Alchemy's exile as a "pseudoscience" or worse was created in the eighteenth century. Principe: alchemy now holds an important place in the history of science. He says Alchemists have rehabilitated their status by studying the documentary sources.
Alchemy's exile as a "pseudoscience" or worse was created in the eighteenth century. Principe: alchemy now holds an important place in the history of science. He says Alchemists have rehabilitated their status by studying the documentary sources.
Alchemy's exile as a "pseudoscience" or worse was created in the eighteenth century. Principe: alchemy now holds an important place in the history of science. He says Alchemists have rehabilitated their status by studying the documentary sources.
Alchemy's exile as a "pseudoscience" or worse was created in the eighteenth century. Principe: alchemy now holds an important place in the history of science. He says Alchemists have rehabilitated their status by studying the documentary sources.
Source: Isis, Vol. 102, No. 2 (June 2011), pp. 305-312 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of The History of Science Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/660139 . Accessed: 29/08/2011 16:19 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. The University of Chicago Press and The History of Science Society are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Isis. http://www.jstor.org Alchemy Restored By Lawrence M. Principe* ABSTRACT Alchemy now holds an important place in the history of science. Its current status contrasts with its former exile as a pseudoscience or worse and results from several rehabilitative steps carried out by scholars who made closer, less programmatic, and more innovative studies of the documentary sources. Interestingly, alchemys outcast status was created in the eighteenth century and perpetuated thereafter in part for strategic and polemical reasonsand not only on account of a lack of historical understanding. Alchemys return to the fold of the history of science highlights important features about the development of science and our changing understanding of it. P ROBABLY THE LAST ACADEMIC ORATION ABOUT ALCHEMY given in the Netherlands took place at Leiden in December 1737. The speaker was the physician Abraham Kaau, and he entitled his address On the Joys of the Alchemists. 1 While the title might seem to promise a positive portrayal of alchemy, Kaaus oration was in fact a mocking account of the ancient art, and one can imagine his audiences laughter at alchemys expense. By 1737, in the Netherlands at least, alchemy had no serious public defenders. The subject had become emblematic of foolishness, a relic of the past, a source of amusing entertainment (as Kaau used it), or an example of what chemistry was not. In 1737, chemistry was a serious academic discipline and an increasingly important com- mercial practice, and in Kaaus mind alchemy had very little connection with it. This was not the case just twenty years earlier. In September 1718, an earlier generation of Leiden professors had gathered to hear the inaugural oratie of their newly appointed professor of chemistry. This new chemistry professor was, ironically enough, Abraham Kaaus uncle and a much more famous personHerman Boerhaave. In 1718, the trans- mutation of metals into gold remained a serious topic of study for many and one of the enterprises that most readily characterized chemistry for the general public. Boerhaave did not mock chemistrys past, but he did nd it necessary to apologize for it. Entitled Chemistry Purging Itself of Its Errors, his oration defended chemistry from critics. I * Department of the History of Science and Technology and Department of Chemistry, 301 Gilman Hall, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, Maryland 21218. 1 Abraham Kaau, Declaratio academica de gaudiis alchemistarum, in Perspiratio dicta Hippocrati (Leiden, 1738). I exclude from the list of Dutch alchemical orationes inaugurales the oratie I gave at Utrecht University on 1 June 2010, which forms a basis for the present essay. F O C U S Isis, 2011, 102:305312 2011 by The History of Science Society. All rights reserved. 0021-1753/2011/10202-0005$10.00 305 must talk about chemistry! Boerhaave lamented. About chemistry! A subject disagree- able, vulgar, laborious, far from the affairs of intelligent people, and ignored or considered suspect by the learned . . . a discipline fruitful of errors, the poorest in good fruit, the progenitor of poverty, the bankruptor of wealth, the destruction and ruin of common sense. 2 Boerhaave was both embarrassed by and proud of chemistry. We are horried and embarrassed by the silly nonsense into which the crowd of chemists plunges with sinful trespass. What fables, superstititions, and fancies! Hardly anywhere can more raving madness be found. His words are understandable only when we recognize that many in his audience did not see a clear distinction between what we call alchemy and chemistry. The search for metallic transmutationwhat we call alchemy but that is more accu- rately termed chrysopoeiawas ordinarily viewed in the late seventeenth century as synonymous with or as a subset of chemistry. This terminological issue is why William Newman and I suggested using the archaically spelled chymistry to refer to the entire subject before its separation into alchemy and chemistry in the early eighteenth century. 3 Many chymists pursued chrysopoeia as part of their activities, and in doing so they employed the same techniques, instruments, and guiding principles as in the rest of their work. All their chymical activities were unied by a common focus on the analysis, synthesis, transformation, and production of material substances. The sundering of chryso- poeia from chymistry was under way when Boerhaave spoke in 1718, and he is among those who promoted it, explaining that the new chemists of his daylike himselfwere busy making their subject respectable and that his colleagues had nothing to fear from this questionable subject. The banishment of chrysopoeiaincreasingly called alchemy in the early eighteenth centuryfrom respectable chemistry remains a topic of study. Yet it is clear that devel- opments in the understanding of nature had little to do with it. No new theories or experiments sounded the death knell for chrysopoeia, and the arguments used against it in the 1720s were the same as those used routinely and ineffectively since the Middle Ages. Early eighteenth-century antialchemical rhetoric, however, laid new emphasis on fraud- ulent practices. It was spokesmen for scientic societies and institutionslike Bernard de Fontenelle and E
tienne-Francois Geoffroy at the Academie Royale des Sciences and
Boerhaave at Leidenwhere chemistry was struggling to take on a new identity in terms of professionalization and social legitimacy, who led the charge. They cast alchemy as an intellectual taboo, its practitioners as socially unacceptable and disruptive, and its content and practice as something other than the chemistry they represented. This campaign was so successful that chrysopoeia disappeared from respectable circles within a generation (although some of the most prominent eighteenth-century chemists who rejected it publicly continued to pursue it privately). 4 2 Herman Boerhaave, Sermo academicus de chemia suos errores expurgante (Leiden, 1718), rpt. in Elementa chemiae, 2 vols. (Paris, 1733), Vol. 2, pp. 6477, on pp. 6566; for an English translation see E. Kegel- Brinkgreve and Antonie M. Luyendijk-Elshout, eds., Boerhaaves Orations (Leiden: Brill, 1983), pp. 193213. On Boerhaave see John C. Powers, Inventing Chemistry: Herman Boerhaave and the Reform of the Chemical Arts (Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press, in press). 3 Boerhaave, Sermo academicus de chemia suos errores expurgante, p. 66; and William R. Newman and Lawrence M. Principe, Alchemy vs. Chemistry: The Etymological Origins of a Historiographic Mistake, Early Science and Medicine, 1998, 3:3265. 4 This topic forms one major theme of my forthcoming Wilhelm Homberg and the Transmutations of Chymistry; for a brief version see Lawrence M. Principe, A Revolution Nobody Noticed? Changes in Early Eighteenth-Century Chymistry, in New Narratives in Eighteenth-Century Chemistry, ed. Principe (Dordrecht: 306 FOCUSISIS, 102 : 2 (2011) Subsequent developments made alchemys original unity with chemistryor other scientic practicesseem increasingly implausible. Late eighteenth-century Germany saw a resurgence of alchemy, but within secret societies. The late nineteenth century witnessed a broader revival of alchemy, but within the context of Victorian occultism. These Victorian occultists reinterpreted alchemy as a spiritual practice, involving the self-transformation of the practitioner and only incidentally or not at all the transformation of laboratory substances. Early twentieth-century psychoanalysts reexpressed this occult- ist interpretation in clinical terms and claimed that alchemical texts actually described psychological processes and archetypal images. These latter-day interpretations became standard explanations of historical alchemy, such that with every passing generation alchemy became more and more distanced from chemistry and from scientic thought in general. 5 Thus, when the history of science emerged as a professional discipline, alchemy seemed far from anything scientic. The positivist outlooks of the day recapitulated Enlightenment polemics, and early historians of science presented alchemy as not simply nonscientic, but antiscientican obstacle to progress. George Sarton penned an ex- tended rant against the extraordinary muddle of alchemy and labeled alchemists as all fools or knaves, or more often a combination of both in various proportions. In 1952 Herbert Buttereld famously wrote that modern scholars who study alchemy end up tinctured by the same sort of lunacy they set out to describe. 6 (Did he have particular contemporaries in mind?) Alchemys separation from the history of science thus contin- ued to deepen for over two centuries. Remarkably, the speed of alchemys rehabilitation today rivals that of its eighteenth- century demise. Historians of science are now paying unprecedented attention to alchemy, and other academic elds are likewise acknowledging its wide inuence and cultural relevance. Has the entire discipline of the history of science become tinctured by lunacy? A brief retrospective on alchemys rehabilitationand the opposition to its revival highlights developments in both our discipline and our wider understanding of science. Several steps paved the way for alchemys revival. The careful researches of Julius Ruska, Paul Kraus, and others addressed long-standing biobibliographical problems. Walter Pagel and Allen Debus championed the importance of iatrochemistry, especially in the cases of Paracelsus, Van Helmont, and their followers. Few scholars, however, dared approach European chrysopoeia seriously. Among those who did, Frank Sherwood Tay- lor, founding editor of Ambix, should be singled out. He wrote his 1952 The Alchemists with great historical sensitivity, insight, and modesty, endeavoring to understand alche- mists on their own terms at a time when most others relied on supercial or programmatic assessments. Such foundational work did not, unfortunately, penetrate far into the eld. Another key step was the revelation that canonical gures of the Scientic Revolution pursued chrysopoeia seriously. This development threw steadfast believers in Enlighten- Springer, 2007), pp. 122, esp. pp. 814; and Principe, Transmuting Chymistry into Chemistry: Eighteenth- Century Chrysopoeia and Its Repudiation, in Neighbours and Territories: The Evolving Identity of Chemistry, ed. Jose Ramon Bertomeu-Sanchez, Duncan Thorburn Burns, and Brigitte Van Tiggelen (Louvain-la-Neuve: Memosciences, 2008), pp. 2134. See also John C. Powers, Ars sine arte: Nicholas Lemery and the End of Alchemy in Eighteenth-Century France, Ambix, 1998, 45:163189. 5 See Lawrence M. Principe and William R. Newman, Some Problems with the Historiography of Alchemy, in Secrets of Nature: Astrology and Alchemy in Early Modern Europe, ed. Newman and Anthony Grafton (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2001), pp. 385431. 6 George Sarton, Boyle and Bayle: The Sceptical Chemist and the Sceptical Historian, Chymia, 1950, 3:155189, on pp. 161162; and Herbert Buttereld, The Origins of Modern Science, 13001800 (New York: Macmillan, 1952), p. 98. F O C U S FOCUSISIS, 102 : 2 (2011) 307 ment or positivist rhetoric on the horns of a dilemmaeither alchemy was more rational than they believed or their heroes were less so. Newtons alchemy would not have become a cause cele`bre of the 1970s and 1980s had eighteenth-century and subsequent genera- tions not recrafted Newton into the very model of the modern scientist and presented alchemy as something removed fromindeed, opposed toscience. Nor would Newtons alchemy have been kept hidden for so long as an embarrassment. The nineteenth-century biographer David Brewster recoiled at Newtons voluminous notes on the most con- temptible alchemical poetry and his study of texts that were the obvious product of a fool and a knave. 7 The commission that examined Newtons manuscripts for Cambridge University concluded that the alchemical materials were of very little interest and his theological work not of any great value. These unimportant materials were returned to their owner and eventually bundled up into lots for the infamous Sothebys auction of 1936. 8 Study of the alchemical papers gathered by John Maynard Keynes and given to Cambridge in 1946 was sporadic at rst and sometimes took the form of sifting nuggets of positive chemistry from mystic alchemy using anachronistic or programmatic criteriathe latter explained away or more often simply ignored. 9 But thanks to persistent scholars like R. S. Westfall and B. J. T. Dobbsdespite the then-meager understanding of alchemy they had to draw on and the criticism they received from more hidebound historiansit is now common knowledge that Sir Isaac Newtons alchemy occupied him as seriously as optics or mathematics, just as his theological pursuits rivaled his physics in terms of the time and energy he spent on them. 10 Robert Boyle received similar treatment. The image crafted for him was that of a Father of Modern Chemistry who cleared the way for modernity by sweeping away misguided alchemy. When biographers examined Boyles papers in the 1740s, they discarded many alchemical materials as worthless. Given the disrepute attached to al- chemy by that time, it was not something they wanted to have connected to their hero. Ironically, much of this materialsuch as the work on transmutational processes Boyle called his Hermetick Legacyhad already been pilfered shortly after his death in 1691, but then probably on account of its perceived value. The surviving material documents unambiguously Boyles lifelong chrysopoetic activities, his search for the philosophers stone, and his attempts to contact adepti. 11 Once again, some authors (but not all) 7 David Brewster, Memoirs of the Life, Writings, and Discoveries of Sir Isaac Newton, 2 vols. (Edinburgh, 1855), Vol. 2, pp. 374375. Note how Sarton parroted Brewsters phrasing in Boyle and Bayle. 8 A Catalogue of the Portsmouth Collection of Books and Papers (Cambridge, 1888), p. xix. On Newtons papers see Rob Iliffe, A Connected System? The Snare of a Beautiful Hand and the Unity of Newtons Archive, in Archives of the Scientic Revolution, ed. Michael Hunter (Woodbridge: Boydell, 1998), pp. 137157; and Peter Spargo, Sotheby, Keynes, and Yahuda: The 1936 Sale of Newtons Manuscripts, in The Investigation of Difcult Things: Essays on Newton and the History of the Exact Sciences, ed. Peter Harman and Alan Shapiro (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1992), pp. 115134. 9 The tendency is visible in the 1888 Catalogue of the Portsmouth Collection of Books and Papers, p. xix; it is clear in Marie Boas and A. Rupert Hall, Newtons Chemical Experiments, Archives Internationales dHistoire des Sciences, 1958, 11:113152. 10 Richard S. Westfall, The Role of Alchemy in Newtons Career, in Reason, Experiment, and Mysticism in the Scientic Revolution, ed. M. L. Righini Bonelli and William R. Shea (London: Macmillan, 1975), pp. 189232 (see Marie Boas Halls critical response, Newtons Voyage on the Strange Seas of Alchemy, ibid., pp. 239246); and Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Foundations of Newtons Alchemy; or, The Hunting of the Greene Lyon (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1975). 11 Lawrence M. Principe, The Aspiring Adept: Robert Boyle and His Alchemical Quest (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton Univ. Press, 1998), esp. pp. 1126. On the fate of the papers see Michael Hunter and Principe, The Lost Papers of Robert Boyle, Annals of Science, 2003, 60:269311; on Boyles biographies see Hunter, Robert Boyle: By Himself and His Friends (London: Pickering, 1994). 308 FOCUSISIS, 102 : 2 (2011) endeavored to ignore or explain away Boyles alchemy, simultaneously elevating his 1661 Sceptical Chymist into an epoch-making book, a death warrant that struck at the root of alchemy (it wasnt and it didnt). 12 As with Newton, revealing Boyles alchemy was sometimes met with resistance or even outrageI recall being yelled at during an international conference in the 1990s for defaming Boyle and more recently have had my claims about Boyle and alchemy attributed to the use of hallucinatory drugs. Current scholarship now removes any grounds for surprise (or horror) over the likes of Boyle or Newton studying alchemy. Further research continues to add to the roster of well-known gures who seriously pursued chrysopoeia. Now that we recognize alchemy as part of natural philosophy, we should instead be surprised if early modern thinkers interested in the constitution and manipulation of matter had not studied or pursued chrysopoeia. Hand-in-hand with historiographical developments beyond earlier great men narratives, historians of science are revealing how ubiquitous chymical practice including chrysopoetic endeavorsreally was. Alchemy extends from well-known gures to a host of lesser-known characters in and out of academic, medical, courtly, and private settings and across the whole social and intellectual spectrum of projectors, entrepreneurs, reners, miners, and others, all the way to brewers, shoemakers, and drapers. 13 Indeed, one of the most important features of the new historiography of alchemy is the recovery of its diversity and dynamism. 14 Part of the rhetorical strategy of the eighteenth century, and of debunkers of alchemy ever since, was to lump all chrysopoeians together, enabling the criticism (or parody) of a part to be extended to the whole. In 1722, for example, Geoffroy cited the most celebrated instances of transmutational fraud and allowed them to be extrapolated to the whole of chrysopoeia. Subsequent writers routinely picked marginal gures or ideas as representative of the whole or lumped excised snippets from authors widely separated in time and cultural context together into an undifferentiated pastiche. Interestingly, authors from opposite ends of the spectrumpositivists and occultists converged on this point. For the former, alchemy was distinguished from progressive science by being static, an unchanging body of inherited ideas based on a priori reason- ings and unresponsive to observations. The latter, encouraged by the notion of continuity promoted by ancient wisdom narratives prominent in esoteric circles, crafted all- embracing, transtemporal denitions of alchemy. Both viewpoints have been raised even recently in objection against the new historiography of alchemy. 15 Certainly, some chryso- poetic authors facilitated such treatment by rhetorically claiming a unity to the alchemical 12 E. J. Holmyard, Alchemy (Hammondsworth: Penguin, 1957), p. 273. 13 One footnote cannot encompass the outstanding work that displays the breadth of alchemy, but see Bruce T. Moran, The Alchemical World of the German Court (Stuttgart: Steiner, 1991); Tara E. Nummedal, Alchemy and Authority in the Holy Roman Empire (Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press, 2007); and Pamela H. Smith, The Business of Alchemy: Science and Culture in the Holy Roman Empire (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton Univ. Press, 1994). 14 Lawrence M. Principe, Diversity in Alchemy: The Case of Gaston Claveus DuClo, a Scholastic Mercurialist Chrysopoeian, in Reading the Book of Nature: The Other Side of the Scientic Revolution, ed. Allen G. Debus and Michael Walton (Kirksville, Mo.: Sixteenth Century Press, 1998), pp. 181200; and Principe, The Alchemies of Robert Boyle and Isaac Newton: Alternate Approaches and Divergent Deploy- ments, in Rethinking the Scientic Revolution, ed. Margaret J. Osler (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 2000), pp. 201220. 15 E
tienne-Francois Geoffroy, Des supercheries concernant la pierre philosophale, Memoires de lAcademie
Royale des Sciences, 1722, 24:6170. For an example of the continued deployment of such outdated notions see Brian Vickers, The New Historiography and the Limits of Alchemy, Ann. Sci., 2008, 65:127156; see likewise the trenchant critique of such notions in William R. Newman, Brian Vickers on Alchemy and the Occult: A Response, Perspectives on Science, 2009, 17:482506. F O C U S FOCUSISIS, 102 : 2 (2011) 309 quest (all the sages say one thing) and by reinterpreting earlier authors to support their own ideas, thereby creating a supercial impression of uniformity. But careful contextual readings of alchemical texts now continue to reveal that alchemy was never monolithic or static. Early modern European alchemy alone displays a stag- gering diversity of theories, practices, and purposes: Scholastic and anti-Aristotelian, Paracelsian and anti-Paracelsian, Hermetic, Neoplatonic, mechanistic, vitalistic, and moreplus virtually every combination and compromise thereof. Arguments ourished over the starting material(s) for the philosophers stone, just as diverse theories drawing on substantial forms, semina, particles, principles (one, two, three, four, or vedepend- ing on the author), and other concepts abounded to explain its transmutational abilities and the nature of chymical change. Experimental results and observations fed into both theory and practice. Notwithstanding the caricature of alchemists single-mindedly seeking the philosophers stone, legions of hopeful chrysopoeians in fact collected, traded, and experimented with a myriad of processes for less potent transmuting agents known as particulars, and most practitioners diversied their activitiesfor practical economic reasons, if nothing elseto include pharmaceutical and commercial production. Such diversity renders it impossible to make blanket statements about the content and inuence of alchemy without careful qualication and guarantees that we will have much to learn about alchemy for many years to come. Another key step toward resituating alchemy in the history of science required getting a handle on what alchemists actually did every day. The enigmatic character of alchemical texts seemed to defy understanding. Rhetorically motivated parodies from the eighteenth century or misguided interpretations from the nineteenth and twentieth lled the resultant vacuum, providing a consensus that, whatever alchemists did, it was neither chemistry nor scientic and in some cases was not even related to the material world. Of course, many scholars did enumerate specic contributions from alchemy, often by identifying the earliest appearance of some substance or technique. 16 Such endeavors were valuable but could do little to rehabilitate alchemy as part of the history of science, both because these isolated rsts t easily with the notion that alchemists stumbled on things more or less by accident and because the extraction of such positive nuggets left the bulk and fabric of alchemical writings, theories, and practices, especially chrysopoetic ones, unexplained. Thus it was necessary to show that apparently incomprehensible, seemingly fanciful, or metaphorically expressed texts actually rested on practical chemical foundations. The desire to know what alchemists actually did in practice led meinitially back in the early 1980sto try to replicate their results, to see what they saw (and often enough smell what they smelled, although I continue to draw the line at tasting what they tasted). Eventually, many processes that seemed implausible were found to work once impurities present in early modern starting materials were taken into account. Boyles transmutation of gold into silver worked exactly as he described, even if his silver turned out to be silvery antimony. Even some of the most bizarre alchemical imagery supposedly hiding routes toward the philosophers stone, once decoded, yielded surprising and workable processes that must have required astonishingly well-developed experimental techniques. 17 Interest- 16 E.g., John Maxson Stillman, The Story of Early Chemistry (New York: Appleton, 1924), rpt. as The Story of Alchemy and Early Chemistry (New York: Dover, 1960); and J. R. Partington, A History of Chemistry, 4 vols. (London: Macmilllan, 19611970). 17 Lawrence M. Principe, Chemical Translation and the Role of Impurities in Alchemy: Examples from Basil Valentines Triumph-Wagen, Ambix, 1987, 34:2130; Principe, The Gold Process: Directions in the Study of Robert Boyles Alchemy, in Alchemy Revisited, ed. Z. R. W. M. van Martels (Leiden: Brill, 1990), pp. 310 FOCUSISIS, 102 : 2 (2011) ingly, just as the revelation of Boyles and Newtons alchemical endeavors did not always nd a warm welcome, neither did these results or the very technique of replicating experimentsby either die-hard alchemical skeptics or exponents of the then-prominent sociological schools. It is particularly encouraging, therefore, to witness the recent interest in historical replications, not just in alchemy but across the history of science, as a tool for increasing our historical understanding. Together with fresh understanding of the theo- retical systems chrysopoeians developed, and the clear-minded interplay between theory and practice, these new ndings proved that alchemists could not be written off as fabricators of imagined processes, mere empirics, or frauds. While prevailing attitudes toward alchemy (formerly among historians, and still today among much of the general public) required that pioneers in the eld emphasize how alchemy was truly part of the history of sciencein short, opposing the routine label of pseudoscienceit would obviously create an unsatisfactory view of alchemys richness, character, and context to reduce it to some sort of protochemistry. But I know of no modern scholar who maintains that alchemy is part of science in the modern sense. The point is that it was fully part of contemporaneous natural philosophy. This important distinction can be too easily obscured by an automatic usage nowadays of natural philosophy as a historiographically correct substitute term for science without adequate reection on the difference of meaning. Over half a century ago, Walter Pagel, defending the study of topics that positivistic historians of the day saw as rubbish, emphasized that early modern thinkers pursued Philosophia Naturalis, dened suc- cinctly as nature in her entirety, cosmology in its widest sensethat is a mixture of Science, Theology, and Metaphysics. 18 In the eyes of earlier generations, the theological, religious, and metaphysical content of alchemical texts disqualied them from being part of the scientic tradition, even while those same eyes overlooked similar features in early modern physics, astronomy, or natural historyindeed, in all of early modern science. Alchemical textslike other contemporaneous natural philosophical textsare implicitly structured on the vision of a tightly interconnected cosmos of God, man, and nature that is full of meaning, purpose, and symbol. In this context chymical transforma- tions frequently and easily carried linkages for their authors with ideas in theology, literature, mythology, and other elds that since the eighteenth century have been con- sidered extraneous. The shift away from such comprehensive perspectives is clear in Boerhaaves oration, for example; as a pedagogical reformer and Calvinist biblical literalist, he was horried by the metaphorical use of Scripture to support specic laboratory processes and by the linkage of chymical ideas to Christian doctrines. The key rolesometimes explicit, always implicitof theology and metaphysics in alchemy does not disqualify it as part of the history of science any more than these same features in, for example, Kepler or Newton would disqualify their work. Indeed, the rehabilitation of alchemy helps broaden our understanding of what is meant by science, its development, and its evolving place in society. Alchemys exile resulted 200205; and Principe, Apparatus and Reproducibility in Alchemy, in Instruments and Experimentation in the History of Chemistry, ed. Frederic L. Holmes and Trevor Levere (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2000), pp. 5574. Detailed descriptions of decoding and replicating transmutational and other chymical processes appear in my forthcoming The Secrets of Alchemy (Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press, in press). 18 Walter Pagel, The Vindication of Rubbish, originally published in the Middlesex Hospital Journal (1945), rpt. in Religion and Neoplatonism in Renaissance Medicine (London: Variorum, 1985), pp. 114, on p. 11; see the similar denition of natural philosophy as a topic in which physics, metaphysics, and theology could meet and negotiate their claims in Dennis Des Chene, Physiologia: Natural Philosophy in Late Aristotelian and Cartesian Thought (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell Univ. Press, 1996), p. 3. F O C U S FOCUSISIS, 102 : 2 (2011) 311 from a conscious redrawing of the boundaries of science, and the modern resistance to assertions of alchemys importance came from proponents of a narrow view of what counted as science. This view was shaped by eighteenth-century rhetoric and enhanced by nineteenth- and early twentieth-century positivism, progressivism, and a priori or norma- tive philosophical or political formulations about science. Alchemy represented the other, a convenient foil against which chemistry or science in general could be set off. Alchemys estrangement exemplies how science does not always develop by means of cold reason or demonstrable experiment. Transmutational alchemy, vilied by declama- tion rather than disproved by demonstration, was ostracized for the sake of professional expedience at a time in which there was no way to know that its goals were physically unobtainable. Chemists of the day had the problem of their social status and reputation to solve, and the public sacrice of transmutational alchemy was the way they chose to solve itcleansing their eld and dening themselves as reputable by marking out a disrep- utable other. An analogous dynamic explains the antagonism of some twentieth-century historians and scientists toward claims for alchemys importance and its connection to major gures. They were invested in a particular foundation myth of science. To maintain it, they needed alchemy to be something other, something in opposition to which modern, rational, experimental science could dene itself and upon which they could in turn dene themselves. Hence the intensely personal nature of some of their attacks. There was no place for alchemy in accounts of the canonized heroes of modern science. A similar incredulity or dismissal (and often by the same individuals) sometimes greeted the fact that religion was a crucial motivating force behind the Scientic Revolution and that our heroes from the period were almost invariably committed Christians. 19 Over the past fty years, insistence on the importance of alchemy (and theology) has broadened our disciplines vision and enhanced our understanding of the ever-evolving thing we call science. Alchemys exclusion illustrates strategic redenitions of science, while its rehabilitation points to the contextual nature of those denitions. One gift offered by the history of science is the recognition that science is a far messier process than simple models, wishful thinking, or programmatic philosophies will allow. It collects elements from unexpected sources and synthesizes them in unexpected and unpredictable ways. It is never a mechanical or impersonal processnor would we want it to be. While the laws of nature exist independently of us, the ways we choose to conceive of them, to explore or not to explore them, to describe or not to describe themthat is to say, scienceis a very human affair, lled with all the complexities and simplicities, errors and insights, pettiness and nobility that customarily attend human activity. And, to be sure, alchemy forms an important part of that story. 19 For the case of religion see Margaret J. Osler, Religion and the Changing Historiography of the Scientic Revolution, in Science and Religion: New Historical Perspectives, ed. Thomas Dixon, Geoffrey Cantor, and Stephen Pumfrey (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 2010), pp. 7186. 312 FOCUSISIS, 102 : 2 (2011)