Voting On Unemployment Insurance Generosity: Stephane Pallage Christian Zimmermann
Voting On Unemployment Insurance Generosity: Stephane Pallage Christian Zimmermann
Voting On Unemployment Insurance Generosity: Stephane Pallage Christian Zimmermann
Stephane Pallage
CREFE - Universite du Quebec a Montreal
Christian Zimmermann
CREFE - Universite du Quebec a Montreal
July 1998
||||||||||||||||||||{
Pallage: Department of Economics, UQAM, CP 8888 Succ. Centre-Ville, Montreal, QC, H3C 3P8, email:
pallage.stephane@uqam.ca.
Zimmermann: Department of Economics, UQAM, CP 8888 Succ. Centre-Ville, Montreal, QC, H3C 3P8,
email: zimmermann.christian@uqam.ca.
This paper circulated previously under the title \Moral Hazard and Optimal Unemployment Insurance
in an Economy with Heterogeneous Skills" and was presented at the University of Miami, the Institute for
International Economic Studies at Stockholm University, Universite Paris I, Concordia University, HEC
Montreal, Universitat Bern, the annual meeting of the Society for Economic Dynamics in Oxford, the
Canadian Macro Study Group in Toronto and the Tow Conference at the University of Iowa. We beneted
greatly from comments by Dave Andolfatto, Paul Gomme, Gary Hansen, Ayse I_mrohoroglu, Vctor Ros-Rull,
Randy Wright and conference participants at the above institutions.
Abstract:
In this paper, we show that in a dynamic general equilibrium economy, the presence of
moral hazard need not induce large cuts in optimal unemployment insurance benets when
agents are asked to vote on these benets. We nd that it takes quite a large proportion
of \shirkers" to bend the generosity of the unemployment insurance program desired by the
median voter. This result stands in sharp contrast to the extant literature. In addition to
their dierences in asset holdings, agents in our economy are heterogeneous in skills and may
dier in their wage as well as in their transition in and out of unemployment. Our results
have important implications in the light of recent unemployment insurance reforms.
Keywords:
Unemployment insurance, shirking, heterogeneity, voting.
JEL classication: J65, E24, D7
1 Introduction
In this paper, we analyze the eect of moral hazard on the generosity of an unemployment
insurance system when heterogeneous agents are asked to vote on the benets.
An unemployment insurance program is a mechanism by which society protects its members
from adverse idiosyncratic employment shocks. Because society cannot perfectly dierentiate
those hit and those pretending to be hit by such shocks, the optimal unemployment insurance
[UI] is necessarily less generous than under full information. The economic literature is
unanimous on this qualitative impact of moral hazard. It remains an open question, however,
how much less generous the optimal unemployment insurance should be under moral hazard.
In other words, what are the quantitative consequences of the possibility of shirking? This
question has a great social signicance since, in the name of moral hazard, many governments
have recently proposed a reform of their UI program aiming at a reduction of expenditures.
The few quantitative studies to date all seem to agree that moral hazard matters a lot.
Hansen & I_mrohoroglu (1992) question the opportunity of an unemployment insurance pro-
gram when a small proportion of agents can abuse the system and go undetected. Using a
general equilibrium model of the United States economy, they show that even little moral
hazard can cause the optimal replacement ratio to drop dramatically. Zhang (1995) and
Wang & Williamson (1996), in models with unobservable search and job{retention eorts,
draw similar conclusions.
In this paper, we revisit these results by passing to voters the choice of UI generosity. When
confronted with a certain level of moral hazard in the economy, how does a majority arise
in favor of a certain unemployment insurance program? If agents are heterogeneous in
their asset holdings but also in their chances of nding a job and in their expected income,
would they rather vote for a public UI system or a private, self{nanced one? In previous
studies, the model is tted to the United States economy under the assumption that skills
are homogeneous accross agents. Yet, in the United States people who never nished high
school account for 12% of the labor force, high school graduates represent a 61% share,
while only 27% of the labor force holds a college degree.1 Furthermore, it appears that these
groups have very dierent average incomes and unemployment rates. An individual without
a high school degree earns on average 3.4 times less in the United States than a university
graduate2 and is 4.3 times as likely to be jobless.1
Our model is a dynamic general equilibrium model with indivisible labor and a storage
technology like that of Hansen & I_mrohoroglu (1992).3 Agents in our economy are categorized
along four skill types which determine their income level and the matrix of their transition
probabilities in and out of employment opportunities. They choose how much to consume,
whether to work or not if oered a job, and how much to save. Their skill is common
1 Source: Statistical Abstract of the United States, based on Current Population Survey, 1993, Bureau of
the Census.
2 Based on the Survey of Income and Program Participation for 1990 (US Bureau of the Census).
3 Gomes, Greenwood, & Rebelo (1997) use a similar model, but add aggregate uncertainty since their
focus is the study of the unemployment rate over the business cycle.
1
knowledge, but the reason for unemployment is imperfectly monitored: as a result, some
agents may choose to shirk by rejecting oers and still try to collect UI benets.
Aside from the works of Hansen & I_mrohoroglu (1992), Zhang (1995) and Wang & Willi-
amson (1996), a good number of studies also try to assess the welfare implications of UI
programs. Baily (1978) was one of the rst to estimate the optimal replacement rate. Follo-
wing Shavell & Weiss (1979), Hopenhayn & Nicolini (1997) characterize the unemployment
insurance as an optimal contract between a risk neutral principal (the state) minimizing cost
and a risk-averse agent (the jobless worker). They determine the ecient size of benets
over time as a function of the unemployment spell. Since their notion of eciency is one of
minimum cost, it says little about the eects of the UI program on output and welfare in
general. The merit of their study, however, is to be precise about the terms of the ecient
contract, while we take the contract as given.
The potential welfare gains of an unemployment insurance scheme can be of three types.
First, a UI program allows for better consumption smoothing. Second, by providing insu-
rance it can allow workers to be more selective in their job search. This in turn may lead to
better job matches. Third, it may have redistributive eects. Part of the literature can be
divided in the way these eects are considered. For instance, Andolfatto & Gomme (1996),
focussing on the welfare impact of smoother consumption, show that the 1971 reform of the
Canadian UI system, giving way to broader benets, was welfare improving. Their model,
however, is deprived of saving technologies, hence agents cannot self{insure. Such a model
is likely to over{estimate the welfare gains of a generous UI program. An empirical study by
Gruber (1994) also focussing on the consumption smoothing eect in a model without moral
hazard, suggests that current replacement rates in the US are too high. Valdivia (1996)
nds similar results in a calibrated search model. The job{matching eect is analyzed by
Acemoglu & Shimer (1997) who nd it non{negligeable within a search model without moral
hazard. In this paper we bring a novel focus on redistribution while also analyzing consump-
tion smoothing eects. Our methodology does not permit us to account for the last source
of welfare gains. But the job{matching eect would only strengthen our results.
Only Wright (1986) and Hassler & Rodrguez Mora (1997), however, analyze the process
of voting for a UI system. Wright shows a time inconsistency in the votes of agents. Two
identical people would vote dierently whether they are employed or unemployed. We show
that this inconsistency does not necessarily carry through in our economy with moral hazard
and incentive eects. Hassler & Rodrguez Mora, in a model similar to Wright's, except for
the possibility of revoting, show that low turnover has a positive impact on the generosity
of the UI program chosen by the median voter.
We proceed as follows. In the coming section, we outline the model economy, that we later
parametrize to the United States economy in Section 3. We discuss our results in Section 4,
and conclude in Section 5.
2
2 The Model Economy
Our model economy is the economy of Hansen & I_mrohoroglu (1992) augmented with skill
heterogeneity. The economy is made of a continuum of innitely{lived agents. The conti-
nuum is divided in four groups j 2 f1; : : :; 4g of invariant measure j .4 The four groups
dier by one characteristic, the level of education. This heterogeneity in population allows
us to account for the dierences in transition probabilities and income between population
groups observed in the United States.
Agents have preferences over consumption c and leisure l. One good is produced in this
economy through labor. It can be consumed or saved using a storage technology. The
quantity of that good that was saved to date represents an agent's asset m. Labor is indi-
visible. If a worker, individual i in group j works for ^h hours out of his un it{endowment
of time (lij = 1 ^h). This worker produces yj units of output, where yj re
ects his group's
productivity. Job opportunities occur randomly in a way that is described below.5
The sequence of events and actions is as follows. Every period t, agents learn whether
they are given a job opportunity or not. They carry with them their savings mijt to date
and a \certicate" of employment in the previous period (tij = 1 if a job opportunity was
taken at t 1, 0 otherwise). Whoever is (not) oered a job at t is indexed by st = e (u).
Employment opportunities follow Markov transition probabilities pj (st+1jst). A person who
is currently oered a job can choose to take it or leave it. In the latter case, he may receive
unemployment benets with a certain probability, itself depending on his previous state of
employment, (tij ) | that is whether he is a quitter (st = e, tij = 1, tij+1 = 0) or a
searcher (st = e, tij = 0, tij+1 = 0). Once agents have found out their job opportunity and
labor decisions have been taken, those who work are paid yj , those without job opportunity
receive UI benets and those who shirk learn if they have been successful at collecting
benets. Given their disposable income and their current assets, agents nally choose their
level of consumption and savings.
To sum up, each agent i in group j chooses a consumption{leisure{savings bundle (cij ; lij ; mij )
so as to maximize the following objective function:
1
X
U (cij ; lij ) = E0 tU (cijt ; ltij )
t=0
4 In other words there are no exchanges of population between the four groups. This assumption highly
simplies the computation of equilibrium since the distribution of agents between these groups does not
enter as a state variable.
5 Previous models of indivisible labor such as Hansen (1985), Greenwood & Human (1987) and Rogerson
(1988) all suered from the peculiarity that in equilibrium unemployed agents were better o than workers,
because they ended up consuming equal amounts. Rogerson & Wright (1988) have shown that non{separable
preferences prevent this from occurring. The model developed in Hansen & I_mrohoroglu (1992) and ours
use this type of preferences.
3
subject to the budget constraint:
where, U (:; :) is a strictly concave and increasing function of consumption and leisure, yijd
stands for the agent's disposable income and his discount factor. Note that introducing an
interest payment on goods stored would not change the results, as Hansen & I_mrohoroglu
(1992) have argued.
Unemployment insurance is oered by a government which collects a tax ( ) to nance its
program. A public UI program in this set{up is a pair (; ) specifying a replacement ratio
common to each skill group and a tax rate . The UI policy is taken as given by individual
agents when they solve their intertemporal expected utility maximization. The government
balances its budget every period and chooses the UI program that rallies the majority of
votes. The following agents are eligible for UI benets: Every unemployed agent (s = u),
that is anyone who did not receive an employment opportunity, but also every quitter or
searcher who refused a job and went undetected. The probability for a shirker to receive
benets (tij ) corresponds to the probability of not being caught when abusing the system.
It depends on the monitoring eort chosen by the government. We can view monitoring as
a lottery. Since there is a one{to{one relationship between (:), the success rate of shirking,
and the level of moral hazard, we will use (:) as an index of moral hazard.
Eligibility is governed by the following binary function:
8 8
>
>
> >
< with probability 1 if sijt = u
>
>
>
< 1 > with probability (0) if sijt = e; tij = 0; tij+1 = 0
ij
t = > :
>
with probability (1) if sijt = e; tij = 1; tij+1 = 0
>
>
>
>
:
0 otherwise.
The problem of the agents is recursive and admits the following Bellman equation, which
will prove very useful when we compute the equilibrium. Agents take as given the level of
moral hazard (0) and (1) as well as the UI policy. For ease of notations, we drop the time
4
subscript and use primes to denote future states. Call the vector of exogenous variables {
i.e. = (j; ; ; (0); (1)). Agents solve:
v(m; s; ; ) =
8
>
>
>
maxm U (m + (1 )yj m0; 1) + Ps pj (u; s0)v(m0; s0; 0; )
0 0 if s = u
>
>
>
>
> 8 9
< >
>
>
>
maxm U (m + (1 )yj m0; 1 ^h) + Ps pj (e; s0)v(m0; s0; 1; ) ;
0 0
>
>
>
>
> < =
>
>
> max > ()[max U (m + (1 )yj m0; 1) + P pj (e; s0)v(m0; s0; 0; )] > if s = e
>
>
> > m >
> > s >
: +(1 ( ))[maxm U (m m0 ; 1) + P pj (e; s0)v (m0; s0; 0; )]
0
> >
0
: ;
0
s 0
We will call \private", an insurance scheme in which agents of a given skill group nance
their own UI program, with the result that replacement ratios as well as tax rates (insurance
premia) may dier accross skill groups. By private, we therefore understand a UI program
that is compulsory and that can discriminate with an easily visible criterion, here education.
Eligibility to benets from either public or private programs will be governed by the same
rules.
In the next section, we parametrize this model to the United States economy and solve it
numerically.
5
to 1, the unemployment rate to 6% (to be consistent with Hansen & I_mrohoroglu (1992))
and choosing 6 weeks as the period length, we have the statistics summarized in Table 1.
We consider the following utility function:
1
ij ij cij 1t lij t 1
U (ct ; lt ) = 1
with = 0:67 and = 2:5 as in Hansen & I_mrohoroglu (1992) and Kydland & Prescott
(1982). The discount factor is set to 0.995. It is very dicult to assess the extent of moral
hazard empirically. We therefore perform our computations for a wide set of (:){values.
To solve the model, for given replacement ratio () and levels of moral hazard [(0) and
(1)], we iterate on the agents value function over a grid of state variables. Our asset space
is composed of 301 points between 0 and an upper bound that is never chosen by agents
in our computations. We x this upper bound at 8 as in Hansen & I_mrohoroglu (1992).
Other state variables include the skill group, the current job oer status and previous period
employment. Since there is no transition from one skill group to another, we can analyze
each group separately thereby reducing the dimensions of our state space. Once the value
functions and the corresponding optimal decision rules are found, the invariant distribution
of the agents is obtained iteratively. This is performed with an initial guess on the tax rate,
which is then veried given the decision rules and the invariant distribution of each skill
group. When the tax rate balances the government budget, we have reached an equilibrium.
To assess the desirability of an equilibrium, we ask the agents in our economy to vote on ,
given a certain exogeneous level of moral hazard.8 Simple majority rule is applied to select
an equilibrium. A replacement ratio ~ that survives all alternatives is our optimal voting
level of benets. We contrast the results of the votes with the optimal level of benets ^
from the perspective of a planner maximizing a social welfare function with identical weight
on each individual agent's utility (average utility criterion), which is used in the literature.
The votes we consider involve steady{state to steady{state comparisons. Hence agents are
really asked under what system they would rather be born. The dynamics from one system to
another are not taken into account by the voters. In that sense, these are really \helicopter{
drop" votes. Krusell & Ros-Rull (1993) do present dynamic voting equilibria for an optimal
taxation problem. We restrict ourselves to steady{state votes, however, to ensure tractable
computations.
Two types of UI systems will be made available. On the one hand, a purely public system,
cross{nanced by the various skill groups. On the other hand, a private system, nanced
within each skill group and in which the insurer is able to discriminate by the skill level.
Agents will be asked to vote on the optimal level of benets within a system, be it private or
public, but also, in a separate vote, on whether they would rather switch to the alternative
system.
8 Note that there is a one{to{one relationship between the replacement ratio and the tax rate. Hence
voters choose along a single dimension.
6
4 Results
In this section, we present our results. Each subsection deals with one question.
7
moral hazard is increased, ~ drops but less sharply than ^ and remains more generous for
high moral hazard levels. As quitters are more likely than unemployed agents to receive job
oers, they have a higher propensity to forego an oer, especially as they may receive UI
benets if monitoring is not perfect. Finally, the fact that the pool of potential quitters is
much larger than the pool of potential searchers weighs heavily in the welfare cost of moral
hazard.
4.3 A private UI
If instead of a public, cross{nanced UI system, each skill group were to organize and nance
its own unemployment insurance program, for what replacement ratio would its members
vote?
To answer this question, we consider an economy with the same heterogeneity in skills as
above, but deprived of redistributive means across groups. In our Experiment 2, each skill
group runs its own UI program that balances its budget. Results are presented at the bottom
of Table 2.
Each skill group chooses a generosity similar to that of the public system, at least for low
levels of moral hazard. Of course, tax rates dier widely from the public system and take
their toll on generosity for higher levels of moral hazard, especially for groups that have
high unemployment incidence. From the results in Table 2, it appears that, regardless of the
moral hazard level, the tax rate of the high skill [HS] agents in Experiment 1 exceeds their
tax rate under the private system, while the opposite is true for the other skill groups. Since
the median voter belongs to the latter, it is not surprising to observe a high generosity of
the public UI program.
For low levels of moral hazard on searchers [(0) :15], all skill groups vote for the same
benets ~ than a social planner maximizing the average utility within each skill group. For
higher levels of moral hazard, the median voter in virtually all skill groups chooses more
generous replacement ratios than her group{specic social planner would pick.
10Taking transitions into account in the voting process would probably lead to a single and stable optimal
replacement ratio.
9
4.4 Going private? Going public?
Next, we submit to popular vote the following proposition. Given the success rate of shirking
in the economy and a status quo consisting of the public UI program (Experiment 1 with ~
chosen in Table 2), would you consider switching to a privately run UI system (Experiment
2)?
For each level of (0), we successively oer voters alternative replacement ratios ranging
from 0 to 1. As appears in the second column of Table 4, the median voter, however, is
not eager to switch. Only in two instances would the private insurance be chosen: for
(0) = :15, the median voter accepts to switch provided her group specic private insurance
has a replacement ratio of 60%; similarly for (0) = :50, switching would happen if the
median voter obtains a replacement ratio of 15%. In the latter case, Table 2 provides the
explanation for this vote: with a public system, all groups are guaranteed a ratio = :15.
The tax rate is then 1.12%. In the private insurance program, the MS group self{nances
the same replacement ratio with a tax rate of 1.11%. The slight dierence in tax rates is
sucient for the MS group to choose to go private. Detailed analysis of the votes would
reveal that the HS group is willing to switch for almost any private insurance program, while
LS and mS groups vote as a block against it, regardless of its generosity.
In the reverse scenario under which the status quo is a private UI system, where all groups
have settled for their optimal ~ of Experiment 2, would a majority of agents arise in favor
of a public insurance?
The third column of Table 4 answers this question. For all levels of moral hazard other than
15% and 50%, the switch from private to public UI programs rallies a majority of votes. We
never observe \ping{pong" voting as agents never consider \switching back" to the program
they chose to quit. Detailed analysis would show that, consistently with the above results,
high skill agents are categorically opposed to any public alternative.
5 Conclusion
In the extant literature, moral hazard is reported to exert a large in
uence on the optimal
unemployment insurance. We show that this is not necessarily the case. Acknowledging the
dierences in skills within the United States labor force, which translate into income and
unemployment rate disparities, we ask agents to vote for unemployment insurance benets.
We do so within a dynamic general equilibrium framework with a population heterogene-
ous along several dimensions: asset holdings, current and past employment status, income
prospects and employment transition probabilities. As we increase the level of moral ha-
zard in the economy, the median voter does not choose to cut benets as drastically as was
previously reported.
When oered the possibility to switch to a privately run insurance, nanced within each skill
group, voters in majority prefer to stick to their public, cross{nanced UI program for most
levels of moral hazard. If the status quo were a private UI system, the public alternative
would rally a majority of votes for most levels of shirking.
11
In contrast to Wright (1986), our voting equilibria suggest that votes within a skill group
can be time consistent when groups dier suciently strongly. Whether unemployed or not,
agents within skill groups tend to vote as a block.
Hansen & I_mrohoroglu (1992) suggested that when a small proportion of people could refuse
oers and still collect unemployment insurance benets, the optimal replacement ratio had
to be extremely small. Our ndings do not support such drastic conclusions. It takes quite
a big proportion of abusers to make large cuts in benets optimal.
12
References
13
Table 1: Calibration
Skill group HS MS mS LS aggregate
measure .2691 .2606 .3514 .1189 1
income 1.6220 .8950 .7577 .4779 1
unempl. rate .0280 .0518 .0696 .1209 .06
Transition probabilities
HS MS mS LS aggregate
p(eje) .9856 .9727 .9623 .9224 .9681
p(uje) .0144 .0273 .0374 .0776 .0319
p(uju) .5000 .5000 .5000 .5000 .5000
p(eju) .5000 .5000 .5000 .5000 .5000
Note: This table summarizes the key elements of our calibration. All parameters are chosen so that on aggregate, we have the
same calibration as Hansen & I_ mrohoroglu (1992).
14
Table 3: Moral hazard on quitters only
Moral hazard (1) 0 .10 .15 .20 .25 .30 .50
Benchmark ~ .65 .45 .40 .30 .25 .20 .10
^ .75 .35 .25 .15 .15 .10 0
Experiment 1 ~ .65 .45 .35 f.25, .35g .20 .25 .10
^ 1 .55 .45 .20 .15 .15 .05
Note: This table is similar to Table 2, but for moral hazard on quitters only ((1) 0 and (0) = 0).
Note: This table presents, for every level of moral hazard on searchers (0), the results of the votes on whether to switch from
a public to a private UI system (2nd column) or alternatively to switch from a private to a public UI program (3rd column).
Status quos are characterized by the optimal replacement ratios ~ of the corresponding UI program in Table 2. Switches have
been highlighted.
15
Figure 1:
Experiment 1, no moral hazard
−1
−1.005 MS
−1.01
Normalized average utility
−1.015 HS LS
−1.02 mS
−1.025
−1.03
−1.035
0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1
Replacement ratio
In this gure we have normalized average utilities so that -1 is the maximum in each
group.
Figure 2:
Experiment 1, Status quo: θ=.20, π(0)=π(1)=0
1
0.9
HS
0.8
0.7
Proportion of votes in favor
0.6
MS
0.5
0.4
0.3
mS
0.2
0.1
LS
0
0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1
Alternative θ
Note: Given the status quo above, this gure displays the proportion of voters in each
group who accept an alternative replacement ratio. HS, MS, mS and LS groups are
respectively of measure: 26.91%, 26.06%, 35.14% and 11.89%.
16
Figure 3:
Experiment 1, Status quo: θ=.40, π(0)=π(1)=0
1
0.9
0.8
HS
0.7
Proportion of votes in favor
0.6
MS
0.5
0.4
0.3
mS
0.2
0.1
LS
0
0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1
Alternative θ
Note: See note of Figure 2.
Figure 4:
Experiment 1, Status quo: θ=.65, π(0)=π(1)=0
1
0.9
0.8
0.7
Proportion of votes in favor
0.6
0.5 MS
0.4
HS
0.3
mS
0.2
0.1
LS
0
0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 1.1
Alternative θ
Note: See note of Figure 2.
17
Figure 5:
Experiment 1, Status quo: θ=.65, π(0)=.1, π(1)=0
1
0.9
0.8
0.7
Proportion of votes in favor
0.6
0.5 MS
0.4
HS
0.3
mS
0.2
0.1
LS
0
0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 1.1
Alternative θ
Note: See note of Figure 2.
0.9 0.9
0.8 0.8
0.7 0.7
0.6 0.6
0 0.5 1 0 0.5 1
pi(0)=.3 pi(0)=.5
1 1
0.8 0.8
0.6 0.6
0.4 0.4
0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 0 0.5 1
For a given level of moral hazard, each gure plots employment participation against
replacement ratio for all skill groups in Experiment 1. The curves from top to bottom
represent HS, MS, mS and LS employment.
18