HIGLEY, John BURTON, Michael FIELD, G. in Defense of Elite Theory PDF
HIGLEY, John BURTON, Michael FIELD, G. in Defense of Elite Theory PDF
HIGLEY, John BURTON, Michael FIELD, G. in Defense of Elite Theory PDF
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
American Sociological Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
American Sociological Review.
http://www.jstor.org
JOHN HIGLEY
MICHAEL G. BURTON
G. LOWELLFIELD
Universityof Connecticut
421
AMERICANSOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
422
tured and thus powerful on a sustainedbasis.
This alone enables such leadersto affect political outcomesregularlyand substantially,as our
definitionof elites stipulates.We do not deny
thatunstructuredand more or less spontaneous
popularprotestsanduprisingsoccasionallyhave
majorpolitical effects, but unless they take on
bureaucratictrappingsand articulatea distinct
leadershipcomponentthey usually dissipateor
are promptly suppressed. Whether relations
between movement leaders, in our sense, and
otherelites are consensual is thereforean empiricalquestion.
Threeadditionalpoints aboutdefining elites
need mentioning.First, in our empiricalinvestigations of national elites, none of which is
mentionedby Cammack,we have, with various collaborators,applied the concept restrictively, not permissively, in order to focus on
the few thousanduppermostleaders of major
organizationsand movements in societies like
theU.S., Australia,Norway,andWest Germany
(Higley, Field, and Groholt1976; Higley, Deacon, and Smart 1979; Higley and Moore 1981;
Higley, Hoffmann-Lange, Kadushin, and
Moore, unpublished). Second, problems in
defining and identifying elites exist, but they
are minor comparedwith the problems of defining and applying competing concepts like
"rulingclass,""powernetworks,"or "thestate."
As Marcus(1983, p. 25) pointsout, elite theory
has the great advantageof being the only macrotheoryin political sociology thatoperateson
a "small-group,personallevel of conceptualization,"focusing on small numbersof people
who can plausiblybe viewed as sources of politicalcontinuityandchange,who possess some
importantdegree of internalorganization,and
who can often be described in considerable
detail. Third,by adoptinga Weberian-Michelsian conception of elites, we draw attentionto
the organizationalconstraintson elite behavior. The need to maintaincontrolof the organizations that give them power shapes their actions and outlooks in many ways, frequently
overridingthe substantiveinterests and vague
ideological principles on which Cammack
places so much emphasis, and often impeding
their ability to enter into the settlements and
othertransformationsfrom disunity that Cammack thinks should be routine if elites generally gain from such maneuvers.
Cammacknext takes us to task for positing
allegedly circularrelationshipsbetween types
of elites and patternsof regime stability/insta-
423
ELITETHEORYDEFENDED
"imperceptiblycloser"only laterto "driftapart."
Thus, our distinction between disunified and
consensually unified elites is excessively "polarized"and "disproportionate"
to the regime
patternswe seek to explain. We have several
responses to this criticism.
First,in allegingthatwe "polarize"elites into
consensually unified and disunified types,
Cammackforgetsthatwe also distinguisha third
elite, the ideologicallyunifiedtype.If one wants
to thinkin termsof a continuum,ideologically
unified elites would clusterat one end, consensually unifiedelites would be arrayedalong the
middle, and disunified elites would cluster at
the other end. In a recent paper, we invoked
Sartori's (1976) discussion of typologies to
point out that our distinctionsconstitute ideal
or pure types that "representthe standards,
parameters,or models against which ... concrete instances can be compared in terms of
greateror lesser proximity"(p. 145). We wrote:
"Inreality,nationalelites appearto vary along
a continuum while nevertheless clustering
around three fundamentally distinct forms"
(Field, Higley, and Burton 1989, pp. 13-14),
andwe referredto the clustersthata numberof
contemporarynationalelites form.
Second, it is easy to assert that the relative
unityof nationalelites is a continuousvariable,
but since neitherCammacknor anyoneelse has
produceda continuousmeasure of elite unity/
disunity,the assertionleads nowhere theoretically; indeed, without typologies and the classifications they engenderthere can be no theory. Third,our distinctionscorrespondclosely
to the typological work done by other students
of elites (Burton and Higley 1987a). Finally,
we (along with various collaborators) have
conducted several empirical investigations of
national elites that appearto be consensually
unified, andmuch of this work is aimed at providing the criteriaand referentsby which such
elites can be identified. But, again, Cammack
ignores these investigations.
Today it is nearlyaxiomaticin political sociology that a key featureof stable democracies
is substantialconsensus and accommodation
amongelites on rules of the political game and
the worth of political institutions.In Sartori's
(1987) recent formulation, stable democracy
requires that elites perceive politics as "bargaining" ratherthan "war"and that they see
outcomes as positive- not zero-sum (pp. 2246). Whatdivides the field is how this elite conditioncomes aboutandhow it is sustained.Is it
424
AMERICANSOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
Higley 1987b), Cammackbelieves that 168889 was merely the political coda to what had
been a class-conflict symphony, i.e., the English Civil Warsandupheavalsof 1640-60. This
fairlyorthodoxMarxistinterpretation
has drawn
devastatingcriticism(see Goldstone 1983 for a
compelling summary).Our thesis of elite settlement is in step with a growing body of historical scholarshipthat stresses the watershed
characterof the events of 1688-89 (e.g., Jones
1972; Schwoerer 1981; Speck 1988). Full appreciation of our thesis is possible, however,
only when it is placed in comparativecontext,
where it offers a much more plausibleinterpretationthanMarxismfor why it took so long for
most Europeansocieties to achieve the kind of
peaceful conflict managementthat has characterized English politics since 1689, and why
many societies in the world still have not
achieved it.
But let us also dispel the idea that our aim is
to refute class analysis. In some of our work
(e.g., Field and Higley 1980, esp. pp. 21-32;
Field, Higley, and Burton 1989), we hold that
the interdependenceof elites and mass publics
can best be capturedby combining elite and
class theory.In slogan form,ourposition might
be renderedas "Classespush, elites effect" (cf.
Dahrendorf,1988, pp. 53-4). The difficulty is
that classes presumably"push"in ratheruniform ways among similar societies, yet political outcomes are radically different. It is thus
necessary to consider how elites "effect"such
differentoutcomes, and thereinlies the significance of the elite transformationswe examine.
In our investigation of elite convergences
("two-step"transformations),we do not reverse
our method, as Cammackcharges.Analyses of
both settlementsandconvergencesaretriggered
by observations that previously unstable regimes achieved stabilityat some fairly specific
point (e.g., England after 1689, Sweden after
1809, Italy and France duringthe 1970s). According to our theory, such stabilizationof regimes (which also operate according to principles of representative politics) means that
elites achieved substantialconsensus and unity
prior to, or perhapscoterminouswith, stabilization. In concrete cases, the research questions are:Is there evidence of such consensual
unification and, if so, how did it occur? Elite
settlement is one possibility. Another is elite
convergence, in which some of the powerful
but previously warringfactions in a disunified
elite form a winning electoral coalition and,
ELITETHEORYDEFENDED
throughrepeatedelectoralvictories,eventually
leave dissidentelites no alternativebut to compete for governmentexecutive powerunderthe
same rules of the game and other tacit understandingsas the winning coalition. This seems
to capturethe processby which French,Italian,
and other nationalelites became consensually
unifiedin recentdecades,andit is, for example,
the process throughwhich South Koreanelites
are apparentlymoving at present. Though we
thinkthatour thesis of elite convergenceneeds
furtherinvestigation,Cammacktakes no issue
with its accuracy in the cases we have examined.
Cammackis right that we have not as yet
spelled out, let alone documented,the complex
ways in which elite consensus and unity,
whether created through settlements, convergences, strugglesfor nationalindependence,or
otherways, are sustainedover time. He is right
to observethatnew elites emerge andold elites
arepushedaside, andthatthereis, in his words,
"a continual process of negotiation among
changingelite groups"withconsensusandunity
waxing and waning. But he is wrong to assert
thatthe rules of the game change in any fundamentalway. The basic rules of the game, summarized as "restrainedpartisanship,"do not
change.Cammackalso goes astrayin imputing
to us the contentionthat elite consensualunity
is an all-or-nothingcondition, so thateither an
entire national elite agrees publicly on everything importantor it is disunified. Our basic
distinctionbetween ideologically unified elites
(which are what Cammack actually seems to
have in mind)andthe consensuallyunifiedtype
avoids just this confusion. The hallmarkof the
former is uniform public utteranceson major
policy questions in conformancewith a single
ideology. Lacking ideological unity, members
of a consensually unified elite regularly and
publiclydisagreeon suchquestions,thoughthey
just as regularlypull their punches shortof the
point where violence and regime instability
would begin. Finally, while much needs to be
done to specify why and how consensually
unified elites persist in various circumstances,
we cannotidentify a single case in the modern
historicalrecord in which a consensually unified elite, once created,failed to make the adjustments necessary to its continuance. Cammack seems equallyunableto find such a case,
while the history of the last 300 years in his
own country, Britain, testifies forcefully not
only to the lasting effects of elite settlements
425
and the permanenceof this kind of elite, but to
the importanceof elites for comprehendingthe
broadsequencesof politicsin themodemworld.
is Professor of Sociology and
Governmentand Director of The EdwardA. Clark
Centerfor Australian Studies at The Universityof
Texas at Austin.
JOHN HIGLEY
&
Kegan Paul.
. 1985. "National Elites and Political Sta-
bility."Pp. 1-44 in Research in Politics and Society: Studies of the-Structure of National Elite
Groups, Vol. 1, edited by Gwen Moore.
Greenwich,CT: JAI Press.
Field, G. Lowell, John Higley, and Michael G.
Burton. 1989. "A New Elite Frameworkfor Political Sociology." Paper presented to the
Roundtableon "TheNew Elite Paradigm:Opposing Views," American Sociological Association
annualmeetings, San Francisco.
Goldstone, Jack A. 1983. "CapitalistOrigins of the
English Revolution:Chasinga Chimera."Theory
and Society 12:123-42.
Higley, John and Michael G. Burton. 1989. "The
Elite Variable in Democratic Transitions and
Breakdowns." American Sociological Review
54:17-32.
Higley, John,Desley Deacon, and Don Smart.1979.
Elites In Australia. London:Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Higley, John, G. Lowell Field, and Knut Groholt.
1976. Elite Structureand Ideology:A Theorywith
Applications to Norway. New York: Columbia
426
AMERICANSOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
UniversityPress.
Higley, John, Ursula Hoffmann-Lange, Charles
Kadushin,andGwen Moore. Unpublished."Elite
Integrationin Stable Democracies:A Reconsideration."
Higley, JohnandGwen Moore. 1981. "EliteIntegration in the UnitedStatesandAustralia."American
Political Science Review 75:581-97.
Jones, J.R. 1972. The Revolution of 1688 in England. New York:W.W. Norton.
Marcus, George E. 1983. "'Elite' as a Concept,
Theory, and Research Tradition." Pp. 3-27 in
Elites: EthnographicIssues, edited by George E.
MANUSCRIPTSFOR THE
ASA ROSE SOCIOLOGYSERIES
Manuscripts(100 to 300 typed pages) are solicited for publica-