Characteristics of Politics
Characteristics of Politics
Characteristics of Politics
This essay argues that the study of discourse is an inevitable part of political science, but
should not be the single focus of the discipline as suggested by many discourse analysts.
The premise that politics and power is made up of ʻhuman individuals participating in forms
the need for a hermeneutical angle to politics through discourse analysis, since we can
use this angle to further understand the ʻhuman individualsʼ that make up and are the
As a start, this essay will offer a clear assessment of what the study of political science is
focussed on and what definitions in that field give us a clearer need for a more prominent
use of discourse analysis. Secondly, this essay will elaborate on what ʻthe study of
discourseʼ entails and what can be seen as weaknesses and strengths in discourse
analysis. This essay will approach the study of discourse from the premise of political
science, instead of vice versa. Studying the core features of political science first to
determine what it lacks, needs or could use that discourse analysis has to offer.
And third, this essay assesses what benefits and additions discourse theory poses for the
study of the political and political science and how these features can be further
Discourse theory is a crucial part of social sciences and political science in specific, for the
focus of these disciplines is largely on the human individual and how their relations and
activities constitute the ʻsocialʼ in ʻsocial sciencesʼ. As a conclusion this essay sees
discourse as a very important study within political science, and therefore significant to a
1
981418
What is ʻpolitical scienceʼ? This is a logical question to start with when determining if
political science itself could benefit from the study of discourse. ʻWhat is the nature and
purpose of political science? Posed in such a direct and stark manner, this may well be a
rather uncomfortable question to ask.ʼ (Hay, 2002, p.64) Not only is this question a rather
uncomfortable question, the posed answers in academia are rather confusing and
numerous as well. Leftwich tries to narrow it down by assessing that most academics are
concerned ʻwith the analysis of the origins, forms, distribution and control over
power.ʼ (Leftwich, 2004, p.2) or the ʻstudy of influence and the influentialʼ (Lasswell in
Leftwich, 2004, p.2). The terms coined in these definitions - such as power and influence -
show a strong trend: they are all extremely subjective and depend almost entirely on
interpretation and perception. This leaves us with the question of how we can or should
construct our perception and interpretation of definitions like that. Whose subjectivity and
interpretation do they depend on? One clear characteristic is the involvement of humans
and social conventions. This seems to be one of the few clear and widely agreed upon
(Leftwich, 2004, pp.1-2). Or as Bevir and Rhodes put it: ʻpeople act on their beliefs and
preferencesʼ (in Marsh & Stoker, 2002, p.132) Bevir and Rhodes thus acknowledge that
beliefs and preferences - such as concepts of power - are created and acted upon by
people themselves. This essay will elaborate on this angle to politics, power and discourse
The study of discourse sees ʻlanguage as a form of social practiceʼ (Fairclough, 2001, p.
18) and ʻassumes that all objects and actions are meaningful, and that their meaning is
conferred by historically specific systems of rulesʼ (Howarth, Norval & Stavrakakis, 2000,
p.2). But discourse theorists ʻfirmly reject the search for scientific laws of society and
2
981418
politics grounded on empirical generalizations, which can form the basis of testable
Language in this case is not limited to the system or code we most commonly refer to, but
more general to all signs and symbols that convey meaning. Discourse theorist like to refer
to texts. Fairclough claims it is good to move towards a wider and more cultural concept of
a text, not only having a text refer to written or spoken language but to basically any
cultural artifact. (1995, p.4) Fairclough uses television as a clear example: it is not only the
spoken or written words that convey the information, but also the visual images, music and
sound effects.
Discourse analysts argue from a relativist point of view that our concepts of the world rely
on our interpretation and relative view of it. There is no ʻreal worldʼ - or ʻreal politicsʼ for that
matter - only the relative definitions and interpretations we accept as true or viable. This
discursivity signifies a clear playing field for discourse theory. Laclau elaborates clearly on
The fact that every object is constituted as an object of discourse has nothing to do
with whether there is a world external to thought, or with the realism/idealism
opposition. An earthquake or the falling of a brick is an event that certainly exists, in
the sense that it occurs here and now, independently of my will. But whether their
specificity as objects is constructed in terms of 'natural phenomena' or 'expressions
of the wrath of God', depends upon the structuring of a discursive field. What is
denied is not that such objects exist externally to thought, but the rather different
assertion that they could constitute themselves as objects outside any discursive
condition of emergence.
Popper even goes on to claim that our entire perception is not based in observation: ʻThe
By seeing that discourse theory does not reject the existence of an ʻexternal worldʼ - as
described by Laclau - and that it thus creates a stable basis for different ontological
3
981418
approaches, we can see that it is basically designed as a research or observational tool for
acknowledging the hermeneutic and interpretivist angle to the political it can provide a
useful tool in analysing political science, rather than being the only appropriate view.
So discourse and politics are not two different or separate entities; there is no external, but
an internal relationship. Discourse is part of politics and highly interconnected with both the
practice and the study of politics. (Fairclough, 2001) Shown in the observation that politics
is defined and practiced by humans and therefore dependent on their perception and
interpretation.
political science, since it is a clear part and foundation of the science itself. This essay will
further determine to what extent discourse analysis proves to be important and what it
This essay agrees with Purvis and Hunt that the attempt by discourse analysts to reduce
politics entirely to hermeneutics is not feasible, but that hermeneutics and discourse theory
are too crucial and useful to political science to be ignored. Discourse theorists should
aspire offering tools, guidance and new dimensions to political science instead of claiming
By trying to define for example politics, we also define what it is not at the same time. By
claiming politics is concerned with the study of government, we immediately create the
opposite definition of politics not being the study of e.g. gender relations. Discourse
4
981418
theorists see this an oppression of certain groups in society. By labeling people as ʻblackʼ
or ʻwhite, or ʻgayʼ or ʻstraightʼ, these actors are put into groups/boxes in society by the
groups that manage to use language to construct power most effectively. Discourse
theorists therefore claim that in society every individual should aspire to step out of these
identities and devise a personal purpose within society. However, this approach clearly
Because when feminists stop identifying themselves as feminists, but start devising
separate identities, it will be unlikely for these people to identify with one another, in this
case identify with feminism. On an arena level this ʻgroupʼ will thus lose its claims to power
and fall apart in individual agents with all different identities. Not having binary oppositions
at an arena level can have serious consequences in power levels for individuals that have
This examples shows how too much emphasis on using the ʻcorrectʼ and open discourse -
or none at all - can affect the outcome negatively. And sticking with the feminist example
this essay sees another clear problem with using the concept of discourse theory too
extensively in this way. Discourse analysts do not leave enough space for the effects and
implications of context.
Social identities are exceedingly complex. They are knit from a plurality of different
descriptions arising from a plurality of different signifying practices. Thus, no one is
simply a woman; one is rather, for example, a white, Jewish, middle-class woman, a
philosopher, a lesbian, a socialist, and a mother. Moreover, since everyone acts in a
plurality of different social contexts, the different descriptions comprising any
individualʼs social identity fade in and out of focus. (Wexler, 1991, p.99)
It is especially this last point that is commonly overlooked by discourse analysts. The way
we are identified or like to identify ourselves relies heavily on the context we are in. And
there is an other aspect: the aspect of time. ʻIt is not the case that peopleʼs social identities
are constructed once and for all and definitively fixed. Rather, they alter over time, shifting
So when discourse theorists are left to construct a political system, this system will lack
identityʼ (Howarth, Norval & Stavrakakis, 2000, p.208) as an absolute necessity in decent
political environments. Practically no discourse theorists aim for something in the middle of
ʻno fixed identitiesʼ and ʻcomplete societal fixed identitiesʼ. This shows how discourse
this essays still hold that discourse analysis is a strong tool in making political science
more comprehensive.
In conclusion, this essay has argued that the study of discourse and political science are
indissoluble and that discourse clearly is a part of political science. Discourse theory can
not offer a foundation comprehensive enough for the entire discipline of political science to
be based on. It does however offer crucial and useful tools to further assess practices and
processes in political science. And since political science consists of ʻhuman individuals
1993, p.474) this essay acknowledges a clear need for a hermeneutical stance to politics
through discourse theory. Discourse theory in the end offers us a better understanding of
ʻhuman individualsʼ and how ʻpeople act on their beliefs and preferencesʼ (in Marsh &
6
981418
Bibliography
Fairclough, Norman, (1995), Critical Discourse Analysis : The Critical Study of Language,
New York: Addison-Wesley Longman
Fairclough, Norman, (2001), Language and Power, New York: Addison-Wesley Longman
Hay, Colin, (2002), Political Analysis : Contemporary Controversies, New York: Palgrave
Macmillan
Howarth, David, Aletta J. Norval, and Yannis Stavrakakis, eds. (2000), Discourse Theory
and Political Analysis : Identities, Hegemonies and Social Change, New York: Manchester
UP
Laclau, Ernesto, (2001), Hegemony and Socialist Strategy, New York: Verso Books
Leftwich, Adrian, (2004), What Is Politics? : The Activity and its Study, New York: Polity P
Marsh, David, and Stoker, Gerry, eds., (2002), Theory and Methods in Political Science,
New York: Palgrave Macmillan
Meehan, Eugene, (1982), "Norms and Values." International Political Science Review/
Revue internationale de science politique 3, pp. 254-56
Purvis, Trevor & Hunt, Alan, (1993), “Discourse, Ideology, Discourse, Ideology, Discourse,
Ideology…”, The British Journal of Sociology, Vol. 44, No. 3, pp. 473-499
Thiele, Leslie P., (2000), "Common Sense, Judgment, and the Limits of Political Theory."
Political Theory 28, pp. 565-88