This document summarizes and compares classical and modern approaches to theories of power. It discusses how classical theories focused on legitimacy of power and located power primarily within political institutions and state law. Modern theories, influenced by thinkers like Foucault, Marx, and Nietzsche, see power as operating across many social institutions and blurring the lines between public and private spheres. The author argues a "discursive account of power" integrating insights from Foucault and Laclau provides a useful framework that moves beyond limitations of both classical and modern theories.
This document summarizes and compares classical and modern approaches to theories of power. It discusses how classical theories focused on legitimacy of power and located power primarily within political institutions and state law. Modern theories, influenced by thinkers like Foucault, Marx, and Nietzsche, see power as operating across many social institutions and blurring the lines between public and private spheres. The author argues a "discursive account of power" integrating insights from Foucault and Laclau provides a useful framework that moves beyond limitations of both classical and modern theories.
Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault
Lotar Rasiski University of Lower Silesia
Abstract. In this text the author draws on two contemporary accounts of powerby Michel Foucault and Ernesto Laclauand, on the basis of thorough analysis and com- parison, he argues for the discursive account of power (DAP) as a new concept re- flecting the novel approach to the theory of power developed by these two philosophers. He opens with a broad methodological outline of contemporary concepts of power, distinguishing between the classical and the modern approaches. Basing his find- ings on Laclaus and Foucaults work, he then presents DAP as a theory characterized by decentralizing, non-normative, and conflict-based tendencies that does not exhibit many of the limitations that usually characterize both classical and modern concepts of power. In the second part of the article the author presents a detailed methodological analysis of Foucaults and Laclaus concepts of power, focusing on three axes: power, discourse, and the subject. The author dedicates the last section to a comparison of both approaches, concluding that DAP is an inspiring project that exceeds the limits of tradi- tional liberal theories of power and politics.
Introduction: classical and modern accounts of power
All agree that the problem of power has been one of the most important issues of political philosophy from Plato till present times. All agree also, as I suppose, that power is one of the most essential elements of social life, without the analysis of which it would be impossible to understand what modern society is. However, most theoreticians stress the fact that so far all attempts to create a unified, complete and satisfactory theory of power have failed. There are fundamental difficulties with defining what power is, how it is manifested and how it influences individuals, to what extent it conditions social behaviour, what are and what should be the limits of exercising power, as well as whether it is at all possible to create a model of power which would be characterized by respect both for individual rights and the rules of social justice. Another problem, concerning not so much power itself as the theory of power, is connected with the fact that each attempt at formulating such a theory is inevitably related to a political choice, and thus becomes Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 118 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault ideological. There are usually two possible stances to take regarding these difficulties. For some (Bourdieu, Foucault, Laclau), any reflection on society which attempts to evade political implications is impossible. In effect, the only task for philosophy is the critique and demystification of this dependency. Thus, theoreticians of this sort will be, most often, a kind of political realists underlining the omnipresence of power relations and giving up on the creation of a good model of power and its implementation by the state. Abandoning the issue of legitimation and improvement of political systems, they focus rather on the characterization of particular manifestations of power in everyday life in order to unravel its mechanisms and range, as well as to consider the possibility of resistance. For others (Weber, Parsons, Rawls), the possibility of grounding the theoretical discussion of power in the sphere of politics would only subvert its authority, and, what follows, the disciplinary grounding of such statements. That is why, according to these theoreticians, it is necessary to defend the independence of knowledge from politico- social influences and try to construct models of power which would be empirically verifiable and philosophically answerable. All of them, though, seem to agree that one working definition of power and one objective and generally accepted theory based on that definition do not exist. Such methodological assumptions lying at the base of a theory will undoubtedly influence how the definition of power is constructed and how questions it forces are being answered. Thus, I assume that there exist two general tendencies in the analyses of power: the classical and the modern one. The differentiation I develop establishes, of course, a certain convention and is meant to serve as a general reference for the clearer and more transparent expression of something we could name the general tendency in the analyses of power. I characterize the classic formulation thus: (1) the problem of power is usually analyzed in the context of its legitimacy or lack thereof, i.e. by asking what is the source of the right to rule (natural law, divine law, social contract, etc.), when is the exercise of political power legitimated and when is it not, etc. etc.; (2) the center of power is most often situated in the state understood as the political institutions which have the right of making laws, to use John Lockes words; (3) the scope of power is associated with the limits of state law; (4) it posits a separation of the public sphere from the private sphere, with which political power (government) is not allowed to interfere; (5) power is a contractual relation between the ruler and the ruled; (6) a breach of the contract by the ruler results in repression or usurpation, and in the right to rebel on the part of the ruled. I argue that the classic formulation of the definition of power has only a limited analytical efficacy. It cannot describe the way in which an individual is embroiled in the social and economic system of institutions, to Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. Lotar Rasiski 119
what extent he (or she) depends on them, and to what extent he (or she) is capable of influencing and transforming them. An analysis of power in terms of how adequatly political institutions function and follow the law ignores a whole series of phenomena occurring in our present social and political reality which I in fact believe to be, quite crucial. If there are significant social groups that consider themselves as having no influence on either current or long-term state policy (e.g. new social movements), the type of analysis which recognizes such conflicts and crosses the artificial divisions between the political and the social is, in my opinion, a more proper analytical tool for understanding contemporary society . Therefore, I contrast this classical conception of power with a modern one, characterized among other things by the crossing over of power relations beyond the sphere of political institutions, and the bracketing of the problem of legitimacy. Since the French and American Revolutions, a common conviction in political theory has been that power is maintained on the basis of general public support. In democratic countries power has been seemingly maintained simply by citizens granting legitimacy to their representatives. In the modern concept of power the situation becomes more complex. The question of legitimacy turns out to be of secondary importance when it becomes apparent that the government endowed with legitimacy does not, in fact, rule in the name of the masses, but instead in the covert interests of the elites, certain classes, sexes, races, etc. According to theoreticians of the modern approach to power, the exercise of power finds entirely new theatres of operation. Foucault, for example, points out manifestations of the exercise of disciplinary power in families, factories, prisons and schools, i.e. in the institutions which could not be consider political by the classic formulation of power. Together with a changed view concerning the location of power, the borderline between the public and private spheres becomes blurred. Historically, we can find the beginnings of the modern concept of power in the Marxist theory of class and in the way it connects domination with access to the means of production; in Nietzsches concept of the will to power, positing the basic social relationship to be that of domination and subjugation (master and slave), which is in some sense a biological relation; and in the Freudian theory of the unconscious, which describes power as a relation within the subject. It is necessary to stress here that the opposition between the modern and the classical approaches to power cannot be reduced only to historical arguments. I do not claim that the theories of Freud, Marx and Nietzsche represent the rupture between the classical and the modern epoch in the study of power. Instead, the opposition lies in the contrasting types of reflection. The most we can say is that in the 19 th century, alongside the classical conception of power there emerged a new type of reflection on Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 120 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault power, which ultimately lead to the treatment of power as a cultural phenomenon. Thus in the contemporary discussions of power both the classical and the modern models of thinking about power are applied. Among the contemporary representatives of the modern conceptions of power are e.g. M. Walzer, J. Habermas, E. Laclau and Ch. Mouffe, S. Lukes, M. Foucault, W.E. Connolly, and many others. The classical theoreticians are, among others, M. Oakeshott, R. Dworkin, R. Nozick, J. Rawls, or R. Aron. It is important to notice that both the classical and the modern conceptions of power favor normative reflection, but it is of a different character in each case. While most contemporary classical theoreticians of power concentrate on the problem of state government and its implementation of the rule of law or principles of justice and liberty (e.g. Dworkin, Rawls), the modern thinkers will unravel the negative effects of the exercise of power outside political institutions in the classic sense, focusing on elements of social life such as education, habits, the influence of technology and media, access to the means of production, ideology, gender and race (e.g. Frankfurt school). Yet in both formulations one may condemn or seek to improve the form of government in the name of postulated normative ideals, such as autonomy, freedom, social justice, etc. The normative element seems to be something natural in the majority of theories of power. Most of them consist in capturing the difference between the existing state of affairs and the required state of affairs. This difference indicates that our social reality is not as it is supposed to be and that it needs to be transformed into a proper one. The downside of this kind of analyses is that they are not capable of critically examining the existing social or political reality; they describe not what it is, but only what it should be. Therefore a number of irresolvable difficulties arises in connection with the normative type of analysis of power, in many cases making it useless and contradictory. First of all, one assumes in this type of analysis that the position from which the demands have been raised is external in relation to the field in which they should be applied. It means that the theorist is not a part of the bad reality described by him, and that he, as the only one, liberated himself from it and recognized what is good for the society. This is the case not only with Marxism, in which the role of such a normative indicator is played by the promise of a future communist society, where man is free of any oppression or apparatus of control, and is able to realize his own real nature. Also in classical liberalism, the concept of the proper state of nature takes a similar position: man in this state is in his natural condition, and the main objective behind the founding of a society is to better preserve his natural Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. Lotar Rasiski 121
rights and capabilities. 1 Subsequently, a series of questions can be raised in relation to this kind of claim: Why should one concept of human nature be better than another? Why should one system of values, e.g. one based on the idea of individual freedom, be better than another, e.g. one based on the idea of equality? Are there any bases other than religious ones for statements concerning the direction in which a given society should evolve? My main goal in this text is to present, on the basis of the concept of power by Michel Foucault and the idea of hegemony by Ernesto Laclau, a mode of thinking about power which is free of the contradictions connected with both the normative and the classical reflection on power. Let me call it the discursive account of power. Let me now summarize in a few points the similarities between Laclaus and Foucaults approaches, which will make it possible, in my view, to speak about a parallel theoretical account: (1) we can find the common roots of both theories in the structuralist theory of language/discourse; (2) both theories reject any kind of foundationalist or essentialist thinking (e.g. critique of economism); (3) in both approaches the concept of discourse, understood as a theoretical horizon within which an analysis of society becomes possible, is the methodological starting point; (4) this results in a view of power that is decentralized and dispersed, i.e. power becomes a set of relationships, techniques and practices with no privileged field of reference; (5) the concept of conflict or antagonism plays an equally important role in both theories; (6) neither theory is based on any normative assumptions; they try rather to show and to depict the mechanisms of power, resigning from utopian visions of a perfect society; (7) in both theories the stress is placed on productive or creative aspects of power, especially in the context of the relationship between the individual and the social, and not only on negative and prohibitive ones.
Foucault: subject, repression, and war
Throughout his working life, Foucault has repeatedly stressed that his intention in research and writing was not to arrive at something one could call a theory of power. In one of his last texts, The Subject and Power, for example, he states:
I would like to say, first of all, what has been the goal of my work during the last twenty years. It has not been to analyze the phenomena of power, nor to elaborate the foundations of such an analysis. My objective, instead, has been to create the history of the different modes by which, in our culture, human beings are made subjects. (Foucault, 1982, p. 208)
1 It does not matter here that the liberal ideal served only as a kind of hypothesis which had only theoretical importance. The fact is that in both approaches we can find a similar theoretical construction, based on some essentialist assumptions. Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 122 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault First of all, the issue is not to create an objective and unhistorical description of power. Foucault is interested in power in so far as it is connected with the subject, as a technique of objectification. By this technique he understands a takeover and rationalization of some unconceptualized field, for example when madness became a subject of newly emerging sciences (at this time still pseudo-sciences, or types of knowledge) of psychology and psychiatry in the nineteenth century. We encounter a similar approach in The Order of Things (1970) where other objectifications appear, that of Man in language, life, and work (his three doubles) or in the prisoner or the subject of sexuality in later works. This understanding stresses the tight connection between the practices of power and knowledge that Foucault describes by means of the concept of power/knowledge. The subject plays a double role here: s/he is the product of historical power relations and, at the same time, the main agent through whom power gains access to knowledge. This means that there is no one- directional relation between power and knowledge, but rather that both elements mutually exchange and support each other. On the other hand, however, stress should be placed on these modes by which human beings are made subjects. Foucaults concern is not to create a general theory of power, but rather to depict the specific and concrete techniques and practices through which subjects become subjugated, processes that belong both to the sphere of politics and that of epistemology. That is why Foucault prefers to refer to his own approach to power as analytics rather than theory. By analytics Foucault understands a definition of a specific domain formed by power relations and a determination of the instruments that will make possible its analysis (Foucault, 1978, p. 82; compare Foucault, 1980a, p. 199). These two tendencies are visible throughout Foucaults work: on the one hand, he seems to be a historian of knowledge in the French meaning of the word, concerned with a whole set of methodological problems that one can find in Bachelard or Canguilhem (e.g. the problem of the status of some sciences, that of historical changes in some of them, or the place of the subject in analysis); on the other hand, he was very often, and gradually more and more so, interested in the political dimension of his work, the consequence of which was placing the concept of power in a significant theoretical position. A clear picture of this tension in his work is to be found in his reference to two complementary methods: archeological and genealogical, where Foucault tries to situate and distribute properly the two components of analysis, the political and the epistemological. Therefore, power in his work is not a separate and privileged theoretical problem, but rather one of several instruments through which analysis of the modes by which, in our culture, human beings are made subjects is possible (Foucault, 1982, p. 208). Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. Lotar Rasiski 123
One of the main arguments of Foucaults account of power is to avoid something he calls economism in the theory of power. Paradoxically, this element can be seen not only in Marxism, but also, and perhaps most importantly, in juridical or liberal conceptions of political power based on the concept of sovereignty. While in the Marxist tradition the economy is a historical raison dtre of power, a principle of its functioning, in liberalism the power is considered to be a right which one is able to possess like a commodity, and which one can transfer to anybody by some legal act that we could call a contract. The partial or total cession by an individual of his/her rights enables the functioning of power and the establishment of sovereignty. As a consequence, one can say that the basis for the constitution of political power is a contractual type of exchange, that is basically an economic relationship (see Foucault, 1980b, p. 88). Foucault believes that this kind of analysis does not exhaust the multiplicity of power relations operating in society. And if power is not to be seen as a possession or a commodity that we can exchange, if it exists only in action, it has to be seen as a relation of force. Foucault differentiates between two kinds of analysis of power based on this view: either power is understood as an organ of repression (repressive hypothesis) or as a relation of struggle, conflict and war (hypothesis of war) (Foucault, 1980b, p. 90). It is clear that the concept of repression played a significant role in Foucaults earlier writings. For instance, the image of the exclusion of madness and its submission to reason in Madness and Civilization (1965) has strong Freudian and Hegelian connotations. Either on the epistemological level, in Descartes reflections on the cogito, or on the social level, in the whole machinery of confinement of the poor and the lazy in asylums, we can find a common mechanism of repression described by Freud in the double play of the conscious and the unconscious. Foucault, however, has always been diffident of the notion of repression, because it is quite inadequate for capturing what is precisely the productive aspect of power (Foucault, 1980c, p. 119). Defining power in terms of repression, one has to adopt a purely juridical conception of power and identify it with law understood as a prohibitive force. Foucault finds impossible the efficiency of such power:
What makes power hold good, what makes it accepted, is simply the fact that it doesnt only weigh on us as a force that says no, but that it traverses and produces things, it induces pleasure, forms knowledge, produces discourse. (Foucault, 1980c, p. 119)
Foucault considers an approach to power based on the relation of struggle and war in his lectures given at College de France in 1976 (Foucault, 2003). He proposes a reversal of Clausevitzs assertion that war is politics continued by other means: politics (power), in his view, is the continuation of war by other means (Foucault, 2003, p. 48). Historically, Foucault Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 124 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault places the beginnings of this kind of thinking about power in the 17th century, in the English and French anti-monarchist movements, even if in both countries they were of a different character. 2 Foucault calls this discourse about power historico-political in opposition to the philosophico- juridical discourse of sovereignty. The main characteristic of this discourse is the assumption that social order, the organization and structure of law, and the functioning of power are not the consequence of pre-established consent or contract, but rather they are an effect of mud of the battle (Foucault, 2003, p. 47). Society, according to Foucault, is based on real war, permanent and silent, which goes on behind the official declarations of peace. Everybody is engaged in this war, nobody stays neutral. A binary structure runs through society (Foucault, 2003, p. 51)Foucault concludes.
Laclau: hegemony, antagonism, and empty signifiers
Laclaus idea of hegemony stems directly from that branch of Marxism which rejected economism as the only and the ultimate factor contributing to social change and highlighted the role of politics, ideology, and culture as equally important. According to Laclau and Mouffe, the concept of hegemony was an attempt to supplement the economic logic of necessity with the political logic of contingency. The need to break the Marxist iron logic of history appeared in the writings of the late 19 th and early 20 th
century theoreticians, who recognized that capitalism is not only far from collapsing, but that it is capable of self-reform in order to avoid the predicted pauperization and polarization of society, which in turn were to be followed by a general revolution and a change of the political constitution. These thinkers started to look for theoretical solutions which would take into consideration the importance of factors other than economic for the historical process. Breaking with the explanation of historical processes which relied on the necessary mechanism of class struggle made it possible to introduce an element of contingency. Thus, in the orthodox version of Marxism by Kautsky, intellectuals are to be the force capable of preventing the fragmentation of the working classes and the depolarization of the social field, and of restoring the proper direction of the historical process. For Bernstein, the inventor of revisionism, the social- democratic party was to be such a factor, while Sorel spoke of the myth of the general strike. According to Lenin, hegemony meant political leadership within a broader class alliance, uniting peasants, agricultural
2 In England it was based mainly on the bourgeoisie and peoples revolt against absolute monarchy; in France the group most opposed to the monarchy was the aristocracy. Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. Lotar Rasiski 125
workers and soldiers under the banner of the working class. The most important issue was no longer the position within the social structure, but rather the struggle against the common enemythe tsarist regime. The most complete depiction of hegemony is provided by Gramsci, who describes it as an ideological struggle of peoples hearts and minds, in which a new collective identity, or to use Gramscis own words, a new collective will is constituted. The economic factor becomes for him only one of the manifestations of the historical process. For Gramsci, such elements as race or religion are equally important. 3
Laclaus initial philosophical standpoint was close to that of such theoreticians of Marxism as Althusser, Balibar or Poulantzas. This is clear from his first work published in 1977, Politics and Ideology in Marxist Theory (Laclau, 1977), which reveals a strong influence of the French wave of Marxism of the sixties. However, even this early work contains elements which herald Laclaus later dismissal of Althusserism and its structural account of Marxism. The concept of relative autonomy of superstructure as it was introduced by Althusser and his followers did not change the traditional concept of economy, which still appeared as an abstract entity located outside of the society and its relations, i.e. having its own logic and being apolitical. The main point of disagreement, however, was class reductionism, which Laclau completely dismissed toward the end of the 1970s. A clear conclusion of this process was the publication, together with Chantal Mouffe, of Hegemony and Socialist Strategy (1985). This work provoked a wave of discussion in the circles of contemporary Marxists. The opponents most frequently criticized the authors for undermining Marxisms scientificity and for decreasing the role of the economy by introducing a new account of historical agency which undermined the idea of class as the main motor of history. It should be stressed, however, that the principal arguments of the work were in agreement with the criticism of Marxism provided not only by the proponents of neogramscianism, but also by feminists, theoreticians of culture, and political scientists who were interested in the emergence of new social movements not directly related to class divisions. The restoration of Gramscis political thought in Great Britain was closely connected to the success of Margaret Thatcher and her party in the general elections of 1979 (and subsequently in 1983 and 1987). This fact provoked the leftist intellectuals sympathizing with the Labour Party to revise their approach and beliefs. They realized that it was not a strong program of economic reforms that decided about Thatchers victory, but rather the ideological battle over the hearts and minds of the British
3 An excellent review of the genealogy of the concept of hegemony in socialist tradition is provided by Laclau and Mouffe in Hegemony and Socialist Strategy (1985), pp. 7-46. Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 126 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault people. Thatcher won not only the ballots of the middle class, but also of a significant portion of the working class vote. To explain this phenomenon, many intellectuals returned to Gramsci and his idea of moral-intellectual reform. The attractiveness of Gramsci, however, was limited by the essentialist residues, which did not allow him to fully develop a non- economic theory of hegemonic articulation. One can place Gramsci, together with Althusser, within the current of Marxist reforms that have been undertaken from the inside, but which regard the logic of contingency, as it appears in the theory of hegemony, rather as a supplement to the general mechanisms of history, which remain unmodified as such. Laclau and Mouffe assume the task of removing these essentialist residues, attempting to elaborate on certain Marxist themes and to complete them by adding elements of social critique developed by poststructuralism. To put it shortly: their main idea is to make essential an area of investigation that was previously considered only a supplementary field. To some degree, Marxism is a starting point for Laclau and Mouffe, but from their theoretical position a return to Marxism in the classical sense is impossible. Laclaus concept of hegemony assumes that the social is a multidimensional field of antagonistic forces, which is ruled by the logic of contingency rather than necessity. Similarly to Marxism, social conflict still plays an important role, but economic conflict has the same status as, for instance, racial or ideological conflicts. There is no ultimate foundation of conflict that would be able to polarize the social while producing at the same time a clear and transparent picture of the social structure. Laclau rejects the idea of the ultimate conflict, as well as the liberal conception of the social contract, according to which free individuals conscious of their rights and interests work to constitute social order by putting a portion of their rights into the hands of their representative, or to use Hobbes words, the sovereign. The core of the idea of hegemony lies in the assumption that such a constituting exchange is impossible. To perform such an act it is necessary to assume that the subjects participating in it have a pre- established identity. And this, in turn, results in the theoretical privileging of some social spheres, those in which these identities could find grounding. Instead, Laclau proposes that every process of representation, as the principle of functioning of democratic societies, understood either liberally or in the Marxist context, assumes some interference with the identity of the representative as well as of the represented.
The original gap in the identity of the represented, which needed to be filled by a supplement contributed by the process of representation, opens an undecidable movement in two directions that is constitutive and irreducible. There is an Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. Lotar Rasiski 127
opaqueness, an essential impurity in the process of representation, which is at the same time its condition of both possibility and impossibility. (Laclau, 1996, p. 98).
The need for representation follows from the fact that the basic identity of the represented is constituted in a certain place A, but the decisions which can influence this identity are arrived at in place B. The representative then inscribes this interest into a complex reality totally different from that in which it was formulated, while at the same time this interest is transformed and established anew. The hegemonic dimension of the social is then contingent enough not to permit the introduction of any privileged position within the social, while at the same time rejecting any necessity to complete such an original state of affairs. The political field is a result of the competition between many various forces, where both the identities and interests of particular agents are forged. Hence, multiple political alliances and configurations are possible which in no way reflect the traditional labels to which we got so used, and which do not fit the political reality. The goal of hegemony is to transform the demands of some social groups into universal ones, so that they would be able to encompass as many particular demands as possible, becoming their representatives. These universal demands are usually an expression of opposition against some dominating force that plays the role of a great oppressor, while at the same time mobilizing and universalizing the demands of particular groups. That is why Laclau stresses so strongly the agonism of the political condition. The interests of particular social groups are constituted mostly in opposition to some dominating political forceat least in the images they produce, for example, for election purposesa force that is to be seen as a threat for the other groups, i.e. for the whole community. Any success of the hegemonic struggle, consisting in the encompassment of the entire field of particular demands by one of the groups, is followed by the loss of that specificity which had been the reason for choosing that particular group as a representative of a broader field of interests. This is because the achievement of hegemony is related to the simultaneous elimination of the great oppressor and the assumption of its role by the new hegemonic group. From this moment the game of hegemony starts again from the beginning. There is no stable and long-term hegemony; it exists only as a temporary intervention, as the mobilization of demands against the existing regime. Following this description of hegemony and generalizing it, one can say that the most important dimension of political power is that of the language/discourse game rather than that of any other social factor. If we understand discourse as an open theoretical horizon through which the analysis of the social is possible, and if we assume together with Laclau that the discursive is a meaningful totality that is not organized around any original foundation, we can recognize the importance of the symbolic or Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 128 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault rhetorical level within the political sphere. That is why Laclau introduces the concept of empty signifierssignifiers without signifieds. Empty signifiers refer to any attempt at encompassing all the differences within a certain field of meaning; one can say that it is the practice of hegemony in the kingdom of meaning. This is the case of Saussures idea of language considered as a closed system. There being a limit to this system is in fact the condition for its existence and for the process of signification. When some set of elements is described as a system, it becomes indispensable to exclude what is not a part of this system. This means constituting an outside by means of a limitthe borderline where the linguistic passes into the extra-linguistic. Speaking more generally, in order to exist every system of signification requires something to limit it, to separate it from what it is not, to exclude what is its opposite. According to Laclau, the limit of the process of signification must present an interruption, a breakdown in signification. Thus we are left with the paradoxical situation that what constitutes the condition of possibility of a signifying systemits limitsis also what constitutes its condition of impossibilitya blockage of the continuous expansion of the process of signification (Laclau, 1996, p. 37). Turning back to our example of hegemony as an attempt to attain political power through the mobilization and universalization of particular demands, we can easily show how empty signifiers are socially constructed. The existence of a particular struggling group is determined by the existence of an oppressive groupno matter whether constructed, imagined, or realthat is its constitutive outside. On the one hand, abolishing the great oppressor is the main goal mobilizing the oppressed group into action. On the other hand, the completion of this demand undermines the very raison d'tre of the group. To use Laclaus words, the great oppressor is the condition of both possibility and impossibility of the group. One can refer to examples of the functioning of empty signifiers which are closer to our political reality. Any political action aimed at attaining hegemony is usually connected with the offering of radical solutions to the undesirable state of affairs. Thus, the aspiring group describes the world dominated by the great oppressor as untrue or unreal, and presents its own solution as the only possible alternative. That is why we hear so often that after elections we will find real freedom or real justice or equality, etc. These expressions are in fact the best examples of the functioning of empty signifiers in politics. As we know very well, they can be used by any political force, whether the right or the left, radicals or moderates; and they can be filled at any time by another meaning, precisely because they are essentially empty. Only temporary fixations of their meaning are possible, and these are historically and politically dependent. Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. Lotar Rasiski 129
That is why the history of thought knows so many versions of what is good and what is bad for society, of what is freedom and what is its violation. Let me summarize in a few points Laclaus view of hegemony, or, speaking more generally, his view of power. The main condition of hegemony is the unevenness of power relations that makes conflict possible. This means that one of the groups competing in the hegemonic struggle is able to attain superiority over others, to propose its own demands, and to present oneself as being capable of representing a universal task. There is hegemony only if the dichotomy universality/particularity is superseded; universality exists only if it is incarnated inand subverts some particularity. Conversely, however, no particularity can become political without also becoming the locus of universalizing effects. Hegemony requires the production of empty signifiers which make the play of the universal and the particular possible, enabling the latter to take up the representation of the former. The relation of representation is the condition of the constitution of social order, and again, of the play between the universal and the particular (see Laclau, 2000, p. 207). Let me illustrate this with the example of Laclaus interpretation of Hobbes idea of the sovereign. According to Hobbes, the therapy for a malady called the state of nature was power. The establishment of community and hierarchy was meant to emancipate people from ruinous equality. Equality embodied extreme disorder, arbitrariness, egoism, and a permanent possibility of the outbreak of conflict; it was a source of suffering and menace. Hobbes noticed an essential issue here: the need for collectivity was due to a lack of order that would be a response to the inconveniences of the state of nature. The only alternative to the state of nature could be absolute power concentrated in the hands of the sovereign as the embodiment of the society as a totality. It was unimportant for Hobbes whether the ruler represented some special virtues or capabilities. The ruler was only an actualization of order, a radical alternative to the disorder of the state of nature. The Sovereign, the highest and the only power in the community is, however, nothing but a concentration of forces held by each citizen individually. In Hobbes opinion, the Sovereign is not a distinct and independent being. Instead, it is an artificial creature, a kind of totality which embodies and collects the capacities of individual subjects; it is a symbol of the unity of a community. As a consequence, the Sovereign must also embody directly the will of the whole community. On the one hand, this logical construction does not allow him to operate against the community, because in this way he would be a threat to himself; on the Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 130 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault other hand, to rebel against the Sovereign is an absurdity, because in principle the subjects would be rebelling against themselves. Paradoxically, in this way Hobbes theoretically eliminated power in two ways. In the state of nature power is distributed evenly among all the people, which completely eliminates power. Nobody can gain advantage over anybody else, because every individual is bestowed with the same capabilities, and therefore with the same ability to rule. We are, however, dealing with a similar situation when power is absolute, when it is concentrated in the hands of an artificial creaturethe Leviathanwhich is nothing but a collection of the capacities of all individuals. We are losing one essential and indispensable element of the power relation: who is to be the ruled, when in the process of this quasi-representation the sovereign directly reflects the will of the individuals? And on the other hand, who is to be the ruler if the will of the ruled decides everything? Power becomes impossible in this way, because the community constitutes an absolute unity. This eliminates the relation of representation, since it requires two separate subjects and the relation of articulation between them. The radical universal moment of the constitution of the Sovereign also eliminates the interplay between the universal and the particular, an interplay which Laclau considers to be essential for the political. This approach, therefore, is located directly on the opposite side of the idea of hegemony, undermining most of its critical assumptions.
Laclau and Foucault: power, discourse, and subject
Let me continue now with a comparison of Laclaus and Foucaults accounts of power. I will analyze their approaches on the basis of the three essential axes: power, discourse and subject, which, I argue, cannot be treated separately. Let me first briefly address certain issues which do not constitute an argument, but which show the preliminary difficulties linked to this matter. The first difference between Laclau and Foucault is of course connected to the theoretical traditions on which they draw. Foucault insists on pointing out his own connections to the so called, philosophy of knowledge, of rationality, and of the concept, reminding the readers that he is the inheritor of Bachelards and Canguilhems thought, and separates this line of thinking from philosophy of experience, of meaning, and of the subject with Sartre and Merleau-Ponty (see Foucault, 1999, p. 466). Laclau, instead, locates himself in the non-orthodox Marxist tradition led by Gramsci. The different backgrounds of the two thinkers affect the objectives they embrace in significant ways. Foucaults goal is rather theoretical: he tries to show the history of how human beings are transformed into subjects. In this sense, I would call him rather a historian Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. Lotar Rasiski 131
of knowledge than a political philosopher. Laclau, on the other hand, sets an essentially political problem: he wants to rethink the project of the left in the face of the theoretical as well as practical defeat of Marxism. The issue here, however, is to find similar modes of thinking about power in their two approaches. We can attain this only by temporarily suspending our knowledge of their theoretical location and purposes and by considering both propositions structurally. We will therefore focus on some methodological issues, as well as on those descriptive parts of their analyses which contain their detailed views of the mechanisms of power. First, it should be mentioned that theory of discourse plays a similar methodological role in Laclaus and in Foucaults thought: it is a certain theoretical tool which enables one to analyze political reality. We can find the roots of the two accounts in poststructuralist revision of Saussures idea of language. Laclaus concept of discourse shares a series of assumptions with Derridas or Lacans critique of the structural approach to language, especially in rejecting the idea of language as a closed system, as well as the idea of strict isomorphism between the order of the signified and that of the signifier which stems from Saussures theory. This criticism results in an account of discourse seen as an open and decentralized signifying field, where one cannot find any privileged position. The meaning of a sign is determined rather in terms of the free play of signifiers and their differential positions, and not as an effect of reference to a stable signified or some extra-discursive object. Laclau and Mouffe fully agree on this point with Foucault, and use his expression from Archeology of Knowledge (1972), regularity in dispersion, to stress the impossibility of any unifying principle of discourse, except the dispersion itself. In this sense, the discursive constitutes a domain where we can find specific rules concerning the functioning of discursive elements, i.e. some regularities which are not at all limited to language relations. This is stressed by Laclau when he speaks about the openness of the discursive pointing to its social and historical character. The determination of meaning depends on the interference of various dimensions of discourse, including social, political or economic relations. Foucault similarly talks about the interdependence of the discursive and the extradiscursive. The system of discourse formation, for example, includes not only the relations between different kinds of discourses, but also the influence of techniques, practices, institutions, or social groups which play an important role in the constitution of the discursive formation. The problem, however, lies in Foucaults assigning, to use Dreyfuss and Rabinows words, a relative autonomy to the discursive, and finally treating it as a privileged and abstract field of analysis. This is precisely what Laclau and Mouffe criticize in their work, Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Foucault, for example, who has maintained a distinctionin our Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 132 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault opinion inconsistentbetween discursive and non-discursive practices, attempts to determine the relational totality that founds the regularity of the dispersions of a discursive formation. But he is only capable of doing this in terms of a discursive practice (Laclau & Mouffe, 1985, p. 107). We encounter similar difficulties when we look at Foucaults concept of statement (lnonc) from the Archeology of Knowledge (1972). Foucault seems to consider discourse to be a very limited collection of utterances which have passed the institutional test and which pretend to spell out the truth and become knowledge. It is obvious that among all speech acts this kind of statement is quite rare. According to Laclau, on the other hand, the whole social reality is meaningful in the sense that it can be understood only through discourse, which for him is a common matrix of both behavioral and linguistic aspects of social practice. It should be stressed, however, that both accounts are directed at the same goal at this point, which is to show the interdependence between the linguistic and the social or political practices, even though they attempt to achieve this goal in two different ways. Furthermore, a natural consequence of defending such a standpoint is to defend also the historical character of discursive formation, which is a point strongly emphasized both in Laclaus and Foucaults writings. Foucault writes about historical a priori as a subject of archeology, and Laclau says that discourse theory can be included into the transcendental turn in philosophy, but only with the restriction that discursive a priori forms are historically dependent. Let us pass now to the concept of power. Laclau, as could already have been noticed, does not use the word power and prefers to talk about hegemony. On the one hand, this serves to remind us that his theoretical project is close to that of Gramsci, according to whom social life and political activity organize themselves around two overlapping and mutually dependent dimensions: political and civil societies. Gramscis idea of intellectual and moral leadership was meant to demonstrate that a condition for taking over state power was the achievement of hegemony on the level of private organisms constituting the civil society. That is why struggling for the hearts and minds of the people was as important as struggling for economic rights. Laclaus project, as a continuation of this aspect of Gramscis thought, introduces a much broader concept of power than what we find in classical accounts, where power is usually strictly limited to state-legal institutions. In his view, power is exercised on many different levels within the society, and it cannot be reduced to any particular source. We find a similar approach in Foucaults depiction of the microphysics of power. His entire theoretical effort is aimed at replacing the view that sees power as a one-dimensional and one-directional force which has its origin in the hands (or perhaps in the head) of the sovereign. As Foucault puts it: We must eschew the model of Leviathan in the study Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. Lotar Rasiski 133
of power (Foucault, 1980b, p. 102) and focus on these peripheral subjects by which power is exercised. That is why Foucault is interested in analyzing the historical formations of power such as bio-power, discipline or governmentality. They are all examples of the exercise of power that surpasses the fabricated manthe State. In Foucault, power manifests itself not only in the laws and political institutions, but rather in the whole network of private organisms, to use Gramscis words, disciplining and controlling the human body by means of families, schools, asylums, factories, prisons or barracks. In summary, both theories present power as decentralized and dispersed throughout the whole society, and as irreducible to the conscious and intentional actions of particular individuals or institution. There is, however, another meaning of hegemony which reminds us of the differences between the two approaches. Laclau inherits also this part of the hegemonic tradition which is closely connected to the idea of restoration and reparation of Marxist thought. In this sense, hegemony is a well- defined political project, with concrete objectives and tasks to perform. Its theoretical framework allows one to locate the source of domination and oppression in a certain historical moment, because the construction of bipolar divisions within the society belongs to the essence of the political- discursive reality. And finally, the goal of hegemony is always to gain power over the entire state, while at the same time eliminating the hegemonic efforts of the oppressed groups. Therefore, one could say that Laclaus view of power is much more clearly outlined and determined than that of Foucault. In Foucaults work power circulates freely through the network of organizations and individuals, and cannot be described at any moment as a clear bipolar structure. The role of conflict in both theories is closely linked to the problem of the range of power. It is precisely a new formulation of the idea of conflict that allows Laclau to develop a theory of power that is multidimensional and not limited to any rigid economic divisions. While the cornerstone of Marxism was the assumption that all conflicts and struggles within the society have an economic foundation, and that they are essentially reducible to the fundamental opposition between the working class and the capitalists, Laclau's understanding of conflict is much more complex and more sensitive to contemporary social problems. Articulations of hegemonic efforts are to be found not only in the struggles for economic rights, but also for racial, ethnic, sexual, gender and other minority rights. What should be stressed, however, is that conflict in Laclau still plays an essential role in the constitution of political reality, and it is this broad understanding of conflict that makes his theory resistant to the traditional criticisms levied against Marxism. In this context Laclaus ideas clearly refer to Foucaults project of eschewing the model of Leviathan. One of its main goals is to Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 134 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault avoid economism in thinking about power. The stake here, however, is not only the elimination of Marxist economism, but also, and perhaps most importantly, the elimination of a specific liberal or juridical kind of economism, named by Foucault contractual exchange or legal transaction, which allows us to make analogies between power and commodity, or power and wealth. A better alternative to this type of analysis proposed by Foucault is the hypothesis of war, i.e. an analysis of power relations in the society in terms of conflict, struggle, and war. Similarly to Laclau, Foucault differentiates between multiple dimensions of struggles which run throughout the society:
either against forms of domination (ethnic, social, and religious); against forms of exploitation which separate individuals from what they produce; or against that which ties the individual to himself and submits him to others in this way (struggles against subjection, against forms of subjectivity and submission). (Foucault, 1982, p. 212)
At this point we encounter the problem which constitutes perhaps the most important connection between Laclaus and Foucaults theories. Paradoxically, in both cases the main condition for conflict to break out in the society is the existence of a free subject, an active and dynamic participant in power relations. One can say that the relation of power is essentially the relation of confrontation between two adversaries, but it is a confrontation which does not paralyze both sides, it is rather a relation which is at once reciprocal incitement and struggle (see Foucault, 1982, p. 222). This becomes evident in Foucault when he speaks of agonism in power relations. A similar assumption can also be found in Laclau, who insist that hegemony consists in the play of the universal and the particular, this play marking out their conditions of both possibility and impossibility. Of course, this is not to say that the subject is totally free. This is rather to say that in both theories the extreme or radical political situations are rejected. On the one hand, there is no society without power relations, and then the actions of the subjects are always somehow limited; in this sense, there is no absolute freedom either. On the other hand, there is no absolute or full power, such that could determine all actions. As a consequence, in both theories power is not only a repressive and prohibitive force, an obstacle to broadening the sphere of freedom, but rather it becomes a factor essential for the functioning of the society. Laclaus concept of articulation, meaning any practice establishing a relation among elements such that their identity is modified as a result (Laclau & Mouffe, 1985, p. 105) aims to indicate that social relations inevitably affect the identities of their subjects, constituting new goals, interests and demands of the particular political agents. And this is also one of Foucaults main arguments: he considers the subject to be a target of a Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. Lotar Rasiski 135
series of techniques and procedures directed not only at controlling, but also at conducting human actions. To summarize, I am not attempting to say that in the case of Foucaults idea of power and Laclaus concept of hegemony we are dealing with one consistent theoretical model of power. One needs to be aware of the significant differences between these theories, even as to the very concept of power. Nevertheless, the evident analogies I tried to point out do allow us, I suppose, to speak of a similar mode of thinking about power, and this is exactly what I wanted to present.
References
Foucault, M. (1965). Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason. (R. Howard, Trans.) New York: Pantheon. Foucault, M. (1970). The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences, New York: Pantheon, & London: Tavistock. Foucault, M. (1972). The Archeology of Knowledge and the Discourse on Language. (A. M. Sheridan, Trans.). New York: Pantheon. Foucault, M. (1978). The History of Sexuality, Vol. 1: An Introduction. (R. Hurley, Trans.). New York: Pantheon. Foucault, M. (1980). Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972-1977 C. Gordon, (Ed.). Harvester Press: London, & Pantheon Books: New York. Foucault, M. (1980a). The Confession of the Flesh. (C. Gordon, Trans.). In Foucault, 1980. Foucault, M. (1980b). Two Lectures. (K. Soper, Trans.). In Foucault, 1980. Foucault, M. (1980c). Truth and Power. (P. Patton, & M. Morris, Trans.). In Foucault, 1980. Foucault, M. (1982). The Subject and Power. In H. L. Dreyfus, & P. K. Rabinow (Eds.), Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics. Harvester: Hemel Hempstead. Foucault, M. (1988). Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with Michel Foucault L. H. Martin, H. Gutman, & P. H. Hutton (Eds.). Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press. Foucault, M. (1999). Life: Experience and Science. (R. Hurley, Trans.) In Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology (Essential Works of Foucault, 1954-1984, Vol. 2) J.D. Faubion (Ed.). New York: The New Press. Foucault, M. (2003). Society Must Be Defended. Lectures at the Collge the France 1975-1976. (D. Macey, Trans.). New York: Picador. Laclau E., & Mouffe Ch. (1985). Hegemony and Socialist Strategy. Towards a Radical Democratic Politics. New York-London: Verso. Laclau, E. (1977). Politics and Ideology in Marxist Theory. London: Verso. Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark. 136 Power, Discourse, and Subject. The Case of Laclau and Foucault Laclau, E. (1996). Emancipation(s). London-New York: Verso. Laclau, E. (2000). Structure, History, and the Political. In J. Butler, E. Laclau, & S. iek (Eds.), Contingency, Universality, Contemporary Dialogues on the Left, London-New York: Verso. Please purchase PDF Split-Merge on www.verypdf.com to remove this watermark.