with duty. However, Liang analyzed the notion itself.31 Liang understood quan (t~ ) to mean political authority and minquan ( ~ t{l ) to mean people's
13
political authority and by extension, the people's right
to that political authority. Minquan was an expressly
political right. It carried no idea of inalienable rights
of life, liberty and property as in classical Lockeian
liberalism. Rather, it was a political right which was to
find expression in a political institution for an ultimate
political purpose. And that purpose was Minzhu - 'democracy'.
However Liang's liberalism could never be disassociated
from contemporary national crisis. Like his forebears,
Liang saw liberalism as being at the heart of Western power.
'If we look at the wealth of America', he said, 'then we
will understand that the political authority of the people should be revived,.32 It was in this sense that the adoption
of minquan was necessary. Again he said that:
in the last hundred years, the democratic spirit (minqi) has spread in western countries. If only China will do the same, she will be as strong
in a few decades.33
Liberalism was the only means by which to unleash the
individual's intellectual energy which when harnessed would
ensure national survival. Liang's prime concern was always
the nation. Until 1903 he saw liberalism as the necessary
means toward a national end though after that time even
Liang turned to a more centralized alternative.
Liang's commitment to the liberal solution is best
evidenced in his Limits of Authority bebveen Government and
People written in 1902. He stated that government authority
should be limited to the extent that it should only undertake
actions which individuals could not undertake on their own
and should only intervene in an individuals actions if they
encroached on the rights of other individuals. Here the idea
14
of the state as the passive policeman is at its best.
However, after 1903, Liang became increasingly
disillusioned with liberalism as a way to wealth and power.
It lacked what Liang saw as the fundamental pre-requisite
for a democracy - a politically conscious and active
citizenry. Liang turned to the 'enlightened despotism'
of Napoleon I and Frederick II as models for the development
of a strong Chinese state. Strong central government, unity
and discipline were emphasized over and above his earlier
concerns for individual liberty. Liang now saw the prime
criterion for government as being its ability to survive in
the international arena.
Even if a governmental system nearly robs the people of the bulk of their rights, it is a good system provided that it is founded on the spirit of meeting the exigencies of national defence.34
Liang's commitment had always been primarily to the
nation. When liberalism had been seen in the national
interest, it was promoted. When its utilitarian value was
suspect, it was rejected. Like his predecessors, Liang
lacked a fundamental commitment to his intrinsic worth of
the individual. Even when commenting on Mill, he had
frequently rendered Mill's 'individual' as 'people' and
Mill's 'society' as 'government'. Despite his initial
iconoclasm, Liang was too steeped in his tradition and too
concerned about the fate of his nation to give any
paramountcy to the rights of the individual.
Most of Liang's writings on liberalism had been written
during his exile in Japan after the failure of the 'hundred
days reform' of 1898 - when Tan had been executed and Liang
and Kang forced to flee for their lives. The fate of the
15
'hundred days reform' had demonstrated the court's
resistance to any notion of institutional reform. However,
it had been China's humiliation in the aftermath of the
Boxer Rising that had caused even the die-hard conservatives
of the imperial court to seriously contemplate ideas of
reform. By 1908/9, the court had produced a programme for
constitutional reform, but more as a reaction to the rise
of revolutionary parties than a commitment to the
institutional recognition of the notion of popular rights.
The most prominent of the revolutionary parties was the
Tongmeng hui whose principal architects had varying views as
to the role of rights in a new republic. Sun Yat-sen
rejected individualism as he did the idea of a state based
on a social contract. He saw the state more 'as an
organized body for mutual assistance rather than the
conglomeration of individuals for the protection of each one's rights,.35 Chen Tianhua stated the position even more
explicitly:
v-Jhat we seek is the freedom of the group. 'We do not seek the freedom of the individual ... in a republic the majority decides and it cannot but restrict the freedom of the minority.36
At the opposite end of the spectrum was the anti-
authoritarian Zhang Binglin who declared that 'only the
. d i . d 1 . 1 th ··11 I 37
ln 1V1 ua 1S rea ... e group 1S 1 usory.
Somewhere
between these poles was Wang Jingwei who saw the role of the
constitution as clearly delineating the powers of government
and the rights and duties of citizens.
'Under absolutism',
he said, 'the state has only rights with respect to the
individual but no obligations while the individual has only
duties to the state but no rights. Under constitutional
democracy, both the state and the individual have rights
16
and duties,.38 Clearly, the Tongmenghui's contradictory
commitment
to the roles of citizens and state did not
augure well for the role of rights in the republic which it founded in 1911.
The reasons for the failure of the republic both as an exercise in popular sovereignty and as an attempt at
.' unifying a disintegrating state are well documented. The republic's constituion and duly elected national assembly were to prove ineffectual with the rise of Yuan Shikai's dictatorship and the spread of warlordism. F. Wakeman has suggested that another reason for the failure of republican democracy lay in its insistence on consensual poli tics. The reformers had argued for representative assemblies in terms of their ability to effect national unity and through that unity, national strength and salvation. Therefore, 'the Great Harmony' would be endangered if partisan interests were promoted - so preventing the development of a conflict theory of constitutional politics. The early reformers 'still sought plurality in the place of pluralism'.38 that a loyal opposition was unacceptable more readily facilitated the rise of a dictator.
REPUBLICANISH - POST 1911
Reacting against the failure of liberalism in the first years of the republic, the intellectuals of the May the Fourth Period sought new solutions for the salvation of China. Cai Yuanpei's appointment to the Chancellorship of the Peking University in 1916 had led to the creation of a vigourous intellectual environment in the university where all ideas could be debated.
17
Cai's idea of education was one 'above politics' and 'beyond political control,.39 He stated that all
must follow the general rule of freedom of thought and freedom of expression and not allow anyone branch of philosophy or anyone tenet of religion to confine our minds.40
It was under these conditions that both liberals and
leftists joined in their condemnation of the old order
and demanded a genuine democracy. Though their notions
of democracy varied considerably.
Immediately after the Hay the Fourth incident itself,
the liberal educator Jiang Menglin likened the movement
to the emancipating effect of the European Renaissance:
It is a first step toward this kind of emancipation. We are going to ... bring about a Chinese Renaissance, emancipating emotions, emancipating thought and demanding human rights.41
In August 1920 both Hu Shi and Li Dazhao were signatories
to a 'Manifesto for the Struggle for Freedom'. Referring to
the 'pseudo - republicanism' of the previous decade, the
manifesto stated that
when politics brings us to such a dead end, we have to arouse ourselves and realize that genuine republicanism can never be achieved until politics is initiated by the people. In order to get people
to initiate politics, we must have as a pre-requisite an atmosphere wherein a genuine spirit of free thought and free ctiricism can be nurtured.42
Again, in May 1922, Hu and Li presented 'Our Political
Proposals' which was concerned about both government
legislation for the wellbeing of society and government's
guarantee of adequate individual freedom for the development of the individual's personality.43 The rights of the
individual came to the fore during the early days of the
movement - particularly rights of free expression as those
18
rights were fundamental to the life of the movement.
However, by 1923, the liberal and leftist elements within
the movement had begun to diverge. And so too did their
respective notions of individual rights.
J.B. Grieder has described Hu Shi's liberalism as
follows:
Hui Shi's vision of the new individual - critical, tolerant, creative, intellectually his own master, seeking to mould his ... surroundings to suit his own benign purposes - gave expression to an ideal that had no precedent in the traditions of Chinese social thought and found no echo among his adversaries of the radical extremes. It is, however, a vision that lies close to the heart of modern liberal theory.44
Hu was unique insofar as he expressed a radical
commitment to the ultimate value of the individual. The
individual was not simply a means to 'wealth and power'
as had been the case with earlier 'liberal' reformers. Hu saw the individual as an end in himself.45 He defined
human rights as 'the right to be a man - the conditions necessary for being a man',46 rather than the conditions
necessary for deriving maximum contribution from that man
for the good of soceity. He saw the function of the state
as being the protector of these human rights. If it failed
in this task, man would no longer owe it his allegiance. In fact, it would lose its 'raison d'etre,.47 Of all the
reformers, Hu comes closest to the ideals of classical
Western liberalism.
Chen Duxiu's notion of rights underwent a number of
changes as he became increasingly identified with the
left-wing of politics which grew out of the May the Fourth
Movement. As early as 1915, Chen had suggested that the
19
fundamental difference between Western and Eastern
civilizations lay in their respective emphases on the
individual and the family. In the East, societal demands
destroyed individual dignity, independent thought and
freedom of choice. There were no equal rights because
there were no rights to begin with. He therefore openly advocated individualism.48
However by 1919, Chen's articles in New Youth (Xin
qingnian) commenting on John Dewey's lectures on
political and economic democracy stated that China's prime
concern lay in socio-economic democracy rather than the political notion Of popular rights.49 He made the curious
observation that 'in implementing democracy, China must
follow the British and American models, paying attention to
the social and economic aspects and laying a strong foundation,.50 By 1920, the rights of the individual had
become the 'rights of the proletariat'. The proletariat
was 'to create a new power for itself and to completely conquer the capitalists. ,51 He criticized socialists who
participated in parliamentary politics as that would 'result only in their assimilation by the capitalists. ,52
Chen advocated the notion of 'class rights', a notion that
was completely antithetical to liberal notion of the
inalienable rights of all individuals.
Lin Yusheng has argued that for the May the Fourth
Reformers, liberalism served only 'as a ground for the
legitimation of their iconoclasm' as there was nothing
'more alien to their consciousness' than Western
Li.b I' 53
1 era 1sm.
I wou Ld suggest that Hu Shi and at times
20
even Chen Duxiu provide grounds for this contention to
be contested. Hu's position is clear. Chen, despite his
founding role in the Chinese Communist Party (Gongchan
dang), never seems to have completely abandoned his earlier
liberal ideas. His 1928 letter on the lack of inner-party
democracy is a case in point. In the letter, he suggests
that socialist societies should adopt certain western
political institutions such as parliamentary government
and laws protecting individual rights of free speech, press, .strike and universal suffrage.54 However, Lin Yusheng is
correct in saying that liberalism failed to attract a
lasting commitment on the part of the majority of the
'May Fourth' reformers. The military disintegration of
China in the mid-1920's undoubtedly exacebrated this waning
commitment as once again, national imperatives became pre-
eminent over any doctrine which promoted the primary of the
rights of the individual.
Following Chiang Kai-shek's northern expedition of 1927
which succeeded in re-uniting China after a decade of
political fragmentation, the Guomindang government in
Nanjing debated the form of a national constitution. The
Guomindang had evolved out of the Tongmenghui and it
inherited a varied tradition concerning the importance of
individual rights.
In the 1927-37 debates, Hu Shi's
notion of rights was hotly contested.
Zhou Fohai, for example, argued that
human freedoms are not inalienable but are granted by and may be taken away by society. The concept of the natural rights of the individual has been concocted in the West and does not now fit China.
21
He maintained that the Guomindang stood for the doctrine
of 'peoples revolutionary rights' which he defined as the 'exclusive rights of the supporters of the revolution,.55
Even the more liberal elements with the Guomindang such as
Wu Jingxiong stated that 'westerners in struggling for
freedom start from the individual' while Chinese start
from the group. He contended that in this struggle, it
must be demanded 'that each individual sacrifice his own freedom in order to preserve the freedom of the group,.56
Later, Chiang Kai-shek was to remark that
the people that promoted (liberalism and communism) forgot that they were Chinese ..• their copying of Western theories only caused the decay and ruin
of Chinese civilization and made it easy for the imperialists to carry out cultural aggression.57
The constitution of 1936 left almost unrestricted
powers in the office of the presidency. Following the
Japanese invasion of that year, those powers became more
absolute. Chiang was soon proclaimed Director-General of
the Guomindang - a position of virtual dictatorship.
Neither the first generation of reformers, nor those
of the May the Fourth period, nor the liberal elements
within the Guomindang succeeded in gaining effective
institutional recognition of the rights of the individual.
To be sure, the constitutions of 1912 and 1936 made
mention of rights, but in both cases actual power was
monopolized by dictators. With the rise of the Communist
Party, liberalism as a potent political persuasion receded
further into the background.
22
COMMUNISM - PRE 1949
Mao Zedong had been a long-time opponent of liberalism.
As early as 1920 he had said that liberalism and even democracy 'are fine in theory, but not feasible in practice!58
He saw parliaments as acting in the interests of capitalists
and serving only as a handicap to the proletariat. Rather
than a parliament, Mao conceived of a 'dictatorship of
workers and peasants' as the means by which to realize his
goal of a communist society.
Mao's most definitive critique of liberalism and liberal
rights came in Mao's speech of 1937 simply entitled Combat
'b I' ( du i huv i.) 59
Ll era lsm Fan Ul ZlyOUZ Uyl .
Mao's fundamental
objection was that liberalism entailed an unprincipled
toleration of the actions of others irrespective of the
implication of those actions for the masses. 'Liberalism',
he said, 'negates ideological struggle and advocates
unprincipled peace' to the point that even 'counterrevolutionary opinions' are tolerated.60 Underlying Mao's
objections were the diamatrically opposed notions of
individualism and collectivism inherent in liberal and
Marxist thought. For Mao, 'not to care for the principle
of collective life but only for unrestrained selfindulgence' was a hallmark of liberal values.61 He saw
liberals as demanding 'special dispensations' from the
collective but rejecting its discipline. He concluded
that 'liberalism conflicts fundamentally with Marxism'
and that 'all loyal communists must unite to oppose it,.62
Though written in the early years of the second United
Front with the intent of keeping the party faithful
23
untainted in their co-operation with westernized liberals,
the speech remains a basic text in understanding Mao's
hostility to the notions of individual primacy and
individual rights.
By 1940, Mao's position on liberalism had remained
essentially unchanged though his ideas on class dictatorship
had been modified to cope with the new challenges faced by
the party.
In that year, Mao was faced with the dual problems
of providing some form of theoretical rationale for his
continuing United Front with the Guomindang, as well as
providing a wider base of support for the Communist Party
itself. Both these concerns are reflected in his essay on
New Democracy (Xin minzhuzhuyi lun).
In this essay, Mao distinguished his 'new democratic
republic' from both 'the old, western type bourgeois
democratic republics that are under the bourgeoisie' and
'from the newest Soviet style republic which is under the dictatorship of the proletariat' .63 As to the nature of
this 'new democratic republic', it was to be a 'joint
dictatorship of several anti-imperialist classes ... a
coalition of several revolutionary classes in a united front,.64 He went on to say that the 'proletariat, peasantry,
intelligentsia and other petty bourgeois elements ... were
bound to be the basic parts of the state and government framework of the Dernoc r at.Lc Republic of China'. 65
As far as rights are concerned, this statement had a
number of important implications. First, the notion of
individual rights implicit to liberal democracy is again
uncategorically rejected. Second, and more significantly,
24
a distinction is made between 'proletarian dictatorship' (which Mao himself had endorsed in 1920) and what was to
be the uniquely Chinese practice of the 'dictatorship of several revolutionary classes'. Under the former system,
all non proletarian classes are disenfranchised of their rights whereas the latter system leaves an undefined number of these non proletarian classes with the same rights as
the proletariat.66 Third, implicit to this idea of 'joint dictatorship' is the fact that those undefined classes which are not deemed as being revolutionary therefore cannot participate in the dictatorship and therefore cannot enjoy the rights of the enfranchised classes. Mao's vagueness on this point in 1940 is understandable in the context of .the insecurity of the times. Significantly in 1949 when his
party held the reins of power, he became much more explicit as to who was revolutionary and who was not. Mao's On Coalition Government (Lun lianhe zhengfu) of 1945 is perhaps more conciliatory in tone than his statement of 1940. In 1945 it was necessary to leave two options open: a peace time coalition government with the K.M.T., or a military confrontation with them, in which case the broadest possible base of support would be necessary. Whereas in 1940, Mao had spoken of the 'joint dictatorship of revolutionary classes', in 1945, he spoke more leniently of 'a new democratic state based on the coalition of several democratic classes,.67 Rather than being revolutionary, people were simply required to 'adopt a co-operative and friendly attitude towards the C.C.P.' Presumably, therefore, rights would be enjoyed by
all such friendly people. Again, however, there was a studied
25
vagueness as to who was democratic and who was not.
On the Peoples Democratic Dictatorship (Lun renmin
minzhu zhuanzheng) of 1949 provides the clearest statement
of who was and who was not to have rights in the new People's
Republic of China. Under the People's Democratic Dictatorship
it was 'the people' who had rights. 'Who are the people?'
Mao asks.
'At the present stage of China they are the
working class, the peasantry, the urban petty bourgeoisie
and the national bourgeoisie'. He goes on to enumerate the
rights which are possessed by 'the people'.
Democracy is practised among the ranks of the people, who enjoy the rights of freedom of speech, assembly, association and so on. The right to vote belongs only to the people •..
Whereas in 1940 and 1945 Mao refrained from overtly stating
who was excluded from his revolutionary and democratic
coalitions, his statement of 1949 goes some way towards
defining who are the 'unpeople':
The running dogs of Imperalism - the landlord class and bureaucratic bourgeoisie - as well as the representatives of those classes, the K.M.T. reactionaries and their accomplices ...
These classes had no rights, least of all the right to speak.
In fact it was the responsibility of 'the people' to
exercise their dictatorship over these enemies of 'the people'.
Mao states that
The combination of these two aspects, democracy for the people and dictatorship over the reactionaries, ... constitutes the peoples democratic dictatorship.
Yet democracy and dictatorship were not left to the popular
prerogative of the people because what had hitherto been
a vague notion of proletarian leadership in 'New Democracy'
was now made concrete.
'The People' were now to be 'led by
26
the working class and the Communist Party' because 'the peoples democratic dictatorship needs the leadership of the
working class'.
It will be noted that at least the
theoretical distinction is maintained between proletarian leadership and proletarian dictatorship.68 Yet one must speculate as to whether there was any practical difference. Certainly, in reality, the exercise of the rights of 'the people' would at least be tempered by the dictates of the proletariat - or more specifically its party, the C.C.P. The rights of 'the people' were completely conditional upon the performance of their duty. And their duty was loyalty to the party.69
In post revolutionary China it was the party rather than 'the people' - even the limited notion of 'the people' defined by the party - which was the locus of real political power. This centralist formula for the administration of
the state also applied to the adminstration within the party itself. This formula had been clearly expounded in Mao's writings of 1942. His essay On Democratic Centralism
stated that 'the C.C.P. not only needs democracy, but needs centralization even more,.70 Democratic Centralism was a
system in which 'the minority is subordinate to the majority, the lower level to the higher level, the part to the whole, the entire membership to the Central Committee ... ,71 There was certainly no populist notion of decision making within the party. Nor was there a representative one whereby local members elected central members. Rather, in common with Confucian tradition, it was totally hierarchical.
As regards the party's attitude towards intellectual
27
liberty, Mao's famous Talks on Art and Literature (Zai Yan'an
wenyi zuotanhui shangde jianghua) of 1942
stated that all realms of activity - even artistic activity -
must be subjected to certain political requirements determined
by the party. The party's internal rectification movement
of the same year was further evidence that it was not a party
which tolerated individual dissent.
Therefore with respect to rights, the communist party had
laid down a number of premises from the outset. First, rights
were only to be enjoyed by 'the people'. 'The people' were
to use their rights to exercise dictatorship over the
'enemies of the people' and these 'enemies' had no rights.
Second, this limited definition of 'the people' was temporary.
Mao had stated that 'at the present stage', 'the people'
comprised a certain number of classes. Thus he implied that
at a later stage this definition of the people would be
limited even further. Third, any rights possessed by 'the
people', and even those possessed by 'the people' who were
members of the party, were completely conditional on their
loyalty to the central leadership of the party.
COMMUNISM - POST 1949
These principles were encapsulated in the Constitution of
the People's Republic of China (Zhonghua renmin gongheguo xianfa) of 1954.72 This document contains fourteen specific
articles in its section on the 'Fundamental Rights and
Duties of Citizens'. Of these, the most important is
article eighty-seven.
Citizens of the People's Republic of China have freedom of speech, freedom of press, freedom of
28
assembly, freedom of association, freedom of procession and freedom of demonstration. By providing the necessary material facilities, the state guarantees to citizens enjoyment of these freedoms.75
However, these freedoms are subject to two major
qualifications found elsewhere in the document. First,
article nineteen deprives enemies of 'the people' of
74 political rights until such time as they have reformed.
Second, article eighteen requires that 'the servants of
the state' (i.e. 'the people') be loyal to the people's democratic system.75
In Liu Shaoqi's report delivered immediately prior to
the ratification of the constitution, he defined people's
democracy as a system where 'personal interests are
indivisible from public interests of the country and society'. They were, he said, 'one and the same,.76 Though
loyalty to the people's democratic system appears less
stringent than the loyalty to the Communist Party leadership
prescribed in the 1978 constitution, its effect was to place
individual rights in the context of an overall collectivist
objective. Therefore, 'people's democracy' limited the
number of people entitled to rights. And for those who were
considered among the ranks of 'the people', there were also
limitations on the pruposes for which they could exercise
their rights.
Events during the 1950's indicated that the party's notion
of limited individual freedom was more than an abstract
theoretical doctrine. Writers such as Yu Pingbo, Feng
Xuefeng and Hu Feng who refused to abide by the party's
definition of ideological orthodoxy became the object of
29
nation-wide rectification campaigns in 1954-55 in an
attempt to eliminate intellectual dissent.
However, the party was not unwavering in terms of its
commitment to limited individual expression. Mao's
speeches on Let a Hundred Flowers Bloom, (Baihuaqifang
baijia zhengming), The Ten Major Relationships, (Shi da
guanxi), and The Correct Handling of Contradictions
among the People (Guanyu zhengque renmin neibu mao dun de wenti)77 of 1956-7 had a liberalizing effect on freedom
of expression. The first of these was primarily concerned
with intellectual freedom in the arts and sciences.
However, the remaining two served to fundamentally amend
previous statements on the rights of the individual.
First, Mao's definition of 'the people' is enlarged
to include 'all classes, strata and social groups that
approve, support and work for the cause of socialist construction,.78 Of Mao's three previous definitions of
'the people', this is perhaps the most liberal. Second,
Mao spoke of the possibility of non-violent resolution of
the non-antagonistic conflicts which existed between the
various classes of 'the people'. This implied lattitude
for discussion and debate. Third, he spoke of righting the
imbalance between rights and duties:
Within the ranks of the people, democracy stands in relation to centralism and freedom to discipline.
They are two aspects of a single entity, contradictory as well as united, and we should not one-sidedly emphasize one to the detriment of the other.79
Here Mao advances the notion that freedom and discipline
should be equally contending forces, whereas previously
the former was largely conditional on the latter.
30
It is difficult to ascertain whether Mao's policies
were reflective of a genuine concern for the liberalization of the system in the light of Kruschev's revelations about the real nature of Stalinist Russia. Certainly events in Hungary were prominent in Mao's thinking. Irrespective of the cause of this policy shift, its long term effect lay
in that the party was now equipped with a greater degree of ideological flexibility. When individual initiative was required (invariably for the realization of a particular economic objective), democracy was emphasized over centralism. Conversely, centralism was emphasized over democracy when the party required tighter control.80 However, the 'contradictions' speeches by no means serve
to alter the fundamental notion that the rights of 'the people' are ultimately for the collective wellbeing.8l
In the history of the P.R.C., there have been a number
of periods of relaxation of the controls on individual expression - invariably separated by rectification
movements which then re-established those controls. The periodic revitalization of the slogan 'let a hundred
flowers bloom, let a hundred schools contend' usually indicated the return of more liberal policies. In the decade which elapsed between the enunciation of Mao's
'contradictions' policy and the beginning of the Cultural Revolution (Wuchanjieji wenhua dageming) there were a number of periods of liberalization which in different ways challenged the party's centralized notion of authority.
The first and most celebrated of these liberalizations was the 'Hundred Flowers Movement' which occurred as a
31
direct consequence of Mao's 'contradictions' speeches of 1956-7.82 Non communist intellectuals spoke out
initially against the party's control over intellectual
activity. However, the focus of this attack was broadened
to encompass the party's monopoly of power generally.
Zhu Anping of the 'China Democratic League' {Zhongguo minzhu tongmeng)83 argued through Guangming ribao that the
party 'sought to bring about the monolithic structure of a
f 'I " 84
one aml y emplre
He demanded institutional changes
which would lend substance to what had been no more than
a sham of coalition government. His colleague, Chen Xingui,
took the argument to its conclusion:
The system adopted by the Soviet Union and the New Democracies is the dictatorship of the proletariat ... is it any wonder that sectarianism thrives on a system which regards all outside the party as pagan elements .. How can the democratic parties supervise a one party dictatorship.85
Chen challenged the very idea of a vanguard party, or at
least as it had been interpreted by the Chinese communists.
In fact, inherent in the challenge is a call for a type of
parliamentary opposition - a loyal opposition. This in
turn had obvious implications for the individual's political
rights.
Students of Peking University (Beijing Daxue) adopted an
even more radical posture. They began a 'democratic wall'
for displaying 'contending' wall posters, they produced
unofficial journals and organized themselves into various
d ' ,,86
emocratlc socletles.
One such society was appropriately
called the 'Hundred Flowers Society' (Baihua she) whose
stated purpose was the initiation of 'a movement for
freedom and democracy' in wh i.ch people could learn from the
32
1 f th . t I' . 87
examp e 0 e cap1 a 1St countr1es.
Lin Xiling, the
most prominent of the student activists, had stated that
whereas socialism in its pure form was democratic, the
party's version of socialism was the antithesis of 88
democracy.
Whereas the China Democratic League had called for
political reform, the students suggested that the models
for that reform should be drawn from the liberal democracies
of the west.
Undoubtedly, all those who 'bloomed and contended' in
the Spring of 1957 had in common an assertion of the
individual's right to freedom of expression. In doing so
they had attacked the system which had previously dictated
the parameters of that freedom. Clearly, the party was not
about to tolerate dissent of such magnitude. The ensuing
'anti-rightist campaign' (fanyoupai yundong) aimed at
re-establishing party control. As the Minister for Education
stated:
The tendency to relax ideological and political indoctrination, to practice democracy in the extreme, to emphasize individualism one-sidedly, and to neglect collectivist acts and discipline should be rectified.89
A second period of liberalization occurred in the years
immediately following the failure of the Great Leap Forward.
(Dayuejin). The official press began re-emphasizing Mao's
'hundred flowers' speech, though this time seemingly at Liu
Shaoqi's rather than Mao's direction. In fact, it was Mao
who became the target of criticism over his autocratic
handling of the 'Great Leap'.
Criticism was expressed through literary analogy. Wu
33
Han's play The Dismissal of Hai Rui from Office (Hai Rui
ba guan) was a critique of arbitrary government,
particularly in terms of its inability to tolerate dissent.
Wu's play and his other writings on Hai Rui clearly painted
an analogy with Mao's dismissal of Peng Dehuai following
the latter's criticism of Mao's 'Great Leap' policies at the Lushan conference of 1959.90 Tian Han's play Xie
Yaohuan repeatedly lamented the passing of the 'thaw'
(jiedong), a term used by Soviet writers of the time when
referring to more liberal attitudes towards the toleration of dissent.9l Deng Tuo's famous Evening Chats at Yens han
(Yanshan yehua) eulogized the dissident spirits of
the Danglin Academy of the Ming. The jointly authored
Notes from a Three Family Village (Sanjiacun zhaji) was
a thinly veiled attack on Maoism itself. However, these
calls for a genuine plurality of views in 1961-2 met with
Mao's call for a return to intellectual orthodoxy at the
September plennum of 1962.
However, Mao's call went largely unheeded by the party
bureaucracy which was responsible for the carrying out of any rectification.92 So while party cadres busied themselves
with the 'Socialist Education Movement' (Shehuizhuyi jiaoyu
yundong) aimed at imbuing agricultural workers with
collectivist values, a number of intellectuals again set
out to challenge the party's claim to be the embodiment
of all orthodoxy. The January 1963 editorial of New
Construction (Xin jianshe) stated that:
Scholars of any subject, including those of Marxism, have no authority to consider themselves absolutely correct and suppress views at variance with their own.93
34
Students of the party idealogue Yang Xianzhen challenged
Mao's theory of contradictions. Whereas Mao stated that
opposites would ultimately become a single entity by means
of struggle, it was now held that opposites should reconcile
with one another rather than struggle for one another's
elimination. They criticized those who 'saw only good and bad' and advocated an ongoing diversity of viewpoints.94
In harmony with these calls for a more pluralist society,
Wu Han suggested that New China should incorporate various
Confucian and bourgeois values - including bourgeois democracy and the bourgeois profit making motive.95
However, by June 1964 there were new calls for
rectification though the ensuing campaign proved as
indecisive as the campaign of two years earlier. Mao's
inability to re-establish ideological control during these
periods of liberalization undoubtedly led him to adopt
the extreme measures which became evident in the Cultural
R 1 . 96 evo utlon.
It is true that those who were active in these various
periods of liberalization seldom addressed themselves
directly to the issue of individual rights. Nonetheless,
the individual's freedom of expression and freedom of
participation in the political process were obviously at
the heart of their proposals. Whereas their common call
had been for a type of pluralist democracy, the
ideological zealots of the Cultural Revolution sought a
return to the populist principles which they ascribed to the
model of the Paris Commune.
In July 1966, Mao proclaimed a poster written by Nie Yuanzi97 as the 'manifesto of the Chinese Paris Commune
35
of the sixties of the twentieth century,.98 The nature
of the new order was left largely undefined though it was
stated that a system of general elections would be 't' d 99
lns ltute .
The proclamation of the 'Shanghai People's Commune'
(Shanghai renmin gongshe) in February 1967 provided a
more concrete example of this populist notion of government.
The Commune referred to itself as a 'proletarian
dictatorship' for the self government of the producers.
Officials were to be 'democratically elected' and thereupon
subject to 'popular supervision' and 'popular recall'.
However, the central government was wary of the potentially
anarchic consequences of Shanghai's populist experiment.
After a brief nineteen day existence, the Commune came under
the rule of a 'revolutionary committee' (geming weiyanhui)
which became the instrumentality through which centralized
control was eventually re-established.
This reimposition of central control did not go
unchallenged. Various Red Guard (Hong weibing) groupings
saw this as a betrayal of the ideal of the Paris Commune.
The most famous of these was the 'Hunan Provincial
Proletarian Revolutionary Great Alliance' (Hunansheng
wuchanjieji geming dalianmeng) or more commonly Sheng wulian) - which was active in late 1967 and early 1968.100 Their manifesto, Whither China (Zhongguo xiang hechu qu)lOl
stated that the power that had been seized from the party
had been taken by the people who had then organized their
own administration of the party, state and economy. This
was pursuant with their ultimate objectiv~ of realizing
36
the 'China People's Commune' (ZhOngguo renmin gongshe)~02
They saw the realization of this objective as being totally
incompatible with central control:
We openly declare that our establishment of the China People's Commune can be attained only by the forcible removal of the Revolutionary Committee's dictatorship of the bourgeois
class ... 103
This 'bourgeois dictatorship' would be replaced by a system
of cadres
'vested with genuine proletarian authority' who
could be dismissed and replaced at any time at the masse's demand.104
The Sheng wulian notion of proletarian rights was
completely at variance with the idea of a vanguard party.
And the challenge to the party came not only from Hunan.
Guangzhou, Shanghai and Zhejiang produced similar such
alliances. The party's response was to send in the army
to restore central control and as of July 1968, to
despatch the Red Guards to the countryside for re-education.
Gradually, a revitalized party re-emerged as the effective
locus of political power.
Whereas in the Cultural Revolution, the significance
of the individual lay in his participation in an ill defined
populism,
there have been several movements since that
time which have indicated a general retreat from such
exclusively collectivist notions of the individual. And
at least one began to speak of the need to protect the
rights of the individual.
The first such movement - though movement is
undoubtedly an overstatement - involved those Red Guards
who found their way to Hong Kong in the latter days of
the Cultural Revolution. They produced a limited number
37
of editions of a magazine entitled Voice of China
(Zhongguo zhi sheng) which defined the principle
contradiction in Chinese society as being between peasants
and privileged Maoists. They disclaimed Mao's proletarian
dictatorship as nothing more than a swindle and predicted
that China would eventually 'take the great way of freedom,
l' d d" 105
equa lty, emocracy an SClence.
The significance of
this group lies not in its influence on subsequent events
on the mainland because it had none. Rather, it is perhaps
symptomatic of the reaction of the red guard generation
against the authority which ultimately suppressed them
and against many of the very principles for which they had
once fought. This disillusioned generation were to be the
principal actors in the dissident movements of 1974, 1976
and 1978-9.
In November 1974, three ex-Red Guards under the
pseudonymn of Li Yizhe posted a hundred metre long poster
in Guangzhou entitled On Socialist Democracy and the
Legal System (Guanyu shehuizhuyi minzhu yu fazhi). The
poster commended the recent campaign criticizing Lin Biao
and Confucius insofar as it was a critique of arbitrary power.106 However it then criticized .t.h a't; campaign's affirmation of the revolutionary role of Qin Shihuangl07 -
an affirmation which Li Yizhe described as an exhortation
to feudal autocracy and the physical elimination of all
opposition. As the official campaign implied that Mao was
the Qin Shihuang of modern China, Li Yizhe's criticisms
were aimed at the autocratic powers of the helmsman
himself. The poster maintained that as power corrupts,
38
the people must be protected from its arbitrary exercise through effective democratic rights.l08
Li Yizhe maintained that democracy is a cornerstone of
new China. Citing the Chairman as their authority, they
note that 'without extensive people's democracy, the dictatorship of the proletariat cannot be consolidated. ,109
The poster then dwells on whether that democracy has ever
been effective. The country's constitution had guaranteed
democratic rights but these rights had never been
effectively exercised, partly because of the anti-democratic
nature of certain elements within the party and partly
because of an anti-democratic tradition. The flagrant
disregard for individual rights during the Cultural
Revolution had caused people to rediscover the value of
their rights - 'just like a traveller from the well rivered
south who treasures water only when he comes to the 110
desert', However the aftermath of the Cultural
Revolution had not witnessed the establishment of a genuine
democracy, but rather the rise of a 'factional democracy'
in which one faction's objective is the elimination of III
the other. Clearly, the author's saw democracy as
practised in People's China as completely impotent In the
face of actual political power.
Li Yizhe then calls for democracy to be injected with
a political potency of its own. They say that contending
factions should have democratic rights and that these
rights should be mutually respected. In fact, one faction
should not seek to overcome the other through class
struggle. Rather, both (or all) factions should remain
39
ln a type of continuing opposition.112 They further
stated that:
The masses of people demand democracy, they demand a socialist legal system and they demand the revolutionary rights!and h~man rights
(renshen renquan A. ;.... ~~ ) which
protect the masses of th peop~'.113
Li Yizhe's notion of democracy is therefore twofold:
one which protects the rights of the individual from the
abuse of the state's power and one which enables the
individual to participate in the government of the state
irrespective of his convictions. This call for political
pluralism is reminiscent of the 'Hundred Flowers' movement
and carries with it the same implicit denial of one class
exercising dictatorship over the other. Indeed, the authors
are aware that their arguments largely parallel those of
the 19S7 'rightists' and make the tenuous claim that
whereas the 'rightists' sought to undermine the
proletarian dictatorship, their campaign would only serve to consolidate it.114 P.R. Moody makes the point that
with Li Yizhe, 'Chinese radicalism had come full circle. Li
converges with Lin Xiling and both converge with
liberalism' - separated by an illiberal Cultural Revolution. lIS While to describe them as liberals is
something of an overstatement, the liberal tendencies
of both these activists have much in common.
The Li Yizhe poster evoked a rapid official response
in a poster signed Xuan Jiwen (Collection of Propaganda
Documents) which reportedly orginated in the Central
Committee itself. It redefined democracy in terms of
its class nature - either proletarian democracy or
bourgeois democracy - warning that the latter enabled
40
the bourgeoisie to attack the party.116 It criticized
Li Yizhe for its failure to distinguish between the two
and its failure to state that the essence of the
dictatorship of the proletariat is the dictatorship by
the proletariat over the bourgeoisie. For implicit to
Li Yizhe's argument, Xuan Jiwen suggested, is an extension
of democratic rights to all classes of people - including
such class enemies as the landlords, rich peasants,
bureaucratic-capitalists, bourgeois rightists and counter-
1 t' , 117 h L' Y' h f '1 d '
revo u lonarles. In sort, l lZ e al e to appreclate
that democracy was the pr~vilege of a single class - the
proletariat.
Xu an Jiwen's poster went on to further define the
rights available to the proletariat itself.
The 'four great weapons - great contending, great blooming, big character posters and great debates' (Darning dafang dabianlun dazibao) are not unconditional rights. Rather, they are absolutely conditional on the six standards outlined in Mao's 'contradictions' speech of 1957. By these means, 'fragrant flowers' (xiang hua) could be distinguished from 'poisonous weeds' (du cao), so eliminating the possibility of using 'democracy for smearing and attacking the Party Central, Chairman Mao ... the socialist system and the dictatorship of the proletariat!118
This was a clear statement on the relative nature of
proletarian rights - rights which were called 'weapons'
rather than rights.
Xu an Jiwen dismissed Li Yizhe's poster as trumpeting
'the democracy, liberty and legal system of the bourgeois
class' and 'wildly attempting .. to incite the masses and
create chaos in order to duplicate a Hungarian incident in China,.119 Li Yizhe's democracy was equated with anarchy
and subversion. It came as no surprise that the authors
41
of the poster were imprisoned.
The official response to Li Yizhe widened into a
campaign against 'bourgeois legal rights' (2i faquan) in
1975.
In March of that year, Yao Nenyuan wrote of
bourgeois rights as 'means to carry out insidious
adventures ... to incite certain people of various classes to oppose the dictatorship of the proletariat,.120 Though
the campaign seems to have been primarily directed against
the re-emergence of private property, it was also of
obvious political significance. Unlike the 'anti-rightist
campaign', this campaign drew to a quiet conclusion. As
a public issue, rights remained in the background until
the Tiananmen Incident (Tiananmen shijian) of April 1976.
Unlike the Voice of China or Socialist Democracy and
Legality, the Tiananmen Incident did not produce a body
of literature expounding any thesis on the issue of
democratic rights. Its significance lay in the spontaneous
expression of those rights by one hundred thousand rioters
in Tiananmen Square (Tiananmen guangchang) on 5 April
1976. It was a mass revolt against authority.
The touchstone for the riot was the removal of wreathes
placed at the People's Mero's Monument (Renmin yingxiong
jinianbei) by people honouring the memory of Zhou Enlai
who had died that January. Poems attached to the wreathes
expressed feelings which would be given violent expression
in the riot that would follow. Agence France Presse
reported one poem which read:
Hail Chairman Mao
Beat Down Indira Gandhi and Empress zi Xi.12l
42
The latter two names were apparent references to Jiang
Qing who at that time was at the centre of power.
However, it was the poem printed by Renmin ribao the
day after the riot that was most clearly directed agsinst
the regime.
In part it read:
China is no longer the China of yore,
And the people are no longer wrapped in sheer ignorance,
Gone for good is Qin Shihuang's feudal society.122
Whereas Li Yizhe spoke disparagingly of the campaign
promoting Qin Shihuang, this poem sees the Tiananmen
demonstrations as overthrowing the emperor himself. Again
the reference is Mao and the Maoist order.
It is difficult to ascertain just how representative
these poems were of the demonstrations generally. But the
fact that the ensuing riot was aimed at government
buildings, vehicles and personnel suggests that the
political orientation of the incident extended beyond the
literary exploits of a couple of individuals. Rather, it
was more like a mass revolt against the arbitrary exercise
of power by an arbitrary political order.
That the incident posed a serious political challenge
to the regime's authority is further attested by the
regime's response. It was bloodily suppressed. There were
mass arrests. There was an intensive rectification campaign involving practically every household in peking.123 It
lead to Deng Xiaoping's dismissal from all party and state
positions and the promotion of Hua Guofeng to the
premiership. And the incident itself was labelled 'counter-
revolutionary'. It is completely understandable that when
this counter-revolutionary verdict was finally reversed
43
two years later, it unleashed a torrent of popular resentments which found expression on Democracy Wall (Minzhu qiang) .
Thus, we have seen something of the notion of the rights in Chinese history. In Imperial China, there
was no notion of individual rights. In Republican China, the search for a new identity offered the opportunity
for animated debate on the nature of rights and the
role of rights in a new China - though the military demands of the time meant that rights became little more than a theoretical notion. In Communist China, rights were defined in terms of class rights which were to be exercised by one class over the other. In all these periods, rights were conditional on one's duty to the collective: at one time that duty was to 'save the nation' (jiu guo) while at another it was to rebuild
it. Such conditionality is antithetical to the absolute and inalienable rights of the individual espoused in classical western liberalism. However, Wei Jingsheng was to evince a refreshingly original commitment to the inherent value of the individual.
44
CHAPTER TWO
THE HUMAN RIGHTS r-mVEMENT OF 1978-1979
45
Before analyzing Wei Jingsheng's understanding of
human rights, it is necessary to examine the context in which
he wrote. Wei must be seen as part of a wider movement - a
movement which in turn must be seen in terms o£ political
developments within the regime as reflected in the regime's
mass media.
ORIGINS OF THE MOVEMENT
The origins of the movement are complex. They are complex
because the movement itself reflects a complex interplay of
official, semi-official and unofficial interests. And this
interplay cannot be monitored with any assurance of accuracy.
Since the enunciation of the Yan'an doctrine in 1942,
politics had been at the centre of any literary activity. As
W.F. Jenner recently commented,
the degree of license allowed to writers and editors has been determined by the extent that their views coincide with the policy on the arts of the rulers of the day.l
However, the unofficial literary movement which began in
November 1978 was more than a political pinnochio.
It had
its own being. Certainly, the movement could not have begun
without the support of the regime - or at least the strongest
faction within the regime. And certainly their support was
given for the realization of particular political objectives.
But the fact that no faction enjoyed immunity from the
movement's attacks suggests that the movement had something
of an independent orientation from the outset.
It was no
mere surrogate for the central leadership.
There was, therefore, a temporary coincidence of
interests. One faction of the leadership seems to have seen
46
the movement as a means of isolating its political opponents whereas those who participated in the movement had grievances
of their own.
It is the inter-relationship between these
interests which complicates any analysis of the origins of the movement.
The fall of the 'Gang of Four' (siren bang) 2 in October of 1976 marked the close of an era which was fundamentally committed to Maoist orthodoxy. The new regime, especially the new Deng regime,3 reacted against this emphasis on ideological orthodoxy. Economic reform rather than ideological rectitude became the regime's overriding concern. This change in emphasis was expressed at the Fifth National Peoples Congress (diwuci quanguo renmin daibiao dahui) held between 26/2/78 and 5/3/78 with the campaign for the
'Realization of the Four Modernizations' (shixian sige xiandaihua).4 Hua Guofeng stated that though 'proletarian politics must dominate, ... one must do business according to objective economic laws'S - implying that the economy should be allowed to develop relatively independently of ideological considerations. However, he went on to say that 'MarxismLeninism-Mao Zedong thought will maintain primary position in science and culture, exclusive of any bourgeois liberalism dreamt of by reactionaries inside and outside the country. ,6 Still, a fundamental reorientation towards a more liberal economic policy had occurred.
The regime then set about launching a series of
propaganda campaigns complementing this economic liberalization. Undoubtedly, the purpose was to free people's minds from the ideological shackles imposed by a decade of 'cultural revolution' and so free their individual economic initiative -
47
both for the purpose of the rapid realization of the 'Four
Modernizations~. However, the propaganda campaigns of 1978
served as a double-edged sword : on one hand encouraging
freedom in the economic sphere while on the other, causing
people to inquire why no such freedoms were forthcoming in
the political sphere.
In this way, conditions were created
which led to the wallposter movement of mid-November.
The first of these propaganda campaigns was the 'Study
the New Constitution' campaign (xuexi xinde xianfa)
launched by Renmin ribao on 3 May 1978. The campaign sought
to emphasize the return of the rule of law after the
lawlessness of the Cultural Revolution.
It stated that the
new constitution summed up the experience of struggle against
7 the 'Gang of Four' who wanted 'anarchy and extreme democracy'.
Again, dictatorship was to be exercised over the enemy and
democracy practiced among 'the people'. Among 'the people's'
various democratic rights, the campaign paid particular
attention to article fifty-five of the constitution which
guaranteed
the right to lodge complaints ... against any person working in an organ of state, enterprise or institution for transgression of the law or neglect of duty.8
Renmin ribao encouraged people to vent their grievances by
writing letters to the press and paying visits to the
relevant state departments. The paper went further and
suggested that it may be appropriate for the masses to write anonymous letters if they were afraid of reprisals.9 In
response to these calls from the organ of the Central
Committee, the provinces organized a series of conferences
on 'letters and visits' work (xinzuo fanggong) in order to
48
realize a more effective socialist democracy.10 Such
exhortations to publicly criticize the authorities may well
have encouraged those who were more fundamentally opposed
to the system to eventually speak out.
In another sense, the constitution was a curious
combination of both liberal and illiberal innovations. It
was the first constitution to encapsulate Mao's 'Hundred
Flowers' slogan:
The state applies the policy of "letting a hundred flowers bloom and a hundred schools contend" so as to promote the development of the arts and sciences and brin1 about a flourishing socialist culture. 1
Yet it was also the first constitution which required its
citizens to 'support the leadership of the Communist Party' 12
and to 'support the socialist system'. These clauses
imposed a conditionality on any rights which may be
guaranteed in other clauses of the constitution. However,
on balances it seems to be a more liberal document than that
of 1975.
The 'Study the Constitution' campaign was followed by a
more widespread campaign which challenged the fundamentalist
interpretation which had been given 11arxism-Leninism-Mao
Zedong thought during the Cultural Revolution. The campaign
went under either of two names: tSeek Truth From Facts'
(shishi qiushi) or the more longwinded version 'Practice is
the Sole Criterion for the Verification of Truth' (shijian
shi jianyan zhenlide weiyi biaozhun). It seems to have been
launched by Deng Xiaoping in a speech at an army conference
on 2 June 1978.
Signs of an impending re-evaluation of Mao Zedong had
been evident since the end of 1977 when the official press
49
began suggesting that one should not 'act in accordance
with every sentence' (juju zhaoban) - that is, every
sentence uttered by the Chairman.
In April 1978, Renmin
ribao criticized those who venerated ~1arxism-Leninism-Mao
Zedong thought as 'objects rather of faith than of knowledge'
and those 'who do not allow people to use their brains, much less to discern truth from falsehood,.13 In the following
month, Guangming ribao said that Mao Zedong thought must be 'subjected to an examination on the basis of social practice,.14
Therefore, Mao Zedong thought was no longer to be accepted as
an article of faith but rather was to be subjected to a type
of empirical analysis.
These themes were brought together in Deng's important
speech of 2 June:
There are comrades who ... turn against the basic concept and method of Marxism, the realism (shishi qiushi) of Chairman Mao, which always starts from facts, and combines theory and practice ... there are even persons who believe that a realist who relies on facts and combines theory with practice commits a crime. They think that it is enough to parrot the words of Harx, Lenin and Chairman Mao ... This is not a minor matter. It is a problem of how Marxism-LeninismMao Zedong thought should be regarded.lS
That this was not regarded as a minor matter is attested by
the nationwide coverage given both to the speech and the
maxim of 'Seeking Truth From Facts' which it encapsulated. Mao, and to the same extent Mao's Cultural Revolution,16 could
now be publicly debated within the parameters of an ill-
defined notion of 'practice'.
The official press subsequently widened the debate17
(Jiefangjun bao) attempted to clarify the criterion of the
debate by defining 'practice' as the 'revolutionary practice
50
of the masses,.18 A theory's value should be determined
in accordance with how it actually advantages 'social
productive forces, socialism and the masses'. The article
implies that a theory's utilitarian value is of central
importance.
In July, Renmin ribao for the first time published
Mao's 30/1/62 speech in which Mao accepted responsibility
for mistakes both he and his central committee had made -
indicating that the Chairman was fallible at his own
admission. In June, the same paper had stated that as
Marx, Engels and Mao had all been fallible, their theories
must constantly be revised, corrected and supplemented. The
paper stated that as truth was developing,
the development of ... Mao Zedong though undoubtedly involves the revision (xiuzheng) of some outmoded principles.19
At the end of July, Zhou Yang maintained that seeking truth
from facts did not deny the guiding function of Marxism-
Leninism-Mao Zedong thought, although the latter should be 20 seen as a developing doctrine rather than a dead dogma.
These statements suggest that Marxism-Leninism-Mao Zedong
thought was no longer to be regarded as absolute truth. This
in turn implied that it could be criticized, albeit from the
point of view of 'practice'. It also implied that new
theories verified by practice could be added to it. These
developments served to loosen the definitions of ideological
orthodoxy to the point that by October, Renmin ribao was
calling for the purging of all the superstitious qualities
that the Cultural Revolution had attributed to Mao Zedong 21
thought.
51
However, the campaign encounted considerable
resistance as indicated by a number of articles in the 22
official press. Though not quoting opposing views, the
articles nonetheless attest to the existence of opposition.
Something of a literary debate occurred between Guangming
ribao and Renmin ribao in August and September on the question of absolute and relative truth.23 Something of a
more fundamental difference of opinion is evidenced by the
fact that by November, the party theoretical journal Hong
qi had yet to endorse the shishi qiushi campaign. While
Renmin ribao waxed lyrical on the subject, Hong qi
maintained a conspicuous silence.
In fact, wallposters
attacking Hong qi for its silence appeared in early November. 24
Differences of opinion were further evidenced by the
sudden withdrawal from circulation of the first edition
of Zhongguo qingnian on 11 September only hours after its
, , , 1 d i i.bu t.i 25
lnltla lstrl utlon.
When it reappeared on 21 September,
its contents were unaltered but for the addition of two
loose sheets which carried Mao's photo, some poems by Mao
and some calligraphy by Hua. It would seem that the
magazine had been too zealous in its reappraisal of Mao
by not even acknowledging him on the second anniversary of
his death.
Both the Hong qi and the Zhongguo qingnian cases
suggest dissension within the highest levels of the party
on the programme of de-Maoization which had been set in
motion by Deng's shishi qiushi campaign. Such dissension
could be explained by the fact that a number of Central
52
Committee members owed their position to their relationship
with Mao, not least of whom was Hua Guofeng.
However, that the supporters of the campaign prevailed
over their opponents was attested by the fact that by
October, twenty-five of the twenty-six provinces had
announced their support for the campaign. The only province 26 to remain silent was Hunan - the province of Hua Guofeng.
The overall effect of the campaign was two-fold. First,
it stated that a thing should be evaluated on the basis of
its practical utility rather than on its class character or its
ideological rectitude generally.
It provided a new frame of
analysis which was officially sanctioned. It is significant
that a number of the wallposters of November invoked shishi
qiushi as their rationale for attacking all manner of things.27 Second, the campaign specifically addressed itself
to a re-evaluation of Marxism-Leninism-Mao Zedong thought,
Mao Zedong himself and the Cultural Revolution.
It is again
significant that these were the issues which became the
focus of the wallposter attacks.
At least in terms of the
re-evaluation of Mao, it seems that the wallposters took up
where the official campaign left off.
A third liberalizing campaign seems to have been 28
launched in September, using a variety of slogans such as
'emancipate thinking' (jiefang sixiang), 'give full play to
democracy' (fayang minzhu) and 'strengthen socialist
democracy and the socialist legal system' (jiaqiang
what can generally be described as a democratization
campaign. On 18 September, Renmin ribao printed a lengthy
53
article entitled Uphold the Principles of Socialist Democracy (Jianchi shehuizhuyi minzhu de yuanze) stating that by the turn of the century, the Chinese people 'are completely capable of realizing a strong socialist state wi th a high level of economic modernization and a high
level of political democracy'.
In remarkably unremarkable
style, the article went on to point out that the main obstacles to the development of democracy lay in the feudal
and bureaucratic tendencies of leading cadres who were indifferent to the masses' material advantage and their 'rights of economic democracy'. However, following the
publication of this relatively innocuous piece, the official democratization campaign seems to have developed in different directions: one which emphasized democracy as a means of criticizing the 'Gang of Four' and realizing the 'Four Modernizations' and one which emphasized the nature of
democracy itself.
The former was undoubtedly the more cautious of the two in that it never attempted to define democracy. It simply invoked the term 'democracy' as a better way of coping with modernization and the 'Gang of Four'. This part of the campaign centred around the jiefang sixiang slogan - a slogan which the official press invariably attributed to Hua. On 15 October, Wenyi bao reported on a conference which it held on liberating thinking among literary workers. It stated that 'literature must produce the effect of
exploring and criticizing the "Gang of Four"', and that
literary innovation should be encouraged when it contributes to a more profound and penetrating criticism of the gang.29
54
Howeve~ such criticism should only be aimed at 'the enemies of socialism, not the socialist system itself,.30 And while
literary workers may criticize the defects of any particular
work, they 'must not immediately link themselves with
I, , l' I 31
po ltlca lssues
Subsequent articles in Renmin ribao confirmed "Nenyi bao's interpretation of jiefang sixiang.32 This campaign
carried no call for any fundamental political reform. In
fact it warned against any such political interpretation.
At best, it was a call for a more creative endorsement of
the regime's policies.
However, the democratization campaign also took a less
conservative direction, particularly in articles concerning
socialist democracy and the socialist legal system. This
part of the campaign proposed a number of actual reforms
Guangming ribao demanded 'a perfect legal system which
, 1 d "h' 33 , i.b d
lnsures peop es emocratlc rlg ts. Renmln rl ao state
that one of these rights was the right to elect cadres.
The paper called for resistance to 'such traditional
concepts that hold that "elections of cadres is ultra-
democracy.'" Cadres should be elected and after an
appropriate period in office, should stand for re-election.
Though the article does not stipulate which cadres should be
subject to such a system, it does speak of the advantages
of replacing 'leading members of county municipal or
the 'Gang of Four' for its inability to tolerate dissident
views and implies that dissidence should be countenanced by
55
the new regime. The article then goes on to enumerate
the rights of the citizens to criticize the state and the
right of a party member to criticize the party leadership.
Finally, the article infers that though these rights are
safeguarded by the constitution, 'struggle' is the only
b h' h t th' ff t' ,35
means y w lC 0 ensure elr e ec lve protectlon.
Unlike articles concerned with jiefang sixiang, these
articles underline the direct political significance of
the democratization campaign.
By mid-November, this democratization campaign in the
official press had become even more outspoken. Renmin ribao
stated that the success of the socialist transformation of
China did not mean that 'the struggle to fight for people's democracy had come to an end,.36 Despotism had still to be
eliminated. In a pointed reference, the article then
criticized what it described as the Confucian doctrine
that 'one should not talk about the emperor's shortcomings,.37
Elsewhere, it quoted Liu Bang of the Han as saying that
'the Qin dynasty fell because its emperor refused to listen
t i t Lc i 38
o crl lClsm .
This is perhaps the clearest call for
criticism of Mao and for the toleration of dissent generally
since the beginning of the official campaigns of 1978. As
Renmin ribao concluded, 'there is no reason why a communist
h Ld f ' " ,39
s ou ear crltlclsm .
The same 10 November edition of Renmin ribao carried
another article which called upon the leadership to conquer 'the theory of brilliant leadership,40 which again is a
reference to Mao. The article continued that the leadership should 'enthusiastically welcome criticism from the masses',41
irrespective of whether their criticisms accorded with facts.
56
And should the criticisms be accurate, 'they should be acted on,.42
On 13 November, the same paper reprinted an article
from the third edition of Zhongguo qingnian entitled
It is Necessary to Bring Democracy into Full Play and 43
Consolidate the Legal System. It will be recalled that
the first edition of Zhongguo qingnian was withdrawn for
its insufficiently reverential attitude towards Mao. In
the article reprinted on 13 November, it is stated that
'the workers real ownership in the economic field calls for corresponding democratic rights in the political field,.44
It goes on to cite Engel's questioning whether 'we demand
others to give us freedom of speech only for the purpose of suppressing free speech among our own ranks' .45 It responds
by stating that:
the people have the right to use the methods of extensive democracy including speaking out freely, airing views fully, writing big character posters, holding great debates, staging parades, demonstrations and even strikes against any cadre who lacks a democratic work-style,.46
The article then argues that it is fallacious to equate
democracy with bourgeois democracy and asks: 'why shouldn't
we instead of the bourgeoisie hold aloft the great banner 47
of democracy'. Finally, it asks a question similar to
one asked by Wei Jingsheng some months later:
Could it be that the people have followed the Communist Party for decades only to have a bunch of new overlords sitting on their backs.48
This is a strong statement. It is particularly strong in
that it comes from the organ of the Central Committee itself.
This article was published just three days before the
appearance of the first wallposters of the so-called 'Peking
57
Spring'. The article was undoubtedly the most outspoken of all those associated with the official democratization campaign, the shishi qiushi campaign and the campaign to study the constitution. All three of these campaigns
tended to encourage a plurality of views. At the very least, they elevated the notion of democracy to the level of general public consciousness and declared that this democracy was desirable. At most, it called for public criticism of Mao and the Cultural Revolution. Certainly, there were sobering aspects of the campaigns such as the inclusion of article fifty-six in the constitution and
the conservative character of the jiefang sixiang campaign which saw innovation in terms of its contribution to the
higher tasks of eliminating the gang's influence and promoting modernization. Nonetheless, the overall effect of the campaigns was one which suggested political liberalization - a liberalization which crystallized with the events of 15 November.
At the beginning of November, the Central Committee had convened an enlarged central work conference in preparation for the third party plennum which was held
18 - 22 December. Unofficial reports from Hong Kong49 suggest that the work conference produced heated exchanges between supporters of Deng Xiaoping and those of Wang Dongxing. The latter was identified with what was described as a 'whatever faction' (fanshi pai) - so named because its adherents supposedly endorsed 'whatever' Mao said. This fanshi pai was therefore in direct conflict with Deng's campaign for a re-evaluation of Mao. That Deng's supporters
58
prevailed during the November meetings is evidenced by
the decisions publicized on 15 November which repudiated
a number of Mao's policies.
The first of these decisions was the rehabilitation
of the last of those who had been labelled 'rightists'
after the 'Hundred Flowers' movement of 1957. In explaining
the decision, Renmin ribao stated that while the mainstream
of Mao's decisions were correct, it had to be admitted
'that owing to interference by wrong political lines, there were some innocent people wrongly charged,.50 Significantly,
the wording is such that there is ambiguity as to who was
responsible for these 'wrong political lines'. However, the
article then says that a number of 1957 'rightists' were
'truly wronged' and that the Central Committee had advised
the removal of their rightist designation. The obvious
implication was that Mao was wrong as it was his Central
Committee of September 1957 which officially sanctioned
th t i i crh t i ,51
e an 1-r1g 1st campa1gn.
The removal of the 'rightist'
designation also suggested a more favourable interpretation
of the 'Hundred Flowers' movement itself and its associated
demands for democracy and human rights.
The second decision of 15 November was a repudiation of
Yao Wenyuan's 1965 criticism of Wu Han's play Hai Rui
Dismissed from Office.
It will be recalled that Wu Han had
been critical of Mao in the aftermath of the 'Great Leap'
and that his play eulogized Peng Dehuai's defiance of Mao
in 1958. The publication of Yao's critique in November 1965
was reportedly at the personal request of Mao. Its
publication was subsequently described by the official
59
press as having triggered the Cultural Revolution. In its
repudiation of Yao's critique, Guangming ribao praised
Hai Rui as an 'impartial and upright official with a
courageous spirit
bold enough to speak the truth and
bold enough to point out the corrupt practices of the
. 52
court of that time'. It criticized Yao's interpretation
of the 'courageous spirit' as encouraging 'right
opportunists to attack the party', saying that such an
interpretation was applied in order to suppress popular
dissent. The article then said that 'the courageous spirit'
had always been promoted by the party. Taking Mao as its
reference, it then cited him as saying that all people
should be allowed to 'express their opinions freely so
that they dare to speak, dare to criticize and dare to
debate'. As with the decision on the rightists, Mao is criticized implicitly and the right to dissent is
asserted in a positive light.
The third and the most important of the decisions of
15 November was the rehabilitation of the Tiananmen
Incident by the Beijing Municipal Committee
with the
approval of the Central Committee.53 The announcement was
made in a Xinhua despatch late in the evening of the
fifteenth and followed by two lengthy articles appearing
in Renmin ribao on the twenty-first and twenty-second of
November entitled The Truth About the Tiananmen Incident
(Tiananmen shij ian de zhenmian).
The process leading up to the eventual rehabilitation
of the incident had begun soon after the fall of the 'Gang
of Four'. On the first anniversary of the incident, an
60
internal document was allegedly circulated to the effect
that Deng was not responsible for the incident, that Deng
would soon return to his duties and that the masses
behaviour in the incident itself was 'understandable'.
Yet it was the actions of a small number of counter-
revolutionaries among the masses that had 'created the
t 1 t' i.n c i.d t' 54
coun er-revo u lonary lnCl en .
On its second
anniversary, thousands of people again gathered in the
square and through posters and poems demanded the
rehabilitation of the incident. Some of these posters
called for the realization of democracy and human rights.
These calls included 'making the square into a democratic
forum' and declaring the fifth of April the 'China Poetry
Festival' when people could come to the square and exercise their rights of freedom of speech and publication.55 Signs
of an impending reversal of verdict began appearing in the official press as early as July 1978.56 The process
gained momentum after Wu De lost the mayoralty of Beijing
on 10 October. Wu De, among others, had been prominent in
the actual suppression of the incident. When a play
emphasizing the revolutionary character of the incident
was staged in Beijing in early November, it was clear that
rehabilitation was imminent.
The Renmin ribao articles explaining the reversal of
the incident's verdict sought to interpret the incident
as a spontaneous mass revolt against the 'Gang of Four',
ln support of Deng, Zhou and Mao. The exoneration of Mao
was to prove the most problematic. It was now claimed that
Mao had been struggling against the gang since 1975. Even
61
the famous poem about Qin Shihuang was now aimed at the
gang rather than Mao - though Renmin ribao makes an
apallingly weak attempt to explain this mysterious
h ' 57 metamorp OSlS.
In short, it was now the gang and the
gang alone who were the objects of the people's wrath
in April 1976.
The gang was also made solely responsible for the
suppression of the demonstrations. In the only reference
as to who actually ordered the militia to move in on the
demonstrators in the evening of 5 April, Renmin ribao
quotes 'the gang's sinister henchman in the Public Security Bureau,58 as saying that 'a united action will be carried out tonight,.59 The paper conspicuously avoids any
explanation of the activities of the then Minister for
Public Security - Hua Guofeng. Elsewhere, the article
rather limply defends Hua as having been persecuted by
the Gang after they had eliminated Deng. But the banquet
hosted by Hua on 17 April to honour those who had 'bravely
suppressed the counter-revolutionary incident in Tiananmen Square'is not mentioned in the article.60 There is also no
mention of Wu De's speech in the early evening of 5 April
in which he described the demonstrators as counter-
revolutionary and threatened to suppress them unless they
d i d 61
1sperse .
And there is no mention of Ni Zhifu who at
that time commanded the Beijing militia which participated in the actual suppression of the demonstration.62 These
omissions are understandable in that at the time of this
article's publication, Ni was a member of the Central
Committee, Wu a member of the Politbureau and Hua,
62
Chairman of the Party.
It was these decisions of 15 November - especially
the Tiananmen decision - that provoked the first wallposters. For the people of Peking who had experienced the bloody reality of Tiananmen, Renmin ribao's explanations proved completely inadequate. Emboldened by the liberalizing campaigns of the previous nine months and angered by the party's treatment
of 'their' incident, people protested.
THE ~HDER MOVEMENT
The movement, like its origins, was complex. In fact, the term 'movement' is a misnomer as there were many movements. There were movements in Beijing, Tianjin, Shanghai, Hangzhou and wuhan,63 of which the one in Beijing was undoubtedly the most important. There were, in turn, many submovements within the Beijing movement. There was criticisms of the sexual exploitation suffered by females. Rapidly rising prices of consumer commodities were also criticized. There were pleas for the redressing of personal grievances. There were pleas for food,clothing and employment from peasants who came to the capital from the provinces. There were calls for a thorough re-examination of the Tiananmen Incident while other lauded the
official account given in Renmin Ribao.
There were calls
for the rehabilitation of Peng Dehuai, Tao Zhu and Liu
Shaoqi as there were calls for the purging of Wu De, Wang Dongxing, Chen Xilian, Ji Dengkui and Ni Zhifu. There were attacks on Mao, Hua and even Deng. And there were refutations of these attacks on the central leadership. There were demands for democracy and human rights and repudiations of
63
these demands. Some posters rejected the socialist system
itself while others described the authors of such posters
as 'out and out counter-revolutionaries'. And there were
posters which supported the war against Vietnam. The
'movement' embraced all these themes. Some of them
undoubtedly enjoyed official sponsorship - or at least
the sponsorship of a faction within the regime. Other
themes were pursued in complete defiance of the regime.
These varied themes were expressed through varied media:
speeches, rallies, marches, wallposters and journals. Yet
this multifaceted movement did have one unifying symbol.
And that was a wall in the centre of Beijing which became
known as 'Democracy Wall'.
'Democracy Wall' was so named because it became for
people from Peking and the provinces a forum for free
expression. It was actually the back wall of a bus station
on the corner of Chang'an jie and Xidan dajie.
It was
not the only 'Democracy Wall' in Peking. Posters also
appeared near the Renmin ribao building in Wangfujing as
well as at two locations in Tiananmen Square itself beneath
the Monument of the Peoples Heroes (Renmin yingxiong
jinianbei) and beside the National Historical Museum (Guoli
lishi bowuguan). However, when people spoke of 'Democracy
Wall', they invariably referred to the Chang'an - Xidan
. 64
site as it was there that the activity was the most lntense.
It was at this wall that people exercised what was at that
time their constitutional right to 'put up big character
posters'. It was here that unofficial journals were sold.
And it was here that speeches were delivered, rallies were
64
held and protest marches began.
The history of the movement until the end of !"1arch
1979 broadly encompasses three periods. The first is from
16 November until 28 November when the movement seemed to
be at its height and without encountering any official opposition. The second period followed the publication of some sobering comments by Deng in Renmin ribao on 28
November and lasted until the third anniversary of the
death of Zhou Enlai in early January 1979. During this period, critics of the regime were relatively restrained whereas critics of the critics were increasingly outspoken. However, in the week following the anniversary, the entire nature of the movement changed. Disparate interests were brought together into a number of democratic societies which began producing their own journals. A number of these journals came increasingly into conflict with the regime
over such issues as democracy and human rights and increasingly drew direct fire from the official press. This third period lasted nearly three months until the publication of the 29 March circular which imposed substantial restrictions on the movement.
There are always inconsistencies with any attempt at periodization and this attempt is no exception. For example, some journals began publishing as early as November and some posters had been appearing sporadically in the weeks prior to the events of 15 November. Nonetheless, the periodization suggested above does account for the major developments in the life of the wider movement.
Immediately following the rehabilitation of the
65
Tiananmen Incident, two wallposters appeared on the wall:
one congratulating the Beijing Municipal Committee on its
fine decision and one criticizing the role played by Wu De
. th . f the' 'd t 65
In e suppresslon 0 lnCl en .
Though Wu had
recently been relieved of his duties as First Secretary of
the Peking Committee, he still retained his positions on
the politburo
and the Standing Committee of the National
Peoples Congress
(quanguo renmin daibiao dahui changwu
weiyanhui)
It was the fact that Wu had not been completely
removed from office that inspired many wallposters of the
following weeks. Posters accused Renmin ribao of protecting wu.66 Wu himself was accused of having delayed the
incident's rehabilitation and the suppression of the
September edition of Zhongguo qingnian which carried articles
commending the demonstrators'
. 67
actlons.
Other posters
claimed that Wu was a 'feudal fascist dictator who should be put on public trial,.68
On 24 November, posters implicated Ni Zhifu with Wu in
the suppression of the incident and demanded that 'both must give an account for their role,.69
On 25 November, Wang Dongxing became the third
politburo member,
and the most senior, to be attacked
by wallposters. Wang was criticized for 'decorating the
executioners' of Tiananmen - referring to those members of
Ni's militia who were honoured at Hua's banquet after the
suppression of the incident. Wang was also criticized for
his opposition to Deng's rehabilitation, Deng's shishi
. . h .' 70 .
qiushi campalgn and the magazlne Z ongguo qlngnlan. HlS
expulsion was called for.71
66
There was even opposition to Hua himself when a poster demanded that Deng rather than Hua write the inscription
for a book of Tiananmen poems. If Hua's inscription was
not removed, then the author warned that he would withdraw his poem from the collection.72 Elsewhere, it was stated that the two remaining resolutions of 7/4/76 - one promoting Hua and the other purging Deng - should be categorically
abrograted. In an ironic reference to Mao's supposed
remark to Hua that 'with you in charge, I am at ease'(ni banshi wo fangxin), the same author said in another poster that 'with Deng in charge, the people feel at ease' (Deng banshi min fangxin). Deng's good press among the wallposters was further enhanced by other posters praising individuals closely identified with Dengist policies. Hu Yaobang, Hu Qiaomu, Wan Li, Zhang Aiping and Zhao Ziyang who has since been elevated to the premiership in place of Hua.73
Common to Wu, Ni, Wang and Hua is that their political promotions were to varying degrees enhanced by the events
of the Cultural Revolution, or by the personal patronage
of Mao himself. Thus when the posters began attacking Mao, his political beneficiaries were at least indirect targets. On 20 November, Mao was accused of having supported the 'Gang of Four' in the suppression of the Tiananmen Incident and the subsequent removal of Deng.74 Another poster claimed that since 1966, there had been a struggle between two intra-party groups: the democrats led by Zhou and the fascist dictators represented by Mao.75 Three days later,
a poster announced the establishment of a 'Torch Society' (Huojushe) which dedicated itself to the eliminination of
67
all dictators. In an obvious reference to Mao, it said
t,pa t though Qin Shihuang had united the country, he should
be condemned for having 'oppressed the people and burnt 76
the books'.
Mao's Cultural Revolution was also criticized. A
poster which was signed 'Communist Youth League' members
(Gongchanzhuyi qingniantuan) described the Cultural
Revolution as both 'a disaster and a great leap backwards'
and held Mao personally responsible for the extreme violence
. f h 77
o t ose years.
Mao's image was tarnished even further by calls for the
rehabilitation of a number of leaders who had been purged
during the Cultural Revolution, chief among whom was Liu
Shaoqi. One poster proclaimed that 'the principles of Liu Shaoqi must be put into practice,.78 Another called for the rehabilitation of Tao Zhu and Peng Dehuai79 and there
were demands for the reinstatement of Peng Zhen who had
been First Secretary of the Beijing Committee until his purge in 1966.80
Such outspoken attacks on Mao's person, his purges
and his revolution not only threatened his prot~g~s but
also the more fundamental notions of revolution and class
struggle which Mao symbolized.
Other posters during this first period in the life of
the movement addressed themselves to vague concepts of
democracy. On 22 November, a poster signed Min Yi, or
'Interests of the People', proclaimed in banner headline
manner: 'Long Live Democracy, Long Live the People, Long Live the Spirit of 5 April' .81 In terms reminiscent of
68
Cultural Revolution populism, it said that leading cadres
should be directly elected by the masses after the model of
the Paris Commune. It was this poster that marked the
beginning of that part of the movement concerned with
democracy and later with human rights.
On 27 November, the first of the April Fifth Forum
(Siwu luntan) series called for the right of the individual
to choose his profession and the right for people to elect officials by secret ballot.82 Another poster demanded
the right to dissent:
Why must people be overthrown if they have different opinions ... why not let different opinions exist ... Liu and Peng had different opinions to Mao, so they became traitors.83
Other posters claimed that 'only those leaders who allow themselves to be criticized are good leaders,.84 Here there
are the initial calls for a political pluralism which were
eventually to prove unacceptable to the existing order.
On 26, 27 and 28 November, there were a series of
speeches, rallies and marches which marked the climax of
this initial phase of the movement. Western correspondents
estimated crowds of up to ten thousand people at some of
these meetings. One protest march extended over half a mile
along Changa'n jie with demonstrators shouting 'long live
d 1 I, f d 1 I' human rl'ghts,.85 emocracy, ong lve ree om, ong lve
At another rally, one orator proclaimed that as Yan'an was
the base for supporting the revolution of the 1940's, so 'Xidan is the base supporting democracy in China today,.86
These heady days immediately preceded an article
appearing in Renmin ribao in which Deng suggested that the
masses needed guidance in the exercise of democracy. During
69
this initial period, all aspects of the movement were
orginally related to the reversal of the verdict of the
Tiananmen Incident. That decision marked the headwaters
of a widening movement. There were no reports of posters
being torn down during this period. And there was only one
poster which attacked the movement and defended Hao as
I· h 87
a great revo utlonary ero.
However, with the publication
of the Renmin ribao article on 28 November, this period of
seemingly unrestricted blooming and contending came to an
end.
The change in the tone of the movement was evidenced
in the last days of November. In a rally on 28 November, in
addition to chanting 'support democracy', the crowd for
the first time chanted their support for Mao, Ye (Jianying)
Deng, the 'Four Modernizations' and 'Stability and Unity' (anding tuanjie) .88 On the following day, it was stated
at another rally that democracy and freedom should be discussed 'within the framework of socialism,.89 Agence
France Presse suggests that the authorities also began
conducting study sessions while actively discouraging
outdoor political activities. The study materials reportedly
included a Renmin ribao editorial on how to go about
correcting errors, if in fact there were any errors to be corrected.90 Though this toning down of the movement met with some resistance,91 it signified the beginning of a
period in which posters contended with one another on the
merits and de-merits of the system, rather than attacking
the system with the kind of unanimity evidenced in the
earlier period.
70
During this period, however, the attacks on Wang, wu
and Ni continued. And indeed they were extended to include
Ch 'I' d J' , 92
en Xl lan an l Dengkul.
They had also risen to
prominence during the Cultural Revolution and both were
politburo members at the time they were attacked by the
wallposters. Chen concurrently held the influential
position of Commander of the Beijing Military Region
(Beijing weishuqu silingyuan), in which capacity he shared
with others the responsibility for suppressing the
Tiananmen Incident. That the wallposter attacks on such
prominent figures continued unabated suggests that they
had been successfully isolated within the politburo itself,
as events of the following year were to prove.
The attacks on Mao also continued. He was again
criticized for his collaboration with the 'Gang of Four' and his role in handling the Tiananmen Incident.93 The Cultural Revolution was still criticized.94 There were still calls for the rehabilitation of Liu.95 And it was
during December that both Peng Dehuai and Tao Zhu were
actually rehabilitated - albeit posthumously. However, for
the first time, substantial numbers of posters began
appearing in Mao's defence.
On 2 December, a poster suggested that:
... if people who want to put up posters criticizing Chairman Mao would only give us their names, then we would smash their dog heads in.96
Another likened such critics to flies who gathered on
the wounds of a noble warrior and went on to urge the
organization of a 'Maoist faction' Mao pai to denounce those
who had criticized the Chairman. It stated that the
71
sacred task for their generation 'was not to examine Mao's
defects but to realize the four modernizations'.
It even
stated that as yet, there was not enough 'practice' by
which to test Mao's mistakes in the Cultural Revolution -
thereby indirectly criticizing Deng's much publicized
shishi qiushi campaign. It warned the people of the capital
to 'be on guard against those who lift up the banner of
democracy and liberty to slander the leadership'. 'Let our
foreign friends have peace of mind', the poster concluded,
implying that political dissension should be discouraged in
order to foster a stable environment which would be
. f" 97
attractlve to orelgn lnvestors.
This was an argument
which later appeared in the official press to justify the
eventual suppression of the movement. Posters such as this
sought to counter the criticism that Mao had suffered in
previous weeks.
Democracy also became a more contentious issue during
this period: it was contentious in the sense that its
apologists became more articulate and for the first time
came under attack itself. On 5 December, Wei Jingsheng
posted his first poster calling for a 'fifth modernization' -
democracy. On 7 December, the Zhongguo renquan tongmeng
(China Human Rights Alliance) posted its first poster. It
referred to a speech made by President Carter on the role of human rights in American foreign policy.98 It called
on Carter and Congress to 'pay attention to the state of
human rights in China' because the Chinese people 'did not
want to repeat the tragic life of the Soviet people in the Gulag Archepelego,.99 A week later, an open letter to
72
Carter and Brezinski was posted, calling on these 'prime
movers of the worldwide human rights' movement to 'speak out for the respect of human rights in China,.lOO Another
poster advocated the adaptation of the Yugoslov model of
'freedom of speech, publication, meeting, demonstration,
strike, press, religion, ideology, work, dwelling and 101
travel'. Finally, Renquan tongmeng published a nineteen
point manifesto on 5 January.l02 Among its demands were
calls for direct elections and public participation in the
formulation of government policy, including government
fiscal policy. It also carried an appeal to various
international human rights organizations to support the
Chinese movement. Thus, by the early new year, the 'human
rights movement' within the wider movement, had assumed
its own identity.
However, it did not go unchallenged. The first of the
Renquan tongmeng posters was torn down within twenty-four
h h' 1 d ' d' 103
ours.W en It was rep ace, It was torn own agaln. It
was attacked in a poster on 7 December which described
the American President as a'democratic emperor'. It went
on to cite the mass suicides by a thousand Christians in
Guyana as a testimony to 'the magnificent image of
't I' t d and f d I 104
capl a lS emocracy ree om .
Further indication
of opposition to the movement came with reports of increases
in plain clothes police at the wall and the arrest of two 105
people on 13 December.
It was also during this period that the dimensions of
the movement were widened through the arrival of large
numbers of peasants from the provinces in the hope of
73
bringing their local grievances to the attention of the
central authorities. It is debatable as to whether these
peasants should be considered as part of the 'wider movement'
or as their own separate entity. Certainly their demands
differed from the political activists in that they were
primarily concerned with basic material sustenance.
Nonetheless a common bond existed in that both groups
were making vocal demands of the authorities - a commonality
of purpose which was evidenced in an increasing degree of
co-operation between them. Posters attacked Renmin ribao
f . . h 106 h . d
or 19norlng t e peasants. T e peasants In turn seeme
to allign themselves with a number of the human rights
activists in the hope of furthering their own cause. And
activists such as Fu Yuehua attempted to organize the
peasants into an effective movement.
On 3 January, one of the many democratic groups
which had arisen during December announced that a rally
would be held in Tiananmen Square on 9 January to commemorate the anniversary of Zhou Enlai's death.l07 The
events of the week of the anniversary seemed to bring the
movement's consciousness back to the Tiananmen Incident
which had begun as an expression of the people's grief
over the premier's death. The rallies of 7 - 13 January
re-radicalized the movement.
It was during the week of the anniversary that at least eight unofficial journals appeared. lOB Among them
was Wei Jingsheng's Tansuo. Although unofficial journals
had appeared earlier, after the anniversary they replaced
the wallposters as the most important medium of expression
74
for the movement. It was also during this week that
peasant activists joined with the human rights advocates
in a march along Changanjie. The peasants now marched under banners of 'we want human rights,.109 After this march,
protesting peasants became increasingly active in the
. 1 110 caplta .
The movement was developing its own momentum,
independent of any course that the regime may have
originally intended.
During this third period, there were no reports of
further attacks on Wang, Wu, Ni,Chen or Ji. Only one poster called for Liuls rehabilitationlll and there was no
further mention of Peng Dehuai, Tao Zhu or Peng Zhen. The
attacks on Mao himself continued but they increasingly
became attacks on the communist system itself. These
developments suggest that for whatever purpose the regime
had allowed the movement to begin in the first place, and
whatever purpose it had subsequently used the movement
for, by early January it was clear that it was no longer
a vehicle for the realization of central policies.
This thesis is supported by the fact that during this
period, the new movement came into increasing conflict
with the authorities. In mid-January, an internal document
seems to have been circulated to the effect that the
municipal authorities were contemplating a crackdown.
Renquan tongmeng posted the text of a speech alleged to
have been given by the Second Secretary of the Municipal
Committee (Wang Shouyi) which stated that the activists
should be dealt with before they became counterrevolutionaries. 112 On 23 January, Renquan tongmeng
75
produced a poster in response to the alleged speech which
claimed that the exercise of one's constitutional rights
of freedom of speech could not be defined as counter-
1 . 113 revo ut1on.
On 25 January, Siwu luntan demanded that
the authorities retract their accusations.114 And Tansuo
inquired of the Municipal Committee:
Who gives you the right to speak like that. No one appointed you to make such accusations and you do not represent the hopes of the people. 115
That there was substance to their fears of impending
repression was evidenced with the arrest of Fu Yuehua on
23 February.
In mid-March, both Beijing ribao and Gongren ribao
attacked the movement's activists as lackeys of bourgeois
, '1' 116
1mper1a 1sm.
Again the journals counter-attacked.
They maintained that human rights was not a 'bourgeois
slogan but an expression of the profound desire of the people,117 and that the official press was engaging in 'absurd polemics,.118 On 25 March, Tansuo's special
edition accused Deng Xiaoping of betraying the movement
for the purpose of realizing his own dictatorial ambitions.
From the outset, Deng's support for the movement had been qualified. (See chapter four)l19 By mid-March, he
was attacking it publicly. When he was then attacked by
Tansuo, the suppression of the movement was inevitable.
Beijing ribao published a circular prohibiting all posters 120
opposing the leadership of the Communist Party. On
29 March, Wei was arrested. On 4 April, when Renquan
tongmeng protested against his arrest, its leaders were also arrested.12l Posters soon appeared praising Mao,
'76
the Cultural Revolution and the Beijing Municipal Committee
, 1 122 Clrcu are
Ironically, but by no means coincidentally,
the movement was suspended on the eve of the third
anniversary of the Tiananmen Incident.
'TANSUO' WITHIN THE WIDER MOVEHENT -t~ ,h
Tansuo ( 1q' \~, ) may be translated as I Exploration' ,
'Investigation' or 'Enquiry'. It was the name of the
unofficial journal edited by Wei Jingsheng.
The story of Tansuo originates with the posting of
Wei's poster The Fifth Modernization - Democracy And Other
Topics (Diwuge xiandaihua - minzhu ji qita) on 5 December.
A number of people subsequently contacted him to express
their support for his poster. At a meeting of these people
held on 1 January, Wei suggested the publication of a
magazine in order to attract a wider audience. It was
unanimously decided to launch Tansuo. Apart from Wei,
th' Y G 'd ' J' h 123
e prlme movers were ang uang, Lu Lln an LlU lngs eng.
In all, six editions of Tansuo were published, including
one special edition. These were published on 9 January,
29 January, 11 March, 25 March (Special Edition) I 9
September and 1 October. Of these I the latter two were
published after Wei's imprisonment and are therefore not
directly related to this study. The magazine was written
by hand and then mimeographed on a privately owned machine:
200 copies each for the first and second editions, 1000
copies for the third edition and 1700 for the special
d i 124 e ltlon.
They were sold for between 30 and 50 fen per
125 copy though the special edition sold for only 10.
Foreigners were usually charged higher prices. They were
77
sold at all three of Peking's 'Democracy Walls' - Xidan,
Wangfujing and Tiananmen Square. The third edition was
also taken to Tianjin for distribution. Given the population
of Peking, these details suggest an extremely modest
circulation though no figures are available to compare it
with other unofficial publications.
By the end of March, Tansuo had published a total of
thirty separate articles written by authors who used the
pen-names Jin Sheng, Chu Tian, Mu Mu, Liang Yao, Chun Si
(~. f:l:
and Ah Q. Jin Sheng ~
was Wei's
pen-name. Other articles were written in the name of the
'Editorial Department' (Bianjibu). Still others were
reprints from foreign magazines including Far Eastern
Economic Review, Ming bao, Dongxiang and the Amnesty
International Report on Political Imprisonment in the
People's Republic of China. Tansuo probably gained access
to these publications from the foreign community in Peking,
or possibly from members of their immediate families who
may have held senior administrative positions. Of the
thirty articles printed, eight are known to have been written by wei.126
Tansuo primarily addressed itself to political issues -
either polemical attacks on the regime or attempted
theoretical discourses on the ideal nature of government.
Though only one of its articles was specifically addressed
to the question of human rights, the wider notion of rights
was a continuing theme for most of its contributors.
Tansuo was one of many unofficial journals which
appeared during the life of the movement. Altogether, there
78
were at least twenty-seven such journals of which I have had
access to incomplete collections of fifteen - either as
t 1 t' . . . 1 127
rans a lons, reprlnts or orlglna s.
Some, such as
Qimeng (Enlightenment) began appearing when the movement
began. But most began in early January around the
anniversary of Zhou's death. And most were discontinued
after the suppression at the end of March, though a couple continued until early 1980.128 During the November - March
period, the number of editions produced by each of these
publications ranged from a single issue to as many as ten.
Altogether, the various journals produced some eighty-seven
editions of which Tansuo produced four - slightly less 120
than the average. J
Broadly, there were three types of journals. First,
there were those exclusively devoted to creative writing
such as Jintian (Today) and Baihua (Hundred Flowers) f
though the literary nature of these journals did not
preclude poignant political comment.
Second, there are journals with a relatively orthodox
political standpoint. These would include Beijing zhi chun
(Peking Spring), Renmin zhi sheng (Voice of the People) ,
Qimeng she (Enlightenment Society), Qunzhong cankao xiaoxi
(Reference News for the Masses), Qiushi bao (Truth), Minzhu
.yu shidai (Democracy and the Times), Qiushi (Harvest), Sihua
luntan (Four Modernizations Forum), and Women (Us). The
publication statements of these journals invariably pledged
the journals' support for the leadership of the Communist
Party. Beijing zhi chun's statement reads in part:
This pUblication takes Harxism-Leninism as its guide, adheres to the socialist road and follows
79
Comrade Mao Zedong's policy of letting a hundred flowers bloom.130
It is significant that some articles from this particular
publication were later included in officially commissioned
k 'h' i.d 131
wor s commemoratlng t e Tlananmen InCl ent.
A third group was comprised of those journals that
were not concerned about political orthodoxy. This group includes Renquan tongmeng,132 Tansuo and Jiedong (Thaw) of
which Tansuo was the most unorthodox. While Jiedong
dedicated itself to the abolition of the anachronisms contained in Marxism-Leninism-Mao Zedong thought,133
T 'd t' f . d 1 '1 134
ansuo re]ecte any no lon 0 an 1 eo oglca norm.
Of course, these are general groupings which do not
account for some journals' tendency to oscillate between
radical and conservative positions. Changes in policy were
often dictated by the political exigencies of the time.
One such journal was Siwu luntan which I have deliberately
omitted from the categories above. When it began, it
stated its opposition to 'bourgeois factionalism and
135 anarchy' and called for a correctly centralized democracy.
However, this conservative position contrasts with its
subsequent attacks on the regime for slandering the
movement and for its abuse of the law in its handling of
W ' 136 el.
Journals such as Siwu luntan defy any attempt at
categorization. Nonetheless, it is clear that Tansuo was
always at the radical fringe of the movement.
There were times when Tansuo co-operated with other
journals such as in a joint declaration by Tansuo, Siwu
Renmin luntan and Jintian published on 25 January. The
80
statement declared that articles forty-five and fifty-two
of the constitution rendered any criticisms of the movement
unconstitutional. It also committed itself to continuing
opposition to such criticism and support for those who
had been 'unconstitutionally arrested'. For Tansuo, this
was mild language. However, the joint declaration did
demonstrate its ability to co-operate with the wider
movement.
There were other times when the journals carried on
literary debates with one another. After Renquan tongmeng
split in March, one faction accused the other of betraying
the human rights cause and rival publications were established.137 Siwu luntan attacked Qimeng she which it
accused of deviating from the principle of 'making foreign
things serve China' by advocating the American model of democracy.138 Siwu luntan also attacked Tansuo over Tansuo's attack on Deng Xiaoping in its special edition.139
It was a diverse movement. Wei Jingsheng was one of a
number of authors who contributed to Tansuo. Tansuo was
one of a number of journals which appeared during the
movement. And journals were not the movement's only
medium of expression. However, the movement's diversity
should not obscure two fundamental facts: that the official
campaign that was subsequently directed against the movement
concentrated its attack on the movement's position on
human rights and that of all the movements activists, Wei
1 b bl" 1 140
was the on y one to e put on pu lC trla .
For these
reasons alone, it is necessary to examine Wei's specific
notion of human rights.
81
CHAPTER THREE
WEI JINGSHENG ON HUMAN RIGHTS
82
BIOGRAPHY
Little is known about Wei's background. The only
reliable source of information is the transcript of his trial.l He was born in 1950 in Chao District in Anhui
Province. His class origin (chushen) is given as
revolutionary cadre (geming ganbu), indicating that either
or both his parents were party members. It has been
suggested that his father was a deputy director of the
State Capital Construction Commission (guojia jiben jianshe
. hu i.) 2
welyuan Ul .
However, this cannot be verified.
He attended both primary and high school in Beijing.
When he graduated from the Junior High School attached to
the People's University (Renmin daxue fuzhong) in the
Spring of 1966, Beijing was experiencing the initial
convulsions of the Cultural Revolution. Between 1966-68, Wei served as a Red Guard both in Beijing and shanghai.3
Along with most other Red Guards, he was 'sent down to
the countryside' (xiaxiang) in 1968 where he spent more
than a year 'learning from the poor and lower-middle peasants' in his native province of Anhui.4 He then served
as a soldier both in Anhui and Shanxi until his discharge
in 1973. Wei was then employed by the Beijing Municipal
Parks Service as an electrician in its Administrative
Office. (Beijingshi gongyuan fuwu guanlichu). There he
remained until his arrest on 29 March 1979.
DIFFICULTIES IN ANALYSIS
In the first three editions of Tansuo, Wei wrote the
following articles: the Publication Statement (Fakan
83
shengming), The Fifth Modernization - Democracy And Other Topics, The Fifth Modernization - Democracy And Other Topics Part II, (Xu diwuge xiandaihua - minzhu ji qita) ,
The Fifth Modernization - Democracy And Other Topics, Part III (Zaixu diwuge xiandaihua - minzhu ji qita) , The 'Limits' to Democracy (Minzhu de 'xiandu'), Human Rights, Equality and Democracy (Renquan pingdeng yu minzhu), The Bastille
of the Twentieth Century - Qincheng Number One Prison
(Ershi shiji de Bashidiyu - Qincheng yihao jianyu) and the
special edition's Democracy or a New Dictatorship (Yao minzhu haishi yao xinde ducai).5 Of these eight, five
have Wei's pen-name Jin Sheng while he admitted having written the other three during his cross-examination during the trial.6
However, in the course of the trial, Wei also admits
to having written 'most of the articles' appearing in Tansuo. If taken literally, this would imply that he was responsible for at least fifteen articles. Wei was responsible for reviewing all manuscripts prior to their inclusion in the journal, though the final decision to include an article seems to have been taken by a meeting of all the contributors. Though Wei may have exercised general editorial responsibility for the journal,7 it cannot be conclusively established that he actually wrote any more
than the eight articles listed above.
In any case, these
were the articles which provided the central thrust of the journal.
An analysis of the ideas contained in Wei's articles is fraught with its own difficulties. First, Wei was
84
principally a polemicist. He was more adept at attacking the regime over its abuse of human rights than he was at systematizing his attacks into a comprehensive theory of human rights. And polemical literature by its very nature does not lend itself to a systematic conceptual analysis. In fact, there is a danger in attempting to systematize
such literature in that it imposes a logical structure which may not be evident in the original.
Second, Wei's polemics are at times contradictory.
Wei had been isolated from western intellectual traditions as well as his own classical tradition. Even his regular education had been seriously interrupted by the Cultural Revolution which in turn, effectively prevented him from attending university. Therefore, when Wei came to address himself to the notion of human rights, he had no alternative but to begin at its conceptual beginnings. That some of
his notions apparently contradict one another is completely understandable in this sense.
Therefore, any analysis of Wei must take into account both these sets of complexities. To weld Wei's disparate ideas into a cohesive conceptual scheme would only result
in an inaccurate impression. Wei's ideas need to be
analyzed article by article in order to accurately ascertain both the consistencies and the contradictions in his argument.
ANALYSIS
Perhaps the most fundamental of Wei's convictions concerned the absolute or relative nature of truth. It will be recalled that Deng's shishi qiushi campaign had suggested that Marxism-Leninism-Mao Zedong thought should be viewed
85
in accordance with the particular dictates of any given
time or place. Indeed, it had corne close to suggesting
that shishi or reality should be the ultimate determinant or orthodoxy. It involved only a small step to then conclude that all truth was relative and subject to unfettered enquiry. The regime avoided this step by making the contradictory claim that though Marxism-Leninism-Mao Zedong thought be 'scientifically revised', this revision would in no way alter its status as 'scientifically revealed truth'. There were others who were less willing to accept the contradiction. Among them was Wei who rejected all the parameters of what had hitherto been accepted as orthodoxy. His commitment to a relativist understanding of truth was fundamental to his other proposals.
These proposals were principally threefold: First, that the individual had the inherent right to seek selffulfillment; second, that this right should be protected
by a democratic system - a system based on a total rejection of the 'Marxist' model and a partial adaptation of 'Western' democratic concepts; third, that these reforms be achieved through struggle. These are the themes (including his
theme on the relativity of truth) that will be examined in this examination of seven of Wei's articles.8
As will become evident, not all the essays deal with all of these themes. If my analysis neglects anyone theme in a discussion of anyone article, it is because Wei himself has not mentioned it. There is, however, sufficient continuity between his articles to explore the development of his various themes - developments which at times appear contradictory.
86
Wei's Publication Statement defines his relativist
understanding of truth from the outset. Article three of
the statement reads:
Our explorations (tansuo) shall be based on realities in Chinese and world history. In other words we do not recognize the absolute correctness of any theory or person. All theories, including current theories and those which may emerge soon, shall be the themes for our discussions as well as the tools for analysis.9
Wei's reference to 'realities' and 'tools for analysis',
are concepts parallel to those used in the official press
in the shishi qiushi campaign. But Wei's implicit rejection
of Mao and Mao Zedong thought went beyond even that
campaigns elastic parameters of acceptability.
The Publication Statement has no explicit reference
to the individual or individual rights. It does refer to
the need to develop people's spiritual lives (jingshen
shenghuo) - a theme to which he returns in a later article criticizing the 'soullessness of Marxism,.lO In the same
sentence, he refers to the need to speedily achieve
d . . 11
mo ernlzatlon.
In the context of the sentence, this
'modernization' is simply a means towards an end which is
the people's spiritual and material wellbeing. However,
the nature of Wei's 'modernization' varies in some of his
later writings.
Though Wei's 'Fifth Modernization' essays were written
as a trilogy, there is little evidence of a continuing
theme.
It seems that after the posting of Wei's first
and most famous 'Modernization' poster, Wei used the title
a second and third time to symbolize a certain style of
writing - namely invective. The three essays do not
87
represent a cumulative thesis on democracy.
In the first of these essays, Wei elaborated on the
relationship between the individual and modernization:
Why is human history oriented towards progress - which may also be called modernization. It is because mankind needs all the advantages which
only a developed society can provide. It is because the social consequences of these advantages are the surest way to achieve the primordial human objective in its pursuit of happiness - and that is freedom. 12
And again
The only reason why we want to achieve modernization is to ensure democracy, freedom and happiness for the people.13
Here, the ultimate human aspiration is happiness, though
Wei speaks of the people's rather than the individual's
happiness. Nonetheless, modernization is a means to that
happiness rather than a prescription for the national wealth
and power dreamt of by earlier 'liberal' reformers.
Wei contrasted this notion of modernization with the
regimes campaign for the 'Four Modernizations'. He
criticized its use of the campaign to consolidate its own
dictatorship. He likened the campaign to the Great Leap
Forward, the Cultural Revolution and even the shishi qiushi
campaign. All held out a vision of utopia. All used that
vision to justify the need for strong centralized leadership
to co-ordinate the people - those 'dutiful packhorses of the
revolution' .
In Wei's view, the people were no more than
'mere tools in the hands of despots with expansionist
b't' ,14 am l lons .
Wei distinguishes his modernization, which aspires to
such liberal values as 'freedom and happiness', from the
regime's campaign which is seen as no more than a ploy to
88
consolidate its own power.
Wei maintained that his modernization could only be
achieved through democracy - which Wei describes as the
'Fifth Modernization':
If the Chinese people wish to modernize, they must first establish democracy. They must first modernize China's social system.lS
Wei argued that without democracy, the economy would
continue to stagnate. With democracy, production would
increase because the producers would be working 'in their
own interests'. This would cause an economic recovery.
However, it will be recalled that one of the purposes
he assigned to modernization was to 'ensure democracy'.
Therefore, Wei's democracy is both a means to an end, and
an end itself.
It is both the prerequisite of modernization
and the object of modernization. It is the state of
'happiness' to which he aspires and the system through which
he must work to achieve that 'happiness'. And Wei is
seemingly unaware of the distinction.
Wei attacks Marxism and Maoism as antithetical to
democracy. He accepts what he terms as Marx's original
concept of socialism though not explaining what he
understands that concept to be. But he rejects the
dissonance between Marxist theory and practice:
"The people are the masters of history" is mere hollow chatter. Its emptiness is plain because we see that in point of fact, the people are deprived of any possibility to determine their fate according to the wishes of the majority.16
He attributes the Chinese people's powerlessness to the
evolution of a Maoist dictatorship:
89
After the Chinese Communist Party victory, what came of all the earlier promises (of democracy) . First, they changed the slogan "People's Democratic D~ctatorship" into the "Dictatorship of the Proletariat". And the last leftovers of democracy ... disappeared too, to be replaced by the personal despotism of the Great Leader.17
In fact, he went on to equate China with Nazi Germany and
warned that it was only through democracy that the Chinese
people could escape the fate suffered by their German counterparts. 18
Wei's notion of democracy is primarily defined in
terms of a number of foreign models. He states quite boldly
that:
If one compares the democratic centralism of socialist countries with the democracy of the exploiting classes in capitalist regimes, the difference is as great as between night and day.19
However, he then equates democracy with both the Yugoslav
and the American models. It was both a system which gives
'all power to the worker's collective' and a system which
'allows the people to choose ... representatives who
administer in the name of the people' and who can always be 20
replaced by the people. Wei's commitment to economic
as well as political democracy implies that there is no
private property in his scheme. But this seems to
contradict his earlier statement regarding the producers
working in their own interests. His commitment to the
'right to recall' may be as much drawn from his experiences
in the Cultural Revolution as from his reading of the
American constitution. Nonetheless, his notion of
representative government, however illdefined, is clearly
at variance with the doctrine of democratic centralism.·